Fro** {kz {o {A* 3^kA n assessing the significance of the ready-made, Octavio Paz underlines its challenge to traditional concepts of art and value. According to Paz, the ready-made represents a contra-j. uictory gesture, since the artist's gratuitous choice of an anonymous, mass-produced object converts it into a work of art, while destroying the notion of an art object: * The essence of the act is contradiction; it is the plastic equivalent of a pun. As the latter destroys meaning, the former destroys the notion of value. . . . The Ready-made does not postulate a new |- value: it is a jibe at what we call valuable. It is criticism in action: a ; kick at the work of art ensconced on its pedestal of adjectives.1 The ready-made implies an active critique of the notion of value. This critique is not dialectical: it involves neither the negation nor the affirmation ■ of value. Rather, the ready-made is conceived as the "plastic equivalent of a pun," that is, as a mechanism staging the gratuitous conversion of an ordinary object into a work of art, while simultaneously undermining the notion of an art object through this gesture. The destruction of value, entailed by the first moment, corresponds to the annulment of meaning in the second. As "criticism in action," the ready-made radically disrupts the valuative judgment of a work as art. C<\/v o*ve r^e^kz works of VH"? As the ready-mades demonstrate, Duchamp's exploration of the concepts of art and value is not an abstract philosophical inquiry but a literal one. Instead of asking what value is, Duchamp proceeds to demonstrate its conditions and modes of operation as a social phenomenon. Not content to explore the philosophical conundrums generated by the ready-mades, he takes on the question of value on its most basic level, not merely as artistic abstraction but also as an economic phenomenon. In a series of works starting with Tzanck Check (1919), and later continuing with Cheque Bruno {Cheque Bruno; 1965) and Czech Check (1965), Duchamp proceeds to explore the relationship between art and economics, by presenting the facsimile of a check, both as monetary payment and as art. The idea of producing a work that problematizes the transactions involved in both the circulation of a work of art and of monetary currency is pursued in Wanted/$zooo Reward (1923), a parody of a police "wanted" poster. This is followed by the Monte Carlo Bond {Obligations pour la Roulette de Monte Carlo; 1924), a financial document issued by Duchamp in order to raise funds to test his formula for a betting system at the roulette wheel. In these works the autonomy of the artistic and economic domains is challenged by a speculative interpretation of value that uncovers their shared social and symbolic concerns.2 This inquiry into value as a function of art and economics culminates in Duchamp's return at the end of his oeuvre to a ready-made that is both an artistic and economic artifact. First issued under the title Drain Stopper {Bouche-Evier; 1964), this work is reissued subsequently as a set of numismatic coins, and retitled Marcel Duchamp Art Medal (1967). These works return to Duchamp's Fountain (fig. 48, p. 125) by commemorating the urinal that literally flushed the notion of artistic value down the drain. The reproduction of Drain Stopper as Marcel Duchamp Art Medal transforms the work of "art" into a limited edition of numismatic coins, that is, works embodying both artistic and economic notions of value. Duchamp's deliberate conflation of artistic and economic categories, however, produces a paradoxical effect: that of undermining both art and economics. By challenging the concept of inherent value through reproduction, the notion of the artistic value will emerge as a speculative correlative of economic value. Hence the questions that this study will address are: 1) what is the relation of artistic and commercial activity, 76 0 ttKJ AtilAH ucA tions Duchamp's forays into commercial activity, since they blatantly contradict his own expectations of Duchamp's artistic attitude and supposed "detachment" from material concerns.3 Cabanne is not alone in asking these questions. When asked about why Duchamp allowed an expensive edition of ready-mades to be done by Arturo Schwarz, John Cage echoes Cabanne's sense of contradiction: "Why did you permit that, because it looks like business rather than art" and so forth. Marcel admitted that it could be so interpreted, but it did not disturb him. He was extremely interested in money. At the same time, he never really used his art to make money. And yet he lived in a period when artists were making enormous amounts of money. He couldn't understand how they did it. I think he thought of himself as a poor businessman. These late activities were like business.4 Cage's comments demonstrate the difficulty of sorting out, or rather, understanding how art and commerce come together in Duchamp's works. Insisting that Duchamp was not "using" his art to make money, Cage underlines both Duchamp's interest in money and his attempt to disengage his art from monetary concerns. Still, Cage has problems with the late editions of the ready-mades, which, unlike the "original" editions, he now considers to be like "business." While Cage recognizes Duchamp's caution and discipline in not "extending the notion of the Ready-mades to everything," as well as his original difficulty of coming to the decision to make them, he also feels that later in life, Duchamp abandons this caution and "would sign anything that anyone asked him to."5 Thus, while Cage is able to recognize the limited edition aspect of the ready-mades, he is unable to deal with Schwarz's reissuing them as a "second edition." Whereas Cage is willing to assume Duchamp's initial signature as the signature of the artist, he is uncertain whether the second signature is not merely that of the businessman.^ The effort to extricate art from economics proves to be extremely difficult, since Duchamp's oeuvre stages significant questions regarding the effects that the ready-mades, as reproducible objects, will have on the relation between art and economics, as well as the definition of the artist as author and guarantor of artifacts. Cage's and Cabanne's difficulty in reconciling art and business reflects a fundamental prejudice in the Western conception of the artist, which supposes art to be entirely removed from the economic sphere. There is, however, something fundamental shared by art and economics: the notion of value. It can be argued that value in art is an abstraction, since masterpieces are so valuable that they are often priceless. Yet the same is true of the value generated by commercial transactions, insofar as worth is relative to the system of exchange that generates it. What fascinates Duchamp is the process by which a work acquires artistic and commercial value. The production of value entails, for him, a social and speculative dimension. In his interview with Cabanne, Duchamp describes his earliest venture into commercial activity "sometime before" 1934: That was with Picabia. We agreed that I would help him with his auction at the Hotel Drouot. A fictitious auction, however, since the proceeds were for him. But obviously he didn't want to be mixed up in it, because he couldn't sell his paintings at the Salle Drouot under the title "Sale of Picabias by Picabia!" It was simply to avoid the bad effect that would have had. It was an amusing experience. It was all very important for him, because, until then, no one had had the idea of showing Picabias to the public, let alone selling them, giving them a commercial value. ... I bought a few little things then. I don't remember what, anymore. (dmd, 73) 7 6 l H^pftcilK^ . Marcel Duchamp, Tzanck Check, 1919. Imitated rectified ready-made: enlarged manuscript version of a check, 8 1/4 x rj 118 in. Galleria Scbwarz, Milan. Courtesy of Arturo Schwarz. Now we can begin to understand Duchamp's interest in economics, since the question of value in the economic domain presents problems that are analogous to those Duchamp explores in the artistic domain — most particularly, his rejection of the artisanal production of objects (the cult of the "hand"), such as we see embodied in the ready-mades. It is this intellectual dimension of ready-mades that is regarded with some suspicion by artists, such as Robert Smithson, who claims that in the case of the ready-mades, Duchamp is trying to "transcend production itself" and that "He has a certain contempt for the work process and here ... he is sort of playing the aristocrat."15 Smithson's comment highlights the contradictions that the ready-made poses as a work of art, insofar as its "value" cannot be linked to a manual system of production, since it is mass-produced. Rather, the "value" of the ready-made is determined in relation to the artistic norms that it defies and reduces to meaninglessness. Based on the discussion in chapter z, it seems that while the ready-made is not the result of artisanal production but rather of mass reproduction, this aspect forcefully engages the spectator in another kind of "work" of an intellectual order. The ready-made is not an object in the ordinary sense, since it is the "plastic equivalent of a pun," that is, a visual and lin- if guistic machine. This mechanism "works" by translating a set of abstract concerns, about the effects of mechanical reproduction on the work of art, into their plastic equivalents. Consequently, given Duchamp's interest in how an art object accrues both artistic and financial value, his own involvement in the sale and acquisition of art should come as no surprise. Rather than viewing Duchamp's commercial activity as a betrayal of both his artistic detachment and putative disinterest in financial value, his fascination for the speculative value of art can be better understood in intellectual terms. It is a fascination with how artistic and monetary value is generated arbitrarily through social exchange. Duchamp's interest in the speculative character of money does not translate itself into the subservience of his own artistic work to monetary considerations. Instead, it expresses the recognition that value, be it artistic or financial, is embedded in a circuit of symbolic exchange. Duchamp's explicit interest and involvement in commercial and artistic transactions becomes the very subject of a series of works, starting in 1919. These works include several types of facsimile checks, Tzanck Check, Cheque Bruno, and Czech Check, which were issued over a period of forty years. In these works the question of value is no longer implied as an abstract reflection, hence the discrimination between what may or may not be art. Rather, Duchamp chooses to address the question of value literally, not as abstract worth but as concrete currency. Just as Duchamp problematized the distinction between art and nonart, so he now proceeds to examine the distinction between art and economics as a function of the social and institutional exchanges they imply. * Although contemporary to Duchamp's reproduction of the Mona Lisa in l.h.o.o.q. (fig. 53, p. 140), the Tzanck Check (fig. 59) is a reproduction of money, rather than a work of art. In this particular case money, as a means toward the acquisition of art, becomes the end, since its reproduction through a check transforms it into a work of art. It is important to note, however, that Duchamp chooses to reproduce a check rather than «\j jtosiiLU to currency. 6 A check is merely an order for the payment of money on demand. It is another kind of legal tender, which is more specific than money, since it involves a blank (the addressee), a bank (institutional endorsement), a date, and a signature (individual endorsement). These institutional markers that define the legal identity of a check also define the institutional parameters of a work of art. The anonymous spectator of the work of art occupies the blank space of the addressee, while dates are essential to both art and business. The author's signature, however, acts as the guarantor of the authenticity of the work, as well as the general guarantor, the "bank" (the artist's reputation that backs this particular issue of the work}. But the work of art has a title, descriptive or poetic, although it is unclear whether this type of designation is specific or generic. It is this entrance into nomination that distinguishes art from checking, to the extent that the name confers identity by individualizing the object. This "entitlement" of art is relatively recent, however, and reflects a shift in our definition of the authority of the artist and the status of an artwork.17 Like Duchamp's ready-made Fountain, which embodies his "dry" interpretation of art, these checks become the basis for exploring the conceptual interval between art and economics. This process literally involves "checking," that is, verifying by comparison how value is posited and expended in these otherwise autonomous domains. The Tzanck Check documents a transaction between Duchamp and his dentist Daniel Tzanck, which Duchamp summarizes as follows: I asked him how much I owed, and then did the check entirely by hand. I took a long time doing the little letters, to do something which would look printed — it wasn't a small check. And I bought it back twenty years later, for a lot more than it says it's worth! Afterward I gave it to Matta, unless I sold it to him. {dmd, 63) As Duchamp explains, this check is a payment in "art" for medical services rendered. In return for what he owes Duchamp gives his dentist a work of art, whose value, however, unlike money, continues to accrue interest. In settling what appears to be an ordinary debt Duchamp's payment In "art" exceeds the terms of the original obligation. It is important to recall, however, that in addition to being a dentist, Tzanck was an avid art lover and the founder of a society of art collectors dedicated to the appreciation of modern art, who proposed the creation of a museum of modern art in Paris.18 Given Tzanck's involvement with modern art, one must wonder whether the Tzanck Check is more than an ordinary payment. By recording their anecdotal transaction through a check that is also a work of art, Duchamp translates his obligation from financial into symbolic terms. Within this system of symbolic exchange, reciprocity replaces debt, insofar as Duchamp's gesture leads to Tzanck's indebtedness for having "slipped into the history of art."19 * A closer examination of the Tzanck Check, created in December 1919, reveals how these apparent contradictions are explicitly staged by this work. Given the fact that this work immediately follows the notorious l.h.o.o.q., which dates to October 1919, the question of the shared concerns of these two works imposes itself. Notably, both are reproductions, albeit in different ways. Whereas l.h.o.o.q. is a commercial reproduction of a masterpiece, a ready-made, the Tzanck Check is a hand-drawn, larger-than-life facsimile, which looks as if it were printed. The difference is that the "artist has painstakingly applied his skill to the manual imitation of an item which modern techniques of mass production would normally print out in an instant."20 This work is an "Imitated Rectified. Ready-made," that is to say, a work that reproduces mechanical mass production, like a mechanical drawing that, according to Duchamp, "upholds no taste, since it is outside all pictorial conventions" (dmd, 48). Although we are dealing with two different types of reproduction, commercial and manual (based on commercial), the effects of these two gestures are very different. In the first instance, the act of commercial reproduction challenges the uniqueness of the masterpiece, insofar as mechanical production displaces pictorial and artisanal techniques. In the second instance, the deployment of manual dexterity is merely an imitation of commercial reproduction and hence, no more original than an industrial drawing or prototype for a machine. Duchamp provides clues to how the Tzanck Check should Be interpreted by comparing it to the phonetic puns of l.h.o.o.q., where in his words "reading the letters is very amusing" (dmd, 63). If l.h.o.o.q. is a very elaborate linguistic and visual game, what are the puns staged by the Tzank Check} In addition to the alliterative sound of the title, this work, a. r { a h i -e < o k a r*. 1 c $ also published under the title of Dada Drawing (Dessin Dada) in Francis Picabia's journal Cannibale (2.5 April 192,0), presents a network of puns combining artistic allusion with monetary analogy. The name of the bank, designated on the check as "The Teeth's Loan tk. Trust Company," seems initially a gratuitous inversion of the guarantor (the Bank) and its client (the dentist), since in this case the check appears to be backed by a loan and trust (not exactly a savings) bank called "Teeth." The insistence of the phrase "the teeth'sloanandtrustcompanyconsolidated," which is repeatedly stamped on the lower half (with a rubber stamp of the phrase made especially, to be used on this one occasion) along with the word "ORIGINAL" printed across in red, can be interpreted at face value as attempts against forgery and guarantees of the "originality" of this fake check.21 But the face value of this check is only backed by a "rubber stamp," whose limited use by no means clarifies the nature of such fictitious backing. What then is the fiction that underlies the history of this check? Duchamp's references to "teeth" in his Notes invariably involve combs: "Classify combs by the number of their teeth" (wmd, 71).22 Thus the "teeth" in the title of the Tzanck Check's bank, "The Teeth's Loan & Trust Company," is a reference to one of Duchamp's earlier ready-mades, entitled Comb (Peigne, a pun on painting, in French). This allusion to painting in Tzanck Check, scripted in the guise of the bank (as the check's backer or guarantor), is not altogether surprising given the affinities of this work with l.h.o.o.q. As respective reproductions of money and art, these works reflect the problem of assigning, defining, and preserving a classical notion of value in the modern context. The emergence of mechanical forms of production redefines economic and artistic modes of production, as modes of reproduction. As a reproduction of money, which also makes claims to be art, the Tzanck Check alludes both to the loss of painting's bite, engineered by industrialization, and also to its potential to prevail by "hanging on by its teeth." Thierry de Duve summarizes the paradoxical relation of the Comb to the history of painting: The work refers to painting as it is both impossible and possible, i.e., on the one hand, felt and judged as doomed by industrialization and therefore having to be actively destroyed or abandoned, and on the other, retaining a potential that lies precisely in its abandon- 170 katftdu? 5 fro Rrose is an independent partner, one who, as president, presumably has authority over Duchamp, who is a mere administrator: "Rrose becomes an author through signing and yet she herself has been 'authored'."32 Duchamp's game with his own authorial persona, Rrose Selavy, legitimizes the bond through the production of a corporate entity whose composite identity is generated by the fiction of his alias, of himself as an other. The collective signatures designating the corporate identity embodied in the bond, which both authenticate and authorize it, here emerge as the punning mirrors of Duchamp's literal embodiment as a corporation. By problematizing his own authority as an artist, through the fictional inscription of an other (be it Rrose, his female counterpart, or the spectator who "makes the picture"), Duchamp reveals the tenuous bond between the author and the work, especially when the work functions as a putative embodiment of the artist. Duchamp's photograph on the Monte Carlo Bond, a self-portrait of his head covered with shaving foam and his hair pulled up into horns, further destabilizes the authority of this financial document. The fact that this bond is framed by the uninterrupted phrase "Moustiquesdomestiques-demistock:i'' (domestic mosquitos half-stock), only adds evidence that the visual appearance of this work might be as unreliable as the signatures backing it up. While Duchamp's appearance, his readiness for a "shave," might be interpreted psychoanalytically as a sign of decapitation or castration, such a premise fails to take into account the fact that the context of this bond involves gambling.33 Could Duchamp's ready-to-be-shaved head be the Joker, that extra card used in certain card games as the highest trump, or in another context the nullifying clause of a legislative measure? What kind of concealed obstruction or difficulty does this image represent, and is the threat of this close shave the sign of a narrow escape? The clue to this image, as in most of Duchamp's works, lies not merely in its visual referent, but in its dis-cursive one as well. To shave means to fleece or cheat, to drive a hard bargain, and in commercial slang it means to buy notes or securities at a discount greater than the legal rate. Is Duchamp's impending "shave" intended to take a barb at the spectator — a pointed joke on himself and others? Having "shaved" the Mona Lisa by taking a reproduction that has not been altered by his graffiti mustache and goatee, Duchamp 780 "spends" this image by putting it into circulation under his own signature. By reinvesting this reproduction with a new kind of "interest," in effect, he "banks" on it, thereby reducing it to a financial issue, a "bond" of sorts. Duchamp and Leonardo become the corporate backers of this reproduction, which now attains an "original" status. Likewise, in the case of the Monte Carlo Bond, Duchamp's hint at "shaving" himself suggests a clue as to how he might be "shaving" (cheating or fleecing) the spectator. The threat of his impending "shave" implies restoring his own image to its female counterpart, Rrose Selavy. This act of restoration, however, does not lead to the uncovering of an original but that of an alias (a reproduction), whose financial authority is backed by the fictitious corporate identity of Duchamp/Rrose Selavy. Duchamp's calling card (and perhaps his business card, as well) introduces him as "precision oculism/ rrose selavy/ New York-Paris/ complete line of whiskers and kicks" [Oculisme de Precision/ Foils et Coups de Fieds en Tous Genres). This dual specialty in precision oculism and whiskers and kicks further emphasizes Duchamp's particular expertise as an artist whose business is visual and linguistic puns. Oculiste sounds like {an culiste, meaning "in the ass" in French), yet another allusion to Duchamp's 1..h.o.o.q., thereby attesting to Rrose's specialization in precision ass and glass work. Whiskers and kicks refer to Duchamp's pointed barbs at tradition, his travesties of the Mona Lisa "shaved" and "unshaved." As Michel Sanouillet and Elmer Peterson point out, "Duchamp hardly ever misses a chance to boot us in the rear when we are reverently bent over examining and explicating his work" (dmd, 105). Rather than identifying its carrier, this calling card thus establishes Duchamp's particular intervention as an artist of multiple embodiments: his interrogation of the visual (ocular) invariably sets the spectator into motion by forcing him/her to stumble through puns. Robert Lebel points out that Duchamp "cheerfully masqueraded as an American style 'businessman'." He participated in the management of a cleaning and dyeing establishment, simply because it allowed him to designate himself as a "tinter" (a pun on peintre [painter] and teinturier [dyer]).34 Thus, while it may seem that Duchamp is abandoning art when he turns to issuing bonds, this gesture emerges as yet another attempt to rethink art in speculative terms. 78? The public reception of Duchamp's bond verifies the speculative conflation of the artistic and the economic. Duchamp's issue of the Monte Carlo Bond was immediately valued not for its financial interest but as an artistic investment. In The Little Review (New York, Fall-Winter, 192/4-25) we find an account of the public's reaction to this work: If anyone is in the business of buying art curiosities as an investment, here is a chance to invest in the perfect masterpiece. Marcel's signature alone is worth much more than the 500 francs asked for the share. Marcel has given up painting entirely and has devoted most of his time to chess in the last few years. He will go to Monte Carlo early in January to begin the operation of his new company. (tod, 185) This account of Duchamp's work indicates that the "interest" of the public is not focused on the "interest" bearing possibilities of the bond but rather on the value of this work as an art investment, guaranteed by Duchamp's signature. Given the fact that Duchamp "gave up" painting, buying a bond assures getting a "masterpiece," since the artistic value of this limited edition work is guaranteed to exceed its actual value as a financial investment. The interest bearing value of this work as art exceeds its reality as financial security by invoking contingencies that extend beyond the authority and life of the artist into the speculative futures of posterity. In order to illuminate the artistic implications of the Monte Carlo Bond it is important to consider Duchamp's letter to Jean Crotti (17 August 1952.). In this letter Duchamp explains that artists are like gamblers, and that their reputation is made by the chance encounter of the work with the spectator: Artists throughout history are like gamblers in Monte Carlo and in the blind lottery some are picked out while others are ruined. .„. . It all happens according to random chance. Artists who during their lifetime manage to get their stuff noticed are excellent travelling salesmen, but that does not guarantee a thing as far as the immortality of their work is concerned.3-^ 18 1 I ! By identifying artists with gamblers in a blind lottery, Duchamp underlines the arbitrary way in which value is generated by the artwork. The successful artists are like traveling salesmen, able to capitalize on their chance encounters with the spectator, in order to valorize their work. By defining the viewer as someone who "makes the picture" alongside with | the artist, Duchamp inscribes the work within a circuit of symbolic exchange. The artwork is thus redefined: it is neither an independent object nor does it belong to the author any more than the viewer. The artistic value of the work cannot be isolated from its social context: its display, consumption, and circulation. This is why "Posterity is a form of the spectator" (dmd, 76). This redefinition of the artistic process as a gamble, which relies on the regard, or rather, "interest" of the spectator, leads to a radical challenge of the autonomy of painting as a discipline. As Duchamp explains to Crotti: "I don't believe in painting itself. Painting is made not by the painter but by those who look at it and accord it their favors; in other words, there is no painter who knows himself or is aware of what he is doing."36 The authority of painting is fractured by the fact that the artist alone cannot confer value on a work. The appeal to the tradition, to those works whose value is ensured by the museum, is unreliable to the extent that the exhibition value of the work depends on institutional considerations. A last resort to individual judgment is also doomed to failure, since neither self-knowledge nor self-discipline can guarantee the future "interest" of the work. As Duchamp points out to Crotti, "don't judge your own work, since you are the last person to see it truly (auec des vrais yeux). What you see is not what makes it praiseworthy or unpraisewor-thy."37 The individual judgment of the artist is shaped by the authority of one's education or one's reaction against it. Thus the effort to evaluate the work reveals the artist's subjective limits, the extent to which they are arbitrarily mediated by institutional givens. Duchamp's refusal of aestheticism, the belief in painting for its own sake, is visible in Duchamp's earliest attempts to move away from painting and toward mechanical drawing and experiments with chance operations. The Monte Carlo Bond is issued in order to test a formula for turning the odds at roulette in the player's favor by "pitting the logic of chess against the luck of the gaming tables."3*' This work may be considered as 1 yet another instance of Duchamp's efforts to "can chance," as in Three Standard Stoppages and Dust Breeding (the photograph of dust in the region of the Sieves on the Large Glass). The Monte Carlo Bond represents a deliberate effort to examine the speculative gamble entailed by both financial and artistic endeavors.39 If the logic of chess is invoked in the context of this financial and artistic parody, this is by no means accidental, given the punning relation of chess (jeu d'echecs) to checks (jeu des cheques).40 How can the "logic" of chess be pitted against the "luck" of the roulette table? As we have shown earlier, Duchamp sees chess as a "visual and plastic thing," that is, not purely geometric, since it moves — "it's a drawing, it's a mechanical reality" (dmd, 18). According to Duchamp, playing a game of chess is "like designing something or constructing a mechanism of some kind by which you win or lose" (wmd, 136). In chess this mechanism is constituted by a strategy (a set of moves or decisions) of two opponents, who, in order to play, must literally put their "heads together." The case of roulette, however, is closer, as Hubert Damisch notes, to a head or tails game.41 Yet roulette is more than a game of chance, since at each moment the player must decide on a number and a color.42 But despite its arbitrary character, betting is often handled like chess, through predetermined strategies attempting to contain the chance element through the number of moves.43 The Monte Carlo Bond is issued by Duchamp to raise funds for a betting system for the roulette, which Duchamp describes as follows: It's delicious monotony without the least emotion. The problem consists in finding the red and black figure to set against the roulette. . . . The Martingale is without importance. They are all either completely good or completely bad. But with the right number even a bad Martingale can work and I think I've found the right number. You see I haven't quit being a painter, now I'm drawing on chance, {wmd, 187; emphasis added)44 Duchamp's attempts literally to "draw on chance" [dessiner stir le hasard) can be understood as an effort to recognize its plastic character by outlining its mechanism through a number of moves, thus, containing it through a calculus of probability.45 Rather than functioning as an invocation of pure contingency, chance, for Duchamp, is contextually defined, like value. Betting strategies have no meaning in and of themselves; they are indifferent. What matters, on the contrary, is the fact that these betting mechanisms contextualize chance, by literally "drawing" it in. The monotony of repeating a set of moves, with very small variations, uncovers the strategic and transitory outline of chance, an imprint of its fugitive passage. Duchamp's financial gambit stages his artistic gamble as an artist whose reputation is, like life itself, "on credit." If art is a blind gamble, then the Monte Carlo Bond represents the obligation: it is a guaranteed interest-bearing certificate. As a speculative financial instrument, this bond provides the strategic mechanism for addressing the question of "interest" art. As Duchamp explains in a letter to Jacques Doucet (Paris, 16 January 1925): "Don't be too skeptical, since this time I believe I have eliminated the word chance. I would like to force the roulette to become a game of chess. A claim and its consequences: but I would like so much to pay my dividends" (wmd, 187-88). Duchamp's belief to have eliminated chance corresponds to his efforts to "can chance" (hasard en conserve), by conserving or containing it. Duchamp's gesture emerges as a challenge to Stephane Mallarme's statement that "a throw of dice will never abolish chance." At issue for Duchamp is not the abolition of chance (which has little meaning) but rather, the effort to foil it by "canning" it, that is, preserving it as a strategic gesture particular to a set of determinations. Thus Duchamp's "canning" is also another way of "drawing" (dessiner) on chance, like drawing checks (or drafts) on a bank. The Monte Carlo Bond enacts, in its "interest" generating potential as a financial document, the gamble that the artist is engaged in, in terms both of the artistic medium, and of the history and traditions that validate the work. If Duchamp is able to issue bonds as a way of securing and guaranteeing dividends on his "interest," this is because while art may be a gamble, the contextual logic of its operations is like a chess game. If we recall Duchamp's advice to John Cage, "Don't just play your side of the game, play both sides," we begin to see that Duchamp's success in "drawing on chance" is the result of playing the game of art from both sides, interchangeably and simultaneously as artist and spectator.46 ft r { ft>\