Ethical Anxieties Ethical Anxieties Justifying geo-research At its core, climate engineering is a moral question. The same is true of all major environmental disputes - over nuclear power, genetically modified organisms and lead pollution. Each controversy has been driven by ethical arguments. In the case of geoengineering the moral landscape is only just beginning to be recognized. In his 2006 intervention Paul Crutzen wrote: 'By far the preferred way to resolve the policy makers' dilemma is to lower the emissions of the greenhouse gases. However, so far, attempts in that direction have been grossly unsuccessful.'1 The starting point for any consideration of the ethics of geoengineering is this failure of the world community to respond to the scientific warnings about the dangers of global warming by cutting greenhouse gas emissions. When I say it is a failure of the 'world community' this should not obscure the fact that it has been certain powerful nations, and certain powerful groups within those nations, that have been responsible for this failure.2 As we will see, not all those promoting geoengineering research and deployment view it as a response to moral failure, so it helps to set out briefly the 158 ments in favour of research into geoengineering. I will refer jjnly t0 tne case °^ su'phate aeros°l injections because it illus-the ethical anxieties most starkly. Some of the arguments traits 3pp|y equally to the other system-altering technologies, notably ,-ean iron fertilization and marine cloud brightening, but may tjve less force when applied to more localized interventions. Three main justifications are used to defend research into geoengineering and possible deployment: it will allow us to buy time, it will allow us to respond to a climate emergency and it may be the best option economically. The buying-time argument - the main one used in favour of nl0re research in the 2009 Royal Society report3 - is based on an understanding of the failure to cut global emissions as arising either from political paralysis or from the power of vested interests. The logjam can only be broken by the development of a substantially cheaper alternative to fossil energy because countries will then adopt the new technologies for self-interested reasons. Sulphate aerosol spraying would allow warming to be controlled while this process unfolds. It is therefore a necessary evil deployed to head off a greater evil, the damage due to unchecked global warming. It is a powerful, pragmatic ethical argument for research into geoengineering and its possible deployment. The climate emergency argument was Crutzens motive for breaking the silence over geoengineering. Sulphate aerosol injection, he wrote, should only be developed 'to create a possibility to combat potentially drastic climate heating'.4 Today it is an argument growing in influence, reflecting concern about climate tipping points.5 It envisages rapid deployment of a solar filter in response to some actual or imminent abrupt change in world climate that cannot be averted even by the most determined mitigation effort. It's easy to see how, in some circumstances, this argument could be 159 Earthmasters an overwhelming one. Although the solar shield may have backs, failing to deploy it could result in much greater harm As in the case of buying time, the best-option argument woul ^ll by engineering the climate with sulphate aerosol spraying (sorneth' that may prove technically and financially feasible). The Maid ^ for example, would have a strong moral case to argue that the thr ' to its citizens' survival from rising seas caused by the refusal f major emitting nations to change their ways, and its own inability to influence global warming despite sustained efforts, leave it with no choice. Moral hazard It is widely accepted that having more information is uniformly a good thing as it allows better decisions to be made. Geoengineering research is strongly defended on these grounds. Yet for many years research into geoengineering, and even public discussion of it, was frowned on by almost all climate scientists. As we saw, when Paul Crutzen made his famous intervention in 2006 calling for serious study of sulphate aerosol spraying he was heavily criticized by fellow scientists. They felt that investigating climate engineering would erode the incentive to reduce emissions, the response to global warming strongly preferred by scientists, including Crutzen himself. In other words, they were worried about 'moral hazard', a concept developed by economists to capture the impact on incentives of being covered against losses. For example, it is argued that the incentive to drive a car carefully may be reduced if the driver is insured because the costs of an accident are spread across all who are insured. Although commonly used in the climate change context, the argument mistakenly transposes an understanding of incentives developed for private market behaviour into the realm of public policy decision-making. There are a number of ethical 166 f, practical objections to this move,14 perhaps illustrated most rkly ^ unwlttiriS reductio ad absurdum embedded in the im by economist Martin Weitzman that assessing the worth of ■|fe on Earth as we know it' is conceptually analogous' to deciding, r example, how much to pay for additional airbags in a car. Life n Earth itself is converted into a financial value by reducing it to n0w much we'd be willing to pay in the market.15 nevertheless, the idea of moral hazard, suitably modified, is useful for drawing attention to political incentives. The availability 0f an inferior policy substitute that can be made to appear superior may make it easier for a government to act against the national interest.16 It is well established that those whose financial interests would be damaged by abatement policies have been using their power in the political system to slow or prevent action.17 So does geoengineering research create moral hazard? Geoengineering researchers tend to be vague and somewhat dismissive of the likelihood, as though it is only of theoretical concern. The 2009 Royal Society report, dominated by geoengineering researchers, treats it as an uncertain effect that may even work the other way, and refers to some distinctly unpersuasive tbcus group work suggesting that individuals might increase their efforts to cut their emissions if government invested in geoengineering.18 Overall, the report saw moral hazard (wrongly interpreted as concerning individual behaviour) as a 'factor to be taken into account', but in no way decisive. Yet in practice any realistic assessment of how the world works must conclude that geoengineering research is virtually certain to reduce incentives to pursue emission reductions. This is apparent even now, before any substantial publicly funded research programmes have begun. Already a powerful predilection for finding excuses not to cut greenhouse gas emissions is obvious to 167 Earthmasters all, so that any apparently plausible method of getting a party ^ the hook is likely to be seized upon. For the moment, governments and energy companies are staying at arm's length from geoengj neering research, precisely because they fear being accused 0f wanting to evade their responsibilities. But the day when it becomes respectable to support geoengineering research cannot be far 0ff Already, representatives of the fossil fuel industry have begun to talk of geoengineering as a substitute for carbon abatement.19 Economic analysis is in general not interested in the kind of judicious technology mix or emergency back-up defended by some scientists, but will readily conclude that geoengineering should be pursued, even as the sole solution, if that's what the cost curves show. Indeed, the popular but error-riddled book Superfreakonomics insists that the prospect of solar radiation management renders mitigation unnecessary: 'For anyone who loves cheap and simple solutions, things don't get much better.'20 Instrumental thinking does not come much cruder, yet it is just this kind of Promethean wand-waving that prevails in the power centres of the world. For the authors, economics renders ethical concerns redundant: 'So once you eliminate the moralism and the angst, the task of reversing global warming boils down to a straightforward engineering problem: how to get thirty-four gallons per minute of sulfur dioxide into the stratosphere?' We have seen that conservative think tanks are joining the fray, with the climate-denying Heartland Institute and American Enterprise Institute supporting climate engineering. Former Republican presidential candidate and House Speaker Newt Gingrich declared: 'Geoengineering holds forth the promise of addressing global warming concerns for just a few billion dollars a year. Instead of penalizing ordinary Americans, we would have an option to address global warming by rewarding scientific invention ... Bring on the American ingenuity. Stop the green pig.'21 For 1 68 these Ethical Anxieties advocates the problem of moral hazard evaporates because here is nothing wrong with eroding the incentive to cut carbon fissions if a cheaper means of responding to global warming is Gardiner has offered a left-field argument for the irrelevance of conCerns about moral hazard.22 After the Copenhagen fiasco, the aspects for substantial emissions abatement policies in the foreseeable future sank so low that the availability of a substitute to abatement could not drive them any lower. It is an argument from despair. Against it, in some parts of the world - notably the European Union and China - substantial efforts are being made to reduce emissions and accelerate the development of alternative energy technologies. In 2011 parliamentary support for the Australian government's carbon tax was on a knife-edge. Inadequate as they are, these efforts depend on a level of political resolve that could be weakened. Moreover, incentives to act could change rapidly as the effects of climate change become more obvious over the next decade and the availability of an apparently effective alternative to emission cuts could determine the kind of action taken. That in practice moral hazard is the most powerful ethical argument against the development of geoengineering technologies is suggested by the highly germane case of carbon capture and storage (CCS).23 Soon after the 1997 Kyoto agreement, the governments of the two nations that refused to ratify it, the United States and Australia, began talking up the benefits of CCS, a technology that promised to extract carbon dioxide from the smokestacks of coal-fired power plants, pipe it to suitable geological formations and bury it permanently deep beneath the earth. Burning coal would be rendered safe so there was no need to invite 'economic ruin' with policies mandating emission reductions. Quickly branded 'clean coal', the promise of the technology was increasingly relied on by 169 Earthmasters the world coal industry to weaken policy commitments and up its image.24 The promise ot CCS has been used repeatedly t both governments and industry as a justification for buikW & new coal-fired power plants. In the United Kingdom, Prime Minjst Gordon Brown declared that we must have it 'if we are to have m chance of meeting our global goals'.25 US President Barack Obama's public endorsement of clean coal' was featured in PR videos made by the coal lobby.26 German Chancellor Angela Merkel backed industry plans to build dozens of new coal-fired power plants expecting that at some point they would be able to capture the carbon dioxide and send it to subterranean burial sites.2" ln Australia, the world's biggest coal exporter and the nation most dependent on coal for electricity, Prime Minister Kevin Rudd declared CCS critical' to generating jobs and bringing down greenhouse gas emissions.28 Economists also bet on the technological promise. The Stem report called CCS crucial'.29 Jeffrey Sachs, Director of the Earth Institute, repeated the common opinion that there is no way China will stop building coal-fired power plants, so the technology 'had better work or we're in such a big mess we're not going to get out of ■ '30 — it. The Garnaut report wrote that the success of clean coal' will ensure that any negative impacts of greenhouse policies on coal-dependent regions are 'many years away'.31 The International Energy Agency promoted it enthusiastically, describing an ambitious roadmap for the deployment of the technology, to be led over the next decade by developed countries, after which 'CCS technology must also spread rapidly to the developing world', because without it costs of emissions reductions will be 70 per cent higher.32 Torrents of public funding flowed to CCS research. The Obama Administration's 2009 stimulus bill allocated US$3.4 billion and the US Department of Energy announced it would P Ethical Anxieties jg Tjs$2.4 billion to 'expand and accelerate the commercial j loyment °^ carb°n capture and storage technology'.33 In the month, the Rudd government in Australia announced it u|d commit A$2.4 billion (around US$2 billion at the time) to • dnstrial-scale demonstration project.34 In 2009 the high hopes jn in°u vested in CCS provoked the conservative business magazine The economist to comment that 'the idea that clean coal... will save the wL ° vomit if they eat beef, thereby reducing demand for beef The paper, published in a respectable journal, is beyond and its only likely effect is to bring the philosophy profession disrepute. Analytical philosophy, it seems, does not have a test' for filtering out whacky proposals. If we are to engine humans to have cat's eyes and midget babies, why not geneticall modify black people to make them white in order to cool the Earth by increasing its reflectivity? Defending his decision to publish, the editor of the journal claims the authors are engaged in a 'Swiftian philosophical thought experiment'.48 In fact, the opposite is true. Jonathan Swift's 'modest proposal' that poverty-stricken Irish peasants support themselves by selling their babies to be eaten by the rich - a young healthy child well nursed is at a year old a most delicious, nourishing, and wholesome food, whether stewed, roasted, baked, or boiled' - was a savage satire on the heartlessness of society in the face of mass suffering. The three philosophers are not lampooning our disregard of the threat of climate change. It is as if Swift had put forward his modest proposal as a legitimate response to famine. No doubt it could be wholly justified in utilitarian terms; indeed Swift himself carried out the cost-benefit analysis in order to heighten the ridicule. The three bio-ethicists suggest that people who are appalled at the idea of human engineering may have a 'status quo bias', resisting their innovative ideas because of an unthinking conservatism. They seem oblivious to the irony, since their own proposal takes the technofix to a sublime plane, one made possible by an intensely individualistic understanding of the world, which sees 176 Ethical Anxieties lure t0 rcSpond to climate change as arising not from polit-stitutional and cultural forces but from a lack of personal ,er Rarely in intellectual history has such a dire social pleni been so trivialized by this kind of psychologism. The ^ t[,ors are keen to stress they would never compel people to Juce small children or grow cats eyes, which only raises the ^ tion of why anyone who is unwilling to buy a smaller car or tch to green power would be willing to genetically engineer their children. In his critique of the Royal Society's 2009 report on geoengi-eering, Gardiner poses the question bluntly: 'if the problem is jocial and political, why isn't the solution social and political as well [and] if, as the report asserts, we already have adequate scientific and technological solutions, why assume that research on alternative solutions will help?'49 In the end, the answer from geoengineering supporters must lie in an implicit judgement that social change is inconceivable so the only answer is to buy time for the costs of renewable energy technologies to fall far enough or to prepare to deal with an inevitable climate emergency. Yet in investing so much in our ability to take control of the climate are we in danger of attempting to emulate God? Playing God Weapons scientists inside the fence at the Lawrence Livermore National Laboratory were divided from the anti-nuclear protesters at the gates less by their political leanings or religious beliefs than by their commitment to a Promethean as opposed to a Soterian worldview. In a similar way, the concern about Promethean overreach, often known as 'playing God', is not confined to theists but may resonate just as strongly with atheists. For atheists, 'playing 1 77 Earthmasters God' is a metaphor either for humans assuming Godlike a or for mortals attempting to occupy a domain that is not ^ theirs. In the first, the idea is that there are certain qualiti humans cannot and should not aspire to, both because th ^ beyond us and because aspiring to them invites calamity philosopher Tony Coady identifies three attributes of God or godhead that are beyond human capabilities - omniscien omnipotence and supreme benevolence - which seem to captu ' the common sense.M We will return to this meaning. The second interpretation reflects a spatial' metaphysics of the world. Playing God entails humans crossing a boundary to domain of control or causation that is beyond their rightful place In this view, there is a limit to what humans should attempt or aspire to because the division between domains is part of the proper order of things. For theists, this other domain may be the dwelling place of God. For atheists, the domains are contained in an intuitive metaphysical order that defines 'the scheme of things' within which one can find what it means to be human. For both, the idea of staying out of 'God s realm' is an essentially Soterian outlook, sensitive to human shortcomings and the danger of ignoring them. So what in practice is 'God's domain'? In the debate over human genetic enhancement the playing God argument has been prominent. Biologically, DNA is the essence of life, coding all of the information that makes an individual unique. As such, tinkering with genes (and especially the germ-line, or changes to DNA that can be passed on) can be seen by the theist as invading the sacred, or by the atheist as disturbing the essential dignity of the human. Michael Sandel argues that it is the gifted character of human capacities and potentialities that incites a natural reverence, and that there is something hubristic and unworthy about 178 Ethical Anxieties J pting to overrule or improve upon this gift through genetic ement. Manipulating genes to human ends is 'a Promethean tion to remake nature, including human nature, to serve our ^ -ps and satisfy our desires'.*2 Life is reduced to a manipulable genetic code. v The particulars are not ot much help in the case of geoengi-eermg because we are not talking about transforming humans but foe world in which humans live. Yet global dimming via sulphate jer0sol injections is a similarly Promethean aspiration to remake nature' to serve our purposes, this time not at the microscopic jeVel of DNA but at the macroscopic level of the Earth as a whole, ■rhe domain being invaded is not that of the essential code of each life but the sphere in which all life was created or emerged. With solar radiation management the concern is not so much a lack of gratitude for a unique and precious gift, but the invasion of and dominion over the atmosphere that encompasses the planet - the benevolent ring that makes it habitable, supplies the air breathed by all living things and sends the weather. In most cultures for as long as humans have lived, the sky has been the Heavens, the dwelling place of the gods. Global dimming would not only transform the atmosphere but also regulate the light reaching the Earth from the Sun. For some cultures the Sun has its own divine character because it is the source of all growth, the food of plants and thus all living things. It is the origin of the most primordial rhythms that have always governed our lives - the cycles of day and night and the annual seasons. For those cultures the Sun is God, and attempting to regulate it would surely be out of bounds. I mention these cultural facts not because they prove anything but to invoke in the sympathetic reader a feeling for the role of the Sun as a symbol of powers beyond the reach of mortals. The popular preference, revealed by many surveys, for solar energy over nuclear 179 Earthmasters Ethical Anxieties power can probably be traced to a felt distinction between natural gift that flows freely to the Earth and relying 0n an ural and dangerous contrivance that has diabolical conn In general, people are more inclined to endorse technolo>, 1111 • °'es ^at appear to work with, rather than go against, nature.54 So the intuition is that the grander schemes to regulate th climate trespass in a domain properly beyond the human To . ° cross over successfully would require mortals to possess a degree f omniscience and omnipotence that has always been reserved fo God or the great processes of Nature that are rightly beyond human interference. To make matters worse, in this view, we want to supplant the gods in order to counter the mess we have made as faulty humans. Instead of embarking on a vain quest to mimic the gods, it seems safer and more within our powers to face up to our failures and attempt to become better humans. The usual appeals to the power of reason and science make little headway because they are deployed in the service of the same conquering spirit that drives the desire to play God, as if human ratiocination can function as a battering ram to enter the gods' domain, there to dethrone them and elevate humans in their place. So the first argument against mimicking God is not about the dire consequences of entering the domain of the gods, but that playing God betrays a deep fault in the human character. What of the second caution about playing God, that human aspirations to omniscience, omnipotence and benevolence invite calamity? In modern times, we have come to believe that the relentless accumulation of scientific knowledge is taking us closer to total understanding. Recent developments in Earth system science have increased our knowledge substantially, but they have also uncovered cavernous gaps. We have come to see more clearly that the climate system is extremely complex both in itself and because - it cannot be isolated from changes in the other elements Earth system. Human-induced warming is expected to .econfig^ global precipitation patterns, but predictions of reg1 nal rainfall changes are very crude. The importance of tipping that define rapid shifts from one climate state to another point' become apparent from the Earth's geological record, but our ^derstanding of why and when they occur is rudimentary, predicting when or how thresholds might be crossed is extremely imprecise. And how marine ecosystems will respond to acidifying oceans is barely grasped. In this light, omniscience appears as remote as ever. Apart from the uncertainties, unknowns and threshold effects arising from the complexity and non-linearity of the Earth system, the dominant fact is that carbon dioxide persists in the atmosphere for many centuries. So it is possible - indeed, likely - that before the larger impacts of warming are felt, humans will have committed future generations to an irreversibly hostile climate lasting a thousand years. Yet some economists are telling us that they can use their models to estimate future streams of monetary costs and benefits to determine the optimal temperature of the Earth over the next two centuries, as if we know enough to install and begin to operate a 'global thermostat'. Truly this qualifies as monstrous hubris. Humans are powerful, but what kind of power do we aspire to with climate engineering? Beyond deliberate management and exploitation of particular resources or geographical areas, and beyond the unintentional degradation of land, rivers and oceans, we now aspire to take control of and regulate the atmosphere and climate of the planet as a whole. As we will see in the next chapter, geoscientists are now arguing that humans have become a planetary force in their own right. We have so transformed the face of the 180 181 E arthm asters Earth that we have created a new geological epoch, one exp be characterized by more climatic instability than the nr ■ ^'° 1C previoUs In other words, our Promethean aspirations have made the less controllable. If humans were sufficiently omniscient and omnipotent we, like God, use climate engineering methods benevolently? p ^ system science cannot answer this question, but it hardly needs for we know the answer already. Given that humans are proposj to engineer the climate because of a cascade of institutional failin and self-interested behaviours, any suggestions that deployment of a solar shield would be done in a way that fulfilled the strongest principles of justice and compassion would lack credibility, to say the least. We find ourselves in a situation where geoengineering js being proposed because of our penchant for deceiving ourselves and inflating our virtues. If a just global warming solution cannot be found, who can believe in a just geoengineering regime? It is believed that a solar filter would offset some of the impacts of global warming more effectively in some parts of the world than others. In some areas it may even exacerbate droughts. The temptation of those who control the heat shield to manipulate it in a way that suits their interests first would be ever present and almost irresistible. And at no forum will non-human species have a voice. All of these anxieties are deepened by the creeping militarization of geoengineering and the possibility of unilateral deployment. The playing God argument is not necessarily a categorical injunction against solar radiation management, but it does sound a warning about Promethean recklessness, calling for utmost caution and deep reflection. On one view, calculating risks is enough On another, our attitudes and beliefs about ourselves and the nature of the world are so deeply ingrained that they necessarily constrain any calculative thinking to a narrow range of outcomes. According 182 Ethical Anxieties ■an view, if we are so mistaken in our understanding of STTour role in it that we are drawn into playing God t mre of the planet, then thinking must be grounded in a relationship between humans and the natural world, one i,,,L" izes the boundary between the domain of mortals and ^ of the gods. 183