5 In Ada W. Finifltsr, ed. (1993) Pol it tcui Science: The Slate of the Disci pi ine 11 Washington, D.C.: American Political Science Association, The Comparative Method David Collier Comparison is a fundamental tool of analysis. It sharpens our power of description, and plays a centra] role in concept-formation by bringing into focus suggestive similarities and contrasts among cases. Comparison is routinely used in testing hypotheses, and it can contribute to the inductive discovery of new hypotheses and to theory-building. The forms of com|wrison employed in the discipline of political science vary widely and include [hose contained in statistical analysis, experimental research, and historical studies. At the same time, the label "comparative method" has a standard meaning within the discipline and in the social sciences more broadly: it refers to the methodological issues that arise in the systematic analysis of a small number of cases, or a "small N."1 This chapter examines alternative perspectives on the comparative method that have emerged over roughly the past two decades. Although the primary focus is on discussions located in the fields of comparative politics and international studies, the application of the comparative method is by no means restricted to those Ileitis. The decision to analyze only a few cases is strongly influenced by the types of political phenomena under study and how they are conceptualized. Topics for which it is productive to examine relatively few cases include revolutions, particular types of national political regimes (e.g., post-communist regimes), or particular forms of urban political systems. This focus on a small number of cases is adopted because there exist relatively few instances of the phenomenon under consideration that exhibit the attributes of interest to the analyst. Alternatively, some analysts believe that political phenomena in general are best understood through the careful examination of a small number of cases. In the field of comparative and international studies, the practice of focusing on few cases has achieved greater legitimacy in recent years in conjunction with the rise of the school of 'comparative historical analysis," in which small numbers of countries are studied over long periods. This close scrutiny of each country limits the number of national cases a scholar can consider.13 Choosing to study few cases routinely poses (be problem of having more rival explanations to assess than cases to observe, or the quandary of "many variables, small N" (Lijphart 1971, 686). Elementary statistics teaches us that bs the number of explanatory factors approaches the number of cases, the capacity to adjudicate among the explanations through statistical comparison rapidly diminishes. This problem has stimulated much discussion of how most productively to analyze a small N. The late 1960s and early 1970s saw a boom in writing on comparative method (e.g., Merritt and Rolckan 1966; Kalleberg 1966; Verba 1967; Smclser 1968; Lasswell 1968; Przeworski and Teune 1970; Sartori 1970; Merritt 1970; Etzioni and Dubow 1970; Lijphart 1971; VaUier 1971; Zelditch 1971; Armer and Grimshaw 1973). This literature established a set of norms and practices for small-N research, proposed alternative strategies for conducting such analyses, and created a base line of understanding that has played an important role in the ongoing practice of small-N studies. This chapter assesses the issues of comparative method that have been debated in the intervening years and considers their implications for ongoing research. The point of departure is Arcnd Lijphart's (1971) article "Comparative Politics and Comparative Method.* Among the studies published In that period, Lijphart"s piece stands out for its imaginative synthesis of basic issues of comparison and of the relation between comparative method and other branches of methodology.' It therefore provides a helpful framework for examining, and building upon, new developments in the field. A central (heme that emerges in the discussion below is that refinements in methods of small-N analysis have substantially broadened the range of techniques available to comparative researchers. The most fruitful approach is eclectic, one in which scholars are willing and able to draw upon these diverse techniques. 106 The Comparative Method Synopsis of Lijphart Lijphart defines the comparative method as the analysis of a small number of cases, entailing at least two observations, yet too few to permit the application of conventional statistical analysis. A central goal of hi s article is to assess the comparative method in relation to three other methods—experimental, statistical, and case-study—and to evaluate these different approaches by two criteria: 1) how well they achieve the goal of testing theory through adjudicating among rival explanations, and 2) how difficult it is to acquire the data needed to employ each method (see Figure 1). The experimental method has the merit of providing strong criteria for eliminating rival explanations through experimental control, but unfortunately it is impossible to generate appropriate experimental data for most topics relevant to political analysis. The statistical method has the merit of assessing rival explanations through the weaker but still valuable procedure of statistical control, but it is often not feasible to collect a sufficiently large set of reliable data to do this form of analysis. The case-study method has the merit of providing a framework in which a scholar with modest time and resources can generate what may potentially be useful data on a particular case. Unfortunately, opportunities for systematically testing hypotheses are far more limited than with the other methods. Yet Lijphart {pp. £91-93) insists that case studies do make a contribution to testing hypotheses and building theory, and he offers a suggestive typology Df case studies based on the nature of this contribution. He distinguishes among atheoreiical case studies; interpretative case studies (that self-consciously use a theory to illuminate a particular case); hypothesis-generating case studies; theory-confirming case studies; theOry-infirming case studies (that, although they cannot by themselves J: scon firm a theory, can raise doubts about it); and deviant case analyses (that seek to elaborate and refine theory through a close examination of a case that departs from the predictions of an established theory). Lijphart emphasizes that "certain types of case studies can even be considered implicit parts of the comparative method" (p. 691), and to the extent that the assessment of hypotheses does occur in some case studies, it is often because the case studies are placed in an implicit or explicit comparative framework. Yet even within this framework, he emphasizes that findings from a single case should not be given much weight in the evaluation of hypotheses and theory (p. 691). Tbe comparative method, as defined by Lijphart, has an intermediate status in terms of both his criteria. It provides a weaker basis than the experimental or statistical method for evaluating hypotheses, due to the lack of experimental control and the problem of many variables, small N. Yd it does offer a stronger basis For evaluating hypotheses than do case studies. Despite the constraint of addressing more variables than cases, the comparative method allows sysle matic comparison thai, if appropriately utilized, can contribute to adjudicating among rival explanations. Although the data requirements of the L-nmparalive method may be much greater than for cj.se studies, Lijphart argues that they are less demanding than for experimental or statistical research. He therefore views the comparative method as most appropriate in research based on modest resources, and he suggests thai studies using the comparative method might often serve as a first step toward statistical analysis. If at all possible one should generally use the statistical (nr perhaps even the experimental) method instead of the weaker co nspa rative method, But often, given die inevitable scarcity of time, energy, and financial resources, the intensive comparative analysis of a few cases may be more promising than a more superficial statistical analysis of many cases, tn such a situation, the most fruitful approach would be to regard the comparative analysts as the first stage of research, in wliich hypotheses arc carefully formulated, and the statistical analysts as the second stage, in which those hypotheses are tested in as large a sample as possible. . Employ more parsimonious theory : Merit. Eliminates nval j explanations Ihrouoh experimental cc-nirol Inhärent Problem Expenmentai control is impossible for many or most topics of relevance to tieid of comparative politics Statistical Method Merit Assesses nval explanations inrouoh statistical control Inherent Problem: Difficult io colled adequate information in a sufficient number ol cases, due to limited time and resources 108 The Comparative Method other methodologies, and he offers solutions to the characteristic dilemmas of the comparative method. Further Perspectives on Small-N Analysis The two decades following Lijphart's study have seen the emergence of new perspectives on smalls analysis, as well as a renewed focus on methodological alternatives already available before he wrote his article. Though many of these innovations appear in wort explicitly concerned with the comparative method, conventionally understood, others appear in writing on the experimental, statistical, and case-study methods. The result has been an intellectual cross-fertiligation of great benefit to the comparative method. Figure 2 provides an overview of these innovations. Innovations in the Comparative Method Innovations in the comparative method can be discussed in terms of the issues Introduced above, encompassing the goals of comparison, the justification for focusing on few cases, and the problem of many variables, small N. Goals of Comparison A central and legitimate goal of comparative analysis is assessing rival explanations. However, as Theda Skoepol and Margaret Somers (1950) argue, comparative studies should be understood not merely in terms of this single goal, but in terms of three distinct, yet ultimately connected, goals.' The first is that considered above: the systematic examination of covariation among cases for the purpose of causal analysis.1 The second is the examination of a number of cases with the goaj of showing that a particular model or set of concepts usefully illuminates these cases. No real test of the theory occurs, but rather the goal is the parallel demonstration of theory. This use of comparison plays an important role in the process through which theories are developed. The third type of comparison is the examination of two or more cases in order to highlight how different they are, thus establishing a framework for interpreting how parallel processes of change are played out in different ways within each contest. This contrast of contexts is centra] to the more "interpretive" side of the social sciences and reflects yet another way that comparison is frequently used. In addition to providing a more multifaceted account of the goals of comparison, Skoepol and Somers suggest the intriguing idea of a research "cycle* among these approaches (pp. 196-197). This cycle arises in response to the problems that emerge as scholars push each approach up to - or beyond — the limits of its usefulness. For example, a "parallel demonslraiLon" scholar might introduce a new theory and show how it applies to many cases. "Hypothesis-testing" scholars, wanting to specify the conditions under which the theory does not hold, could make further comparisons with the goal of discovering these conditions. Hypothesis-testing studies that loo brashly compare cases that are profoundly different might, in turn, stimulate "contrast of contexts' scholars to examine more carefully the meaning of the differences among the cases. It is thus useful to took beyond an exclusive focus on the role of comparison ia broad causal analysis, to an understanding that encompasses the different elements in this research cycle. This is not to say thai assessing hypotheses does not remain a paramount goal of comparison, and many scholars insist that it is the paramount goal. Yet this broader perspective offers a valuable account of how comparative work proceeds within a larger research community, pointing usefully to the interaction among different goals of comparison. Justification for Small JV A second trend is toward a mors elaborate justification of a focus on relatively few cases. Lijphart's rationale seems in retrospect rather modest, in that it emphasizes only the problem of inadequate resources wid treats the small-N comparison as a way station on the route to more sophisticated statistical analysis. A very different defense of working either with a small N or with case studies had previously been available in arguments favoring a "configurative* approach (Heckscher 1957, 46-51, 85-107), and this perspective was elaborated a few years before the publication of Lijphart's analysis in Sidney Verba's (1967) review essay advocating the "disciplined c-ujfigurative approach.' li: evaluating Robert A. DjhL's Political Oppositions in Western Democracies (1966), Verba points both to the sophistication of the hypotheses entertained in the book and to the difficulty of assessing them adequately, except through a close command of the cases, leading him to advocate this disciplined configurativt! mode of research. Verba's formulation is appealing because he is concerned with systematic hypothesis testing and theory building. At the same uaw, he links this priority with a more explicit appreciation of the difficulty of testing hypotheses adequately and the value of properly executed case studies in providing subtle assessments of hypotheses. It might be claimed thai the difficulty of adequately testing hypotheses ultimately derives from the Collier 105 Figur* 2, Innovations Relevant to the Comparative Method Comparative Method Case Sludy Method New Fi-i!.;jki ioj on Case Studies I. New Oafe-ia* Oi «Nc ^oje imuuv itw;(mCxí (Campboin 2 Relinernerus in Lijonan's typology oi case studies (Eckstein, George) 3 fmprovemen; of causal analysis in case Studies through "process (racing" (George and McKeown| 4. Critique or value ot case studies in assessing rational choice theory (Achen and Snídali Broadened Urtcterstindmo of Type* ot Comparative Studies 1 Emphasis on inierpresrve understanding 2. Idea *ra "research eye le" among the types |SkocpcJ and Somen) Furt tier JutlificaUont lor Focut on B Small-N 1. To pursue "disciplined confiQurative apprqach" (Verba, reinforced by Almond and Genco) 2 To avoid prooiem o1 "conceptual streleh.r.g" (S**ton| 3. To facitisale "thick description" and other forms ot inlerpretiwt understanding (Geertz ana many others) 4. To achieve analytic cepth qt case-oriented approach (Ra-gmj Oebale* on Solutions to Problem ol Many Variables, Sroall-N 1 Value of incroasing number ol cases 2 Comparaofe cases versus contrasting cases (Utfrfiart versus Prraworski and Teune) 3 Reducing number or variables In conjunction with using stronger theory Experimental Utihod Diffusion of Older IdcM arid Introduo Hon of Mew Ideas an GlusJ-EjtpenmBnial D*algn 1. Methodology ot quaii^xpefiiTienls and interrupted time-series design becomes mof e wtdoiy known 2. Analysis of the Connecticut err, >kdcwr. on speeding as exemplar of interrupted time-series analysis (Campbell and Floss) 3. Dffiysion cf iics: about q-jasl-experiments encouraged try codification oi evaluation research 4. Proposed statistical solution 10 problem ot selection bias in quasr-experimenss (Acfwn) Statistical Method New Warnings and New Solutions I Criticism of standard Satirical practice in the social sciences (Freedman) 2. New statistical techmauea relevant to smaJl-N analysis 3 Effort to retirve statistical analysis of a smali-N in the debate on corporatism and economic growih in Western Europe (Lange^Gafrett-JaEkman'Hicks-Patterson) I_____ 110 The Comparative Method problem of limited resources discussed by Lijphart, If enough talented researchers worked long and hard, they could carry out a Political Oppositions study for many dozens of countries. Yet the problem hem is somewhat different from that emphasized in Lijphart's initial formulation. It is not so much that resources arc limited, but that constructing adequate comparisons has proved more difficult than had often been thought in the 1960s and early 1970s, In the initial days of enthusiasm for comparative statistical research. Among these difficulties, that of the valid application of concepts across diverse contexts has been especially vexing. Within the literature on comparative method, a key step in elucidating these problems of Validity, and thereby strengthening the justification for a small N, is Giovanni Sartori's (1970) classic discussion of 'Concept Mis formation in Comparative Politics,' the basic themes of which are elaborated in his later book Social Science Concepts (1984). Sartori suggests that the application of a concept to a broader ranjjc of cases can lead to conceptual 'stretching," as some of the meanings associated with the concept fail to fit the new cases. The concepts that can most easily be applied to a broad range of cases are often so general that they do not bring into focus the similarities arid contrasts among cases that arc essential building blocks in worthwhile comparative analysis. Consequently, a study focused on concepts that are carefully adapted to this "finer slicing" of a given set of cases should be extended to other cases only with great caution. From this perspective, it may be argued that the most interesting studies will often be those that focus on a smaller number of cases. With regard lo the problems of increasing the number of cases untbr study,* Adam Prieworski and Henry Teune1 s Vie Logic of Comparative Social Inquiry (1970) is a major source of insight. Although they argue that achieving a high level of generality should be a basic goal of social science, their framework is centrally concerned with the difficulties that can arise in generalizing beyond an initial set of cases. With regard to problems of validity, they advocate the use, when necessary, of 'system-specific* indicators that serve to operationalize the same, concept in distinct ways in different contexts (pp. 124-130). For the scholar seeking to move toward a larger set of cases, the potential need for system-specific indicators necessitates the close examination of every new case, Przeworski and Teune also address the problem (hat as the analyst incorporates more cases into a study, distinct causal patterns may appear in the new cases. To deal with this problem, Przeworski and Teune advocate "replacing proper names" of social systems by identifying those systems in terms of the explanatory factors that account for why causal relations take a particular form within each system (pp. 26-30).1 This approach makes the invaluable contribution of providing » theoretical, rather than an idiosyncratic and case-specific, basis for analyzing differences in causal patterns. However, extending an analysis to additional cases on the basis of this procedure again requires a painstaking assessment of each new context. Thus, Przeworski and Teune provide a valuable tool for adequately analyzing a larger numher of cases, but their approach again shows that this must be done with caution. Since 1970, the renewal of a Weberian concern with interpretive understanding, i.e., with deciphering the meaning of behavior and institutions to the actors involved, has also strengthened the justification for advancing cautiously with one or very few cases. Clifford Gecrtz's (1973) label "thick description" is commonly evoked to refer to this concern,' and this focus has appeared in many guises relevant to political research, including Gabriel Almond and Stephen I. Genco's analysis of "Clouds and Clocks" (1977) and Skocpol and Somcrs' "contrast of contexts" approach, which encompasses studies that use comparison to richly contextualize research findings. Charles C. Ragin's The Comparative Method (1987) explores another facet oFthis concern in his analysis of the "holistic" orientation of what he calls "case-oriented" research and the complex problems of 'conjunctural causation" — that is, causal pa Items that vary according to the context — to which configurative scholars are typically far more sensitive. Finally, the intellectual success in recent years of the school of comparative historical analysis has played an important role in legitimating a focus on a small N. This approach was pioneered in works such as Reinhartl Bendix (1964), Harrington Moore (1966), and Lipset and Rokkan (1967), and more recent works include Rokkan (1970), Tilly (1975), Paige (1975), Bendix (1978), Trimberger (1978), Skocpol (1979), Bergquist (1986), Luebbert (1991), Goldstone (1991), Collier and Collier (1991) , and Rueschemeyer, Stephens, and Stephens (1992) . Methodological statements focused on this tradition include Skocpol and Somens (1980), Skocpol (1984), Tilly (1984). and Ragin (19S7). The particular form of analysis in these studies varies considerably, as suggested by Skocpol and Somers' typology noted above. In varying combinations, these studies employ both rigorous qualitative comparisons that extend across a number of nations, and also historical analysis that often evaluates each national case over a number of time periods.* This tradition of research thus combines well-thougbt-out comparison with an appreciation of historical context, therehy contributing to an effort to "hisloricize" the social sciences. Although the uses of comparison in this literature are diverse, as Skocpol and Somers emphasized, it may Collier 111 be argued that a major consequence of the growing importance of comparative histories] studies is to further legitimate the approach that was LtjpBart's original concern: the assessment of rival explanations, based on systematic, qualitative comparison of a small number of cases. In light of a spectrum of studies from Barrington Moore's (1966) pioneering analysis of the emergence of alternative forms of modem regimes, to Skocpol's (1979) study of revolution, to Luebberf s (1991) analysis of the emergence of liberalism, fascism, and social democracy in interwar Europe, it is evident that this literature has given new legitimacy to the use of broad historical comparison for systematic causal analysis. Efforts to Codify procedures for assessing hypotheses in this type of analysis, such as that in Ragin's Comparative Method (1987), further reinforce the plausibility of insisting on the viability of small-N analysis as a middle ground between case studies and statistical studies. Solutions to the Problem of Many Variables, Small S The evolving debates on comparative method have suggested further refinements in Lijphart'-S original three solutions lor the problem of many variable-1;, small N, i.e.: 1) increasing the number of cases, 2) focusing on matched cases, and 3) reducing the number of variables. I. Increase the Number of Cases At the time Lijphart wrote, it was believed in some circles that comparative social science would increasingly be oriented toward latge-N comparative studies, based on extensive quantitative data sets and rigorous statistical analysis. Today there can be no question that, for belter or worse, quantitative cross-national research in the subfield of comparative politics, and quantitative international politics in the subfield of international relations, have not come to occupy as dominant a position as many had expected. Within these two subfields, they hold the status of one approach among many. Various factors have placed limits on the success of large-N research based on quantitative data sets, among which is certainly the renewed concern with closely contextual bed analysis and interpretive Studies. Bfoad quantitative comparison may have been set back as many scholars discovered how extraordinarily time-consuming it is to construct appropriate data sets, often out of proportion to the professional rewards that seem to be forthcoming. This is particularly a problem when the focus of analysis extends beyond the advanced industrial countries lo regions for which it is often extremely difficult to develop reliable data, m addition, the quantitative-comparative approach has ptobably been hurt by the publication of too many studies in which concepts are operalionalized with dubious validity and which employ causal tests that are weak, unconvincing, or inappropriate (Ragin 19S7, chap. 4). Vet the fact that broad quantitative comparison has not become a predominant approach should not lead scholars to overlook what has been accomplished. Robert Jackman (1985) insists that comparative statistical research has had more success than is recognized, and Lijphart's own recent work moves La this direction (1990). The failure lo seize good opportunities to do quantitative research could certainly be viewed as being as much of a mistake as premature quantification, and the fruitful debate on corporatism and economic growth in Western Europe discussed below is one of many examples of bow statistical methods can effectively address interesting analytic issues. Further, the availability of new statistical techniques (also discussed below) has made it far more productive to do quantitative analyses with as few as ten to fifteen cases. Consequently, the option of increasing the "N" at least lo that level is still worth pursuing, and it should probably be pursued more often. 2. Focus on Comparable Cases The recommendation that analysts focus on carefully matched cases has been both reinforced and challenged. In a discussion published in the mid-1970s, Lijphart (1975) explores further the trade-off he noted in 1971 between the goal of increasing the number of cases and the goal of matching cases as a substitute for statistical control. Obviously, if a researcher is to select cases that are really similar, however that similarity is defined, the number of appropriate cases is likely to become limited. In the face of this trade-off, Lijphart opts b favor of the more careful matching of fewer cases, and he goes so far as to restrict the application of the term "comparative method" to analyses that focus on a small number of carefully mulched cases. This emphasis parallels a much earlier perspective on the comparative method referred to as the method of "controlled comparison" (Eggan 1954). Arthur Slinchcombe's (1978) advocacy of the methodology of "deep analogy," i.e., the comparative analysis of very few, extremely closely matched, cases pushes this approach even further. A contrasting strategy is advocated by Przeworski and Te-une (1970, 32-39) and Przeworski (1987. 38-41). They suggest that even with careful matching of cases in what tbey label a "most similar" systems design, there remains a problem of "overdetenninatiorj," in that this design fails to eliminate many rival explanations, leaving the researcher with no criteria for choosing among them. They prefer instead a 'most different" systems design, based on a set of cases which are highly diverse and among which the analyst traces similar processes of change,10 Przeworski suggests that the strength of this design is in part 112 The Comparative Method responsible for important advances in the literature on democratization, such as the work of O'Donnell, Schmitter, and Whitehead (19S6). Praeworski maintains that this literature addresses such a broad range of cases that analysts are forced to distill out of that diversity a set of common elements that prove to have great explanatory power.|J This discussion can be placed in perspective by recognizing that cases that are closely matched from one point of view may contrast sharply from another. My own recent work (Collier and Collier 1991) combines the two strategies by starting with a set of eight Latin American countries that arc roughly matched on a number of broad dimensions. Among the eight countries, the analysis focuses on pairs of countries that arc nonetheless markedly different. The overall matching assures that the contexts of analysis are analytically equivalent, at least to a significant degree, and the paired comparison places parallel processes of change in sharp relief because they are operating in settings that are very different in many respects. In conjunction with the debate over the merits of most similar and most differed systems designs, it is important to recognize that in many studies, the conclusions reached in the overall comparison of cases art also assessed — implicitly and sometimes explicitly — through within-case analysis. In the section on case studies below, the discussion of "pattern matching" and "process tracing" suggests some of the forms this takes. It is no coincidence that within the school of comparative historical analysts, findings are often reported in books, rather than articles. Part of the reason is that the presentation of detailed information on each case serves to further validate the conclusions drawn from comparisons across cases. These within-ease comparisons are critical to the viability of small-N analysis. As Stanley Ueberson (1991, 312-315) has correctly insisted, taken by themselves, comparisons across a small number of cases, using either a most similar or a most different systems design, provide a weak basis for causal inference. However, if one considers the role of these internal comparisons, (he "N" is substantially increased, thereby strengthening causal analysis.11 This use of within-case comparison can also help protect the analyst from a problem that arises in the most different systems design, in which countries are matched on the dependent variable and differ in terms of a scries of background variables. Barbara Geddes (1990) has shown that if cases are selected on the basis of scores on the dependent variable, which is how most different systems designs are often carried out, the lack of variance on the outcome to be explained introduces a 'selection bias" that can greatly weaken causal inference. One way of mitigating this problem is to introduce greater variability through internal comparison. The ongoing debate on most similar versus most different systems designs has implications for the staius of area studies. Dankwart Rustow (1968) argued some time ago in favor of moving beyond an area studies approach, and many scholars agree that cases should bo selected in response to the analytic requirements of particular research projects, rather than on the basis of a geographic proximity that at best is often a poor substitute for the analytic matching of cases. Recent "cross-area" studies on successful export-led growth and on democracy suggest that this alternative pen>pective is gaining ground." However, the area studies approach is a booming business today for a variety of reasons, including the impressive fund In £ of area studies by U.S. foundations in recent decades, as well as institutional momentum. In fact, from the point of view of the theoretically oriented small-N comparativist, this is not a bad outcome. The country case studies produced by area specialists are crucial building blocks in mast comparative work, and without them cross-area studies would be on far weaker ground. It is essential to recognise that these case studio benefit greatly from the intellectual leverage gained when individual scholars develop, over many years, a cumulative and well-contextualized understanding of a particular region. Particularly in light of current concerns that broad comparative studies should be attentive to the context of analysis, the contribution of area specialists is essential. 3. Reduce the Number of Variables: The third solution to the small-N problem is to reduce the number of explanatory factors, either through combining variables, sometimes referred to as "data reduction," or through employing a theoretical perspective that focuses On a smaller set of explanatory factors. One of the promising sources of parsimonious explanatory theory is the "rational choice' approach that has gained increasing attention among political scientists. Rational choice modeling offers a productive means of simplifying arguments that contain a multitude of interesting variables, but that may fail to specify the most critical ones. Within the field of comparative analysis, Geddes's (1991) study of administrative reform in Latin America, which models the impact of different electoral and party systems on the incentives of legislators to adopt reform, provides an excellent example of a productive simplification of a complex topic. As such models gain increasing acceptance in the comparative field, analysts will acquire a useful tool for addressing the sruall-N problem.14 More work on concept formation is also needed, notwithstanding the sustained contribution of Sartori Collier 113 (1970, 1984, 1991. 1993, and Sartnri, Riggs, and Tetine 1975); the work of authors such as McKinney (1966), Kalleberg (1966), and DeFelice (1980); and also Burger's (1976) invaluable synthesis of the Weberian approach to concept formation. Comparativists do not devote enough attention to thinking through how well or poorly concepts are- serving them and therefore may have insufficient ground for knowing whether they arc making appropriate choices in the effort to achieve theoretical parsimony. The field of cognitive science has recently provided insights into categorization that may be useful in refining the concepts employed in comparative studies. The application of these insights is illustrated by George Lakoffs {1987) challenge to frameworks, such as that of Sartori, that employ what I^akoff calls "classical categorization," in which the meaning of concepts is understood in terms of defining characteristics that are seen as giving the concepts well-defined boundaries. This understanding is crucial to Sartori's framework, in that the probkm of conceptual stretching which he analyzes hinges on these boundaries. Cognitive scientists argue that in ordinary language, the meaning of concepts derives not from defining characteristics, but from an implicit "cognitive model" that underlies the concept and from "exemplar' cases that serve to anchor the concept's meaning and provide a point of reference for identifying better and worse cases. This perspective provides a different view of the question of boundaries, and hence of conceptual stretching. More work is needed to discover the degree to which these patterns in ordinary language are also present in social science usage, and if so, the implications for the use of concepts in comparative analysis (see Collier and Mahon 1993). Innovations Suggested by Work on Other Methods Experimental Method Although the experimental method itself may 1« of little relevance to the topics addressed in most comparative research, ideas derived from the experimental method can improve small-N studies. Donald Campbell and Julian Stanley's classic Experimental and Quasi-Experimental Designs for Research (1963) shows how the logic of experimental design can be applied to "quasi-experiments," that is, to "observational" studies that include some event or innovation that has a form analogous to an experimental intervention, but that occurs in a "natural" setting. An example would be the initiation of a new public policy whose impact one wishes to assess. Campbell and Stanley underline the great value in quasi-experiments of the "interrupted time series" design. In this design the analyst looks si a long series of observations over time, so that the values of the observed variable are examined not only at two points immediatety before and after the policy change or other innovation (which "interrupts" the series), but also well before and well after. To illustrate the risk of restricting the analysis to these two observations, the authors present several hypothetical eon figurations of data in which restricting the analysis to two observations leads to a finding of sharp discontinuity, whereas the full time series reveals continuity. Causal inferences about the impact of discrete events can be risky without an extended series of observations. Comparativists employing small-N analysis must heed this warning, since they routinely analyze the impact of discrete events, ranging from wars, revolutions, and military coups to specific public policies. Donald Campbell and Laurence Ross's (1968) subsequent analysis of the impact on traffic fatalities of the Connecticut crackdown on speeding in the 1950s provides a Stunning "exemplar" of the muginative application of a quasi expei ji.;. i.!.:- design to public policy analysis. Indeed, Przeworski (1987. 31) has argued that methodology is influenced far more by exemplars than by formal attempts to "legislate" correct methods, and the Connecticut crackdown article has certainly played that role." The case appears to be a simple one. When the State of Connecticut initiated strict enforcement of the vehicular speed limit in the 1950s and traffic deaths dropped sharply, the cause and effect relationship seemed obvious. Yet in evaluating this causal link, Campbell and Ross do an impressive analysis of potential threats to its "internal validity" (was that really the cause in Connecticut?) and its "external validity" (can the finding be generalized?). No sensitive analyst can read this article without acquiring a more sober view of the problems of evaluating policy impacts. IdeiiS about quasi-experimental and interrupted time series design have also been disseminated through the large body of writing on evaluation research. This includes studies that apply these ideas to the analysis of political development (Hoole 1978), as well as excellent treatments of experimental design and evaluation research in introductory textbooks on social science methodology, such as Babbie (1992). Although much writing on quasi-experiments appears to offer helpful guidance and practical advice to small-N' analysts, Christopher H. Aehen's Die Statistical Analysis of Quasi-Experiments (1986) may leave them feeling that the methodological challenges posed by this type of design are overwhelming. In studies of (ho impact of public policy, the core problem is the lack of "randomization" in the application of the policy, which 114 The Comparative Method may result in selection bias. For example, the benefits of a policy are commonly received by some groups and not by others, on the basis of certain attributes possessed by the groups, and it is possible that these prior attributes will themselves reinforce the outcomes that the policy seeks to promote. In the absence of true experimental data, this poses the challenge of disentangling the impact of the policy from the impact of these prior attributes. This causal riddle can be addressed by constructing a model of how citizens are selected to be recipients of the policy. This model then becomes a building block in the analysis of the policy's impact, in that these prior considerations can be "factored out" in assessing the policy. Achen shows that solving the riddle requires a complex form of "two-stage" statistical analysis. The implications of Achen's book may be discouraging for analysts working with a small number of cases. An adequate solution to the lack of randomization requires a form of statistical analysis which can ba applied to an elaborate quantitative data set, but this technique would be hard to apply in a small-N study. A more hopeful view might be that the literature on experiments and quasi-experiments at least provides useful warnings about the peri la of analyzing discrete events as if they were true experimental interventions. In the absence of appropriate data sets, the researcher mast exercise caution in making causal claims. Innovations in Statistics Recent work on statistical analysis has provided both new warnings about the risks of statistical studies and new opportunities for doing meaningful statistical wort with relatively modest case bases. The statistician David Freedman has launched a major assault on the use of multivariate quantitative analysis in the social sciences (1987, 1991), which he claims foils because the underlying research design is generally inadequate and because the data employed fail to meet the assumptions of the statistical techniques. His criticism may bring considerable satisfaction to those who have been skeptical about statistics all along and who take comfort in the greater "control" of the material they feel derives from analyzing relatively few cases through more qualitative techniques. It is realistic to expect that we may go through a period of greater questioning of the use of statistics in the social sciences. However, as with the rejection of quantitative cross-nationai research discussed above, it would be unfortunate if a reaction against quantitative studies went too far. The emergence of new statistical techniques that arc helpful in the analysis of relatively few cases makes such a blanket rejection unwarranted. One example is the development of "resampling strategies" such as the 'bootstrap" and "jackknife" (Diaconis and Efron 1983, Mooney and Duval 1992), These techniques use computer simulation to create, from an initial set of real data, a large number of hypothetical replications of the study, which can then be used in statistical tests that are not as vulnerable to violations of distributional assumptions as are more conventional tests. These techniques may be especially useful when there is great heterogeneity among units, as may readily occur in Cross-national comparisons. The development of "robust" and "resistant" statistical measures (Hampel et al. 1987; Hartwig 1979. Mosteller and Tukey 1977) is promising in much the same way. These measures are relatively unaffected by extreme or deviant values and can therefore help overcome the problem in small-N analysis that findings may be seriously distorted by a single observation that is greatly in error. Another set of techniques concerned with this same problem is 'regression diagnostics' (Eollen and Jackman 1985; Jackman 1987), These axe tests used in conjunction with conventional regression analysis to assess whether unusual values on particular observations, called influential cases, have distorted the findings. The advantage of regression diagnostics in comparison with robust and resistant statistics is that one can employ them with the more familiar coefficients associated with regression analysis. The use of regression diagnostics is nicely illustrated in the recent debate on the relationship between corporatism and economic growth in 15 Western European countries (Lange and Garrett 19S5, 19S7; Jaclcman 1987, 1989; Hicks 1988; Hicks and Patterson 1989; Garrett and Lange 1989), The starting point of this debate is Peter Lange and Geoffrey Garrett's 1985 article, which presents an interesting and complex idea in a simple form. They argue that the organizational strength of unions in the labor market and the political strength of the left in the electoral and governmental arenas both have an impact on economic growth, but that this impact is shaped by a complex interplay between these two factors, which they represent through an * interaction" term in their regression analysis of the 15 cases. In a reanalysis of their article, Robert W. Jackman (1987) employs regression diagnostics to examine certain influential cases that he believes distort their findings. In the ensuing discussions among these five authors, an expanded model with further control variables is proposed, this expanded model is both challenged and defended, and Lange and Garrett subsequently defend their original model and call for new data and further tests. This scholarly debate brings together an important substantive problem, a high level of area expertise and knowledge of specific cases, the inventive Collier 115 use of a relatively straightforward statistical model, a constructive critique based on regression diagnostics, and a sustained process of cumulative knowledge generation based on the scrutiny of a shared data set. Just as the Campbell and Ross article on the Connecticut speeding crackdown is an exemplar of a quasi -experimental design, this debate should stand as an exemplar of a methodologically sophisticated effort by several scholars to solve an important problem within the framework of small-N quantitative analysis, This debate also shows that although an "N" of 15 might often be approached through qualitative small-N comparison, it can likewise be subjected to statistical analysis, with interesting results. Another area in which potential problems of statistical analysis are amenable to solution concerns the issue of "average effects" in regression studies. The results of the simpler forms of regression analysis are based on an average of the strength of causal relations across the cases being studied. For the coefficients produced by regression analysis to be meaningful, it is necessary that these causal relations be homogeneous across the cases. Yet Ragin (1987, chap. 4), among others, has forcefully argued that (his assumption commonly does not hold, given the complex forms of "multiple cortjuncrural causation" often encountered in comparative studies. In different contexts of analysis, the interaction among causal factors may vary. However, solutions to this problem are available. John E. Jackson (1992) shows how it can be addressed wilh advanced statistical techniques, and the interaction term in the I.ange-Garret[ regression analysis, discussed above, deals with precisely this problem: that the effect of one explanatory factor varies depending on the value of another explanatory factor. Finally, Przeworski and Teune's procedure of "replacing proper names," also discussed above, takes this problem of causal complexity and turns it into an opportunity to deal more theoretically with the diversity of causal patterns. Innovations in the Case-Study Method When Lijphart wrote his 1971 article, he apparently felt some hesitation about including a discussion of case- studies in an assessment of the comparative method.1* Yet the two topics are closely linked, and his helpful typology of the uses of case studies in hypothesis testing and theory building set the stage for refinements in case study analysis later introduced by other scholars. One of the most suggestive discussions of the case-study method is that of Campbell (1975). He dramatically recants the bold assertion he made in his earlier hook with Stanley that "one-shot" case studies arc "of almost no scientific value" (1963, 7). He shows instead that case studies are the basis of most comparative research, that they offer many more opportunities than is often recognized for falsifying the researcher's main hypotheses, and that much can be learned from making explicit the comparisons that are often implicitly built into case studies. For example, any given hypothesis about a case has implications for many facets of the case. Campbell uses the label "pattern matching* to refer to the process of discovering whether these implications are real bled. The analyst can thereby increase the "N" by multiplying the opportunities to test hypotheses -within what may initially have been viewed as a "single" case. This procedure of pattern matching is helpful in addressing the long-standing concern that case studies are useful for generating hypotheses, but that the same case cannot then be used to test the hypothesis because it offers no possibility of discontinuation. This is sometimes referred to as the problem of ex post facto hypotheses.LT The procedure of pattern matching opens the possibility that an hypothesis initially generated by a particular case could subsequently fail to be supported by the same case, Thus, the problem of ex post facto hypotheses can be partially overcome." Harry Eckstein (1975, 113-123) is likewise concerned with testing, as opposed to generating, hypotheses in case-study analysis, and he argues forcefully that many analysts have greatly underestimated the value of case studies for hypothesis testing. La particular, the carefully constructed analysis of a "critical case* — for example, one about which the analyst has particularly strong expectations that it will fit the hypothesized causal pattern — can provide an invaluable opportunity to falsify the relevant hypothesis. Alexander George and Timothy McKeown (1985), building on George (1979), present a helpful synthesis of two key building blocks in the process through which hypotheses are tested in case studies. The first corresponds to the conventional approach to placing a case in comparative perspective, which they catl the ■congruence procedure." The scbolar examines the values of an hypothesized independent and dependent variable for a given case and detennines, in light of explicit or implicit comparison with other cases, whether these values are consistent with the predictions of the hypothesis under consideration (pp. 29-30). The second is "process-tracing," through which the researcher engages in a close processual analysis of the Unfolding of events over time within the case (pp. 34^1). The goal is to assesses whether the dynamics of change within each case plausibly reflect the same causal pattern suggested by the comparative appraisal of the case in relation to other cases. Process tracing may be seen as a specific instance of Campbell's patten) matching, and as with 116 The Comparative Method pattern matching the analyst makes a series of within-case observations against which the hypothesis can be further assessed. Overall, these articles, along with works such as Robert K- Yin's Case Study Research (1984), offer a systemaliialiOn of Case-study procedures that provide a valuable poult of reference for scholars concerned with small-N analysts. At the same time, the debate continues On the proper role of case studies in assessing and building theory. An interesting part of this debate, published as a special issue of the journal World Politics (1985) focuses on the contribution of case studies to evaluating one application of rational choice analysis, i.e., rational deterrence theory in international relations. The opening article by Achen and Snidal (1989) argues that the case studies employed by many international relations specialists do not adequately address the central ideas of this body of theory, thereby raising an issue perhaps not often enough considered in discussions of the comparative method: How can the methodological concern with executing good comparisons be linked (o the key analytic issues posed by the particular theories thai W- evaluated? Achen and Said?I also nolc the problem of selection bias in case studies of deterrence theory, that is, the problem that case studies usually focus on deterrence failure, whereas much or most of the time deterrence works. The issue of (he journal includes a series of articles by scholars close to the case-study tradition who debate the issues raised by Achen and Snidal. These articles constitute a valuable efrort to (hint through how case studies have functioned in relation to (he assessment of a particular Ivody of theory, a line of inquiry that should be taken up more often. In this debate on deterrence theory, an intellectual tension emerges that has been a recurring theme in this chapter: between analyses that Seek to achieve t generic understanding, based on relatively few variables and encompassing many cases, as opposed to analyses that seek to draw out the complexities of particular cases. Conclusion Among the diverse approaches discussed in this chapter three major analytic alternatives stand out. First, new perspectives on the case-Study method have strengthened the viability of that approach- Discussions of opportunities for within-case comparisons have in fact begun to blur Ihe distinction between case studies and the comparative method, although the case-study approach does remain a distinct tradition. Interest in case studies has been reinforced by several factors, including the renewed concern with interpretive .social science, the continuing intellectual and institutional strength of arei Studies, and deep skepticism in some circles about ui« validity of broad comparison. Second, it is evident that quantitative tecuniqUcg employing a relatively small number of c^ms can successfully address important substantive quesliorjs. This approach merits attention in light of the tteiv statistical tests suitable for small-N analysis. The C^portunity for cumulative scholarly learning provided by statistical studies is nicely illustrated by the Lange-Garrett-Jackioan-Hicks-Pfltterson debate. This debate is also relevant to the issue of linking rival research traditions, because it shows that insights derived from case studies and from more qualitative comparative work can, after all, serve as stepping-stones on the path toward statistical analysis. The third alternative has been rein forced as well.1 the systematic comparison of a small number of cases, with the goal of causal analysis, which is the approach that Ujpbart originally advocated. In this perspective, broad qualitative comparison is seen as both possible and productive. The growing influence of [he school of comparative historical analysis has substantially enhanced the credibility of this approach, and it plays an important rolu as an analytic middle ground between the case-study tradition and small-N statistical analysis. Al! Ihree of these approaches will persist, and a key question is how well they can be linked. The tradition of research on Western Europe provides an encouraging model, in that the findings of quantitative comparative scholars play an important role in general debates in thai field,1' In research on Latin America, by contrast, quantitative comparative work receives considerably less attention from mainstream scholars. Yet the kind of cross-fertilization found in the West European field can make an important contribution to strengthening research. With good communication, country specialists and experts in qualitative small-N comparison can push the comparative quantifiers toward more carefully conifixtualized analysis. Likewise, the comparative quantifiers can push the country specialists and experts 10 qualitative comparison toward more systematic jueaju re merit and hypothesis testing. A central goal must be to sustain) such communication. Th] Berkeley. Finally. I would like lů note a very producing; manuscript (King, Verba, and Keohane 1991) that unfortunately rime to my attention too late 1« be discussed in Ihii chapter. 1. "N' is used lo refer to Lhc number of ceacs analyzed In any given study. 2. Reference* il> rtpresenfalive work* of comparative tiK-iO: i.-si analyiis are presented below. 3. Jr. .1» compsrisosof these ixsVsikta, Lijphirt acknowledges hit debt in Scnclier's (1968) excellent analysis that employed a parallel framework. See also Smelser (197Ů). 4. This perspective has been elaborated by Skocpol (1984. chap. 11). and a parallel formulation ia found in Charles Tilly (1984, chap 4). 5. SJcocpůt and Somen (1940, 181-ST) refer to this at 'macro-causal' analyiii- Y~el imall-N studies that generate and leu hypothec! can have íiťith a macro and a micro focus, and Ii doer not aeem productive to exclude from this category (hose with a micro focus Hence, (his alternative label ia used, 6. Although Przeworski and Teupe are centrally concerned with issues that arise when additional caw* are added io an analysis, the problems ihey diicuss are also more likely lo occur if one is deeiinj with a larger N to begin with. 7. For example, imlead of referring to "Venezuela," one would refer to » country in which, due to the intpact of nvaaa-ive oil revenue), a particular causal relationship assumes a distinct {arm. 8. Thick description' ii sometimes mistakenly understood (o refer simply lo "detailed description," which ii not what Geirtz intends. 9. Given that thete studies often focus on long perioda of lime within each esse, il might be argued that (he number of use* could be greedy Lureasi J through Cfintnarison over lime, (hereby making (hem something other (hin imall-N studies. However, since the (Oil of many studies in this tradition is to explain overall configurations of national outcomes aa they are manifested over long periods, these outcomes often cannot be disaggregated into a series of longitudinal observations, Hence, the number of cases cannot realistically be increaaed ihr-HJgh the use of comparison over lime. 10. The most similar and most different systems design* correspond, respectively, to John Stuart Mill's (1974) method of difference and method of agreement. Whereas PV/eworskJ and Teune'i labels of "similar" and 'different" refer to whether (he ease* ate matched, as opposed (o contrasting, oo a aeries of bockgn >utiJ vai Lslilc i. Mill's labels of "difference" and 'agreement' refer to whefhrr the eases are contrasting, aa opposed to matched, on lbe dependent variable, 11. Peraonal communication from Adam Przeworaki, 12. Christopher Achen, personal ccrcnmufůcatjon, has long insisted, e-rt this poisst. 13. For example, GcrefE and Wyman (1990). Haggard (1990), Przewurakj (1991), and RuescbtJWVer, Stephens, snd Stephens (1992). 14. For a discussion of strategic choice models (a elotcly related type of model) thai have been applied to (he analysis of political reform, democratization, and democratic consolidation in Latin America, and that likewise offer fruitful sitttplificationa of complex phenomena, aee Collier and Norden (1992). 15. The reprinting of this article in a reader on social science methodology (Tunc 1970) made il widely available to political sciential*, «n.J Eta influence has been aubstantial. 16. Persona! communication from Arend JJjphart. 1?. This problem is routinely discussed in introductory methodology tens, e.g.. Babbie (1992, 24-23. 427). IS. Although panem matching within the same case introduces the possibility of falsifying lhc hypothesis, it doei not overcome all of Use. problems of ex pose fsc(o hypotheses. Thus, pattern auirbing will probably not overcome a p rob In- of unrepresenuiiveness which may arise due to acleetion bias or to the chance selection of an atypical case. 19. Sec, for example, (he debate on interest mediation and corporatism in We ale m Europe, inc luding Wileoik y (197Ů), Hibbi (197«), Sehmitler (1981). and Cameron (1984). The debate started by Ijrjj and Garrett (1985) is a continuation of Uiii line of analysis. Bibliography Achen, Christopher H. I9S6. The Siatiiiicul Analysis of Quasi* Exptfitnenit, Berkeley and Jjos Angeles; University of CtliTornii Press. Achen, Christopher H., and Ouncan Snidal. 1989, 'Rational Deterrence Theory and Comparative Case Studies." Vt'arU PoliHa 41:143-69. Almond, Gahrirl A-, and Stephen). Genco. 1977. "Clouds. Clocks, and the Study of Prdirirs." WnnU Politics 19:*69-521, Armer, Micha«!, and Allen Grinuhaw. eda. 1973. Comparative Social Research, New York; John Wiley. Babbie, Earl. 1992 . 7Jie Practice of Social Research, 6th editiurt- Belmont, CA; Wadswnrth, Bendbt, Reinhild. 1964. Nancn-Sutlding anA &uztr^k\p: Sindla ef Our QmngingSocial Order, New Yurfc: John Wiley, Bendu, Reinhard. 1978. Kings or People: Power and the Morukae to Rule. Berkeley and Lös Angeles; University of California Pius. Bergquist, Charles. 198tt- Labor in Lasin America: Comparative Essayt on Chile, A rgentira, Veneiatie, and Colombia, Stanford; Stanford University Press, Bollen. Kenneth A., and Roben W. Jackman. 1985. "Regression Diagnostics: An Expository Treatment of Outliers a:iJ Influential Cases." Sociological Methods and Research 13:510-42. Burger, Thomas, 1976. Wax Weber's Theory of Concept FormfHon: History. Laws, end Ideal Types. Durham: Duke University. IIS The Comparative Method Citiwfoji, Dmv\4 R. 1984. "Soeiat Dcmonnty, Cňcpomijm, Labour Quiiscénce, and the RcpraseniUtioii of Economic IntíKíl in Advaníed Capital!* Society." Li Ofátt and Conflict in Contemporary Capiutllsjn r ed. Jůtkn it. fjordlhoipe. New Yorfcr Oxfůrtf Uiuvrrsiiy Press. CampťeU, &>n»tJ T. 1975. "'Degree a of Fn^Qffl'*.nd die Cas* 5 -.: H v. * (Sjmpffřoíívc: floiinVn! Smdics g; 174-53. Campbell, Donald T.. End H. Laurence Rom. 1968. The Coanczucul Crackdown ůn Speeding; Ti mí Série* Dili in Quaai-Experimental Anály sta." Law and Society fttw }.:ij-5i. Camjiliřtt, Donald T., nod Juliia C. Snaky. 1963. Experimental and Quasi -experimental Designs^jj- Restařen. Chicago: Ra nd McNaliy. OnJllci. DaviJ, and. Jiitiíj li Moůon. 1993. "Conceptual 'Scfiichiní' Revisited: Alternativa VieWi of CaLígoriei in Cnmparalive Anály bj3;.p American Political Science ffťWíw. Collier. Divid. iťld Debofab L. Nůníirn. 1992, "Stnlíglc ChoLCfl Můdiia of Půliijcít Change in Laljn America." Comparative Politic: H:Í19-Í43, Collier. Rulh Bccina, and: David Collici. E991. Shaping she Political Arena: Critical Junctures. i)\f Labor Movement, flnj Regime Dynůmies in £múi Arwnra. Prijweloa; Princ clon University Presi. Daltl, Růfcnt A., ed. I96Ů. řoífůňií ÍJfijjťríítfdní iia Western -.liiřiT (!.';«. NeW HaVep; Vale Uni venhy Pr-í 11. licFctitc, E-G*rt=- 19S0■ 'ConiparisQn Misconceived: Common Nonsense in Comparative Politic*.' í.---mj--íuji.r Politics iiil19-16. Diaoonjs. Pí ni, and Rťadley JEfíoa. 19S3. * CůJiqíULůf-Intd řiii v* Mf ilithíi in Stiijíiíet. * Scientific American 1 +í:: I 6 30 Eckstein, Hitry. 1975. 'Caae Study and Theory in Political Science." In Handbook of folitirat Stinné, vcjl, 7, ed. Jriud GreeiuJein liNtlwnW. Mwj Readúuj.MA: Addison-Wealey, Eggan, Ffíri. 1954. "Social Anthiopology an.J tne Mtihod o£ Controlled Comparison." AjhenVan 56:743-63. Etzioni, Aiititai, ifid Frederic L. Dubow. eds. 1970. Comparative Peripeetirex.- Thenriet and Afaktkii. Rňsiiín: Linií. Brown, Fnídrnan, Davjd A, ]9S7, 'AuÍTchera $ae U*: A Céh Study in Path Anályaia." Journal o/Educational Statistics 12:101-28. rreedmnn, rj»,id A. |9'Jl. 'Siatiflkul Mo4í lund Shdc- Uiilirr.' In Socioiagicoi Neliicdology 1991, ed. PcierMunden, Sin Fr»nťis;ňí Jcsiiejí-lljai. (iiirta. CcňiTrty, and Pct;: Línge. llíf. 'Govenumni Pirttíatuhin iekI !.-.■;.. ^Iicq smí Hnw Hati LWho CovErna' Milleři" Javrnal of Politics S! :í 7í-93, Gcddit, Eírbarí. 1990. ■Ho* Ihe Ciws Yuu Cim-w AT^-i^c Aiuwin Víki Gel: Stltíjiiiin Biai [ú Compaoiiive Polita"." In Political Analyih-, 'vjji- 2, cit. íairuei. A- Sujiuůří. Ann AAťií- Univítsicy of Michigan Preaj. GectJcin &*rboni, Lů91- ■ A Gimt Tíícůftijc Hodů! oť Reftjrm ín L*lu» Aineriíin Demos neiei/ H/nerifdn PoliSiral Science Review Si:37l-3?2. Ce:tU, CliňttfJ- 1973. "Thif fc Best ríption: To«»rt *n [pmfjsiriive Theory of Cn Hutě. * In The Iňierpntaúon of Cultures, ed. Clifford GiKrtZ. New Vint: Baíií B(m)ti- Ceůrsc. Aieiin-Jer L. JD79. 'Cist Sajdiei ind Tneorj Developmcfit: The ■'■:"-nf ^:.nj;uirej, Foeii^clComput»D,' In Diplomacy; Approachef in tiúiory. Theory, ami Policy, ed. Pan] GyrJi>T3 Lauren. New York: The Free Ftím. Gíorge. AJc"odír L., indTLmothy J. MeKJMswfl- Í9H. "C»k Síli:S:c.m and Ttiioriis of Oígflnizattonaí Cjocqílt^n Matiii^.' Advances in Iffvnpiirictn Processing rn r?^mj'ld^yrtjH vol. 2 -Sir.l.i i!--iri:b: a. J-M '}:■•--■ CJirefti, Gary, and Donald L. Wj-mn. tit. 1990. Mannfecniring itiracla: Pothi of Inltatrtalizooon in £ann ^j«^ w £*d(iflJ. Prinseton: Princetoa Unrvenliy r\tu Qclriiant,. Jack A. i591. ^«ivJhjjö;, W Kebrlliei, in itu-Serf/ Mate™ Wvrld, Eäricetty ifld Loa Ang^lei: Univenii^ of Cilifonua Pteu. HajjfirJ, JiephiH. 1390. Pathways from thz Periphery: The foLia of öhjwifr In the Nevity Industrializing Cotmaiet, Mum- CookU UnivcraJiy Ptcu. Hampet. Ftant t , ;i i.'. 19S7. ffutiui Jiijditti; TJu- Approaek Bated em influence Functions. New Yofl: John Wiic^ Hirtwif, I - with Eriaa E. Dcaripjj. 197°. tLzpksraso^ Oun Ariaiyfts. Stgt UnJverjLly Papef, Seriei No, 07-t>|6. Beveri/ Hilti, CA: Sage Pub(k:aiioni, HectKher. Guoiiv. 1957. The Soidy of Gompurmive Gevtmmmt atf Politics. London: Ceo t^c Allea rni UnwU. Hlbbc, Douglia A., Je, I&74. "On ihe. Poliücal Econömj of Lonj-Am, Trtftdi in Sink* A^iiviiy,* UrWiA Journal af FeNa'eaf SdtTKc S;1S3-17J. llkka, Alexander. 19S8, "Social DemocraiK Corporaiiim tml Ecooomje Gm wüi. " Joarnai of Palmes 50:6T?-704, Kictl, AleXi:kJcf. ind WIIIJaciL DaviJ I'nttenKJn. 19S9. 'Ün Hie Rohmtnta" of ihe Left CfKpünTia Model of Economic Onswlh. * Journal of Politics S \: 6*2-o75. HooJe, FfUKU W. 19TB, Evaluation Researth and Development Activities. Bevcdy Hilts, CA; Sage Publieilioni. Jicfcman. Roben W. 1915. "Crosa-NatlonaJ Sia"jiü"ci I R=jea rrh j nd lhcSmd^uf Cömpirtli Vt Pülitlci. * American Journal of Political Science 29:161 -Bl, Ij^Vjnan, RiActi Vi1. IM7. Ttm Puliüei öf Economic Crtuvdi b l:;..n T :i Dtmocntcics, 197443: I .ci■.!■•: or Sea Od?" Journal af Politics 49:241-50. Jackman, Rot>erl W, 19^9. TKe P^liiica üf Ecnjivjmk Cctiwdi, Ovc Again,' Journal of Politic* 5 \ ;fi*6-M 1. Jt :tson, John E. 1992. "Eatimaüoii of Model* with Viriahle Cu*fCtkail.' In Politieid Amfysii. vol. 3. *d. JanwiA. Sii iiLxn:i Arji Arhnf: U iiiveniiy of Micbl^in Pkm . KjJktaerg, Anhur L, l,J;:o. Tbc Lo^c of Comparison; A MtUiudulo^icil Nute on Ihe Comparalive Study ol" Political System! ~ World Politics 19:fi9-Rl. Kine, Gary, Sidney Verta, und Robeil O, K^ohtlH. 1992. Scienäße Inference in Qpnlitative Aeseoreh. Unpuhlishcd inanuM:npt, IXpi-ivi-ni cÄ Guve^TuAcnlL, Harvard Uikivaraity. La toff. Georje. 19*7. Women. Fire, and Oa.igerau., Thinjci: Vfnat Caieforiei Reveal about the Mind. Chitogib: Uriiveraity of Chicago PrtM. Lange, Peter, and Geoffrey Gurren. ThePötlü^sofGrowih', SiTittgic Laemcüon and Economic PertonnirK t in Advanced bmduitriai DcOMitraeieB, 1974-1950.* Journal of Polities Lange, Peict. and Geaffrey Euren, 1997. The PoliH-st of Growth fttccöüdtied." Jounvoi of Politicr 49:257-74. Lnnwell, Ffarotd D, IMS- The Fnhire ot Ihe Comparatiut- Mclliod." Comparative Potiu'cs lr3-1S-LitbenMMi, Sluilcy. 19*1. "Snüll N't and Big CorKlutlomr Ao ExajibJUüon of the Reasoning in Comparative Studiea Baiad en a Snail Nui*iber of Casei." Sorifli fflrc« 701307-20. Lijphart, Arend. 197t. *r^m^t»Üve foltlic* and Compn raljve Method," American Political Science Review 65:6S3-93, Ujpliail, Aread. 1975. Tho Cöfflpanihle Ciati SUaitgy in Comoanrivc Hattaieh." Comparative Political Studies i.lM-71. Lijptiart, Arend- 1990. The PtiUlicil C«rnK<|Utnc«Df EJectonl Law a, 194i-t9S5.* American. Political Science Re\iev--S4:4*l-96. Lipacl. Seymour Mania, and Slein Rokkac 1967. "Cteavaj;e», Sir.i:;'.:r.:> Party Syatema, and Vutee Align™nta: An tnUio- Collier 119 duerion." In Party Systems and Voter Alignments, ed». StynwurMirtin UpKHod SLrin RuldtiD. New York: Free Press. Uebben. Gregory M. 1*91. liberalism, Fascism, or Soda! Democracy: Social Classes and she Political Origins of Hegimef in InstrWar Europe. Nett York: Oxford University Prtaj. M^Kinney, lohn C. 1966. Constructive Typology and Social Theory. tffii Yurk: Meredith Publtshkc Company. Memo, Richard. 1970- Systematic Approaches to Comparative Politics. Chicago: Rand McNifly. Merrill, Richard, und Stein Rokkan, ed«. 1966. Comparing nations: The Use of Quantitative Data in Cross-National Research. New Haven: YsJc Unrvcraity Frtaa. Mill, John Satan. [18431 1*74. A System of Logic. Toronto: University of Torojwn Pre*s. Moouc-Y, Chrisu^'licr Z., and Rohen D. DuviJ. 1992. "Boouuan Inference: A Preliminary Monte Carlo Evaluation-* Paper pre»er.led ni the auuual meetings of Ihr An].:rPuittiial Science Association, Chicago. Moore. Barrinjton. 1966. Social Origins of Dictatorship and Democracy: Lord and Peasant in the Making of the Modem World Boston: Beacon Preu. Mosteller, Frederick, and John W, Tukey. (977. Dam Analysis and Regression. Reading, MA: Addiaon-Wetley. O'Donnell, GuiUermo. Philippe C. Schmitt« r, and Lawrence Whitehead. eds. [986. Transitions from Authoritarian Rule. Baltimore: John Heiptim Universilv Proas. Paige. Jeffrey. 1975- Agrarian Revolution: Social Movements and Espnrt Agriculture in the Underdeveloped World. New York: Free Pees». Praeworski, Adam- 1937, 'Methods of Cross-National Research, 1970-1983: An Overview.' Meinolf Dierfcea, Hani N. Weiler, and Ansae Benhoi n Ants I, ed*. Comparative Policy Research.- Learning from Experience. Brootfield. VT: Gower. Pficrworaki, Adam. 1991. Democracy and she Market: Political and Economic Reforms in Eastern Europe and Latin America. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press-Przcworfiki, Adam, and Ilenry Teunc. 1970. The Logic of Comparative Social Inquiry. New Yort: John Wiley. Ragin, Charles C. 19&7. The Comparative Method: Moving beyond Qualitative and Quantitative Strategies. Berkeley and Lux Aiurclc*- Univc rsily öf California Pr=*s. Rutkan, Suiin- 1970. Citizens. Elections. Parries: Approaches to the Comparative Study of Processes of Development. New York: David McKay. Rueschemeyer, Dietrich, Evelyne Huber Stephen», and John D. Stephen*- \992- Capitalist Development and Democracy. Osicigo: University of Chicago Pttf. Ruaow. Dsnkwan. !96S. "Mödemi/jüion and Cotnparaüve Politics: PfOapecu in Research and Theory." Comparative. Polities 1:37-M. Ssrton, Giovanni. 1970. "Concept Misformatiun in Comparative Politic?." American Political Science ReviewG4:1033-53, Ssrton, Giovanni, ed. 19S4. Social Science Concepts: A Systematic Analysis. Beverly Hilts, CA: Sage. Sartori, Giovanni. 1991. "Comparing and Miaeimpmnj!." Journal of Theoretical Politics 3:243-57. Sinori, Giovanni. 19/93. "Totalitariinuni. Model Mania, and Learning from Error.' Journal of Theoretical Politics. Sarwri. Giovanni. Fred W. Riggs, and Henry Teune. [975. Tower of B&bel: On she Definition and Analysis of Concepts in the Social Science!. Intrmalioiul Studie» Association. Occisionnl Paper Ko. 6, Umveraily of Piu*burj»is. Schminef, Philippe C. 1981. "Ictercat Intermediation and Regime Govertiability in Contemporary Victim Europe and North America.' In Organizing Interests In Western Europe, ed. Suzanne D. Bergor. Cambridge: Cambridge Uisiveiarty Press. Skocpol, Tbeda. 1979, Sane* and Social Revolution*: A Comparative Analysis of France. Rsasia, and tZhina. Cambridge; Cambridge University Pres*. Sfcrxpol, Tbcda. 19S4. Vision and Method in Historical Sociology. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge University Preaa. Skocpol, TheJa, and Margaret Somen. I93Q. The Uoca of Comparative Hiatory in Ma^roiucial Inquiry." Comparative Studies In Sociesy and Histary 21; 174-97. 5 melt;r. Neil. 1968. Toe. Meilwdology of Comparalivt AAalyaia of E^oaotnte Activity. * In Essays in Sociological Interpretation, ed. Neil Smetaee. EngUrwood CJitfa. NJ: Prenlici-Hall. Snwli:rt Neil 1976. Ovp.z."nivf Methods sr. tt«- .Wo! Sarn,:ex. Enjlcwood ClilTa, NJ: Prentice Hall, Sunchcombe, Anhur L. 1978. TJwonrricai Wetfwctr in Social History, Hz-* York: Academic Press Tilly, Chartts. 1975. The Formation of tSaHtmal Slates in Western Europe. Princeton: Princeton Uorverijly Preaa. Tilly, Charles. 1984. fllrg Ssructurec, Large Processes. Huge Comparisons. New Yort: Russell Sage. Trimberger. Ellen Kay. 1978. Revolution from Above: Military Bureaucrats and Development in Japan. Turkey. Egypt, and Pent. New BiUjuiL-ick. NJ: Tr»;uta^tii.n Bnoti. Tufte, Edward R, 1970. JV Quantitative Arndyst* of Social Problems. Reading, MA: Addiaon-Weoley. Vatlier, Ivan, ed. 1971. Comparative Methods in Sociology: Essays on Trends and Applications, Berkeley and Ltfa Angclca: Univeraity of Califurnii Preaa. Verba, Sidney. 1967. 'Some Dilemmas In Coinparilrve Research." worid" Polities 20:111-27. WUensky, Harold L. 1975. The 'New Corporatism.' Centralization. and the Welfare State. Profeutonal Paper* in Contemporary Political Sociology Series, Beverly Hills: Sage Publications. Yin, Robert K. 196'. .dare Study Restarch: Design and Methods. App I led Social Rescaruh Mcdii>J» Scricn, vol 5. Boveriy II .11 s Sage Publication*. Zeldileh, Jr., Morris. 1071 - 'Intelligible Coenpariaofut.' In Comparative Methods in Sociology: Essays on Trends and Applications, ed. Jvau Vellier. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Pr&n.