Current Anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 1998 by The Wenner-Gren Foundation for Anthropological Research. All rights reserved 0011-3204/98/3902-0002$2.50 Sometimes profound changes in the Zeitgeist reveal themselves in small ways, like the first timid shoots of an oak seedling before it hauls itself skyward. For me,Can Culture Be an article in the monthly New England Archivists Newsletter, a publication presumably unfamiliar to Copyrighted?1 most anthropologists, signaled a potentially momentous change in the future of our discipline. The article, written by Elizabeth Sandager of Harvarďs Peabody Museum, describes a situation common to museumsMichael F. Brown and archives in the United States: the museum's staff discovered in its collection several drawings of Navajo dry paintings (referred to in the article as ``earth images'') made by the anthropologist A. M. Tozzer early in The digital revolution has dramatically increased the ability of in- this century. Aware that the original images on which dividuals and corporations to appropriate and profit from the cul- Tozzer based his sketches are traditionally destroyed at tural knowledge of indigenous peoples, which is largely unprothe end of Navajo healing rituals, the Peabody staff wor-tected by existing intellectual property law. In response, legal ries that the drawings' continued presence in the collec-scholars, anthropologists, and native activists now propose new legal regimes designed to defend indigenous cultures by radically tion constitutes a form of disrespect. Worse still, the expanding the notion of copyright. Unfortunately, these propos- drawings could have come as the result of a violation of als are often informed by romantic assumptions that ignore the contemporary privacy norms (Sandager 1994:5): broader crisis of intellectual property and the already imperiled status of the public domain. This essay offers a skeptical assessEverything that happens in ceremony is privy onlyment of legal schemes to control cultural appropriation--in particular, proposals that indigenous peoples should be permitted to to those who are participants in the ceremony: the copyright ideas rather than their tangible expression and that singer, the assistants, the sponsor, the family, and such protections should exist in perpetuity. Also examined is the the patient. . . . We are attempting to determine thepronounced tendency of intellectual property debate to preempt circumstances under which these earth image recon-urgently needed reflection on the political viability of specialrights regimes in pluralist democracies and on the appropriate- structions were created, and whether privacy was ness of using copyright law to enforce respect for other cultures. breached. . . . Even though Tozzer did not describe the circumstances under which the reconstructions michael f. brown is the James N. Lambert Professor of An- were created, it should not be assumed that they thropology and Latin American Studies at Williams College. Edu- were created surreptitiously. On the other hand, if cated at Princeton University (A.B., 1972) and the University of they were, there remains the possibility of a seriousMichigan (Ph.D., 1981), Brown has taught at Williams since breach of privacy.1980. His research interests include ritual and religion, human ecology, economic development, and emerging forms of indigenous identity. He is the author of three books about Amazonian Because the Tozzer material is in a poor state of conserIndians, most recently War of Shadows: The Struggle for Utopia vation, Sandager explains, the museum is seeking thein the Peruvian Amazon (Berkeley: University of California advice of Navajo consultants before deciding whetherPress, 1991), coauthored with Eduardo Fernández. Brown's ethnographic research among American spirit-mediums, described in the drawings should be restored or, she implies, quietly The Channeling Zone: American Spirituality in an Anxious Age allowed to decompose. Sandager presents this case as an (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997), led to his current example of the responsibility of professional archivists interest in cultural appropriation and proposed schemes to conto ``consider whether we are violating the privacy of thetrol it. The present paper was submitted 14 iv 97 and accepted affected tribe(s) by providing unrestricted access to doc-7 vii 97; the final version reached the Editor's office 12 ix 97. uments describing traditional beliefs and ceremonies'' (p. 5). Sandager's thoughtful reflections raise a host of complex issues: research ethics and the nature of informed consent, respect for religious beliefs, and concepts of ownership at a time when indigenous intellectual property rights are the focus of lively international debate. Although her article asks vital questions, it conspicuously evades others. If the Tozzer papers are found to be 1. My research on copyright and cultural appropriation was made objectionable, for instance, should they not be sumpossible by the financial support of Harry C. Payne, president of marily destroyed rather than simply allowed to biodeWilliams College, and by the Francis C. Oakley Center for the Hugrade? She mentions that the drawings have long sincemanities and Social Sciences. Colleagues kind enough to comment been published in a book. If a logic of ethical quarantineupon an earlier draft include Sylvia Kennick Brown, David B. Edwards, Eduardo Fernández, Jonathan Haas, John P. Homiak, Gary applies to the drawings, then why not to all known copJ. Jacobsohn, William L. Merrill, Molly H. Mullin, Sydel Silverman, ies of the book, which is, after all, more readily availMark C. Taylor, and Alan Wolfe. Two anonymous reviewers also able to the general public?provided many helpful suggestions. Because some of these readers Then there is the question of privacy. In Anglo-Amer-vigorously dispute the analysis offered here, my thanks for their help in no way implies their endorsement of my opinions. ican law, privacy rights cease or become significantly 193 194 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 attenuated when individuals die. Because Tozzer con- dealing with religious matters. Chairman Masayesva additionally requests the immediate closing of theseducted his field research at the turn of the century, it is unlikely that any of the principals are alive today. In records to anyone who has not received written authorization from the Hopi Tribe. ``This request,'' he adds, ``iswhat sense, then, does the presence of Tozzer's notes and drawings in the Peabody collection violate individ- meant to address the `last minute rush' by researchers to access Hopi information and collections before theyual privacy? Or do native societies enjoy an implicit right of collective privacy to which the museum should are declared `off limits' or are actually repatriated back to the tribe.'' (For a longer excerpt from the letter, seebe attentive, a situation implied by Sandager's stated concern for ``the privacy of the affected tribe(s)''? Haas 1996:S4.) The Hopi initiative was soon followed by a declaration issued by a consortium of Apache tribesFinally, what of the rights of A. M. Tozzer, who presumably bequeathed his fieldnotes to the Peabody on demanding exclusive decision-making power and control over Apache ``cultural property,'' here defined asthe assumption that it would curate them and make them available to researchers? Wouldn't the Peabody's ``all images, text, ceremonies, music, songs, stories, symbols, beliefs, customs, ideas and other physical anddecision to limit access to these materials or knowingly permit their deterioration violate the museum's fidu- spiritual objects and concepts'' relating to the Apache, including any representations of Apache culture offeredciary responsibility to Tozzer and to his descendants? After all, had Tozzer known that such a fate could befall by Apache or non-Apache people (Inter-Apache Summit on Repatriation 1995:3). This broad definition of cul-the record of his life's work, he might well have taken his collection elsewhere. Could this act of passive cura- tural property presumably encompasses ethnographic fieldnotes, feature films (e.g., John Forďs Fort Apache),torial destruction lead future donors to bypass public repositories in favor of private collectors, thereby contrib- historical works, and any other medium in which Apache cultural practices appear, whether presented lit-uting to the privatization of the human cultural record? As Sandager's article makes clear, archivists and cura- erally or as imaginative, expressionistic, or parodic embellishments of concepts with which Apache identify.tors routinely confront an ever-widening series of dilemmas in the wake of the Native American Graves The recent history of relations between Indian tribes and major Anglo-American institutions, including theProtection and Repatriation Act (NAGPRA) of 1990, arguably the most important piece of museum-related federal government, suggests that these encyclopedic demands represent an opening gambit in what are likelylegislation in American history. NAGPRA establishes a legal framework for repatriating human remains and rit- to be protracted discussions. The Hopi and Apache declarations echo similar manifestos from other parts ofual objects to Indian tribes that request them, provided that claimants can substantiate direct descent or, in the the world, including South America, Australia, and the Pacific.3 Clearly, a profound shift in the way we concep-case of objects, prior ownership. The implementation of this legislation, which imposed substantial administra- tualize and contest cultural information is under way. The assumptions that inform this emerging perspectivetive burdens and was in some quarters regarded as disastrous for the future of American museums, has now be- can be summarized as follows: 1. An ethnic nation--a people, in other words--cancome a routine part of museum practice. In fact, many curators hail it as the first step in a historic reconcilia- be said to have enduring, comprehensive rights in its own cultural productions and ideas. These include thetion between native peoples and museums, a process that may lead to new and rewarding partnerships.2 right to exercise total control over the representation of such productions and ideas by outsiders, even in the lat-Few anthropologists would today question the legitimacy of the native claims that lie at the heart of NAG- ter's personal memoirs, drawings, and fictional creations.PRA. The outer boundaries of the law, however, remain vague. Although for the purposes of NAGPRA ``cultural 2. A group's relationship to its cultural productions constitutes a form of ownership. This ownership maypatrimony'' refers solely to objects, the law sets the stage for comprehensive assertions of control over cul- be literal--that is, based on some comprehensive definition of cultural or intellectual property--or meta-tural records currently excluded from consideration. In a letter sent to a number of museums in 1994, Vernon phorical, reflecting universal recognition that in moral terms a group ``owns'' the ideas and practices that itMasayesva, chairman and CEO of the Hopi Tribe, formally states the tribe's interest in all published or un- holds dear. 3. Cultural information pertaining to ethnic minori-published field data relating to the Hopi, including notes, drawings, and photographs, particularly those ties that was gathered in the past by anthropologists, missionaries, government administrators, filmmakers, and novelists is by definition so contaminated by the 2. The literature on NAGPRA is too vast to inventory in this essay. realities of colonial power that it cannot meet (today's)Particularly instructive, however, is the richly detailed study of a single high-profile repatriation case offered by Merrill, Ladd, and Ferguson (1993). Other useful essays on the application of 3. Prominent examples include the Mataatua Declaration (1993), the Julayinbul Statement on Indigenous Intellectual PropertyNAGPRA can be found in Ziff and Rao (1997); its legal ambiguities are explored in DuBoff (1992). For an elegant study of the difficulty Rights (1993), and the Suva Declaration (1995). Copies of these documents can be found at http://www.icip.lawnet.com.au/of reconciling Anglo-American notions of intellectual property with those of a Native American people, see Greene and Drescher info6.htm as well as other on-line sites devoted to indigenous and human-rights issues.(1994). brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 195 standards of informed consent. This information may the practical realities of cultural creativity, information storage and transfer, the fluidity of ethnic boundaries,therefore be quarantined or subjected to severe access restrictions when and if its subjects deem its presence and the limitations of judicial process in developed and developing nations alike.in the public domain offensive. In this essay, I undertake a critical examination of these assumptions with the goal of broadening the scope of debate about the status of indigenous cultural Cultural and Intellectual Property: and intellectual property rights. My skeptical interven- Basic Concepts tion is motivated by a belief that current thinking on these issues has been dangerously narrow, marked more The majority of anthropological research on issues of by passionate advocacy than by sustained reflection on intellectual property confronts the appropriation of inthe broader issues at stake in developing ethical stan- digenous knowledge for commercial purposes, usually dards and legislative mechanisms that impose new lim- by transnational corporations. Case studies have docuits on the free exchange of information in the name of mented the acquisition of native crop varieties for the protecting ethnic minorities. genetic improvement of seeds, the transformation of In framing my analysis, I use the recent work of the traditional herbal medicines into marketable drugs by sociologist Alan Wolfe (1996) as a touchstone. Wolfe ar- pharmaceutical firms, the incorporation of indigenous gues that the American tradition of social criticism has graphic designs into consumer goods without the perdeclined in the past three decades because of the ascent mission of native artists, the exploitation of indigenous of a brand of romanticism based on a dream of utopian music by record companies, and the collection of DNA authenticity. The goals of today's romantic social crit- from isolated human populations for medical uses yet ics, among whom cultural anthropologists stand out in to be determined.5 Although these cases raise complex disproportionate numbers, are manifestly therapeutic: dilemmas at the margins, most are fairly cut-and-dried. they want their subjects to be ``empowereď' or even Commercial interests from the developed world pros``healed.'' They celebrate resistance, rebellion, and devi- pect for information available in the unprotected public ance among social others--even when, in their own domain of indigenous societies. Then, by invoking premiddle-class neighborhoods and places of employment, vailing law, they sequester the information in the prothey are likely to advocate ever stricter forms of proce- tected, private realm of copyrights and patents, where duralism. The trouble with romantic criticism, Wolfe it becomes a monopoly from which they alone profit. argues, is that it simply fails to persuade a large public The problem is easy to identify, but, given the complexaudience. Romantic criticism gratifies the writer's ities of international law and the politically marginal sense of moral worth but can offer only ``utopian long- status of many of the indigenous peoples directly afings that ultimately have no critical edge'' (Wolfe 1996: fected, effective solutions are another matter. Never39). The alternative is a return to a realist perspective theless, there are encouraging signs that major instituthat approaches social problems in all their ambiguity tions in the United States and elsewhere are preparing and nuance, confronting squarely the tragic contradic- to consider appropriate remedies.6 tions that inevitably arise in the everyday life of plural- These cases are made reasonably straightforward by ist societies. the simple fact that the primary issues are mercantile: As I will argue, the debate over intangible cultural the native peoples whose intellectual property is being property as it has been conducted by anthropologists, le- raided seek their fair share of any profits. Here the econgal scholars, and indigenous activists has tended toward omy of information can be regarded not as a zero-sum a polemical romanticism that produces memorable game, in which one person's loss is another's gain, but bumper-sticker slogans (``Give the natives their culture as a process by which resources can be propagated to back!'') but little in the way of sober reflection on the everyone's benefit. difficult balancing act required to formulate policies Before pursuing the broader implications of this qualthat provide reasonable protection for minority popula- ity of information, let me review the basic rationale for tions while maintaining the flow of information essen- intellectual property law. Lawmakers have long recogtial to liberal democracy.4 In particular, a narrow focus nized an implicit tension between the need to protect on indigenous rights blinds social critics to the broader a broad and lively domain of public discussion and the implications of the novel forms of cultural protection that some are enthusiastically endorsing. For thinking 5. Key sources on the exploitation of indigenous biological knowl-on indigenous cultural and intellectual property to be edge and resources include Brush (1993), Cleveland and Murray effective for policy-making purposes, it must be not (1997), Cultural Survival (1996), Greaves (1994), and Posey and only ethically sound but also thoroughly grounded in Dutfield (1996). Works that address the appropriation of indigenous art and music include Feld (1994, 1996), Golvan (1992), Pask (1993), Seeger (1996), and Zemp (1996).4. Although I distinguish between anthropologists and indigenous activists here and elsewhere, I recognize that native peoples are a 6. See Grifo (1994) for a brief overview of a bioprospecting program, partially funded by the National Institutes of Health, that has im-growing and welcome presence in anthropology. Some conflict between these two roles seems inevitable, however, because the dis- plemented plans to guarantee compensation for native communities whose ethnobotanical knowledge leads to the discovery ofcipline of anthropology is predicated on a global, comparative perspective rather than on a particular one. marketable drugs. 196 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 creation of institutions that would foster creativity by the scope of the public domain. Rosemary Coombe, a shrewd critic of prevailing intellectual property law, ob-allowing writers, musicians, and inventors to profit from their works. ``The author,'' writes James Boyle, a serves that a key characteristic of postmodern culture is the growing influence of commodified symbols in ev-law professor and an expert on intellectual property, ``stands between the public and private realms, giving eryday thought and political speech. Children use trademarked action figures and cartoon characters in play;new ideas to the society at large and being granted in return a limited right of private property in the artifact politicians encode their messages with references to advertising and popular television dramas (e.g., ``Where'she or she has created--or at least assembled from the parts provided by our common store of ideas, language, the beef?''). ``Copyright laws,'' Coombe asserts, ``restrict the social flow of texts, photographs, music, andand genre'' (Boyle 1996:xii). David Lange (1993:126), another legal scholar, describes copyright as an implicit most other symbolic works,'' a form of control that ``may deprive us of the optimal cultural conditions forcontract that gives an author ``the limited monopoly of copyright for a limited time, but only in exchange for dialogic practice'' (Coombe 1991:1866). According to Coombe and others, then, aggressive expansion of copy-an eventual dedication of the work to the public domain.'' The common theme is that the rights conferred right and trademark is a significant threat to free speech and political dialogue. Concern over growing corporateby intellectual property laws are limited. Patents and copyrights, for example, have a finite term. (In the control of the symbols that constitute everyday social life, as well as the emergence of new technologies thatUnited States, a copyright endures for the author's life plus 50 years; for patents the term is generally 17 years.) make possible cheap replication and instantaneous dissemination of music, graphic art, and text, have led toUpon expiration, the work reverts definitively to the public domain, where it can be used however people claims that copyright is, or soon will be, dead. ``Information wants to be free'' is the slogan of Internet proph-wish. The range of these rights is similarly finite. I am free to quote limited sections of copyrighted works be- ets such as John Perry Barlow and Esther Dyson. Barlow and Dyson are at the cutting edge of spirited grassrootscause of the fair-use doctrine, which holds that copyright is not absolute--nor can it be in a society that val- resistance to the intellectual property assertions of corporations, especially in the worlds of graphic design,ues creativity. Important legal decisions have also established the right to borrow extensively from copy- avant-garde music, and networked communication.8 A critique of intellectual property law based on therighted works for purposes of political parody. In other words, when intellectual property rights collide with fluid and infinitely replicable quality of information harmonizes well with theoretical developments in an-reasonable assertions of free speech, free speech should prevail even if the results are offensive to the creator thropology, which have increasingly emphasized such postmodern realities as globalization, transnationaland intrude upon his or her copyright. The principal goal of intellectual property laws, then, flows, and the creative mixing (``creolization'') or invention of traditions. From this perspective, culture is notis to see that information enters the public domain in a timely fashion while allowing creators, be they indi- a bounded, static entity but a dynamic, constantly renegotiated process. So thoroughly has the processual na-viduals or corporate groups, to derive reasonable financial and social benefits from their work. Once a work ture of culture come to dominate contemporary thinking that anthropologists appear to be backing away fromenters the public domain, it loses most protections. I am free to publish Uncle Tom's Cabin or to manufac- the culture concept itself (see, e.g., Gupta and Ferguson 1992).ture steel paper clips without paying royalties to their creators, whose limited monopoly has expired. The From this theoretical milieu have emerged trenchant critiques of the presuppositions that underlie the devel-same principle applies to prehistoric petroglyphs or to the ``Mona Lisa,'' both of which have become part of our oped worlďs intellectual property laws (see, e.g., Aoki 1996), which were shaped by the demands of 19th-cen-common human heritage, whatever their origins.7 Intellectual property has become the focus of consid- tury industrial capitalism. Copyright, critics have noted, is predicated on romantic notions of an isolatederable theorizing and legal maneuvering in recent years because of general alarm over the increasingly expan- creative genius who plucks beauty out of thin air by an inspired act of the imagination. Copyright law was de-sive claims of ownership made by corporate interests-- claims that threaten the doctrine of fair use and limit signed to ensure that the author and his or her immediate descendants will benefit from this miracle of creation. The identification of inventiveness with a 7. One could, of course, seek a patent for a new form of paper clip solitary human life, however, cannot be easily reconor a new translation of a work already in the public domain. And ciled with the political economy of modern industrial a new drawing or photograph of an ancient petroglyph would be creativity or, for that matter, with the collective pro-copyrightable, although the design itself would not. It should be ductions of indigenous peoples. Because neither corpo-noted that trademarks represent an exception to the time-limited quality of most intellectual property protection. Generally, trademarks are eligible for protection as long as the holders can prove that they have an enduring economic value in identifying a com- 8. Important statements of the libertarian position with regard to information include Barlow (1993) and Dyson (1995). Manifestosmodity or product line and distinguishing it from others. If a company fails to use its trademark for an extended period, however, demanding an expansion of fair-use standards for musicians and graphic designers include Negativland (1995) and Samudrala (1995).trademark protection may lapse. brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 197 rations nor cultures have a predetermined life span--no trates the problem of literalist notions of cultural property with a memorable example. We commonly regardthree-score-and-ten that can be used as a yardstick for protection--the temporal limits of current copyright Greek civilization as the source of a mode of formal reasoning known as the syllogism. Does that mean thatlaw appear exceedingly arbitrary. Finally, the spread of digital technologies and systems of distributed intelli- the Greek people therefore ``own'' syllogistic logic? Should they be compensated by American or British orgence makes it increasingly difficult for the state to police information and thereby to enforce extant copy- Israeli software companies for their collective cultural contribution to modern programming?right laws. The image that I post on my Web page today can be reproduced and distributed around the world in Disjunctions between indigenous and cosmopolitan views of cultural information are particularly acute inseconds, then stored on personal storage devices relatively impervious to legal scrutiny. Digitally sampled matters of the sacred. Although it is impossible to offer a normative statement about how native peoples con-portions of my music can be modified by other artists and then spliced into their work without my knowledge ceive of sacred knowledge, it is fair to say that many see it as a limited good that cannot properly exist in severalor consent. The chance that I will discover their piracy is vanishingly small. places at once. Religious knowledge that resides in inappropriate places may find its power diminished orEveryone, then, agrees that prevailing concepts of intellectual property are in crisis. But what is to be done? dangerously distorted, hence the common practice of compartmentalizing information in order to limit ac-Before reviewing proposed solutions, we must consider indigenous views of information that differ substan- cess to the inner meaning of religious symbols. The latter impulse may have been a factor behind Ziatially from those I have just described. Pueblo's recent request that the state of New Mexico pay damages for the unauthorized reproduction of the Culture Reified: Information as a Zia sun symbol on New Mexico's flags, license plates, and official stationery since 1925. The state's use of thisLimited Good graphic element in no way limits the ability of Zia residents to continue employing the symbol in their ownAs a number of commentators have observed (e.g., Coombe 1993; Jackson 1989, 1995), the ongoing strug- artistic or religious activities. Yet if one believes, as people at Zia evidently do, that this is a design imbuedgle for political and cultural sovereignty often leads indigenous activists to talk about culture as if it were a with inherent power, its use for everyday civic and commercial purposes is at least an affront to their dignity,fixed and corporeal thing. Calls for the return of land and resources have a way of intertwining themselves at worst a dangerous form of blasphemy capable of unleashing genuine misfortune. One may reasonably inferwith demands for religious freedom and other basic rights to such an extent that it is sometimes difficult that the petition was motivated at least in part by a desire to assert control over something that was onceto distinguish culture from its material expression. A United Nations report on the protection of cultural and solely the community's. ``Ownership,'' Strathern (1996: 30) observes, ``gathers things momentarily to a point byintellectual property reflects this mode of thought when it asserts that ``each indigenous community must locating them in the owner, halting endless dissemination, effecting an identity.''9 retain permanent control over all elements of its own heritage,'' heritage being defined as ``all of those things Indigenous resistance to the promiscuous dissemination of knowledge, sacred and otherwise, lies behindwhich international law regards as the creative production of human thought and craftsmanship, such as emerging conflicts over secrecy. The vast majority of native peoples face so many challenges to their eco-songs, stories, scientific knowledge and artworks'' (Daes 1993:11­13). The heritage in which native peo- nomic and political sovereignty that they have little time to fret about the information-management poli-ples have definitive rights, in other words, includes concepts and thoughts as well as their concrete enactment. cies of public archives or museums. A small but growing number of native communities in North AmericaThis makes perfect sense, the report concludes, because for indigenous peoples ``the ultimate source of knowl- and Australia, however, devote considerable energy to the protection of cultural activities from the scrutiny ofedge and creativity is the land itself'' (p. 10). With few exceptions, cosmopolitan scholars find inquisitive outsiders, whether they be scholars or tourists. Anyone who has visited the Hopi or Taos Pueblosuch reified views of culture problematic. In an incisive analysis of the expansion of property concepts into new reservations in the American Southwest, for example, knows that tribal authorities actively discourage non-conceptual domains, Marilyn Strathern (1996:22) notes that basic cultural understandings sit uneasily within a Pueblo people from observing, recording, or even inquiring about a wide spectrum of cultural practices. Eachframework of intellectual property. Cultures lack clear spatial and temporal boundaries; human beings are 9. My request to the governor's office of Zia Pueblo for informationmembers of a society but not ``members of'' a culture, on this case went unanswered. I regret that I must therefore makewhich is a flexible set of understandings, dispositions, inferences about motive without benefit of Zia Pueblo's own perand behavioral scripts that change through time and spective. Although the New Mexico legislature refused to award freely influence and are influenced by social interac- the pueblo cash damages, it did authorize a formal statement of apology.tions with other groups. Philippe Descola (n.d.) illus- 198 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 community has a different policy regarding admission public good except in a sharply circumscribed range of situations.12 We demand that our educational, religious,to community activities, including religious rituals, but overall it is accurate to say that the Pueblo place strict and political institutions practice openness whenever possible. Although archives routinely impose restric-limits on the circulation of knowledge about their cultures. Although it is commonly believed that Pueblo se- tions on access--when, for instance, they abide by a donor's request that documents be closed to researcherscrecy is a defensive tactic reflecting centuries of external interference in the free exercise of religion, it also for a stated period, usually to protect the privacy of living individuals--I know of no cases in which U.S. pub-plays a key role in maintaining the Pueblos' own political system. In an essay on the social functions of se- lic repositories deny access to archived materials on the basis of a potential user's ethnicity, gender, age, or reli-crecy in Taos Pueblo, Elizabeth Brandt (1980) argues that the primary motivation for closing religious gious affiliation. Such selective restrictions would surely qualify as a form of illegal discrimination.13 knowledge to outsiders and for objecting to the collection and permanent storage of this information by non- Native values and the American legal system are especially prone to collision over the question of retroac-Pueblos is to prevent it from cycling back to Pueblo individuals who are not authorized to possess it.10 Strict tive secrecy, the disposition of information that was obtained in the past and has long resided in the publiccompartmentalization of knowledge is necessary to maintain the community's religious hierarchy and ulti- domain. There are few precedents for the removal of information from the public domain in response to the de-mately the integrity of traditional institutions, which are based on theocratic principles. Of equal importance mands of third parties asserting a right to determine when, where, and by whom this information is ac-is the conviction that in the wrong hands religious knowledge loses its power or assumes destructive cessed.14 Yet this is exactly what some Indian tribes are asking American museums and archives to do. There isforms. Few readers will dispute the general right of the no getting around it: in this case, indigenous beliefs about knowledge of the sacred conflict directly with thePueblo or of any other native groups to restrict the gathering of information about their societies as they see fit. majority's commitment to the sacredness of public knowledge. This is a classic collision of irreconcilableBut we must also acknowledge that principles of secrecy and strict control of knowledge contradict the po- values. To resolve it, both sides will have to reflect carefully on the global implications of their respective posi-litical ideals of liberal democracy.11 In the United States, secrecy has long been regarded as inherently in- tions in order to achieve a suitable compromise. In this context, one can easily see the attraction ofimical to democratic process and to personal freedom. There are, of course, circumstances in which secrecy is framing indigenous demands in terms of copyright and warranted: in matters of national security, in deliberations on sensitive administrative or legislative matters, 12. The philosopher Sissela Bok (1983) offers a thoughtful discussion of the moral and philosophical questions raised by secrecy.in certain kinds of law-enforcement activities, and so Amanda Pask (1993:84­85), a legal scholar, indirectly challengesforth. We also recognize that institutionalized secrecy Bok's universalist assessment by arguing that secrecy is inimical nearly always leads to abuses of power. For this reason, to the Western democracies for specific cultural reasons: ``A comwe have implemented a wide range of ``sunshine laws'' munity which conceives of itself solely as the administrative expression of the rational self-interest of individuals depends for itsthat require government officials to conduct deliberalegitimacy on not being seen to limit `information.' . . .'' In Pask'stions in public and to make administrative documents opinion, however, this attitude toward information is a cultural aravailable to citizens on demand. There is also a strong tifact that may not be found among indigenous populations orgapresumption that once information enters the public nized along communitarian lines. 13. Apparently, some public repositories in Australia close specificdomain, it should stay there. Secrecy, in other words, is Aboriginal collections to women and uninitiated men. For a com-inherently threatening to democratic process and to the prehensive analysis of the Australian case, including discussion of several precedent-setting legal decisions related to ethnographic secrecy, see the essays in Anderson (1995).10. Christopher Anderson (1995:12) reports similar concerns about unauthorized access to sacred information among Aboriginal Aus- 14. Jonathan Haas (1996:S5­6) proposes that such a precedent exists in the voluntary de-accessioning and destruction of a contro-tralians. His own institution, the South Australian Museum, ``had numerous requests from remote communities in Central Australia versial collection of photographs of naked college freshman, mostly from Ivy League institutions, taken for scientific purposes that arethat the Museum never allow the Secret/Sacred Room and its collection to be looked after by an Aboriginal person,'' because these now thoroughly discredited. The analogy has merit, but Haas overlooks at least two important facts: (1) the photographs violate thecommunities did not want men from other groups to see their religious objects. personal privacy of living individuals, and (2) the scientific utility of the photographs is and was minuscule, if it ever existed at all.11. The Hopi Cultural Preservation Office (HCPO) recognizes this fundamental difference in cultural perspectives in a judiciously Their value as historical and scientific documents is thus far outweighed by their ethical deficiencies. As I will argue, similar objec-worded statement found on its homepage on the World Wide Web. ``Most European or Western societies are based in a tradition of sci- tions can doubtless be lodged against some ethnographic records (in which case de-accessioning may be warranted), but to applyentific inquiry, the `righť to ask questions and investigate the unknown,'' the document states. In contrast, the HCPO document them to all such records would be irresponsible unless Haas can establish that museum collections have somehow lost their inher-continues, Hopi tradition discourages open-ended curiosity because many cultural activities are regarded as belonging solely to ent value. To do so, he would have to contradict the opinion of those indigenous spokespersons who argue that the collections arespecific clans or religious societies. See ``Respect for Hopi Knowledge,'' http://www.nau.edu/ hcpo-p/current/hopi nis.htm, ac- so valuable that they should be returned to their source communities for safekeeping.cessed 8 September 1997, unpaginated. brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 199 broadened definitions of cultural property. After all, if mon appeal to principles of intellectual property has the insidious effect of making them moral equals. Innative groups ``own'' their knowledge, if it was ``stolen'' from them by government officials, missionaries, and both cases, broad questions of fair use and the free expression of ideas are magically transformed into aanthropologists, then they are simply seeking the return of pilfered goods rather than asking repositories to narrow dispute over commodities. This troubling moral alchemy underscores the observation of William Gassviolate principles of free access. This approach may be appealing to all parties involved in the dispute. The pe- (1997:62) that ``the chief mode of censorship in a commercial society is, naturally enough, the marketplace.''titioners regain exclusive control over their sacred knowledge. Chronically underfunded repositories, Here Gass refers to the power of publishers and booksellers, who largely determine what gets published andwhich may be worn down by expensive litigation, make a persistent problem go away without an apparent viola- sold in capitalist markets, but he could just as well be speaking about the manifold ways in which intellectualtion of their responsibility to the public. Politicians, who as a group are not known for their commitment to property rights strategies can be, and are, used to deny access to information and to inhibit open communica-social research or their support of public access to information, leap at the chance to propose laws that sum- tion.15 Advocates of the dramatic expansion of the intellec-marily convert information into property. In this case, property discourse replaces what should be extensive tual property of native peoples seem oddly blind to the free-speech implications of their proposals. Kamal Puridiscussion on the moral implications of exposing native people to unwanted scrutiny, on the one hand, and se- (1995:338­39), for instance, supports the imposition of laws prohibiting the use of Aboriginal art and symbolsquestering public-domain information, on the other. For those who object that I attribute too much impor- by outsiders. The commodification of Aboriginal art, he argues, ``deprives Aboriginal people of an importanttance to claims that are solely relevant to the unique situation of native minorities, let me mention another economic base; and secondly, if trivialized, it can undermine the autonomy of unique Aboriginal traditions.''case that has striking parallels to contemporary indigenous demands. For several years, the Church of Sci- Although this rationale for cultural protection seems reasonable at first glance, upon reflection one begins toentology has waged a relentless campaign against owners of Internet sites that store and transfer texts wonder where the legal prohibition of religious ``trivialization'' or sacrilege might lead. Would citizens there-regarded by Scientologists as secret, copyrighted material. At the insistence of church attorneys, computers fore be subject to civil and criminal penalty if they trivialized any religious symbols? Would indigenoushave been confiscated in the United States and Finland by law-enforcement officials searching for such docu- peoples themselves be subject to reciprocal fine or arrest if they manipulated Christian imagery for theirments. The Church of Scientology has also filed complaints that led to the seizure of public-domain court own purposes? One can easily imagine conservative evangelical groups taking offense at the use of Christiantranscripts posted on the server of an Internet service provider in Virginia, and it is seeking civil damages symbols by members of the Native American Church during peyote meetings. In the American context, cer-from the Washington Post for publication of what it considers to be proprietary information (Grossman tainly, legal efforts to prevent parodic or creative appropriations of religious symbols would present a serious1995:174, 252). Scientologists offer nearly the same rationale for these search-and-seizure acts as American challenge to the First Amendment. Indians do for their opposition to the presence of religious information in archives (p. 174): ``Scientologists genuinely believe their secrets can save the world, but Information Ethics that they must be doled out only to whose who have proven ready to receive them. Followers hold fiercely to Another element of contemporary debate over cultural and intellectual property is the claim that indigenousthe notion that their revered, secret texts must never be disseminated, save to the rigorously initiated.'' In other knowledge currently available in the public domain was obtained under circumstances so inherently coercivewords, the formidable legal arm of the Church of Scientology has invoked principles of intellectual property that it should be either sequestered or returned to its source community. The most extreme version of thissimilar to those cited by indigenous groups demanding that ethnographic material be removed from public ac- position--the assertion that ethnographic field data have the same moral standing as the now-quarantinedcess. Civil libertarians have denounced the Scientology campaign as a serious threat to free speech, in part be- records of medical experiments conducted in Nazi concentration camps--still has few advocates, but it is onlycause it uses copyright law to silence the church's critics. a step or two removed from today's orthodoxy, which This is not to imply that the claims of the Church of 15. Some experts in intellectual property law express concern thatScientology are morally equivalent to, say, those of the copyright is increasingly used to restrict access to information in-Apache leaders who demand control over Apache constead of encouraging its dissemination (see, for example, Branscepts and images. The Church of Scientology, it must comb [1994] on struggles over access to the Dead Sea Scrolls and be noted, collects large fees from initiates before it Conley [1990] regarding the scholarly use of unpublished biographical information, especially letters and diaries).allows them access to its secret texts. But their com- 200 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 sees ethnography as an important instrument in the he- norms? Did the researcher keep his or her promises about how the information would be used?gemonic project of classifying, representing, and ruling subject populations (see, e.g., Pels and Salemink 1994). Perhaps the hardest condition to establish retrospectively is informed consent. To what degree, for exam-Once we accept the totalizing logic of this formula, the conclusion that all records from formerly colonized ple, did research subjects realistically comprehend how their lives might be affected by their role in an ethnog-places are ethically tainted follows naturally. Yet anyone willing to look carefully at the historical raphy, a documentary film, or an audio recording, especially if they were relatively unfamiliar with these me-evidence will be dissatisfied with blanket condemnations of ethnographic records. At the very least, we dia? Even conscientious and well-meaning researchers fail to anticipate all the possible effects of their work,must acknowledge the agency of indigenous peoples-- their strategic decisions to share ideas and stories and and they are sometimes as disturbed as their subjects by the unexpected impact of their publications, record-songs with inquisitive outsiders when, in their judgment, circumstances warranted. In an informative anal- ings, or images. In this area, the Law of Unintended Consequences reigns supreme; there will always be un-ysis of a major Zuni repatriation case, for example, Merrill, Ladd, and Ferguson (1993:541) mention that several foreseen effects, both good and bad, when information enters the public domain.16 cultural items acquired by the Smithsonian Institution in the late 19th century may have been made expressly Ethical realism holds that each case is unique and therefore subject to careful retrospective review. If sig-for the museum because Zuni leaders believed that greater public awareness of the beauty of Zuni religion nificant violations of the norms of the time took place, with lasting, negative impacts on a particular people orwould improve relations between their tribe and the federal government. Zuni authorities may also have re- community, then it may be appropriate to quarantine the offending research in some way, perhaps by makingvealed certain ritual secrets to the Smithsonian anthropologists Frank Hamilton Cushing, James Stevenson, it available only to members of the affected group or to others authorized by them. In keeping with the empha-and Matilda Coxe Stevenson in the hope that their continued professional involvement with Zuni culture sis that repositories place on freedom of access, one would expect that closure of a collection would takewould lead them to defend Zuni interests in Washington (Merrill and Ahlborn 1997:195). Both strategies place rarely, and only in the face of compelling evidence that continued use would damage the affected commu-seem to have worked. This is hardly a history free of coercion, but it includes powerful elements of volition nity. Such caution is warranted because decisions to quarantine information never take place in a politicaland of cultural resistance through strategic sharing that merit acknowledgment and respect. vacuum. Citizens of all ethnic origins have an interest in continued access to information already residing inInterpretations that reduce ethnography to an encounter between oppressor and oppressed, interacting the public domain. Moreover, voluntary removal of material from public access establishes precedents likelylike automatons in a grim game of power, overlook the complex human motives that animate ethnographic en- to be exploited by other religiously and politically motivated interest groups--some of which, it bears pointingcounters: curiosity, aesthetic delight, mutual self-interest, genuine respect or affection, erotic attraction (rec- out, would advocate positions strongly antagonistic to indigenous political rights and cultural self-expression.ognized or denied), the visceral pleasures of storytelling, and a desire to understand other social worlds. They Published accounts and my own queries to museums and archives suggest that at the level of day-to-day oper-also summarily repudiate the work of countless observers who have dedicated their lives to the documentation ations this commonsense approach to ethics is currently the norm in the United States.17 These reasonableof indigenous lifeways, sometimes at great personal cost. This enterprise may have been facilitated by colo- procedures stand to be usurped, however, by comprehensive claims of ownership. If it can be establishednialism, but more often than not its effect was to challenge assumptions of colonial superiority. Today ethno- that in some meaningful sense ethnographic and historical records are ``owneď' by the peoples who are theirgraphic records provide critical information that indigenous peoples use to revitalize their cultures and subject, then complex questions about the ethical stato substantiate land and resource claims in courts of law. The species of naive presentism that judges histori- 16. Issues of informed consent in the filming of the controversial cal actors by today's ethical standards would, if given documentary Titicut Follies are explored in considerable detail by Anderson and Benson (1988). Zemp (1996:49­63) describes ethicalfree rein, mandate the pious quarantine or even destrucstruggles over the commercial licensing of Rajasthani music re-tion of most of these important resources. corded by a fellow ethnomusicologist many years earlier, at a time The alternative to ethical absolutism is ethical realwhen neither had anticipated the music's potential commercial ism, with all its exacting ambiguities and dilemmas. value. For reflections on the role of ethics in the preservation of Realists judge work by the extent to which it violates or anthropological materials, see Fowler (1995) and Greaves (1995). 17. Letters to 16 American museums and archives to inquire aboutconforms to the ethical standards that prevailed when it their response to the Hopi request for a moratorium on access towas collected. Was information gathered under circumethnographic materials produced 8 replies. Of these, none reported stances that would have been considered dishonest or that it had actually closed collections, although several now mark unduly coercive then? Was deception involved, and, if collections relating to the Hopi and other tribes as ``sensitive'' and encourage scholars to contact tribal authorities before using them.so, how egregious was it in terms of prevailing ethical brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 201 tus of the cultural property become irrelevant. And here ple, depicts the New Age as a particularly offensive example of the commodifying logic of late capitalism.we face one of the hidden ironies of contemporary debate: although advocates of expanded intellectual prop- ``Because so many people have been taught that the world is a giant warehouse in which everything is orerty laws typically denounce capitalist commodification, they implicitly encourage the translation of ought to be available,'' she writes, ``they too easily believe they can achieve enlightenment by payingethical and political discourse into the language of commodities. money'' (p. 97).18 However much we may deplore the cultural insensitivity that underlies these middle-class explorations of Ethnographic Fictions in the indigenous spirituality, Rooťs argument illustrates the strikingly cramped and in some cases misdirected de-Age of the Simulacrum bate that this situation has inspired. For example, when critics declare that indigenous spirituality lacks a com-Contemporary assertions of intellectual property offer other and perhaps more plangent ironies rarely noted by mercial aspect, in sharp contrast to the alleged commercial vulgarity of the New Age, they willfully ignore acommentators. At a moment when many anthropologists have come to regard ethnographic and historical vast literature that establishes the economic nexus of ritual almost everywhere in the world, a pattern that of-texts as interested fictions, indigenous peoples insist that these documents contain sacred knowledge so au- ten includes substantial payments, in cash or goods, to ritual specialists. Nor has the controversy seen contri-thentic and powerful that access to it should be carefully controlled. Even as ethnography moves in a con- butions by anthropologists who in other contexts celebrate cultural flows and creative creolization, of whichfessional direction, offering ever more information about the ethnographer's personal history, feelings, and New Age practices are surely an outstanding example. One might also reasonably call for rigorous analysis ofmotives (to the extent, some would say, that it becomes difficult to find the Other in the text), the Other is how this instance of religious borrowing differs from other kinds of intercultural sharing that underwrite re-claiming ownership of the textual simulacrum. Nowhere have these contradictory currents proved more ligious innovation throughout the world. By pointing to these deficiencies, my purpose is not to defend the imi-acrimonious than in public debate over the New Age ``appropriation'' of Native American religion. tation of native rituals by non-natives. (I don't know how one could possibly endorse a practice as appallingAcross the United States--and, increasingly, in Europe and other parts of the developed world--middle- as the ``Smoki'' Snake Dance, a parody of Hopi ritual conducted annually by wealthy Anglos in Prescott, Ari-class spiritual seekers are enrolling in workshops and therapy sessions that introduce them to rituals identi- zona, vividly described by Peter Whiteley [1997:177­ 79].) My personal view is that middle-class baby boom-fied with indigenous spirituality: ersatz Medicine Wheel ceremonies, sweat lodges, vision quests, and ers looking for spiritual authenticity should explore the rich religious traditions of Europe and allow native peo-even healing sessions involving consumption of the Amazonian hallucinogen ayahuasca. Sometimes those ples to worship in peace. Nevertheless, the phenomenon merits a broader and more dispassionate analysiswho officiate are of native extraction, although few are recognized as religious leaders in their own communi- than we have seen thus far. Perhaps the most interesting feature of the contro-ties. More commonly, they are non-natives claiming knowledge of indigenous lore. versy is the extent to which native religious leaders object to it not on the ground that New Age rituals areTo say that the practices of these ``Indian wannabes'' have evoked intense criticism would be an understate- bogus but precisely because they are, in some sense, real (see, e.g., Whiteley 1997:188; Jocks 1996:418). Ament of the first order. In a ``declaration of war,'' Lakota leaders have denounced the ``absurd public posturing of statement issued by Indian leaders meeting in Window Rock, Arizona, in 1984 notes that New Age ceremonialsthis scandalous assortment of pseudo-Indian charlatans'' (Stampede Mesteth, Standing Elk, and Swift are ``exposing ignorant non-Indians to potential harm and even death'' (AIM Leadership Conference 1984) be-Hawk n.d.). Another Indian activist deems such fauxnative ceremonials to be another example of ``a very old cause of the rituals' inherent power. Much as the general public is repelled by the prospect of cloned humanstory of white racism and genocide against the Indian people'' (Smith 1994:70). Similar denunciations fol- beings, native religious leaders express horror at the monstrous cloning of their visions of the sacred. Forlowed the publication of Marlo Morgan's best-selling Mutant Message Down Under (1994), a book that de- them, the New Age is a kind of doppelgänger, an evil imitation close enough to the real thing to upset thescribes the author's religious experiences--later revealed to be entirely fictional--among a group of Ab- delicate balance of spiritual power maintained by Indian ritual specialists.original Australians. Robert Eggington, a spokesman for Australia's Nyoongah people, has been quoted as saying that Morgan's book ``amounts to nothing less than cul18. The firestorm of criticism directed to New Age practices has tural genocide of the spiriť' (Mutant message downed!!! produced a literature too vast to document fully here. Useful 1996). Academic observers are only slightly more mea- sources include Albanese (1990), Brown (1997), Jocks (1996), Johnson (1995), Kehoe (1990), and Rose (1992).sured in their criticism. Deborah Root (1996), for exam- 202 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 ``The culture of the copy muddies the waters of au- unleashing it in an unregulated market, where consumers can pay for what they want and ignore what theythenticity,'' Hillel Schwartz (1996:377) has observed. As the technologies of the simulacrum proliferate around don't. The illicit replication of information cannot be stopped; only performances can be controlled, so cre-us, producing what Mark Taylor and Esa Saarinen (1994) call the ``simcult,'' souls lost in the forest of cop- ative individuals and groups will have to find ways to benefit materially from performance-like encountersies take up a desperate search for the original that leads them almost inevitably to indigenous peoples, who in with a paying audience. Because this position has few followers among anthropologists and indigenous activ-our time have become icons of primordial integrity, of meaning uninflected by imitation. In seeking the au- ists, I bracket it from serious consideration here. But whatever its flaws and blindnesses, the radical libertar-thenticity of native religions, however, they succeed only in fashioning another flawed simulacrum.19 Under ian proposal injects a note of realism into current debate by reminding us that control of information and thethe circumstances, it is hardly surprising that indigenous leaders want to tighten their grip on the originals. proliferation of simulacra is or soon will be impossible. The principal alternative to informational libertarian-But this particular genie has already escaped from the bottle. Those who dream that knowledge can be ``repa- ism is the creation of new institutions and legal mechanisms designed to protect ``cultural heritage, folklorictriateď' through copyright laws--vain attempts to slow the metastatic self-replication of information in the Age productions, and biological `know-how,''' to quote the language of the Bellagio Declaration, a document pre-of the Simulacrum--are destined to be disappointed. Despite the Church of Scientology's single-minded pared by a diverse group of experts in intellectual property (reproduced in Boyle 1996:192­200). With admira-pursuit of criminal prosecution and civil action to prevent the reproduction of its secret texts, for example, ble clarity and conciseness, the Bellagio Declaration advocates a two-pronged revision of intellectual prop-there is little evidence that it has succeeded in recapturing all or even a significant fraction of the copies held erty practice: on the one hand, it calls for a significant expansion of the public domain by diminishing intellec-by its opponents, doubtless buried on the hard drives of their computers or squirreled away on diskettes. The re- tual property rights--say, by shortening the term of copyrights or by limiting the circumstances undercent history of the Internet demonstrates that draconian attempts to police information are likely to fail, which they may be awarded; on the other, it calls for the creation of ``related rights regimes'' to protect indig-although governments and powerful interest groups may succeed in temporarily stifling open dissent. The enous intellectual property. As experts on intellectual property law, the authors of the Bellagio Declaration aresame fate awaits indigenous groups seeking total control over information about their societies. Its use by aware of conflicts between these two agendas, and within the limits of a brief document they try to recon-law-abiding historians and social scientists will surely decline, but there will soon arise an underground litera- cile them without specifying in detail how this harmonization might be accomplished.ture--a native-knowledge samizdat or, more likely, something resembling the X-Files, the American televi- The measured language of the Bellagio Declaration contrasts with the sweeping demands of those who seesion series that exploits popular belief in the governmenťs secret contacts with extraterrestrials--that is intellectual property law as a mechanism for protecting indigenous philosophies. Recall, for example, the mani-likely to give rise to distortions of fact far worse than the misrepresentations that today infuriate indigenous festo of the Inter-Apache Summit on Repatriation (1995:4), which asserts title to ``symbols, beliefs, cus-leaders. As is true in the case of religious secrets, the conversion of debate about New Age rituals into a toms, ideas and other physical and spiritual objects and concepts,'' or the UN document stating that native peo-struggle over intellectual property undermines prospects for urgently needed public discussion about mu- ple have an inherent right of control over everything encompassed by the term ``cultural heritage'' (Daes 1993).tual respect and the fragility of native cultures in mass societies.20 These documents lay claim to thought as well as its actualization in concrete acts of creation. Those familiar with copyright know that the distinction between ideas and their expression--that is, ``fixing in tangible form''Toward Genre Police and ``Certified (see Litman 1991:239)--is foundational to notions of in-Indigenous PersonsTM''? tellectual property. The reason for this is obvious: because we cannot ascertain the origin of ideas unlessAs I noted earlier, one proposed solution to the crisis of they are expressed in some stable, material form, itintellectual property is the libertarian option articuwould be impossible to enforce claims on them. Yetlated by Barlow and Dyson: let information be free by some experts in intellectual property now urge that the idea/expression distinction be abandoned because of its19. According to David Sanjek (1992:609), the availability of affordable digital sampling equipment has had a similar effect on alleged ethnocentrism, its inability to protect creative contemporary music: ``The elevation of all consumers to potential linguistic, artistic, or musical productions expressed creators . . . denies the composer or musician an aura of autonomy through performance rather than preserved in a perma-and authenticity.'' nent medium such as writing. Proposals for the ex-20. For further discussion of the contradictions and dilemmas of new media, see Schwartz (1996) and Baudrillard (1988). panded protection of indigenous intellectual property brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 203 rights also typically object to the time-limited quality Among other things, folklore-protection boards might be authorized to intervene if nonfolkloric people pro-of current copyright and patent laws. If native knowledge is held to be collective and eternal rather than the duced designs that imitated authorized folkloric styles or if native art were used in ``culturally inappropriateinvention of a solitary author, then it follows that time limitations keyed to the human life span, which clearly contexts.''22 Perhaps I am alone in wondering how a UNESCO-reflect the possessive individualism of Western capitalist thought, should be replaced by some form of perpet- style bureaucracy would further the interests of indigenous peoples by codifying their knowledge in whatual copyright.21 These proposals call to mind Apple Computer's would have to be a byzantine series of regulations. One can only imagine the endless legal actions and legisla-highly publicized infringement lawsuit against Microsoft, which claimed that Microsofťs Windows program tive initiatives that would be required to protect against infringement of the look and feel of Tlingit art or theillegally appropriated the ``look and feeĺ' of Apple's proprietary software (Mota 1995). Although Apple ulti- stylistic particularities of Shuar oratory. And when considering parts of the world where the rule of law is somately lost the suit, notions similar to its look-and-feel claim have been picked up by participants in the ex- tenuous that even basic traffic regulations are the object of collective scorn, we might well question how indige-panding scholarly debate about cultural appropriation. In a recent essay on the ethics and pragmatics of the nous populations would benefit from the implementation of far less enforceable laws relating to intangiblemusic industry, for instance, Steven Feld (1996) brilliantly tracks the processes by which recordings of the cultural property. It is also prudent to consider what the broader socialmusics of Mbuti and other ``Pygmy'' peoples find their way into contemporary jazz and World Beat, usually impact of look-and-feel protection might be. Could it in fact be confined to ``designated folkloric populations''without attribution or compensation. My reading of Felďs analysis is that he views those artists whose work or ``certified indigenous peoples'' without seeping into the broader world of commerce, where corporations arereplicates even the sounds and textures of Mbuti music as performing an act of cultural appropriation. In other already storming the borderland between idea and expression? Who is more likely to be silenced by the en-words, imitating the ``look and feeĺ' of a people's music is a form of cultural theft, even if it occurs within a forcement of look-and-feel copyright: the Sony Corporation, for its infringement of Mbuti flute playing, or thegenre such as jazz, which is largely predicated on improvisational transformations of the artistry of musicians emerging African recording artist whose first commercial CD infringes the style of Michael Jackson? Andfrom every corner of the globe. Although Feld wisely steers clear of proposing that what of scholarship? Anthony Seeger (1996:87) notes that it is already difficult for ethnomusicologists to pub-we create a new species of genre police to protect indigenous musicians from exploitation, other scholars lish articles on popular music because of copyright constraints that prevent the quotation of lyrics and musicalprove less cautious. Indeed, journals devoted to the subject of intellectual and cultural property cheerfully offer scores, an example of the corporate worlďs concerted efforts to downsize the scope of fair use. Consider, then,any number of schemes to codify culture and thereby protect it from misuse. Most of these proposals call for what history or anthropology will become when scholars are prevented by law from writing accounts specificthe redefinition of folklore as part of a national or even a global patrimony. They also encourage the imposition enough to evoke the religious or political practices of protected native populations. Perhaps we can look for-of a regime of ``moral rights'' for cultural property that would exist in perpetuity. (The moral-rights concept, ward to the day when the Freud estate is sued on the grounds that Totem and Taboo violates the folkloricwhich is alien to U.S. copyright law but commonly applied in European countries, asserts that the state has copyright of indigenous peoples--from two world regions, no less. Less fanciful is the prospect of court or-an enduring interest in the integrity of works of cultural patrimony. Any attempt to modify a protected work-- ders that remove works of ethnomusicology, history, and ethnography from library shelves because they pur-say, by altering a classic film or images of a famous painting--would violate its moral integrity even if its formal copyright had long since expired.) UNESCO, 22. In Australia, where the protection of Aboriginal art and culture which has drafted schemes for the application of this is strongly supported by anthropologists, lawyers, and native activkind of protection to indigenous cultural productions, ists, Colin Golvan reports that successful attempts to enforce Aboriginal copyright to traditional designs led wily tee-shirt manufac-envisions the establishment of state folklore protection turers to produce knockoffs that merely imitated the style ofboards that would ``register [folkloric] works and authoAboriginal art. Golvan (1992:229) comments: ``One issue which rize their use,'' allowing exceptions for ``educational justifiably arises for attention is whether there ought to be protecand inspirational purposes'' (Berryman 1994:327). tion to prohibit this bastardization of Aboriginal art, and if so, how this protection would work.'' (See also Blakeney 1995 for additional discussion of Australian legal initiatives.) In the domain of music, Mills (1996:74) provides a detailed description of recent Brazilian21. See, for instance, Berryman (1994) and Mills (1996). The Mataatua Declaration, which was issued after a 1993 conference in New legislation designed to protect the intellectual property of indigenous communities by ``eliminating burdensome, ethnocentricZealand, calls for a ``multi-generational coverage span'' for indigenous intellectual property, leaving unanswered the question of copyright requirements of living authors, originality and tangibility.''whether such protections would be permanent. 204 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 vey stolen property. If time limitations on indigenous domesticated by indigenous populations and used by them for centuries.copyright were waived, as has been proposed by some scholars, then this intellectual stalemate could exist in It is the broader debate about cultural appropriation that I find disturbing--specifically, the reluctance ofperpetuity. For the most radical of indigenous activists--and, in- otherwise thoughtful scholars to dissect the ethnonationalist claim that there exists an inherent, perma-cidentally, for the giant corporations that oversee the worlďs news and entertainment media--such impedi- nent right of cultural ownership and that this right should be guaranteed by new laws that, among otherments to scholarship and the exchange of ideas would be welcome. The Hawaiian nationalist Haunani-Kay things, define ideas as property. Discussions about strategies for preventing cultural appropriation seem toTrask (1991:162), for example, characterizes anthropologists and historians as ``part of a colonizing horde be- take place in a parallel universe unaffected by the fierce struggle of creative artists and the general public for freecause they seek to take away from us the power to define who and what we are, and how we should behave access to information in the face of growing corporate domination of knowledge, now commodified as ``con-politically and culturally.'' Trask evidently hopes that indigenous peoples will eventually achieve exclusive tent.''24 To some extent, of course, ethno-nationalists are reacting to this mad scramble for control by pro-power to represent themselves to the world at large. If realized, this vision would impound knowledge in a tecting what they can. But nothing would serve corporate interests more perfectly than the collapse of thenew reservation system: reservations of the written word, an apartheid of the mind.23 idea/expression distinction or the abandonment of time horizons on copyrighted material. Expectations thatIn his reflections on the separatist movement in Quebec, Richard Handler (1988:194) observes that national- such radical extensions of intellectual property laws could be restricted to indigenous populations throughists make preemptive claims to knowledge because they are ``haunted by a vision of totality'' that can be the establishment of regimes of special rights are extremely naive. The legal frameworks necessary to sus-achieved only when a people becomes ``an irreducible, homogeneous unit, securely in control of its borders, tain the permanent protection of entire cultures will inevitably require greater involvement of governmentalself-contained, autonomous, and complete.'' The ethnic nation, in other words, seeks to recover and then to con- or quasi-governmental agencies in the business of determining who is a native person and exactly what qual-trol its history and its folklore, sharing it with outsiders only in forms that it deems appropriate. A consideration ifies as indigenous knowledge, a situation that one would be hard-pressed to see as beneficial for ethnic mi-of the moral standing of this dream of cultural purity is beyond the scope of this essay. But there can be little norities. One wonders, too, about the fate of those artists--Louise Erdrich, Allan Houser, and Baba Olatunjidoubt that attempts to impose new border controls on the flow of knowledge raise troubling questions that come immediately to mind--who have drawn on native identities to fashion art that transcends ethnic bound-should be resolved, or at least thoroughly discussed, before supporting new legal regimes that codify cultural aries. Would they, too, have to ``repatriate'' themselves to satisfy the demands of a system that defines owner-property and potentially even criminalize its unauthorized possession. ship primarily by ethnicity? A realist perspective acknowledges the uneven hold that intellectual property laws have on the flow of knowledge into and through the new digital technolo-Closing Thoughts gies. Even the supposedly privileged artists and writers of the majority culture routinely find their copyrightsAlthough there are compelling reasons to be skeptical of some indigenous intellectual property rights propos- violated by information-distribution services that provide copies of works to clients on demand (Tisdaleals currently under discussion, I strongly support efforts to create basic mechanisms for the compensation of na- 1997:70). One can imagine how much more difficult it will be to police the comprehensive copyright protec-tive peoples for commercial use of their scientific knowledge, musical performances, and artistic cre- tions now being considered for indigenous cultures. As the legal scholar Jessica Litman (1991:248) has pointedations. Equally necessary are clear guidelines for the collection of culturally sensitive ethnographic data and out, when copyright regulations diverge too dramatically from the practical understandings of authors andpotentially marketable human biological materials, including cell lines. I would hope, too, that anthropolo- the general public, these laws lose legitimacy. This problem would surely intensify were governments togists will continue to register objections to the patenting of medicinal and agricultural plants discovered or implement radically expanded copyright laws designed to protect all forms of intangible cultural property. The ensuing flurry of litigation would favor only the largest 23. ``In such circumstances, a particular version of the past becomes a commodity that can be mobilised for political power and economic gain, where a sovereign territory of knowledge is asser- 24. See, for instance, Bettig (1996), Browning (1997), Samuelson (1997), and Schiller (1989) for discussion of attempts by Northtively appropriated as one's `own,' in the interests of creating a useable history that will serve as a vehicle for correcting past wrongs'' American media interests to impose ever more restrictive copyright laws on the rest of the world.(Munro 1994:233). brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 205 corporate interests, for whom legal fees are simply a more one of respect, but of taking sides, of solidarity.routine cost of doing business. Conspicuous by its absence is a vigorous defense of the concept of a public domain.25 This is doubtless be- Fortunately, something close to Taylor's vision of authentic intercultural respect appears to be taking holdcause postcolonial scholars regard appeals to notions of the civic whole as thinly veiled advocacy for (white) in archives and museums. Aware of their responsibility to protect public records while remaining responsive toelites. ``Whose public are we talking about?'' they ask. The question admits of no easy answer. The realities of the concerns of groups who claim an interest in them, repositories are willing to ask tough questions of thosemoney, power, and social capital make the public domain more accessible--and exploitable--for some citi- who demand that irreplaceable cultural information be destroyed or closed to the multiple publics whom theyzens than for others. Yet the public domain that permits the intellectual colonization of native peoples also of- serve. New working relationships between repositories and indigenous communities, many set in motion byfers resources that they regularly appropriate for their own cultural redefinition and political advancement NAGPRA, are helping to foster relationships of mutual trust that produce realistic compromises appropriate to(Coombe 1997:74­75). The same cannot be said for systems that dispense information on a strict need-to- individual cases (Nason 1997). Similarly pragmatic ethical protocols are being formulated by anthropologistsknow basis. Lurking in the background is a curious reluctance to and ethnomusicologists (see, e.g., Seeger 1996). If clearly communicated and enforced by professional so-come to grips with the pragmatics of multicultural democracy. It is one thing to insist that the deeply felt cieties, these codes are likely to prove more effective than radically expanded legal regimes for the protectionviews of a particular minority be taken seriously, quite another to propose workable procedures by which these of intangible cultural property, which will provide guaranteed employment for bureaucrats while doing little tocultural differences (which of course must be multiplied by the number of ethnic groups and subcultures shield native peoples from the depredations of mass society.that a given nation encompasses) can be reconciled with majoritarian government and a commitment to equal Perhaps the most promising approach is advanced by scholars such as Karen J. Warren (1989) and Donaldtreatment before the law. Every legitimate demand for special consideration, including the claim that native Tuzin (1995), who argue that frameworks based on joint stewardship are preferable to models based on rightspeoples deserve regimes of intellectual property unique to them, must be weighed against the injurious effect and rules. Joint stewardship implies a willingness to compromise, which is essential for hammering outthat special rights have on prevailing notions of fairness. The philosopher Charles Taylor, who along with workable agreements between parties who may hold incompatible attitudes toward the proper use of informa-such legal thinkers as Ronald Dworkin (1986) and Will Kymlicka (1989) has done some of the heavy lifting tion. The historian Doug Munro (1994:236) notes that the intercultural encounter is a shared experience thatshirked by anthropologists, asserts that if one genuinely takes the claims of minorities seriously, they must be belongs solely to neither party. ``In short,'' he adds, ``the terms `insider' and `outsider', far from representing dis-assessed with the same thoughtful deliberation that we insist upon in legal proposals coming from the cultural crete categories, are convoluted and often permeable.'' A basis for joint stewardship is admittedly harder tomainstream. Taylor rejects the simple-minded relativism that says, in effect, ``If the So-and-So demand it, we find in the predatory activities of corporations that seek to appropriate indigenous knowledge for commercialmust give it to them because their cultural values are as valid as our own.'' For Taylor (1994:70), this demon- purposes. Even here, however, situational pragmatism may prove more effective than a radical expansion of in-strates ``breathtaking condescension.'' He continues: tellectual property laws to encompass every aspect of No one can really mean it as a genuine act of re- native cultures. Widespread public sympathy gives naspect. It is more in the nature of a pretend act of re- tive peoples considerable influence in the court of world spect given on the insistence of its supposed benefi- opinion, and this can be used to pressure corporations ciary. Objectively, such an act involves contempt into complying with basic ethical standards. Creative for the latter's intelligence. To be an object of such licensing partnerships between native communities an act of respect demeans. The proponents of neo- and corporate interests offer another path to fair comNietzschean theories [expressed in the work of Fou- pensation and a modicum of indigenous control (see cault and Derrida] hope to escape this whole nexus Cleveland and Murray 1997:488). Like most realist of hypocrisy by turning the entire issue into one of strategies, these options lack the rhetorical appeal of power and counterpower. Then the question is no ethno-nationalist denunciation or the hyperrationalist allure of novel legal schemes, but they are far more 25. A notable exception is the Bellagio Declaration (Boyle 1996: likely to produce the desired results. 195), which advocates ``an increased recognition and protection of In the final pages of The Protestant Ethic and the the public domain'' in tandem with the creation of regimes of speSpirit of Capitalism, Max Weber (1930:181) speakscial rights for indigenous peoples. For critiques of the concept of movingly of modernity's ``iron cage,'' an ascetic ratio-the public domain and the notion of common human heritage, see Pask (1993) and Coombe (1996). nalism driven by the overwhelming power of material 206 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 goods. Weber's iron cage has steadily expanded to in- their knowledge as private property, and it is understandable that their ethnographers should be sympa-clude ideas and images, which have become tokens in economic exchanges facilitated by the new information thetic to their attempts to empower themselves. This process is reinforced when indigenous people see theirtechnologies. To resist the expansion of these processes into indigenous cultures, legal experts and indigenous knowledge of plants and medicines converted into private property by outsiders and corporations throughadvocates have come forward with proposals to sequester some forms of knowledge and to protect everything patenting. Privacy laws in Western democracies establish a dis-else with dramatically expanded intellectual property laws. Unfortunately, the advent of the Age of the Simu- tinction, variously drawn, between public and private spheres of activity, and patents and copyright providelacrum has rendered the first strategy futile, although it may provide a false and temporary sense of security. analogous protection for private ideas. When we are dealing with artefacts and the hidden meanings ofThe second represents a total surrender to the commodifying logic of advanced capitalism. Now it may be time paintings and rituals it may be feasible to work out a compromise between those seeking enlightenment andto temper demands for comprehensive copyrighting of native cultures with earnest reflection on the future of those who wish to protect the privacy of their knowledge. Compromises are harder to reach with referencethe imperiled intellectual and artistic commons called the public domain, whose survival is of vital signifi- to social activities that traditionally have been perceived as part of culture. Cross-cousin marriage can nocance to us all. more be effectively patented than syllogistic logic. A real conflict arises when a material object has different meanings for different actors. One example is recently unearthed bones of individuals who lived long ago. Ar-Comments chaeologists in Australia see these as providing information about the type of DNA prevalent during past millennia, whereas Aborigines tend to see them as thej. a. barnes Sociology Program, Research School of Social bones of ancestors which should be reburied. The difficulties currently faced by social scientists ofSciences, Australian National University, Canberra, A.C.T. 0200, Australia. 7 x 97 all kinds in our quest for enlightenment arise from the shift in the balance of power that has occurred during the past hundred years or so. Not only so-called indige-With limited space I can comment on only a few of the many points mentioned by Brown in his wide-ranging nous people but all segments of society (with the possible exception of children) are nowadays in muchand very perceptive paper. He raises issues likely to become increasingly critical for anyone seeking greater stronger positions to obstruct or influence the gathering of information about them and its subsequent dissemi-knowledge and/or wider justice. Both goals are estimable, but unfortunately the paths leading to them often nation. Though this makes the task of social inquiry more difficult, we should not regret it; reduction of ine-diverge. Roughly speaking, there are three overlapping ways of perceiving knowledge: as a source of enlighten- qualities in the distribution of power is just as essential for maintaining liberal democracy as is a free flow of in-ment, as a source of power, and as a kind of private property (Barnes 1980:64­66; 1990:209­11). Knowledge as formation. Brown's paper reminds us that in our postcolonial world the inequalities we should target are noenlightenment enhances our understanding of the world; the more people possess it the better, and there longer those between indigenous peoples and colonialist ethnographers but those between private citizensis no zero-sum game. Brown stresses that a flow of information is essential to ``a liberal democracy,'' a type and powerful corporations, whether secular or religious. We can put our ethical house in order for the presentof polity he implicitly endorses. As power, knowledge helps us to alter the world; actors compete rather than and future, but what should we do with knowledge gained in the past under conditions we now reject?share, and the game approximates to zero-sum. Possession of knowledge as private property may be a value in Brown mentions the quarantining of the records of Nazi medical experiments. Perhaps in the short term thisitself; secrets can be hoarded unused but enjoyed and shared only very selectively. Anthropology, like other may be the right way to handle these records; nevertheless, we don't feel that we should, for instance, stop vac-social sciences, is premised on knowledge as enlightenment, although administrations have intermittently cinating children against smallpox because Jenner didn't get clearance from an ethics committee before doing histried to use ethnographic knowledge as a source of power. Some societies, notably those of Australian Abo- experiment. There seems no reason for adopting an ostrich-like stance of refusing to see and use informationrigines, elaborate the notion of knowledge as private property; it is local Aborigines who have organized seg- that is already in the public domain. In any case, as Brown points out, for every overconscientious ostrichregated museums at Yuendumu in Central Australia, one for men and one for women. But irrespective of cul- there are many more actors who have no intention of burying their heads in the sands of pseudo-ignorance.tural emphases indigenous peoples everywhere are typically materially poor and politically powerless. Possess- Material objects collected in the past call for different treatment. Much that is now stored in museums woulding meagre resources, they tend not surprisingly to view brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 207 have perished long ago if it had not been taken into et al. 1994). The Zuni also offer evidence that not only museum curators but indigenous peoples can be veryalien custody. Many indigenous communities are, however, now well able to preserve their own heritage and practical in their approach to intellectual property in a globalizing world.thus have good grounds for reclaiming their former possessions. I agree emphatically with Brown's statement that resolution will require reflection on the part of those holding different positions on their ``global implications'' in order to achieve suitable compromises. Rather than fo-david a. cleveland Department of Anthropology, University of cusing on methods, we might better first try reaching a consensus on goals. To the extent that conservation ofCalifornia, Santa Barbara, Calif. 93106-3210, U.S.A. (clevelan@alishaw.ucsb.edu). 12 xi 97 cultural diversity is an agreed-upon social goal, we need to explore how existing and new ways of managing intellectual property can best serve this goal.Brown's review of current approaches to ``rights'' in ``culture'' is an insightful and stimulating critique. He skillfully points out the confusion of values and facts that characterizes so much of the debate over rights to rosemary j. coombe Faculty of Law, University of Toronto, Toronto, Ont.,intellectual property, especially among advocates of indigenous rights. A narrow struggle over intellectual Canada M5S 2C5. 27 x 97 property diverts public discussion about mutual respect and the fragility of indigenous cultures in a global soci- ``Can Culture Be Copyrighted?'' addresses several issues of contemporary political significance to cultural an-ety, and anthropologists should face up to the probable effects on the public domain of greatly expanded intel- thropologists and points to many of the ethical dilemmas that attend the movement towards an intellectuallectual property protection of cultures. I differ with him, however, on several points. property paradigm for promoting cultural self-determination through control over cultural patrimony and theHe accepts the ``political ideals of liberal democracy'' as a standard for dealing with secrecy. Yet many indige- protection of local knowledges. The author's case, however, may be as overstated as the rhetorical strategies tonous groups, such as the Hopi he cites, have a wide range of views on the recognition and treatment of which he is responding. As a lawyer and an anthropologist I think that the debates around intellectual prop-rights in intellectual property (Cleveland and Murray 1997). ``Ethical realism'' is advocated as a ``common- erty are neither sufficiently careful in their articulation of the law nor ethnographically sensitive to the con-sense'' approach to the ethics of intellectual property, but it is only ``realistic'' and ``commonsense'' if one texts in which intellectual property assertions arise as rhetorical claims.agrees with the liberal democratic values on which it is based. My point is that there is a ``realistic'' or ``com- Let me begin with the law. In his title and introductory paragraph, Brown conflates intellectual propertymonsense'' approach only from within particular worldviews. What, for example, is the basis for Brown's with copyright, when in fact many of the assertions made by indigenous peoples have been made as inter-statement that he doesn't know how one could possibly endorse a practice as ``appalling'' as the ``Smoki'' Snake ventions in the fields of patents and trademarks. None of these domains of intellectual property provides abso-Dance yet also condemn those who seek to limit all outsider use of insider religious knowledge? Where one lute rights of exclusion; all are premised on a social bargain that grants specific rights and imposes specific re-draws the line is a matter of values, not of discovering some absolute standard. Any agreement must therefore sponsibilities on holders who exercise these rights in the public sphere. It is true, as Brown recognizes, thatbe based on open-minded negotiation. Brown suggests that it is ironic that those who seek rights of proprietary exclusivity have been expanded over the course of this century at the expense of broaderto protect local cultures with ``expanded intellectual property rights laws'' typically denounce capitalism principles of public policy and that the public domain is increasingly endangered by the overreaching of industrywhile encouraging the commoditization of ethical and political discourse. However, the motives and methods interests. Ironically, as rights to real property have become more and more attenuated to accommodate socialof local groups and their advocates are not homogeneous. Some groups are using industrial-world intellec- needs, rights to intellectual properties have become more absolute. It is precisely in such contexts that prop-tual property rights laws and asking for their expansion because this seems the best way to protect their culture erty claims become compelling as ideological vehicles with which to assert other interests and voice otherfrom outsiders using these same laws. In the case of crop genetic resources, advocates of local farmers' rights concerns. We should, however, bear in mind the political positionings of those who articulate social needs ininitially pushed for free access to all resources, but strong opposition by industrial nations led to a switch the idiom of rights and the imperative of making concerns known in authoritative discursive forms. Prop-to advocating intellectual property protection for farmers' crop genetic resources (Fowler 1994). Other groups erty, though, is more dynamic than its ideological deployment might suggest; it is constituted of flexibledemand that their own intellectual property rights regimes be respected by outsiders, as do the Zuni (Soleri nexi of multiple and negotiable relationships between 208 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 persons and things that continually shift to accommo- with self-development, self-determination, and the promotion of dialogue and dialogic conditions must be cen-date historical recognitions of prior inequities and current social needs. tral to issues of cultural representation. To the extent that anthropological records have been influential inI am uncomfortable, also, with any vision of democracy which poses complete freedom of speech and full characterizing and authoritatively representing the cultures of others in some jurisdictions, questions aboutaccess to all cultural forms as the only response to corporate possession of culture, broadly defined. Absolute the conditions under which such records were compiled and authored seem entirely apposite. To the extent thatrights of private property and absolute rights of access to the public domain entertain only extreme points of anthropologists were complicit in giving cultural identity its contemporary juridical force and providing thea Eurocentric spectrum of possibility that needs to be challenged by the cultural mores of others. Peoples have means by which authorities fixed and defined such identities, it is unfortunate but not surprising that de-other relationships to cultural forms--trust, secrecy, guardianship, stewardship, initiation, sacralization-- scendents of these anthropological informants have to claim these records as their property in order to preventand obligations to relatives, ancestors, spirits, and future generations which make models of access and own- their continuing use to define their cultures. In this context, it is somewhat disingenuous to claim that, asership appear extremely impoverished. Such knowledge is not adequately understood as information, nor may ethnography moves in a confessional direction that situates the author more squarely in the text, ``the Otherits circulation be properly understood as speech. Indeed, Western notions of property are themselves is claiming ownership of the textual simulacrum.'' This is to conflate two distinct historical periods and atti-not nearly as narrow as this dichotomy between exclusivity of possession and an unrestricted public com- tudes towards ethnographic authority and to discount the ways in which ethnographic fictions have histori-mons would suggest. Western juridical traditions recognize relations of trust (express and constructive), cally figured as truths in regimes of power and knowledge. Who determines where fiction resides and in whatfiduciary obligation, implicit license, breach of confidence, stewardship, and local observances of negotiated circumstances? Clearly, if we are to encourage democratic dialogue, we must open these questions up to ancustoms and ethics. Brown asserts that secrecy and strict control of knowledge contradict the political ide- ``urgently needed public discussion about mutual respect and the fragility of native cultures in mass societ-als of liberal democracy, but trade secrets, corporate confidentiality arrangements, and the fiduciary obliga- ies.'' To grant native peoples full voice in these discussions, however, may well involve a preliminarytions of employees (not to mention ties of kinship obligation) have long been important means of maintaining recognition of proprietary claims--not as exclusivity of possession but as bundles of multiple rights and rela-the value of intangibles in industries and family firms in capitalist democracies. Certainly some holders of tionships still to be delineated in contested and contingent dialogues that may well reshape the concept ofvaluable knowledge and cultural forms have had greater resources at their disposal than others to preclude the property as we think we know it. dilutions and devaluations occasioned when these valuables are transformed into mere information freely available in the public domain. By using the idiom of philippe descola Ecole des Hautes Etudes en Sciences Sociales, Paris,property, then, many indigenous peoples may simply be taking the initial and necessary step of insisting upon a France. 23 x 97 leveling of the playing field before working out the details of particular contractual arrangements. Contracts Brown must be commended for his fair and subtle treatment of a difficult topic usually fraught with controver-based upon duress, unconscionability, coercion, and grossly unequal bargaining power are not enforced in sial or shortsighted statements. I share most of his views, especially his strong commitment to the conceptmost democracies, and our legal regimes are constantly forced to deal with demands for restitution and com- of the public domain, and would not have thought it necessary to add a comment had he not treated toopensation in such instances. The trivialization of symbols, the disparagement of peoples, and misrepresenta- lightly perhaps what I perceive to be one of the most serious consequences of what he calls ``ethical absolut-tions in the public sphere are also injuries that legal systems both recognize and redress in fields as diverse ism,'' namely, the covert institutionalization of cultural apartheid as the postmodern form of racial apart-as tort, unfair competition, and trademark; First Amendment concerns are indeed raised and interests in heid. Most claims advocating indigenous intellectual property rights studiously avoid formally defining thefreedom of expression balanced, but speech rights have never been recognized as absolutely trumping claims status of the populations to which special-right regimes should be granted. This is perhaps because the debatebased upon injuries effected by expressive activities. The emphasis upon freedom of expression and its role has been mainly restricted up to now to native peoples of the Americas and Australia, that is, to cultural andwithin a democracy in this critique must begin with some assumptions about why we value this freedom linguistic autochthonous minorities that are clearly identifiable within nations settled by Europeans. In theand to what ends. Although there is a rich vein of philosophy and jurisprudence to be mined here, concerns course of their struggles for land, dignity, and the recog- brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 209 nition of their cultural uniqueness, these minorities populations through the implementation of specific legal frameworks but by a vigorous defense of whathave often obtained special or derogatory legal statutes (concerning land tenure, civic duties, or personal rights) Brown calls ``ethical realism.'' which contribute to setting them apart, socially and spatially, from ordinary citizens and render them more conspicuous as distinct subsets of the national commu- l. r. hiatt 79 Addison Way, London NW11 6AR, U.K. 6 x 97nities. But such visibility is not the norm everywhere in the world, and advocates of ``differentialism'' should perhaps pay more attention to the fact that cultural di- Suppose an ethnic nation wishes to prevent outsiders from (a) making money from its culture that could beversity is not only an internal phenomenon typical of great melting-pot nations but also a feature of the whole made instead by its own members and (b) making any statement about the culture that the ethnic nation findswide world. Now, if there is a lesson that we have learned from anthropology, it is the impossibility of offensive. Anthropological associations might at a certain point be expected to lobby against such protection-conceiving cultures as bounded territorial wholes defined by sets of substantive attributes. Who will decide, ism, since (a) their members' jobs are threatened and (b) they cherish critical inquiry and free speech. The indi-then, and how, that a specific social grouping does or does not qualify as a genuine native minority, ethnic cations at the moment, judging from Brown's exemplary essay, are that anthropologists are ready to aban-nation, folkloric community, or whatever you choose to name the culturally unique potential beneficiaries of a don both profession and libertarian principle in the perceived interests of those whose cultures form theirspecial regime of collective intellectual property rights? Are we to consider the Basques (who are among the eth- subject matter. Support of the weak against the strong is a noble tra-nic samples of the Human Relations Area Files) as likely candidates? Or the Welsh, or the Ossetians, or the dition, long entrenched in the ethos of anthropology, and altruism is a virtue not to be mocked. Brown, as IKabyles? And if not, for what reasons? Are they not minorities within nations, with their own distinctive cul- read him, has no quarrel with either. His argument, rather, is that legal and bureaucratic control of culturaltures and languages and a long history of difficult relations with hegemonic states? Are they not as much property is likely to benefit the strong more than the weak, for example, entertainment corporations moreentitled as the Apache tribes to demand control over all images, texts, ceremonies, music, songs, stories, sym- than folk musicians. It would certainly benefit lawyers, bureaucrats, and political elites more than rank-and-filebols, customs, and ideas relating to them? And if the possibility for these types of cultural minorities to gain culture-bearers in nations and ethnic nations alike. Special pleading has an inherent tendency to backfire.exclusive control over their ``cultural property'' is brushed aside as fanciful or ludicrous, is it not because The very values of the open society that have facilitated the exposure of iniquities perpetrated against indige-an implicit distinction is made between, say, the Basques and the Kabyles, on the one hand, and the nous minorities must surely be compromised if the latter are now encouraged to reconstitute themselves asApache and the Pintupi, on the other, regarding their very essence and claims to authenticity? If this is the closed societies. How can we avoid a charge of cynicism if we insist on freedom of information in the interestscase, it is quite worrying. Europeans have very painful memories (and nightmarish contemporary examples) of of an ethnic nation whose own bureaucrats practice censorship? How can we in good conscience acquiesceideologies that claim ethnic purity as the basis for selfclosure and self-fulfillment. Although the fiction of pu- in a demand that nothing offensive be said about the cultural beliefs and practices of an indigenous minorityrity was established mainly according to supposedly racial criteria, cultural dimensions were also taken into while resisting similar demands from chauvinist and religious interests among the settler majority?account, especially in the German vo¨lkisch tradition, to underscore the uniqueness of communities and the ne- Sooner or later the right to censor statements about ethnic nations made by outsiders would be assertedcessity of their segregation (Conte and Essner 1995). Even now, far-right movements such as the Front Na- against insiders as well. Whatever solidarist illusions may be cultivated for ideological purposes, nations en-tional in France disguise their acute xenophobia under claims that cultures should not be mixed for fear of los- compass competing social forces. Ethnic nations are no exception. And were a metropolitan government to au-ing the specific identities that they convey. To be perfectly clear, I do not mean that advocating collective in- thorise an agency within an ethnic nation to define its culture and decide what might and might not be saidtellectual property rights over cultural patrimony for ethnic minorities is akin to racial segregation; rather, about it, in practice the external power would be favouring certain internal sectional interests and tendencieshistory has taught us that giving special status to specific peoples is fraught with dangers, as it tends to per- at the expense of others. By conferring upon an ethnic nation the right to suppress ideas and productionspetuate the idea of irreconcilable substantive differences between fellow-humans. The collective debt that deemed to be offensive to its subjects, it would in fact be equipping dominant factions with a legal mechanismEuro-Americans have incurred while submitting native populations to different forms of genocide and ethno- for discouraging dissidence and silencing rivals. With Brown, I strongly support measures designed tocide will only be dispelled not by setting apart these 210 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 protect creativity in indigenous communities against tions difficult to handle for any anthropologist engaged in research on indigenous people. Even so, he seems tocommercial exploitation and to ensure a fair return to native artists whose productions enter the marketplace. enter the discussion with the prime aim of provoking advocates of indigenous people's rights, whom he de-Such objectives can be achieved without a totalistic copyrighting of culture. Anthropologists who allow scribes as ``romantic social critics.'' Instead of slogans and ``polemical romanticism'' he calls for a return to atheir compassion for the underprivileged to take them down that path are helping to lay the foundations of to- ``realist perspective'' considering these questions in all their ``ambiguity and nuance.'' But by departing from atalitarian ministates. simplistic polarisation of positions (realism vs. romanticism, analysis vs. slogans) he does not take us far in that direction.jean jackson Anthropology Program, MIT, Cambridge, Mass. Reading Brown's article, I cannot help wondering why a person called upon to defend the sacred principles02139, U.S.A. 27 x 97 of liberal democracy chooses to make Native Americans his target. Brown has no problem with the state'sBrown has written a thoughtful, well-researched essay on a very controversial topic. The basic issue he ex- right to withhold ``sensitive'' information on ``matters of national security'' while getting terribly worried overplores is how best to protect indigenous peoples and culture in a world increasingly characterized by digital the Hopi and Apache peoples' resentment about sharing information relating their religion. One would assumereproduction, commercial interests developing evernew forms of prospecting, and ever-increasing appropri- that a civil rights activist would have it the other way around. I also find it striking that while Brown holdsation of the exotic because it is authentic, curative, natural, etc. The problem is a very real one (see, e.g., the democracy sacred, he fails to extend similar principles of respect and tolerance to others. When Native Ameri-contributors to Greaves 1994). We are right to be concerned about increasing corporate domination of cans oppose New Age groups' misuse of their sacred rituals, Brown remains silent and without compassion. Heknowledge--one of several ironies pointed out by Brown, given that some of the push for commodifica- argues instead that the most interesting thing about this is that the native religious leaders oppose such ap-tion and copyright comes from corporations seeking increased profits by having exclusive rights to produce propriation on the ground of the inherent power of these rituals and not because the New Age rituals are ``bo-medicines, cell lines, and the like obtained from indigenous peoples. However, commodifying and copyright- gus.'' Another problem with Brown's approach relates to his assertion that indigenous people's claim for cul-ing culture as opposed to the products of a culture (such as varieties of corn) is full of hazards, regardless of how tural property rights is an opening bid in political horsetrading. This again is an oversimplification, leaving outappealing the restriction of access to it may appear in the face of egregious cases of disrespect and exploita- existential dimensions having to do with respect, recognition, and identity. This also reflects Brown's argu-tion. After reading this article we have a far better under- ment that as most native peoples face threats to their economic and political sovereignty, they have littlestanding of the many dilemmas involved that have helped turn this issue into a lightning rod. Brown's dis- time to ``freť' over issues of cultural properties (suggesting that such concerns are a luxury that only better-cussion deftly reveals why we--whatever our position--find this issue so threatening. Clearly, many off indigenous people in the ``Wesť' can afford). That indigenous nations even face genocide does not makescholars and activists will disagree with Brown's position, and this is as it should be, for several deeply held them less concerned with cultural matters. In fact, because having a culture of one's own is crucial to con-values are in conflict. Knowing why and how seriously irreconcilable some of these values are helps to keep temporary claims of self-determination, tremendous energies and emotions are invested in things like pro-knee-jerk responses to a minimum and to facilitate the search for more workable solutions. tection of language or preservation of traditional religious practices and symbols.A quibble: I find Alan Wolfe's critique, cited by Brown, seriously flawed and think that he could have When most anthropologists, myself included, argue against or problematize earlier notions of culture as amade his argument without citing this particular example of neoliberalist thought. coherent, bounded, and distinct ``property'' of a people and instead talk about culture in terms of construction and process (as culture-in-the-making), does this make us enemies of those ``unenlightened natives'' who con-b. g. karlsson Seminar for Development Studies, Uppsala tinue to reify culture and claim a culture of their own? Brown thinks so, and casts the ``cosmopolitan'' scholarUniversity, P.O. Box 514, 751 20 Uppsala, Sweden. 20 x 97 against the ``indigenous'' activist. Yes, there are problems in keeping culture an analytic concept when culture has turned into a major site of conflict and popularBringing culture into the domain of rights, ownership, and legislation is indeed, as Brown suggests, deeply mobilisation. Rosemary Coombe, whose work Brown makes use of, argues that such antiessentialist claimsproblematic. Brown also raises several important ques- brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 211 that culture is constructed and mobile always beg ques- teur) and the protracted discussions associated with Article 8.j of the Convention on Biological Diversity. Hetions of perspective--for whom and in what circumstances is it so? And she asks, ``How does this claim also fails to consider the complex critiques put forth in numerous indigenous documents and summarized insound in the struggles of those for whom `culture' may be the last legitimate ground for political autonomy and reports of the Coordinador de Organizaciones de los Pueblos Indígenas de la Cuenca Amazona Regionalself-determination?'' (Coombe 1997:93). Brown avoids these critical matters. He further too easily reduces the Meeting on Intellectual Property Rights and Biodiversity, the UNEP Consultations on Protection and Con-indigenous stance to one of cultural ``essentialism.'' I think that Arif Dirlik is right in arguing that the indige- servation of Indigenous Knowledge, the Suva Declaration, the Mataatua Declaration on Cultural andnous voices in fact are quite open to change, and what they insist on is not ``cultural purity'' as such ``but the Intellectual Property Rights of Indigenous Peoples (mentioned briefly in a footnote), the Indigenous Peo-preservation of a particular historical trajectory of their own'' (1996:18). It then becomes crucial to ask why in- ples' Biodiversity Network, and the Charter of the Indigenous-Tribal Peoples of Tropical Forests--to name adigenous peoples increasingly feel obliged to claim control over what they see as their culture. What is the so- few. These documents show that indigenous ``activists'' are well aware of the dangers of intellectual propertycial and historical context for such assertions? In India the debate over indigenous cultural property rights. Indigenous groups have made it quite clear that the concept of ``property,'' and especially individualrights is largely absent. During my work among the Rabhas or Kochas, an indigenous people in India, I have property, is alien and antithetical to their collective values. They have repeatedly explained how many (but notnever been questioned over rights to my field notes, photographs, publications, etc. And I do not know how all) songs, drawings, ceremonies, plants, animals, and designs are inalienable and, therefore, can never beI would respond to possible later requests perhaps based on the argument that the material was obtained under property. And they point out that individuals who use or display them are the ``holders,'' ``trustees,'' or ``stew-coercive circumstances. As a sahib I have indeed been on top of things, and if a person had nothing else at hand ards'' for communities, lineages, ancestors, gender groups, future generations, or even spirits. Furthermore,he or she would certainly spare time to try to respond to my questions. Power is an issue here, but to describe indigenous peoples have been explicit in showing that ``intellectuaĺ' aspects of culture cannot be separatedfieldwork as an exploitative encounter between oppressor and oppressed is indeed, as Brown suggests, to take from ``physical,'' ``natural,'' or ``spirituaĺ' elements because culture is an extension of nature (and vice versa).things too far. Brown is also right in acknowledging the agency and strategies of the ``objects'' of anthropologi- Thus ``intellectual property'' is doubly inappropriate in that it excludes plants, animals, and knowledge aboutcal inquiry, something which Roger Keesing has brought attention to in his work on the Kwaio people. I them (seeds, soils, minerals, and management practices, etc.)--all of which are inextricable elements of a soci-am looking forward to the day when Rabhas themselves rather than any government department or forest au- ety's ``intellect.'' Brown, in contrast, reduces intellectual propertythority are entitled to issue research permits and control access to their forest villages. rights to a question of copyright protection over material expressions of culture. Most indigenous groups are more worried about patents than copyrights. This is because patents are much more powerful tools of monop-darrell addison posey Centre for the Environment, Ethics, and Society, oly and globalization. Even so, some very innovative proposals have been put forth for the development ofMansfield College, University of Oxford, Oxford, U.K. 12 xi 97 community intellectual property rights, applying know-how and trade secrecy for the protection of traditional knowledge and genetic resources, and adaptingBrown argues that ``the debate over intangible cultural property as it has been conducted by indigenous activ- copyright concepts to community-controlled data. These are recognized by indigenous groups themselvesists has tended toward a polemical romanticism that produces memorable bumper-sticker slogans but little as dangerous experiments but are anything but ``extremely nai¨ve'' proposals as Brown claims.in the way of sober reflection on the difficult balancing act required to formulate policies that provide reason- Brown also states that ``although advocates of expanded intellectual property laws typically denounceable protection for minority populations while maintaining the flow of information essential to liberal de- capitalist commmodification, they implicitly encourage the translation of ethical and political discoursemocracy.'' This is not quite the case. Unfortunately, Brown has chosen examples to give into the language of commodities.'' This may be true in some cases, but the majority of those who discuss intel-the impression that indigenous groups are making demands that will ultimately restrict the liberties and lectual property rights tend to employ the political discourse of human rights: rights to land, territory, and re-freedom of others. He ignores the sophisticated debates on intellectual, cultural, and scientific property in the sources, rights to full disclosure and prior informed consent, rights to cultural integrity and customary prac-United Nations Working Group on Indigenous Populations (although he cites a study by the Special Rappor- tices, and rights to equitable benefit-sharing and control 212 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 over access to ``traditional resources.'' It may be true erty rights. The debate is, I feel, somewhat more positive than Brown has portrayed it. Copyright will notthat in the rarefied discourse of ``cosmopolitan scholars'' (Brown's term, not mine) intellectual property gain additional respect for indigenous people, but its discussion has already brought serious attention torights have been inadequately analyzed, but that is in part because anthropology has not kept up with the rap- their claims. It is, however, useful to take up the different forms of cultural information separately; the follow-idly advancing international debates of indigenous peoples themselves. And, furthermore, anthropologists ing comments relate specifically to written material. Access to information is a core issue in most socie-have restricted themselves to the theoretical discourses in their favorite academic journals. The intellectual ac- ties, however differently phrased and differently constructed. Intellectual property rights (such as copyright,tion is in fact in places like the World Trade Organization (discussions on sui generis systems of intellectual patent, trademark law) are, as Brown notes, economic in scope. Copyright ensures that individual creatorsproperty rights protection), the FAO (expansion or reconceptualization of farmers' rights), the CBD (interses- have the incentive to allow copies to be made available to the public. Access to information is thus never pre-sional process to implement Article 8.j), and ECOSOC (debates on the Draft Declaration of Rights of Indige- cisely free. Costs are involved in locating material and seeing it. Such costs are a control factor, though librar-nous Peoples)--not to mention the myriad conferences and workshops that indigenous peoples themselves or- ies and archives--paid for by taxes, organizations, and philanthropy--are sources available for reading freely.ganize to discuss copyrights, patents, community rights, genetically modified organisms, biosafety, par- Market or political forces constrain the free flow of information.ticipatory democracy, etc. Brown asks: ``What [will] history or anthropology be- New technologies--printing presses, cameras, photocopying machines, computers, etc.--continue to ex-come when scholars are prevented by law from writing accounts specific enough to evoke the religious or polit- pand the availability of materials. These are not free either, but they make access easier and bring it closer toical practices of protected native populations?'' One answer could be: disciplines that finally have to negotiate home. They also raise new issues for copyright, control, and economic benefit, and these issues are argued andthe terms of their intellectual pursuits with those who are affected by the results of their studies--and, as a re- settled, usually in the courts and most often by corporate giants. Protection of individual (or corporate) rightssult, begin to develop questions and methodologies that address the political problems that indigenous peoples in creation has been under discussion since the 15th century (currently, ``creations'' such as databases are be-still face. It would then be impossible for anthropology to ignore the intellectual contributions of indigenous ing examined); it is a fluctuating, ongoing dialogue, changing as society and technology change.scholars, faith-keepers, and political leaders that may be well ahead of the debates academics think they are pio- Copyright and the use of materials through libraries and archives exist in a socioeconomic context. An ex-neering. Despite what may seem harsh comments, I am basi- amination of these same issues in, say, France or Egypt would show differences in such concepts as authors'cally in sympathy with Brown. He is right to warn us of the serious threats from intellectual property rights. creative rights and public domain. The burgeoning field of electronic communication (leaving aside any ques-He is also justified in pointing out the urgent need for sophisticated analysis of ``common property'' concepts tions about the content or context of that information) illustrates the competing forces of corporate interests,in globalization debates. I also heartily endorse one of his principal conclusions: that ``pragmatic ethical pro- rights to privacy and to information, individual economic claims, concerns of community or religioustocols'' (codes of ethics and standards of practice) for science and industry are far more desirable than radi- groups, and questions about preservation of information for the long term. Discussions are ongoing over thecally expanded intellectual property rights. The International Society for Ethnobiology has taken nearly a de- boundary between what is public and what private information, between ``free'' and ``costly'' access, betweencade to develop a draft Code of Conduct that will be debated during its next world congress, to be hosted by secrecy and openness, between what may inform and what may harm.the Maori Congress of Aotearoa/New Zealand. A Maori lawyer co-chairs the Ethics Committee, and the ethno- There is no reason that native groups should not argue these issues in the same courts and in the samebiologists will be in the minority at the Congress for the discussion. That figures to advance understanding, re- manner as all the other parties to this dialogue. If, as Brown notes, secrecy is ``of course'' warranted for na-search, and respect for rights inways that laws never will. tional security, there seems no underlying reason it should not also be warranted for any other culturally determined issues of sensitivity, as it is for privacy. By thewillow roberts powers Department of Anthropology, University of New same token, there is no reason that the legal solutions will be any more satisfying, any less ambiguous. TheMexico, Albuquerque, N.M. 87131, U.S.A. (wrpowers@trail.com). 21 x 97 law is a blunt, two-edged, and expensive tool for deciding the issues. Brown, noting the control that copyright exerts overBrown's essay is a cool-headed discussion of the broad array of issues in the debate regarding intellectual prop- access and hoping that it is not expanded by new intel- brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 213 lectual property rights laws, suggests a joint steward- tance in any discussion of property--particularly as it relates to indigenous peoples--how one constructs a setship of cultural information. His point is that information should be free. This is a cultural ideal shared by the of appropriate analogies. In addition to casting issues of property in terms of relationships rather than controlnation's archivists and librarians. It is a crucially important ideal which, like community harmony, is much over objects it makes a great difference whether the objects currently in dispute are likened to forms of prop-honored in the breach. With regard to archival materials, there are the begin- erty recognized in an existing legal regime or symbolic of a deeper political history. If, for example, in any suchnings of new approaches. Archivists have started dialogues on the issues of access with neighboring, and discussion one replaces indigenous intellectual property with a form common in the West--music, litera-sometimes distant, American Indian communities. The Special Collections director at the Cline Library, North- ture, design--it might seem, given Brown's criteria, that no system of legal protection could ever succeed:ern Arizona University, has opened discussions with the Hopi Tribe, seeking information and joint solutions. the same criticisms he raises for indigenous property-- that someone will always modify the original or hideJohn Adair's papers have been acquired by the Wheelwright Museum in Santa Fe with an agreement to work it (digitally or otherwise) or that borders are invariably porous--would apply equally to similar Western prop-out an access and use policy with one of the communities in which Adair worked for materials relating to that erty forms. But his article (and my comment) are copyrighted by the Wenner-Gren Foundation, and we bothcommunity. Tribal archives across the United States are grappling with incorporating preservation of written presumably have some confidence in these laws or we would not have signed over the rights. Thus from therecords into tribal budgets and in addition to an oral history background. Native archivists are at work in an- outset it may be well to place a similar degree of confidence in the concept of protection and then sort out itsthropological and other archives. These are models to look at in this dialogue. appropriate forms in each circumstance--or forthrightly criticize the very concept of protectible propertyThe issues relating to written materials as I hear them are specific to each tribe or pueblo, tend to be dif- on deeper philosophical and political grounds. Here the issues affecting indigenous intellectual prop-ferently perceived by native communities than by organizations or individuals, relate often not to closed but erty begin to resolve themselves into two related considerations. The first has to do with sovereignty. Brownto appropriate access, are often concerned more with cultural than with economic points, are broadly con- does not mention this issue, but surely the question of whose laws will apply suffuses the entire topic. If indig-strued to include all ``others'' including other tribes, and do not imply total closure of all information for all enous property rights are seen as a subject matter over which some polity will exercise jurisdiction, then ittime. Non-native participants in this dialogue are equally responsible for raising issues and questions, as may be necessary at the outset to come to grips with the appropriate distribution of powers as between indig-Brown has done, that are of concern for long-term solutions. There are many opinions and many stakeholders. enous and superordinate polities. The issue of intellectual property may, of course, serve as a vehicle throughThe quest is for balance. Appropriate access to and use of information is part of this quest, for which the law which such power to control one's own affairs is itself developed. But before one can get to questions such asis not an appropriate means. the use of common accords or the distribution of powers through applicable laws, greater recognition and regularization of the powers of indigenous peoples need tolawrence rosen Department of Anthropology, Princeton University, be addressed (see Rosen 1997). This, in turn, raises the second question: Is it in-Princeton, N.J. 08544-1011, U.S.A. 10 x 97 tergroup relationships that are at issue here or only the control over property-like objects? If it is the former,Not for the first time in history, the fundamental issues that surround the concept of property--who may exer- then, as Brown himself suggests, we are not bound to all-inclusive deference or hegemonic control as our onlycise power over what, for what purpose, and by what right--coincide with technological development, com- options: It is possible to take issues one at a time having laid the groundwork for negotiated accords such asmercial expansion, and cross-cultural contact. It matters, however, which of several basic concepts of prop- those that inform a number of transnational agreements. Differences of power will not predetermine out-erty we employ. If ownership is conceived not solely as control over an object but as the relationships among comes as long as developing international custom supports an array of accords from which parties maypeople as they concern that object, the forms of proprietorship can be seen as inextricably bound to the politi- choose. And specific issues will benefit from the specific attention they require as well as from the generalcal, the moral, and the emotional. To begin an understanding of changing concepts of property with this context of internationally recognized intergovernmental agreements.relational aspect in view may, of course, have a dramatic effect on the very shape of one's analysis. Indigenous intellectual property thus confronts us with a new form of an old puzzle: To what extent shallBrown's splendidly sensible analysis avoids the unambiguous results that single-minded ideologies so of- the internal rules of another group be accorded deference or constitute the subject of good-faith bargainingten demand. At the same time, it is of crucial impor- 214 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 among sovereign entities? If the model of negotiation knowledge, or material culture. If we were indeed to copyright indigenous cultures, to which Amazonianprevails, each troublesome issue may begin to be seen in terms of differentiated political powers and the scope people should we grant rights to, let us say, the hallucinogenic ayahuasca vine? To which Northwest Coastof government-to-government negotiation. The resultant process may then partake of greater scholarly and people should we grant rights to potlatch rituals? Or, for that matter, to which Andean people should we grantpolitical realism than the extreme positions that Brown so rightly challenges. rights to chicha or maize beer? A culture is ``a flexible set of understandings, dispositions, and behavioral scripts'' shared by a given people. However, cultures are not external entities distinctfernando santos granero Smithsonian Tropical Research Institute, P.O. Box from their bearers. Although cultural forms may be collectively constructed, cultural products are always the2072, Balboa, Panama (santosf@tivoli.si.edu). 14 x 97 output of particular individuals. In fact, among Amerindian peoples an individuaĺs high prestige is very muchBrown's thorough analysis of current attempts to expand the notion of copyright introduces much-needed dependent upon masterful production, whether of a basket, a dugout, a garden, a song, or a mythical narration.sense and sensibility into a debate that frequently seems to be disconnected from the harsh realities of an Cultures are not merely replicated ad infinitum by their bearers but constantly enriched by the latter's creativeincreasingly global world. Approaching the subject from different angles, Brown adds layer after layer of solid ar- acts. Thus, if it were possible to copyright cultures, who would reap the profit from the marketing of specificgument to demonstrate the negative consequences that attempting to copyright the cultural heritage of minor- products, the collectivity or the individual? Although cultures have been (and unfortunately con-ity groups could have for free speech, the exchange of information, and, more generally, the ``status of the tinue to be) treated as fixed, bounded realities, recent studies have recurrently demonstrated that culturespublic domain.'' What is especially commendable is that he opposes this copyrighting while leaving no ``change through time'' and are always in the making. If copyrighting the culture of an indigenous people weredoubt that he firmly condemns the appropriation by large corporations of indigenous cultural products for at all possible, which culture should be copyrighted-- the one at the time of European invasion, the one thatcommercial use. More laudable still, he avoids offering ready-made solutions for a problem that, as he con- emerged after subjugation, decimation, missionization, and resettlement, or the one existing at the time thestantly reminds us, is extremely complex. Here I would like to elaborate upon five very practical copyright is granted? Should abandoned traditional practices, some of which are now regarded with embar-issues that derive from the fluid character of cultures. I consider these to be central to the problem being dis- rassment by contemporary Amerindians, be included, or should only ``sanitizeď' versions of culture be copy-cussed, yet they have only been tangentially touched upon, or implied in passing, by the author. righted? Moreover, although the relationship between indige-As Brown states, cultures ``lack clear spatial and temporal boundaries.'' Even the social groups that embody nous peoples and national societies is asymmetric, cultural flows have not been unidirectional, benefitingthem rarely have clear-cut boundaries. More commonly, there is a gradient of more or less inclusive only the latter. There are numerous Western cultural traits that have been adopted by indigenous peoples notgroups that live in a certain region, have similar histories, and share many cultural traits. For instance, the as a result of external pressures but for their beauty, their usefulness, or their symbolic power. Beads, horses,Aguaruna people of the Upper Mayo River studied by Brown are a somewhat distinct offshoot of the Aguar- and writing are good examples. Are these traits going to be abandoned for the sake of purity, or are they goinguna of the Maran~ on River, who in turn have relationships of alliance and hostility with a number of other to be included in the indigenous copyrights? Whatever may be the answers to the above issues,Jibaro-speaking peoples on both sides of the PeruvianEcuadorian frontier. Whose culture should we copy- they bring to mind one last question: Are not those attempting to copyright culture running the risk of trans-right? That of the Upper Mayo Aguaruna, that of the Aguaruna as a whole, that of the Aguaruna and the forming what are still vigorous cultures into fossilized relics?Huambisa, who are now organized in a common ethnic federation, or that of the Jibaro as a whole? Not only do cultures lack clear boundaries but, as Brown stresses, they ``freely influence, and are influ- carlo severi Laboratoire ďAnthropologie Sociale, 52, rue deenced by, social interactions with other groups.'' Cultures do not exist in a vacuum; they are constantly nur- Cardinal-Lemoine, F-75005 Paris, France. 3 xi 97 tured by contact with other cultures. No people exists that can claim that its culture is a pristine product, un- Brown's paper raises important questions, political as well as ethical, and does so with honesty and clarity. Itcontaminated by foreign elements--least of all Amerindian peoples, who share a high proportion of traits, is evident that the confrontation of the Western and the American Indian points of view in this context gener-whether myths, rituals, kinship systems, scientific brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 215 ates two paradoxes. One originates from the attempt to democratic and liberaĺ' Western conceptions would be unfair for at least two reasons. First, nonreligious per-consider a culture as a collective author in order to protect it. From this perspective, the more one tries to pro- sons exist in Amerindian societies, too, and they should obviously have a right to express their views just liketect culture--which should mean ``to preserve it as it is''--the more one transforms it into a fictive construc- the others. Secondly, Amerindian religious customs should be compared with Western religious traditions;tion very different from reality. The second paradox originates from the attempt to apply criteria of legiti- the comparison between the intention to put some Indian ``ideas'' under the control of an intellectual copy-mate property (and legal conditions of trade)--typically applied to merchandise made to be exchanged in a mar- right and the free use of syllogism ``invented by the Greeks'' is not entirely correct. While a Western scholarket--to religious artifacts, which, by definition, are made for ritual performances and do not belong in the would certainly agree that anyone is free to use a syllogism, I wonder whether any use of Western religious no-market. An illustration of this situation is the notion of ``cul- tions would be considered acceptable by Western religious authorities.tural heritage'' as applied to American Indian societies. At first sight, this notion seems obvious. Everybody is Indeed, it would be hard to deny that we seem to accept ``syncretism'' only when the contact of differentcommitted, at least in Europe, to the preservation of the cultural heritage of a nation. If the Italian or French gov- cultures is realized under the domination of a Western framework. When the Indians of Mexico worship a Vir-ernments have the right to prevent, for instance, a Michelangelo or a Chardin from being commercialized on gin Mary unconventionally there is no question but that this results in a local variety of Christianity, not athe international market, one does not see why the American Indians should not be keen to protect their continuation of Nahuatl cults marginally including certain Christian elements. When this is not the case--asown techniques, religious beliefs, traditional narratives, and works of art. The assimilation of a native culture to in Haiti, where Christianity was really subverted by African traditions--religious authorities do not hesitatea collective author, however, can also have near-absurd consequences. The idea of having not only documents, to respond violently. In order to repress too free a use of Christian images, artifacts, and such Christian religiousdrawings, and artifacts but also traditional ``ideas'' protected by intellectual copyright seems a self-defeating concepts as ``communion'' and ``repentance of sin,'' the Catholic bishop of Port au Prince organized an immensestrategy. How is language or thought itself to be preserved from the risks implied by communication? Since auto da fé --a spectacular burning of ``contaminated images'' of saints in the public square--as recently as inimages are made to be seen and words are made to be exchanged, it is difficult to decide what images or what the early forties (Métraux 1958). In short, when the cultural contact happens under the control of Western reli-words must become someone's exclusive property. However, it is one of the merits of Brown's article to gions, we call it ``syncretism''; when it escapes it, we call it ``blasphemy.'' Religious intolerance, in our tradi-make it clear that there is more to this question than mere propaganda or political naiveté. Few anthropolo- tion as elsewhere, has little use for legal rights. gists would deny that ``complete freedom'' in the field of information and marketing would expose American Indian societies, as in the past, to all kinds of injuries david j. stephenson jr. 3888 W. Grambling Dr., Denver, Colo. 80236-2444,and theft. Distinctions and clear thought are everywhere diffi- U.S.A. 11 xi 97 cult to achieve in political debate. In this respect Brown's paper is useful in that it clearly establishes the This thoughtful, provocative article is a valuable contribution to the ever-widening conversation about the in-premises for a crucial debate. Pursuing this debate, I would like to add two remarks: tellectual property rights of indigenous peoples. Brown graphically supports his healthy skepticism of legal1. The ``implicit assumptions'' emerging from the discussion of the protection of ethnic minorities (at least schemes to control cultural appropriation, or misappropriation, with a wide spectrum of poignant, timely con-in Brown's account) seem reluctant to make any distinction between scholarly examination and analysis of crete examples. The thrust of his article is to force critical reflection in an arena where it is much needed,cultural facts, imitation or theft of cultural items for commercial use, blasphemy, and even sacrilegious cari- because without such critical reflection the notion of intellectual property rights for indigenous peoples willcature of rituals. However, it is one thing to study, with the permission of the local authorities, the meaning of a be abused to the point that it eventually is eviscerated. Brown's clarion call is reminiscent of the arguments ofreligious object and quite another to caricature a ritual. Scholarship and blasphemy are not the same, and this the more moderate and dispassionate commentators during the tumultuous sixties in the United Statesholds true, in my experience of fieldwork with the Kuna, for some Indians as well as for some anthropolo- that the country needed fewer uncritical lovers and unloving critics and more critical lovers. Brown is agists. In this respect, Brown's account seems to me too pessimistic. critical lover. He offers positive insights and constructive suggestions (e.g., ethical realism and frameworks2. On the anthropologisťs side, I see another risk. Opposing religious Amerindian traditions to ``scientific- based on joint stewardship) alongside his thorough cri- 216 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 tique of overzealous advocacy for native intellectual strument for the recognition of rights of a ``culturaĺ' nature is merged with the anthropologists' perpetual fash-property rights. His concerns about how to reconcile Western notions ioning of their relations with those whose cultures they study. The curator's response was not to destroy the pa-of intellectual property with native claims to the right to protect virtually everything that may be deemed part pers or prioritise the rights of the donor but to pose questions about the conduct of relationships. This is aof the broad fabric of ``culture,'' including thoughts, is consistent with my own cautions about the dangers sensibility with (so to speak) a life of its own, a triumph of anthropological theories of culture and of two de-posed by the inherent vagueness and overbreadth of the term ``cultural patrimony'' in the Native American cades of enhanced sensitivity to professional practice. It is interesting that it should be a museum example, forGraves Protection and Repatriation Act (Stephenson 1996) and the arbitrariness and overbreadth of the In- here ``cultural property'' (in tangible items) flourished as an issue long before it became blown up into a ubiq-dian Arts and Crafts Act recently detailed by Gail Sheffield (1997). Brown's call for ethical realism is echoed uitous index of ethical awareness (apropos tangible and intangible items alike). (Busse [1997] notes that in Pa-in my prediction that the most successful strategies for protecting, conserving, and compensating cultural prop- pua New Guinea the change from the language of antiquities to the language of national cultural property, anderty ``are more likely to be those that translate broad, lofty principles into local sui generis initiatives'' (1996: thus cultural heritage, dates from 1965.)1 The intellectual property rights problematic has in ef-118). Brown's observation that zealous protection of intellectual property rights is inconsistent with other fect taken over others, and Brown appraises the consequences of this. It is an important task. Thus propertyhighly valued principles, such as freedom of expression, as reflected in the First Amendment, is encapsulated in discourse replaces, he argues, what should be discussion on the moral implications of subjecting people to un-Sheffielďs comment that ``the right to foreclose another's use of Indian identity will conflict with that indi- wanted scrutiny or sequestering public-domain information. It runs the danger of what he wonderfully callsviduaĺs right to freedom of expression'' and her reflection on David Lange's (1981:147) comment that ``the the moral alchemy of converting multiple interests and questions about fair use and fair expression into narrowgrowth of intellectual property in recent years has been uncontrolled to the point of recklessness'' (1997:141). disputes over commodities or of overlooking the ``complex human motives'' that coalesced at the time whenAt the same time, it is ironically precisely the broadening of traditional intellectual property concepts in re- ethnographic items were obtained or of abandoning the conventions of ``reasonable procedure'' or a common-cent years, brought on by such technological revolutions as the Internet and computer software, that offers sense approach to complex ethical issues in favour of comprehensive claims to ownership. I might add topromise for finding a proper fit between traditional legal rules for protecting intellectual property in the Western these the late-20th-century money effect; bodies such as the British Economic and Social Research Council,tradition and the integrity of the attributes of traditional cultures, however intangible those attributes by analogy with commercial companies, may use the rubric of intellectual property to reify national interestsmay be (Stephenson 1994). Because the concept of intellectual property in Western law is itself undergoing in the nationally funded. While this proprietorship refers in the first place to research with a financial poten-such rapid transformation, it would be premature to dismiss its potential utility for protecting at least the more tial, in the ESRC case it sits side by side with requirements that research-generated information (includingmeasured attributes of native cultures identified in the Bellagio Declaration about which Brown comments fa- primary data from interviews or diaries) be datasetted and thus archived for use by third parties. No mentionvorably. By the same token, Brown's analysis might have ben- is made of intellectual property rights here except as a ``problem'' which may affect the deposition of data. Theefited by a consideration of efforts to develop alternatives to traditional intellectual property, such as Darrell issue is not claims to original ownership but the assertion of national interests against other claims to thePosey's concept of ``traditional resource rights,'' as more appropriate for non-Western traditions (Posey and country's store of information. Brown dryly observes that in the mad scramble forDutfield 1996). On the whole, however, I applaud Brown for thor- control, ethno-nationalists are similarly promoting ideas about cultural protection--the collapse of theoughly exposing important issues that desperately need more critical reflection. 1. And enshrined in the 1970 UNESCO convention on the illicit transfer of ownership of cultural property, part of the postwar anmarilyn strathern thropological effort to put ``culture'' into the international vocabuDepartment of Anthropology, University of lary. But if the formula (cultural property) was relatively new, some of the sentiments concerning the appropriation of people's heritageCambridge, Cambridge CB2 3FR, U.K. 26 x 97 had been long in place: see Winter (1993) on Greenfielďs (1989) The Return of Cultural Treasures. Busse notes that the Ordinance reBrown's opening remarks pinpoint an inflationary di- lating to Papuan Antiquities dates from 1913; the issue then was mension to recent discussions of intellectual property. not claims to original ownership but the assertion of national interests against other claims to the country's ``antiquities.''The idea of intellectual property rights as a potential in- brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 217 idea/expression distinction or the abandonment of time the practical, sentimental, and philosophical ties that bind them to the peoples they study, but, as Brown'shorizons--which, converted into intellectual property rights regulations, would certainly serve the interests of masterful analysis shows, in the case of the more draconian versions of ``cultural copyrighť' such partisanshipcorporations. This is a judicious and cool account. If it leans to- can run afoul of principles of equal or more compelling value, such as public domain, fair usage, and, perhapswards particularly American cultural pragmatics in its concerns for native peoples, Brown's careful weighing is above all, the preservation of cultural knowledge in all its variation.also more generally useful. On the one hand, he advocates compensation mechanisms for the commercial Furthermore, even if one were to accept the validity of radical claims, such as that of the Apache tribal con-use of knowledge/artefacts and clear guidelines for collecting culturally sensitive ethnographic data. On the sortium, who gets to speak for ``the tribe''? Regardless of whether such spokespersons are designated by demo-other hand, he is in despair over some of the broader debate about cultural appropriation, the very kind of cratic elections or by nondemocratic customary procedures, as social actors they are subject to situationalwider contextualisation that anthropologists normally favour. He sees anthropologists abandoning social cri- constraints and temptations that could result in faulty decisions; only a naive observer--a fortiori a poor eth-tique when it comes to ethno-nationalist claims to enduring rights. Yet this politics has its own social reality: nographer--would mistake rhetoric for the complex motives that drive high-stakes culture politics in mat-people who feel that their ancestors were duped do not want their descendants to have been. Brown does appeal ters of copyright and other new arenas. And yet, this said, who should determine whether and to what extentto ``situational pragmatism''; a multicultural democracy implies weighing the benefits of special rights culture should be copyrighted? What solomonic process will sort out and create enlightened, sustainable policyagainst the injury done to notions of equity and fairness. This of course is an old political-economic issue that upon the balance of rights among individuals, culturally identifiable collectivities, commercial interests, andrecurs at every angle or joint in the social body. I have a single comment: one needs to pick one's so- the long-term public good? For the present, at least, these issues are being decided in the courts, but in thecial domain. In terms of the many decision-making contexts Brown summons (e.g., the ethics of Native Ameri- end it is posterity--the descendants of ourselves, as anthropologists, and those of the peoples we study--whocan churches' using Christian symbols), he is absolutely right to point to the excesses and absurdities of ``the will judge whether, in retrospect, cultural privacy was worth the price of cultural oblivion.dramatic expansion of the intellectual property of native people.'' But if we shift into the world of already Brown's sane and judicious study is not only a timely wakeup call for anthropologists to ponder the poten-existing inequities, where--to use a romanticist metaphor--it is hard to make one's voice heard, then intel- tially grave implications of cultural copyright legalities for the future of the discipline; more positively, throughlectual property rights is a forceful sound bite. Precisely because it rolls so much up into a bundle, precisely be- detached, clearsighted renderings it discloses the very anthropological saliency of the value contests sur-cause it has rhetorically inflationary potential, and precisely because it invokes property, it is a political slogan rounding cultural copyright. Do we glimpse, here, a research orientation constructive for anthropology in anof power. Power is not always so easy to come by. The anthropologist just needs to be careful not to mistake era when so many old disciplinary verities no longer apply? If so, this would be good news, indeed, for ``cul-slogan for social analytic. tural copyrighť' is only one in an emergent family of issues that pose important challenges and opportunities for future anthropology. For instance, how far does cul-donald tuzin Department of Anthropology, University of tural relativism go in defending practices, such as infibulation and clitoridectomy performed on little girls,California, San Diego, La Jolla, Calif. 92093-0532, U.S.A. (dtuzin@ucsd.edu). 19 x 97 that seem to offend more universalistic values? Similarly, what should be anthropology's stance on the knotty issue of cultural asylum--as, for example, in theIn these postmodern times, anthropology, to quote the Lord Ko-Ko and friends, finds itself in a ``pretty how-de- case of the Saudi Arabian woman who sought Canadian asylum on the grounds that Saudi culture deprived herdo.'' The debates over cultural copyright are filled with strange bedfellows and moral dilemmas. Having barely (as a woman) of her basic human rights? On a much larger scale, the combined effects of runaway popula-completed the task of dereifying culture and discrediting the concept of ``the tribe'' as an instrument of 19th- tion growth and prospective global warming imply that the not-too-distant future will witness population dislo-century imperialism, anthropology, at times, seems ready to welcome back such notions in order to defend cations of monumental proportions. Never mind indigenous intellectual property rights; how defensible willintellectual property rights on the part of indigenous collectivities and the corresponding right to prevent exclusionary real property rights and sovereignty be, for the autochthone, when a growing proportion of the hu-``outsiders'' from emulating or commercially exploiting their cultural patrimony. The role of indigenous advo- man race, with rights of its own, is beating on the door? And again, as the loss of biodiversity on the planet even-cate may come easily to anthropologists, considering 218 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 tually approaches crisis levels, how far will anthropol- hopeful because it signals the arrival of native peoples as significant players in global debates about social andogy go in defending the rights of indigenous groups to dispose of their resources entirely as they see fit? economic justice. Here, however, I part ways with some commentators. Coombe, for example, seems unable toThese are the sorts of challenges that anthropology will face in the coming century. If anthropology's arid distinguish between comprehension of native claims and unthinking support for them. I have no trouble un-response is to invoke what ĎAndrade (1995) has called ``moral models'' and join the babble of competing advo- derstanding the historical circumstances that lead indigenous groups to assert control over cultural records,cacies--reifying and sentimentalizing culture all over again--it will fail in its purposes; it will fail to develop nor do I contest demands that they should have a voice in determining how such records are used. Neverthe-new purposes appropriate to the new sociocultural realities of the 21st century; and it will become part of the less, those who value anthropology and other forms of social inquiry also have a responsibility to ask whetherproblem, not part of the solution. the wholesale ``repatriation of information'' is either feasible or morally defensible and, if we destroy cultural records or sequester them through novel forms of indigenous copyright as some would insist, what legal princi-Reply ples will prevent other social groups--defined by ethnicity, religious affiliation, or political agenda--from advancing similar claims. In an age of identity politics,michael f. brown Williamstown, Mass., U.S.A. 10 xii 97 it seems only prudent to ponder the broad implications of such policies before embracing them. Coombe is mistaken when she implies that I advanceThese 15 reasoned responses illustrate the wide-ranging thought needed to gain analytical purchase on issues of absolutist visions of free speech and freedom of access to information. Although I argue that standards of freeinformation policy and cultural ownership. Some commentators (e.g., Santos Granero, Powers, Posey) would speech and freedom of access should be considered in cultural-property debates, nowhere do I contend thatmove the analysis farther in the direction of concrete policies, whereas others (Barnes, Coombe, Descola, Hi- these goals always and everywhere trump other considerations. I have no more sympathy for unqualified appli-att, Strathern, Rosen, Tuzin) argue for situating the issues within larger debates about property concepts and cation of the principle of free speech than I do for preemptive claims of cultural ownership or for thetheir limitations, the politics of knowledge and representation, and dilemmas of ethnic sovereignty within simple-minded notion that a people has an inherent right to control how it is represented to the world atmulticultural states. The subject clearly demands both approaches, and I am grateful for the impressive erudi- large. Only by clearing away such totalizing positions can we begin the difficult business of finding a middletion that the commentators have brought to bear on its many facets. ground that balances the genuine concerns and grievances of native groups with the democratic values (how-Let me begin by underlining areas of general agreement. The commentators acknowledge that the lan- ever imperfectly applied) of the liberal state. In this sense I find myself drawn to the pragmatism of Powers,guage of cultural property is a problematic and in many ways impoverished way of talking about social prob- Cleveland, and Stephenson. It may be time, as Cleveland says, to focus on goals rather than on methods.lems that really turn on questions of sovereignty, mutual respect, and the precarious status of native cultures Karlsson misconstrues my references to American Indians. I mention Hopi and Apache assertions of controlwithin mass society. As Strathern notes, however, intellectual property discourse is a ``forceful sound bite'' over cultural information because on this issue, as on many others, these tribes are leading the way for otherbecause it condenses many issues into a compact notion that feeds upon public uneasiness about the future indigenous groups in North America and elsewhere. The tribal documents in question offer unusually clearof authenticity in a world increasingly defined by simulation. and straightforward expressions of the authors' positions. My respect for their views does not, however,Most of the commentators also recognize that comprehensive claims of cultural ownership can, if taken to oblige me to agree with all of their assertions. I do not dispute the sovereign right of native peoples to restrictextremes, play into the hands of demagogues. European observers--in particular, Descola and Hiatt--are more the activities of outside researchers as they see fit. The principal point at issue is the claim that indigenoussensitive to this issue than their colleagues from North America, South America, and Australia, doubtless be- groups ``own''--that is, possess inalienable and exclusive rights in--cultural information that they havecause of their proximity to recent cases of genocidal violence rooted in ideologies of ethnic nationalism. Even shared over the years with outsiders and that has long resided in the public domain.those who do not share their dark view of the trajectory of indigenous political assertion must acknowledge the American Indian spokespersons have every right to criticize New Agers who imitate Indian rituals or en-power of their cautionary tale. We also agree that the current struggle over intangi- gage in other offensive behavior. In fact, vigorous condemnation of New Age practices by Indians is far moreble cultural property can be seen as a hopeful sign-- brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 219 likely to promote greater cultural sensitivity than are a free of an insidious naturalism. Given anthropology's long struggle against essentialist approaches to culture,score of scholarly treatises on the problem of cultural appropriation. Nevertheless, there is little evidence that I would expect Posey to be more cautious about jumping onto this particular bandwagon.greater native control over material in libraries, museums, and archives will discourage the activities of those With the exception of Jackson, Rosen, and Stephenson, the commentators express little concern about thedetermined to emulate Native American religious rituals, who are far more likely to talk things over with impact of digital technologies on proposed schemes to protect indigenous heritage. Rosen uses the copyrightedtheir channeled spirit guides than to consult works of anthropology. status of this current anthropology article as evidence that intellectual property laws still work, yet theKarlsson incorrectly concludes that I question the sincerity of American Indian activists simply because example illustrates perfectly why copyrights and patents cannot protect indigenous knowledge that wassome happen to be skillful negotiators. Indians have been forced to hone their negotiating talents through never intended for uncontrolled circulation. Rosen and I write to disseminate our thoughts, not to shield themdecades of involvement with state and federal governments, the news media, nongovernmental organiza- from scrutiny. A century ago we would have been reasonably assured that our exchange would be read onlytions, and researchers of various descriptions. I see no necessary contradiction between a sincere commitment by those possessing a copy of the journal. Now that we have inexpensive photocopying, however, this article isto one's cultural values and mastery of the skills of cross-cultural communication. It bears noting, how- far more likely to be seen in facsimile than in its original form. This may be disturbing to the Wenner-Grenever, that burgeoning revenues from tribal gaming enterprises now permit American Indians to hire some of Foundation, which bears the journaĺs production costs, but for academic authors it is cause for quiet celebra-the nation's most influential lobbyists and lawyers to advance their interests in the public arena. Elsewhere, tion, since our ambition is to be read and cited. If our goal were to restrict access to our words, in contrast,for instance, in Australia, the state routinely finances litigation and other legal activities that contest the the journaĺs copyright would afford us no protection whatsoever. Compared with the digital technology nowstate's own power. These developments beg for dispassionate analysis by scholars willing to jettison habitual on the horizon, the photocopy machine is as crude as an Oldowan hand-axe, and we are sure to witness profoundassumptions about the relative powerlessness of native peoples, especially in the developed world. Despite an- changes in the ways in which information is created, circulated, transformed, and used--changes that willthropology's claim to be attentive to human agency, we prove highly selective in our willingness to acknowl- undermine cultural-protection schemes based on the logic of patents and copyrights.edge it, especially when the fate of received wisdom hangs in the balance. It would seem that we need vic- Cleveland raises the important question of cultural values, a theme also developed to a greater or lesser ex-tims far more than they need us. Posey is right to emphasize the many efforts being tent in the comments of Rosen, Severi, and Tuzin. Anthropology has found its place in Western thought bymade to develop workable strategies for the protection of indigenous know-how from corporate efforts to alien- showing how practices that seem illogical or immoral in one culture appear perfectly normal from the per-ate it through the prevailing system of copyrights and patents. But the devil, as they say, is in the details. I spective of another. Yet, as Tuzin points out, in a globalizing world our analysis cannot stop there. We musthave read most of the documents to which he refers, and I do not share his conviction that they offer a clear now come to grips with the challenges of reconciling widely divergent cultural values in our neighborhoods,vision of how the desires of indigenous peoples to ``control their heritage'' (to frame the issue in an idiom fa- schools, and workplaces. The turn toward indigenous sovereignty solves some problems but in turn createsvored by the United Nations) can be balanced against the legitimate claims of other social actors.1 The situa- others, especially as social boundaries become more permeable. It is crucially important to move the cul-tion is hardly helped by the recent reemergence in international forums of what Descola identifies as vo¨lkisch tural-property debate beyond reflexive expressions of solidarity to a more nuanced consideration of the con-philosophy, that is, belief in a transcendent, mystical link between a people and its territory. This is not to flicting rights and responsibilities at stake in the formulation of public policies relating to information.deny that many native peoples identify closely with their land, investing it with sacred qualities and seeing I was reminded of the human dimension of this struggle several months ago while observing an intellectualit as a source of knowledge. But as a generalization about indigenous cultures it seems neither accurate nor property trial in the city of Darwin, the capital of Australia's Northern Territory. The plaintiffs, a wellknown Aboriginal artist from Arnhem Land and his se-1. An important exception is Janke (1997), an Australian document that came into my possession while this reply was being drafted. nior clan relative, were asking the federal court to recConsisting of a general overview of Aboriginal intellectual property ognize the clan's economic and moral rights in the and legal frameworks that affect its disposition and use, the docuartisťs graphic designs, rights tied to the clan's territoryment proposes a range of specific changes in Australian laws and ritual knowledge. Representing them were a localrelating to copyright, patents, trademarks, and archives management. solicitor and a genial barrister from Melbourne named 220 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 anderson, christopher. Editor. 1995. Politics of the se-Colin Golvan, who brought to the case his considerable cret. Oceania Monograph 45.expertise in intellectual property litigation. The responaoki, keith. 1996. (Intellectual) Property and sovereignty: dent, a company that had pirated the artisťs work for Notes toward a cultural geography of authorship. Stanford Law mass-produced tee-shirts, was nowhere to be seen, ap- Review 48: 1293­1355. barlow, john perry. 1993. Selling wine without bottles:parently because prior litigation had forced it into bankThe economy of mind on the global net. http://www.eff.org/ruptcy. Instead, opposing counsel was provided by the pub/Intellectual property, accessed 1 January 1996.Ministry for Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Afbarnes, j. a. 1980. Who should know what? Cambridge: Camfairs, which feared that the case, if won by the plaintiffs, bridge University Press. [jab] could destabilize Australia's system of native land ti- ------. 1990. Models and interpretations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [jab]tles. In gowns and wigs, the lawyers from both sides prebaudrillard, jean. 1988. ``Simulacra and simulations,'' insented cogent arguments on behalf of their clients. Jean Baudrillard: Selected writings. Edited by Mark Poster, Documentation was brought forward in impressive pp. 166­84. Stanford: Stanford University Press. quantities. A museum curator furnished an example of berryman, cathryn a. 1994. Toward more universal protection of intangible cultural property. Journal of Intellectualthe artisťs work for the inspection of the court. The Property Law 1:293­333.presiding judge, obviously engaged by the case, seemed bettig, ronald v. 1996. Copyrighting culture: The politicalwilling to do the right thing if only he could figure out economy of intellectual property. Boulder: Westview Press. what it was and then reconcile it with existing laws and bok, sissela. 1983. Secrets: On the ethics of concealment and commercial practices. revelation. New York: Vintage. boyle, james. 1996. Shamans, software, and spleens: LawAlthough it was impossible not to admire the goodand the construction of the information society. Cambridge:will of the participants and, indeed, of a society that Harvard University Press. would devote so much institutional energy to the reso- brandt, elizabeth a. 1980. ``On secrecy and the control of lution of an isolated community's concerns, I found knowledge: Taos Pueblo,'' in Secrecy: A cross-cultural perspective. Edited by Stanton K. Tefft, pp. 123­46. New York: Hu-myself wondering whether this was the most effective man Sciences Press.way to help Aboriginal artists carry on the traditions of branscomb, anne wells. 1994. Who owns information?:their people while receiving reasonable compensation From privacy to public access. New York: Basic Books. for their efforts. Max Weber's analysis of bureaucracy brown, michael f. 1997. The channeling zone: American demonstrated long ago that modern procedural rational- spirituality in an anxious age. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.ity inevitably spawns its own forms of irrationality. As browning, john. 1997. Africa 1, Hollywood 0. Wired,heritage-protection laws come into effect and legal precMarch, pp. 61­64, 185­88. edents accumulate, lawyers will apply ever more intri- brush, stephen b. 1993. Indigenous knowledge of biological cate casuistry to contests over cultural ownership. Each resources and intellectual property rights: The role of anthropology. American Anthropologist 95:653­86.innovation in legal thinking invites new claims in a spibusse, mark. 1997. The National Cultural Property (Preserva-ral of complexity increasingly removed from the goal of tion) Act [Papua New Guinea, 1965/1975]. Paper delivered tocreating social spaces in which indigenous peoples are Intellectual, Biological, and Cultural Property Rights Seminar, safe from predatory corporations and mass cultures Port Moresby, August. [ms] hungry for glimpses of human understanding perceived cleveland, david a., and stephen c. murray. 1997. The worlďs crop genetic resources and the rights of indigenousas uniquely authentic, perhaps even as redemptive. farmers. current anthropology 38:477­515.Hence my contrarian arguments, offered as a profesconley, diane. 1990. Author, user, scholar, thief: Fair use sion of doubt. If they cause readers to pause for a mo- and unpublished works. Cardozo Arts and Entertainment Law ment of reflection before blindly supporting plans to bu- Journal 9:15­60. conte, e., and c. essner. 1995. La que^te de la race: Unereaucratize and police the public domain in the name anthropologie du nazisme. Paris: Hachette. [pd]of respect for other cultures, then they will have served coombe, rosemary j. 1991. Objects of property and subjectsa useful purpose. of politics: Intellectual property laws and democratic debate. Texas Law Review 69:1853­80. ------. 1993. Cultural and intellectual properties: Occupying the colonial imagination. Political and Legal Anthropology Review 16(1):8­15. References Cited ------. 1996. Marking difference in American commerce: Trademarks and alterity at century's end. Political and Legal Anthropology Review 19:105­15.aim leadership conference. 1984. AIM Resolution on sale of sacred ceremonies. Sovereign Dine Nation, Window ------. 1997. ``The properties of culture and the possession of identity: Postcolonial struggle and the legal imagination,'' inRock, Ariz.: Center for World Indigenous Studies/Fourth World Documentation Project, http://www.halcyon.com/pub/ Borrowed power: Essays on cultural appropriation. Edited by Bruce Ziff and Pratima V. Rao, pp. 74­96. New Brunswick:FWDP, accessed 9 April 9 1996, unpaginated. albanese, catherine l. 1990. Nature religion in America: Rutgers University Press. Cultural Survival. 1996. Genes, people, and property. 20From the Algonkian Indians to the New Age. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (2). daes, erica-irene. 1993. Study on the protection of the cul-anderson, carolyn, and thomas w. benson. 1988. ``Direct cinema and the myth of informed consent: The case of tural and intellectual property of indigenous peoples. E/CN.4/ Sub.2/1993/28. New York: United Nations Economic and So-Titicut Follies,'' in Image ethics: The moral rights of subjects in photographs, film, and television. Edited by Larry Gross, cial Council, Commission on Human Rights. ďandrade, roy. 1995. Moral models in anthropology. cur-John Stuart Katz, and Jay Ruby, pp. 58­90. New York: Oxford University Press. rent anthropology 36:399­408. [dt] brown Can Culture Be Copyrighted? 221 descola, philippe. n.d. Exploitable knowledge belongs to sale: Sacred knowledge in the consumer age. American Indian Quarterly 20:415­31.the creators of it: A debate. Social Anthropology 6(1). dirlik, arif. 1996. The past as legacy and project: Postcolo- johnson, paul c. 1995. Shamanism from Ecuador to Chicago: A case study in New Age ritual appropriation. Religionnial criticism in the perspective of indigenous historicism. American Indian Culture and Research Journal 20(2):1­31. 25:163­78. kehoe, alice b. 1990. ``Prima Gaia: Primitivists and plastic[bgk] duboff, leonard d. 1992. 500 years after Columbus: Pro- medicine men,'' in The invented Indian: Cultural fictions and government policies. Edited by James M. Clifton, pp. 193­209.tecting Native American culture. Cardozo Arts and Entertainment Law Journal 11:43­58. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers. kymlicka, will. 1989. Liberalism, community, and culture.dworkin, ronald. 1986. Law's empire. Cambridge: Belknap/ Harvard University Press. Oxford: Clarendon Press. lange, david. 1981. Recognizing the public domain. Law anddyson, esther. 1995. Intellectual value. Wired, July, pp. 136­ 41, 182­84. Contemporary Problems 44:147­78. [djs] ------. 1993. Copyright and the Constitution in the Age of Intellec-feld, steven. 1994. ``From schizophonia to schismogenesis: On the discourses and commodification practices of `World tual Property. Journal of Intellectual Property Law 1:119­34. litman, jessica. 1991. Copyright as myth. University ofMusic' and `World Beat,' '' in Music grooves: Essays and dialogues, by Charles Keil and Steven Feld, pp. 257­89. Chicago: Pittsburgh Law Review 53:235­49. merrill, william l., and richard e. ahlborn. 1997.University of Chicago Press. ------. 1996. ``Pygmy POP: A genealogy of schizophonic mime- ``Zuni archangels and Ahayu:da: A sculpted chronicle of power and identity,'' in Exhibiting dilemmas: Issues of representationsis,'' in Yearbook for traditional music 1996, pp. 1­35. New York: International Council for Traditional Music. at the Smithsonian. Edited by Amy Henderson and Adrienne L. Kaeppler, pp. 176­205. Washington, D.C.: Smithsonian Insti-fowler, cary. 1994. Unnatural selection: Technology. politics, and plant evolution. Yverdon: Gordon and Breach.[dac] tution Press. merrill, william l., edmund j. ladd, and t. j. fer-fowler, catherine. 1995. ``Ethical considerations,'' in Preserving the anthropological record, 2d edition. Edited by Sydel guson. 1993. The return of the Ahayu:da: Lessons for repatriation from Zuni Pueblo and the Smithsonian Institution. cur-Silverman and Nancy J. Parezo, pp. 63­72. New York: WennerGren Foundation for Anthropological Research. rent anthropology 34:523­67. mé traux, a. 1958. Le vaudou haitien. Paris: Gallimard. [cs]gass, william. 1997. Shears of the censor: Notes on excision, imprisonment, and silence. Harper's Magazine, April, pp. 59­ mills, sherylle. 1996. ``Indigenous music and the law: An analysis of national and international legislation,'' in Yearbook65. golvan, colin. 1992. Aboriginal art and the protection of in- for traditional music 1996, pp. 57­86. New York: International Council for Traditional Music.digenous cultural rights. European Intellectual Property Review 14:227­32. morgan, marlo. 1994. Mutant message down under. New York: HarperCollins.greaves, tom. Editor 1994. Intellectual property rights for indigenous peoples: A source book. Oklahoma City: Society for mota, sue ann. 1995. Apple Computer v. Microsoft: The Ninth Circuit finds no copyright infringement of Apple's graph-Applied Anthropology. ------. 1995. Cultural rights and ethnography. Bulletin of the ical user interface. Western State University Law Review 23: 39­51.General Anthropology Division, American Anthropological Association 1(2):1­6. munro, doug. 1994. Who ``owns'' Pacific history? Journal of Pacific History 29:232­37.greene, candace s., and thomas d. drescher. 1994. The Tipi with battle pictures: The Kiowa tradition of intangi- Mutant message downed!!! 1996. http:// www.newage.com.au/panthology/mutant.htm, accessed 4 Au-ble property rights. Trademark Reporter 84:418­33. greenfield, jeanette. 1989. The return of cultural trea- gust 1997. nason, james d. 1997. ``Native American intellectual prop-sures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [ms] grifo, francesca t. 1994. ``Chemical prospecting: An over- erty rights: Issues in the control of esoteric knowledge,'' in Borrowed power: Essays on cultural appropriation. Edited byview of the International Cooperative Biodiversity Groups Program,'' in Emerging connections: Biodiversity, biotechnology, Bruce Ziff and Pratima V. Rao, pp. 237­54. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.and sustainable development in health and agriculture. Edited by Julie Feinsilver. San José, Costa Rica: Proceedings of Pan negativland. 1995. Fair use: The story of the letter U and the numeral 2. Concord, Calif.: Seeland.American Health Organization Conference. grossman, wendy m. 1995. Alt.Scientology.War. Wired, De- pask, amanda. 1993. Cultural appropriation and the law: An analysis of the legal regimes concerning culture. Intellectualcember, pp. 173­77, 248­52. gupta, akhil, and james ferguson. 1992. Beyond `cul- Property Journal 8:57­86. pels, peter, and oscar salemink. 1994. Introduction:ture': Space, identity, and the politics of difference. Cultural Anthropology 7(1):6­23. Five theses on ethnography as colonial practice. History and Anthropology 8:1­34.haas, jonathan. 1996. Power, objects, and a voice for anthropology. current anthropology 37:S1­S22. posey, darrell a., and graham dutfield. 1996. Beyond intellectual property: Toward traditional resource rightshandler, richard. 1988. Nationalism and the politics of culture in Quebec. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press. for indigenous peoples and local communities. Ottawa: International Development Research Centre.inter-apache summit on repatriation. 1995. InterApache policy on repatriation and the protection of Apache cul- puri, kamal. 1995. Cultural ownership and intellectual property rights post-Mabo: Putting ideas into action. Intellectualtures. MS. jackson, jean. 1989. Is there a way to talk about making cul- Property Journal 9:293­347. root, deborah. 1995. Cannibal culture: Art, appropriation,ture without making enemies? Dialectical Anthropology 14: 127­43. and the commodification of difference. Boulder: Westview Press.------. 1995. Culture, genuine and spurious: The politics of Indianness in the Vaupés, Colombia. American Ethnologist 22:3­ rose, wendy. 1992. ``The great pretenders: Further reflections on whiteshamanism,'' in The state of Native America: Geno-27. janke, terri. 1997. Our culture, our future: Proposals for the cide, colonization, and resistance. Edited by M. Annette Jaimes, pp. 403­21. Boston: South End Press.recognition and protection of indigenous cultural and intellectual property. Canberra: Australian Institute of Aboriginal and rosen, lawrence. 1997. The right to be different: Indigenous peoples and the quest for a unified theory. Yale Law JournalTorres Strait Islanders Studies. jocks, christopher ronwanie` n:te. 1996. Spirituality for 107. [lr] 222 current anthropology Volume 39, Number 2, April 1998 samuelson, paula. 1997. Big media beaten back. Wired, ------. 1996. A comment on recent developments in the legal protection of traditional resource rights. High Plains AppliedMarch, pp. 61­64, 178­84. samudrala, ram. 1995. The free music philosophy. http:// Anthropologist 16:114­21. [djs] strathern, marilyn. 1996. Potential property: Intellectualwww.eff.org/pub/Intellectual property, accessed 2 January 1996. rights and property in persons. Social Anthropology 4(1):17­32. taylor, charles. 1994. ``The politics of recognition,'' insandager, elizabeth. 1994. Ethical implications of the documentary record. New England Archivists Newsletter 21 (2):4­ Multiculturalism: Examining the politics of recognition. Edited by Amy Gutmann, pp. 25­74. Princeton: Princeton University6. sanjek, david. 1992. ``Don't Have to DJ No More'': Sampling Press. taylor, mark c., and esa saarinen. 1994. Imagologies:and the ``autonomous'' creator. Cardozo Arts and Entertainment Law Journal 10:607­24. Media philosophy. London: Routledge. tisdale, sallie. 1997. Silence please: The public library asschiller, herbert i. 1989. Culture, Inc.: The corporate takeover of American expression. New York: Oxford University entertainment center. Harper's Magazine, March, pp. 65­74. trask, haunani-kay. 1991. Natives and anthropologists:Press. schwartz, hillel. 1996. The culture of the copy: Striking The colonial struggle. The Contemporary Pacific 3:159­77. tuzin, donald. 1995. ``The Melanesian Archive,'' in Preserv-likenesses, unreasonable facsimiles. New York: Zone Books. seeger, anthony. 1996. ``Ethnomusicologists, archives, pro- ing the anthropological record, 2d edition. Edited by Sydel Silverman and Nancy J. Parezo, pp. 23­34. New York: Wenner-fessional organizations, and the shifting ethics of intellectual property,'' in Yearbook for traditional music 1996, pp. 87­105. Gren Foundation for Anthropological Research. warren, karen j. 1989. ``A philosophical perspective on theNew York: International Council for Traditional Music. sheffield, gail. 1997. The arbitrary Indian: The Indian ethics and resolution of cultural property issues,'' in The ethics of collecting cultural property: Whose culture? Whose prop-Arts & Crafts Act of 1990. Norman: Oklahoma University Press. [djs] erty? Edited by Phyllis Mauch Messenger, pp. 1­26. Albuquerque: University of New Mexico Press.smith, andrea. 1994. For all those who were Indian in a former life. Cultural Survival Quarterly 17(4):70­71. weber, max. 1930. The Protestant ethic and the spirit of capitalism. Translated by Talcott Parsons. London: Routledge.soleri, daniela, david a. cleveland, donald eriacho, fred bowannie jr., andrew laahty, and whiteley, peter. 1997. ``The end of anthropology (at Hopi)?'' in Indians and anthropologists: Vine Deloria, Jr., and the cri-zuni community members. 1994. ``Gifts from the Creator: Intellectual property rights and folk crop varieties,'' in IPR tique of anthropology. Edited by Thomas Biolsi and Larry J. Zimmerman, pp. 177­207. Tucson: University of Arizonafor indigenous peoples: A sourcebook. Edited by Tom Greaves, pp. 21­40. Oklahoma City: Society for Applied Anthropology. Press. winter, irene. 1993. Cultural property. Art Journal 52:103­7.stampede mesteth, wilmer, darrell standing elk, and phyllis swift hawk. n.d. Declaration of war [ms] wolfe, alan. 1996. Marginalized in the middle. Chicago: Uni-against exploiters of Lakota spirituality. http:// www.maple.lemoyne.edu/ bucko/war.html, accessed 10 versity of Chicago Press. zemp, hugo. 1996. ``The/an ethnomusicologist and the recordApril 1996. stephenson, david j., jr. 1994. ``A legal paradigm for pro- business,'' in Yearbook for traditional music 1996, pp. 36­56. New York: International Council for Traditional Music.tecting traditional knowledge,'' in Intellectual property rights for indigenous peoples, A sourcebook. Edited by Tom Greaves, ziff, bruce, and pratima v. rao. Editors. 1997. Borrowed power: Essays on cultural appropriation. New Bruns-pp. 179­90. Oklahoma City: Society for Applied Anthropology. [djs] wick: Rutgers University Press.