Ideal Language and Kinship Structure Ernest Gellner Philosophy of Science, Vol. 24, No. 3. (Jul., 1957), pp. 235-242. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0031-8248%28195707%2924%3A3%3C235%3AILAKS%3E2.0.CO%3B2-9 Philosophy of Science is currently published by The University of Chicago Press. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/ucpress.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. http://www.jstor.org Tue Mar 25 07:21:17 2008 IDEAL LANGUAGE AND ICIMSHIP STRUCTURE* ERNEST GELLNER University of Lonclon This paper is inter-disciplinary. Its disadvantage is that the author is not sufficiently conversant with the disciplines it is inter. He may however, like Lord TVavell, claim that at least the thread that binds them is his own. The paper is of philosophic interest in that it is inspired by, and hopes to shed some light on, the notion of an ideal language. It is of interest to social anthropologjr in that its main subject is kinship structure. It may be of interest to mathematicians in setting a task. Ideal Language. The notion of an ideal language played an important part in philosophy earlier in this century. The notion lacks clarity-though clarity is just one of the things an ideal language hopes to provide-but certain features nevertheless seem to emerge: an ideal language must be unambiguous. This means, amongst other things, that it observes the rule "one thing, one name"; no two things may have the same name, nor may two names be given to one thing. Secondly, an ideal language is no deceiver, it does not mislead; permissible and impermissible inferences and transitions are clearly evident from the very notation. Thirdly, an ideal language does not distort the nature of reality; the notation clearly shows what is due to the notation and what is due to fact. It equally shows up the possibly related boundary between what is logically necessary and what is contingent. The above is not clear. But then, nor are the reasons ~vhichled to the abandonment of this ideal. I shall return to both. Kinship Structure. Kinship structure theory is an important and well developed social anthropology. I t is well developed for a number of reasons. The kind of question originally asked about primitive societies were often connected with kinship; kinship structure is an aspect of society which is more tangible and stateable with accuracy than most; kinship lends itself to comparison between societies. In fact, "kinship structure" means two separate things, though, as will emerge, ailthropologists are right in not normally separating them. I shall:A society consists of people, male and female, any pair of whom can mate (with certain obvious qualificatioiis concerning age) as far as biology is concerned. In actual fact, matings are not random in any society. In other words, actual matings are a sub-class of biologically possible matings. Kinship-structure in the jrst sense means the specification of how that sub-class is selected, in other words which matings, or rather which kinds of matings, actually occur. For instance in a strictly monogamous society with no pre- or extra-marital relations or re-marriage, the actual matings woi~ldbe such that if A and B mate, then this precludes any mating of A with B' or of B with A'. * Received March, 1956. 235 236 ERNEST GELLNER The second sense of "kinship-structure" is the correlation of social roles (which are not logically entailed by biologically-defined relationships) with kinship roles defined within the first sense of the term. For instance, the assertion that the provider or protector of the woman is ex officio her biological mate. Kinship structure in this sense specifies which roles, with what rigidity and to what extent, are so to speak functions of the biological kinship position of the agent (or vice versa). I t will also contain negative assertions to the effect that such and such a role is not related to kinship. I t is, for instance, often said that industrial society differs from most agrarian societies in that fewer roles are functions of kinship. The first and second sense of kinship-structure are logically distinct. Nevertheless anthropologists are right in lumping them together, this being inevitable. The reason for this is that many important limitations of matings (kinship structure sense 1) operate in terms of social roles; for instance, in one society I know a man may not marry a woman who was suckled by the same breast as he (though it belong to a mere wet-nurse of either/or both "siblings of milk," as they are called). I t followsthat the tasks of the first and second kind of kinship study can only be carried out pari passu, and can be separated neither in the study nor in the presentation of material. Contemporary social anthropologists, perhaps because they are anxious to assert to social nature and the autonomy of their discipline vis-a-vis physical or biological disciplines, tend to stress their concern with the second aspect of kinship, sometimes almost to the point of implying that the first does not concern them. But this cannot be so for the degree of overlap-admittedly incomplete-between social and physical kinship is precisely one of the most interesting things in the subject, and one to which the investigation of which social anthropologists are committed by the 'functionalist' theory that social kinship structure is explained by its serving the basic needs connected with procreation. I shall nomi try to indicate what I think would count as an ideal language for kinship structure theory. In many languages a man is named by some locution such as "John, son of Peter". Sometimes it is extended to something like "John, son of Peter, son of Stephen". There is no necessary upper limit to this kind of thing. Nor is there any reason why only the ancestors in the direct male line should be specified. All ancestors, male and female, up to a certain point back could be specified, and moreover specified according to a fixed order which would indicate just who they were, biologically speaking, in relation to the person to be named. No society, as far as I know, possesses anything like so complete a system of naming its members. That, however, is no reason why such a system should be devised. If such a scheme were devised, we should then have a way of naming human individuals such that their very name would promptly place them within their biological logical space. Is one justified in calling this a kind of logical space? I think so. The fact that man is born of woman and has a man for father is not a logical truth; it is "merely" a synthetic, empirical truth of biology, though IDEAL LANGUAGE AND ICIRTSI~IPSTRUCTURE 237 allowing for parthenogenesis as good a generalisation as ever we shall find. But for the purposes of the social sciences, it can be taken as a logical truth defining certain universal relations between objects they are investigating (namely, human beings). In certain contexts "Mother's son" is indeed synonymous with "man"; there are some languages in which "son of man" is used in the sense of "man". I t is now worth specifying some of the difficulties that would have to be overcome in order that the above objective is attained. 1) If an individual's "name" in our ideal naming system consists of or at least contains an ordered list of his ancestors, one has to take into account that the names of those ancestors, or at least some of them, will be similarly complex. Concretely, if John's name contains the sequence GHK each letter of which names one of his ancestors, it is likely that G, H, and K may also in fact be ordered strings of names. Hence there must be some device for indicating whether a symbol occurs as part of a name other than the "total" name, or whether it occurs atomically. Or alternatively, if the constituents of John's name build up from his ancestors' names so that the preceding distinction vanishes, (every symbol occurring in both ways) then some rule must still be made specifying in what way one may break up John's name and get the names of ancestors, rather than strings of symbols naming no one. If this system were ever applied to an actually existing group of human beings, ancestors of a certain generation past would have to be "primitive" ancestors and be assigned "primitive" names. Though I do not think that if the present device xere ever worked out, its use, if any, would be in actually naming people-people's names would be too impossibly long. On the other hand if the device is to be sound it is necessary that it should, however cumbersomely, be in principle so applicable. Incidentally, the names nrould indicate the person's ancestors but never his descendants. After all, he may not have any, or he may acquire some after naming. The least a good name must do is not to depend on the empirical fortunes of the man named. This is what distinguishes names from descriptions. I t is a curious fact that it is logically true (in our sense) that we all have ancestors, but not even factually true that we all have descendants. Those philosophers unfortunate enough not to be able to tell the direction of time, and who sometimes look for guidance in abstruse things such as entropy, may if they wish use this more homely fact to guide them. 2) If the construction of an individual's name involved nothing but the ordering of the names of his ancestors, the consequence would be that all siblings would have the same name. This ~~youldcause confusion in his and the next generation, and a violation of the principle "one name, one thing" in both the first and the subsequent generations. Hence a device is again necessary for obviating it. I t must in principle be possible. For instance, if GHKL is a string of names of ancestors specifying in good order the common ancestors of Paul and Peter, then Paul might be IGHKI; and Peter 2GHI