Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=mijs20 International Journal of Sociology ISSN: 0020-7659 (Print) 1557-9336 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/mijs20 4 The Three Political Economies of the Welfare State Gøsta Esping-Andersen To cite this article: Gøsta Esping-Andersen (1990) 4 The Three Political Economies of the Welfare State, International Journal of Sociology, 20:3, 92-123, DOI: 10.1080/15579336.1990.11770001 To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/15579336.1990.11770001 Published online: 18 Nov 2016. Submit your article to this journal Article views: 45 View related articles Citing articles: 29 View citing articles 4 The Three Political Economies of the Welfare State G0STA ESPING-ANDERSEN Introduction The protracted debate on the welfare state has failed to produce conclusive answers as to either the nature or the causes of welfare state development. This chapter has three aims: (I) to reintegrate the debate into the intellectual tradition of political economy thus putting into sharper focus the principal theoretical questions involved; (2) to specify the salient characteristics of welfare states since the conventional ways of measuring welfare states in terms of their expenditures will no longer suffice; and (3) to "sociologize" the study of welfare states. Most studies have assumed a world of linearity: more or less power, industrialization, or spending. This chapter insists that we understand welfare states as clusters of regime types, and that their development must be explained interactively. The legacy of classical political economy Contemporary welfare state debates have been guided by two questions. First, does social citizenship diminish the salience of class? Or, in other words, can the welfare state fundamentally transform capitalist society? Second, what are the causal forces behind welfare state development? These questions are not recent. Indeed, they were formulated by the nineteenth-century political economists one hundred years before any welfare state can rightfully be said to have come into exis- 92 FALL 1990 93 tence. The classical political economists-whether of liberal, conservative, or Marxist persuasion-were preoccupied with the relationship between capitalism and welfare. Their answers obviously diverged, but their analyses were unequivocally directed to the relationship between market (and property) and the state (democracy). The question they asked was largely normative: What is the optimal division of responsibility between market and state? Contemporary neoliberalism echoes the contributions of classical liberal political economy. To Adam Smith, the market was the superior means for the abolition of class, inequality, and privilege. Aside from a necessary minimum, state intervention would likely stifle the equalizing process of competitive exchange and create monopolies, protectionism, and inefficiency: in short the state upholds class; the market can potentially undo class society (Smith 1961, Vol. 2 especially 232-36).1 Liberal political economists were not necessarily of one mind when it came to policy advocacy. Nassau Senior and later Manchester liberals emphasized the laissez-faire element of Smith, rejecting any form of social protection outside the cash nexus. John Stuart Mill and the "reformed liberals," in tum, were willing to let markets be regulated by a modicum of political regulation. Yet, they all agreed that the road to equality and prosperity should be paved with a maximum of free markets and a minimum of state interference. This enthusiastic embrace of market capitalism may now appear unjustified. But, we must take into account that the state. which confronted these early political economists. was tinged with legacies of absolutist privileges. mercantilist protectionisms. and pervasive corruption. They were attacking systems of governance that repressed the ideals of both freedom and enterprise. Hence. theirs was revolutionary theory. and from this vantage point. we can understand why Adam Smith sometimes reads like Karl Marx.2 Democracy was an Achilles' heel to many liberals. Their ideals of freedom and democratic participation were grounded in a world of small property owners. not of growing propertyless masses who held in their sheer numbers the possibility of seizing state power. The liberals feared the principle of universal suffrage. for it would likely politicize the distributional struggle. pervert the market. and fuel inefficiencies. Many liberals discovered that democracy would contradict the market. Both conservative and Marxist political economists understood this 94 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY contradiction, but proposed, ofcourse, opposite solutions. The most coherent conservative critique of laissez-faire came from the German historical school; in particular from Friedrich List, Adolph Wagner, and Gustav Schmoller. They refused to believe that capitalist efficiency was best assured by the pure commodity status of workers in the raw cash nexus of the market. Instead, conservative political economists believed that patriarchal neoabsolutism could provide the kind of legal, political, and social framework that would assure capitalism without class struggle. One prominent conservative school promoted a "Monarchical Welfare State" that would, at once, provide for social welfare, class harmony, loyalty, and productivity. It was discipline, not competition, that would guarantee efficiency. The state (or church) was the institution best equipped to harmonize conflicting interests.3 Conservative political economy emerged in reaction to the French Revolution and the Paris Commune. It was avowedly nationalist, antirevolutionary, and sought to arrest the democratic impulse. It feared social leveling and favored a society that retained both hierarchy and class. It held that class conflicts were not natural; that democratic mass participation and the dissolution of recognized rank and status boundaries were threats to social harmony. The key to Marxian political economy, of course, was its rejection of the liberal claim that markets guarantee equality. Capitalist accumulation, as Dobb (1946) put it, disowns people of property with the end result being ever deeper class divisions. Here, the state's role is not neutrally benevolent, nor is it a fountain of emancipation; the state exists to defend property rights and the authority of capital. According to Marxism, this capitalist state is the foundation of class dominance. The central question, not only for Marxism but for the entire contemporary debate on the welfare state, is whether and under what conditions the class divisions and social inequalities produced by capitalism can be undone by parliamentary democracy. The liberals feared that democracy would produce socialism and they were consequently not especially eager to extend it. The socialists, in contrast, suspected that parliamentarism would be little more than an empty shell or, as Lenin suggested. a mere "talking shop" (Jessop 1982). This line of analysis. echoed in much of contemporary Marxism, leads to the conclusion that social reforms emerge in response to the exigencies of capitalist reproduction. not the emancipatory desires of the working classes..t FAlL 1990 95 Among socialists, a more positive analysis of parliamentarism came to prevail after the extension of full political citizenship. The theoretically most sophisticated contributions came from Austro-Marxists such as Adler and Bauer, and from German social democrats, especially Eduard Heimann. Heimann's (1929) starting point was that even conservative reforms may have been motivated by desires to repress labor mobilization, but that their very presence nonetheless alters the balance of class power: the social wage lessens the worker's dependence on the market and employers. The social wage is thus also a potential power resource that defmes the frontier between capitalism and socialism. It introduces an alien element into the capitalist political economy. This intellectual position has enjoyed quite a renaissance in recent Marxism (Offe 1985; Bowles and Gintis 1986). The social democratic model, as outlined above, did not necessarily abandon the orthodox assumption that fundamental equality requires economic socialization. Yet, historical experience soon demonstrated that socialization was a goal that could not be pursued realistically through parliamentarism.5 Social democracy's embrace of parliamentary reformism as its dominant strategy for equality and socialism was premised on two arguments. The first was that workers require social resources, health, and education to participate effectively in a democratized economy. The second argument was that social policy is not only emancipatory, but it is also economically efficient (Myrdal and Myrdal 1936). Following Marx on this point, the strategy therefore promotes the onward march of capitalist productive forces. The beauty of the strategy was that social policy would also assure social democratic power mobilization. By eradicating poverty, unemployment. and complete wage dependency, the welfare state increases political capacities and diminishes the social divisions that are barriers to political unity among workers. The social democratic model. then. puts forward one of the leading hypotheses of contemporary welfare state debate: the argument that parliamentary class mobilization is a means for the realization of socialist ideals of equality, justice, freedom, and solidarity. The political economy of the welfare state Our political economy forebears defined the analytic basis of much recent scholarship. They isolated the key variables of class. state, mar- 96 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY ket, and democracy, and they formulated the basic propositions about citizenship and class, efficiency and equality, and capitalism and socialism. Contemporary social science distinguishes itself from classical political economy on two scientifically vital fronts. First, it defmes itself as a positive science and shies away from normative prescription (Robbins 1976). Second, classical political economists had little interest in historical variability; they saw their efforts as leading toward a system of universal laws. Although contemporary political economy sometimes still clings to the belief in absolute truths, the comparative and historical method that, today, underpins almost all good political economy is one that reveals variation and permeability. Despite these differences, most recent scholarship has as its focal point the state-economy relationship defmed by nineteenth-century political economists. And, given its enormous growth, it is understandable that the welfare state has become a major test case for contending theories of political economy. Next, we shall review the contributions of comparative research on the development of welfare states in advanced capitalist countries. We will argue that most scholarship has been misdirected, mainly because it became detached from its theoretical foundations. We must therefore recast both the methodology and concepts of political economy in order to adequately study the welfare state. This will constitute the focus of the final section of this chapter. Two types of approaches have dominated in the explanation of welfare states: one, a systemic (or structuralist) theory; the other, an institutional or actor-oriented explanation. The systemidstructuralist approach The first approach, system--or structuralist-theory, seeks to capture the logic of development holistically. It focuses on the functional requisites for the reproduction of society and economy; it tends to emphasize cross-national similarities rather than differences. One variant of structuralist theory begins with a theory of the industrial society, and argues that industrialization makes social policy both necessary and possible. It makes welfare states necessary because preindustrial modes of social reproduction, such as the family, the church, noblesse oblige, and guild solidarity, are destroyed by the forces attached to modernization-social mobility, urbanization, individualism, FALL 1990 97 and market dependence. The crux of the matter is that the market is no adequate substitute because it caters only to those who are able to perform in it. Hence, the "welfare function" is appropriated by the nation state. The welfare state is also made possible by the rise of modem bureaucracy as a rational, universalist, and efficient form of organization. It is a means for managing collective goods, but also a center of power in its own right, and will thus be inclined to promote its own growth. This kind of reasoning has formed the so-called logic of industrialism perspective, according to which the welfare state will emerge as the modern industrial economy destroys traditional forms of social security (Flora and Alber 1981; Pryor 1969). But, the thesis has difficulties explaining why government social policy only emerged fifty or even one hundred years after traditional community was effectively destroyed. The basic response draws on Wagner's Law (1962) and on Marshall (1920), namely that a certain level of economic development, and thus surplus, is needed in order to permit the diversion of scarce resources from productive use (investments) to welfare (Wilensky and Lebeaux 1958). In this sense, the perspective follows in the footsteps of the old liberals. Social redistribution endangers efficiency, and only at a certain economic level will a negative-sum trade-off be avoidable (Okun 1975). The new structural Marxism offers a surprisingly parallel analysis. It breaks with its classical forebears' strongly action-centered theory. Like the industrialism thesis, its analytical starting point is not the problems of markets, but the logic of a mode of production. Capital accumulation creates contradictions that social reform can alleviate (O'Connor 1973). This tradition of Marxism or "logic of capitalism" much like its "logic of industrialism" counterpart, fails to see much relevance of actors in the promotion of welfare states. The point is that the state, as an actor, is positioned in such a way that it will serve the collective needs of capital. The theory is thus premised on two crucial assumptions: first, that power is structural and, second, that the state is "relatively" autonomous from class directives (Poulantzas 1973; Block 1977; for a recent critical assessment of this literature, see Therborn 1986; and Skocpol and Amenta 1986). The logic of capitalism perspective invites difficult questions. If. as Przworski (1980) has argued. working class consent is assured on the basis of material hegemony. that is. self-willed subordination to the 98 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY system, it is difficult to see why up to 40 percent of the gross national product must be allocated to the legitimation activities of a welfare state. A second problem is to derive state activities from a "mode of production" analysis. Eastern Europe may perhaps not qualify as socialist, but neither is it capitalist. Yet, there we fmd "welfare states," too. Perhaps accumulation has functional requirements in whichever way it proceeds (Skocpol and Amenta 1986; Bell 1978). The institutional approach The classical political economists made it clear why democratic institutions should influence welfare state development. The liberals feared that full democracy might jeopardize markets and inaugurate socialism. Freedom, in their view, necessitated a defence of markets against political intrusion. In practice, this is what the laissez-faire state sought to accomplish. But it was this divorce of politics and economy that fueled much of the institutionalist analyses-the second approach used to explain the welfare state. Best represented by Polanyi (1944), but also by a number of antidemocratic exponents of the historical school, the institutional approach insists that any effort to isolate the economy from social and political institutions will destroy human society. The economy must be embedded in social communities in order for it to survive. Thus, Polanyi sees social policy as a necessary precondition for the reintegration of the social economy. An interesting recent variant of institutional alignment theory is the argument that welfare states emerge more readily in small, open economies, which are particularly vulnerable to international markets. As Katzenstein (1985) and Cameron (1978) show, there is a greater inclination to regulate class distributional conflicts through government and interest concertation when both business and labor are captives to forces beyond domestic control. The impact of democracy on welfare states has been argued ever since the days of J. S. Mill and Alexis de Tocqueville. The argument is typically phrased without reference to any particular social agent or class. It is, in this sense, institutional. In its classical formulation, the thesis was simply that majority groups will favor social distribution to compensate for market weakness or market risks. If wage earners are likely to demand a social wage, so are capitalists (or farmers) apt to demand protection in the form of tariffs, monopolies, or subsidies. FALL 1990 99 Democracy is an institution that cannot resist majoritarian demands. In its modem formulations, the democratic-institutionalist thesis has many variants. One identifies stages of nation-building in which full citizenship incorporation requires social rights (Marshall 1950; Bendix 1964; Rokkan 1970). A secbnd variant, developed by both pluralist and public choice theory, argues that democracy will nurture intense party competition around the median voter that will, in tum, fuel rising public expenditures. Tufte (1978), for example, argues that major extensions of public intervention will occur around elections as a means of voter mobilization. The democratic-institutionalist approach faces considerable empirical problems (Skocpol and Amenta 1986). According to the thesis, a democratic polity is the basic precondition for welfare state emergence, and welfare states are more likely to develop the more democratic rights are extended. Yet, the thesis confronts not only the historical oddity that the first major welfare state initiatives occurred prior to democracy, but also that they were often motivated by desires to arrest its realization. This was certainly the case in France under Napoleon II, in Germany under Bismarck, and in Austria under von Taaffe. Conversely, welfare state development was most retarded where democracy arrived early, such as in the United States, Australia, and Switzerland. This apparent contradiction can be explained, but only with reference to social classes and social structure: nations in which democracy appeared early were overwhelmingly agrarian and dominated by small property owners who used their electoral powers to reduce, not raise, taxes (Dich 1973). In contrast, ruling classes in authoritarian polities were better positioned to impose high taxes on an unwilling populace. Social class as a political agent We have noted that the case for a third approach to analyzing the welfare state, the class mobilization thesis, flows from social democratic political economy. It differs from structuralist and institutional analyses by its emphasis on the social classes as the main agents of change and its argument that the balance of class power determines distributional outcomes. To emphasize active class mobilization does not necessarily deny the importance of structured or hegemonic power (Korpi 1983). But it is held that parliaments are, in principle. effective ZOO INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY institutions for the translation of mobilized power into desired policies and reforms. Accordingly, parliamentary politics are capable of overriding hegemony, and may be made to serve interests that are antagonistic to capital. Further, the class mobilization theory assumes that welfare states do more than simply alleviate the current ills of the system; a "social democratic" welfare state will, in its own right, establish critical power resources for wage earners and, thus, strengthen labor movements. As Heimann (1929) originally held, social rights push back the frontiers of capitalist power and prerogatives. The question of why the welfare state itself is a power resource is vital for the theory's applicability. The answer is that wage earners in the market are inherently atomized and stratified, compelled to compete, and are insecure and dependent on decisions and forces beyond their control. This limits their capacity for collective solidarity and mobilization. The social rights, income security, equalization of income, and eradication of poverty that a universalistic welfare state pursues are necessary preconditions for the strength and unity that collective power mobilization demands (Esping-Andersen 1985a). The single most difficult problem for this thesis is to specify the conditions for power mobilization. Power depends on the resources that flow from the unity of electoral numbers and from collective bargaining. Power mobilization, in tum, depends on the levels of trade union organization and voter shares and the number of parliamentary and cabinet seats held by left or labor parties. But how long a period of sustained power mobilization is required in order to produce decisive effects? If power is measured over a brief time span (five to ten years), we risk the fallacy of a "Blum"/"Mitterand" effect: a brief spell of leftist power that proves ineffectual because the left is ousted before having had a chance to act. There are several valid objections to the class mobilization thesis. Three, in particular, are quite fundamental. One is that in advanced capitalist nations, the locusofdecision making and powermay shift from parliaments to neocorporatist institutions of interest intermediation (Shonfield 1965; Schmitter and Lembruch 1979). A second criticism is that the capacity of labor parties to influence welfare state development is circumscribed by the structure of rightist party power. Castles (1978; 1982) has argued that the degree of unity among the rightist parties is more important than is the activated power of the left. Other authors have emphasized the fact that denominational (usually social catholic) parties in countries such as the FALL 1990 101 Netherlands, Italy, and Gennany mobilize large sections of the working classes and pursue welfare state programs not drastically at variance with their socialist competitors (Schmidt 1982; Wilensky 1981). The class mobilization thesis has, rightfully so, been criticized for its Swedocentrism, that is, its inclination to defme the process of power mobilization too much on the basis ofthe rather extraordinary Swedish experience (Shalev 1983). These objections address a basic fallacy in the theory's assumptions about class fonnation: we carmot assume that socialism is the natural basis for wage-earner mobilization. Indeed, the conditions under which workers become socialists are still not adequately documented. Historically, the natural organizational bases of worker mobilization were precapitalist communities, especially the guilds, but also church, ethnicity, or language. A ready-made reference to false consciousness will not do to explain why Dutch, Italian, or U.S. workers continue to mobilize around nonsocialist principles. The dominance of socialism in the Swedish working class is as much a puzzle as is the dominance of confessionalism in the Dutch. The third and, perhaps, most fundamental objection has to do with the model's linear view of power. It is problematic to hold that a numerical increase in votes, unionization, or parliamentary seats will translate into more welfare statism. First, for socialist as for other parties, the magical "50 percent" threshold for parliamentary majorities seems practically insunnountab1e (przworski 1985). Second, if socialist parties represent working classes in the traditional sense, it is clear that they will never succeed in their project. In very few cases has the traditional working class been numerically a majority, and its role is rapidly becoming marginal.6 Probably the most promising way to resolve the combined linearity-and working class minority-problem lies in recent applications of Barrington Moore's path-breaking class coalition thesis to the transfonnation of the modem state (Weir and Skocpol 1985; Gourevitch 1986; Esping-Andersen 1985a; Esping-Andersen and Friedland 1982). Thus, the origins of the Keynesian full employment commitment and the social democratic welfare state edifice have been traced to the capacity of (variably) strong working-class movements to forge a political alliance with fanners' organizations; in addition. it is arguable that sustained social democracy has come to depend on the fonnation of a new working class-white collar coalition. The class coalitional approach has additional virtues. Two nations. 102 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY such as Austria and Sweden, may score similarly on working-class mobilization variables, and yet produce highly unequal policy results. This can be explained by differences in the two countries' historical coalition formation: The breakthrough of Swedish social democratic hegemony stems from its capacity to forge the famous "red-green" alliance; the comparative disadvantage of the Austrian socialists rests in the .•ghetto" status assigned to them by virtue of the rural classes being captured by a conservative coalition (Esping-Andersen and Korpi 1984). In sum, we have to think in terms of social relations, not just social categories. Whereas structural-functionalist explanations identify convergent welfare state outcomes, and class-mobilization paradigms see large, but linearly distributed, differences, an interactive model such as the coalitions approach directs attention to distinct welfare state re- gimes. What is the welfare state? Every theoretical paradigm must somehow define the welfare state. How do we know when and if a welfare state responds functionally to the needs of industrialism, or to capitalist reproduction and legitimacy? And how do we identify a welfare state that corresponds to the demands that a mobilized working class might have? We cannot test contending arguments unless we have a commonly shared conception of the phenomenon to be explained. A remarkable attribute of the entire literature is its lack of much genuine interest in the welfare state as such. Welfare state studies have been motivated by theoretical concerns with other phenomena, such as power, industrialization, or capitalist contradictions; the welfare state itself has generally received scant conceptual attention. If welfare states differ, how do they differ? And when, indeed, is a state a welfare state? This turns attention straight back to the original question: what is the welfare state? A common textbook definition is that it involves state responsibility for securing some basic modicum of welfare for its citizens. Such a definition skirts the issue of whether social policies are emancipatory or not; whether they help system legitimation or not; whether they contradict or aid the market process; and what, indeed, is meant by "basic"? Would it not be more appropriate to require of a welfare state that it satisfies more than our basic or minimal welfare needs? FALL 1990 103 The ftrst generation of comparative studies started with this type of conceptualization. Its authors assumed, without much reflection, that the level of social expenditure adequately reflects a state's commitment to welfare. The theoretical intent was not really to arrive at an understanding of the welfare state, but rather to test the validity of contending theoretical models in political economy. By scoring nations with respect to urbanization, level of economic growth, and the share of aged in the demographic structure, it was believed that the essential features of industrial modernization were adequately captured. Alternatively, by scoring nations on left party strength, or working-class power mobilization (with complex weighted scores of trade unionism, electoral strength, and cabinet power), others sought to identify the impact of working-class mobilization as formulated in the social democratic model. The fmdings of the ftrst generation of comparativists are extremely diffIcult to evaluate. No convincing case can be made for any particular theory. The shortage of nations for comparisons statistically restricts the number of variables that can be tested simultaneously. Thus, when Cutright (1965) or Wilensky (1975) ftnds that economic level, with its demographic and bureaucratic correlates, explains most welfare state variations in "rich countries," relevant measures of working-class mobilization or economic openness are not included. A conclusion in favor of a logic of industrialism view is therefore in doubt. And, when Hewitt (1977), Stephens (1979), Korpi (1983), Myles (1984), and Esping-Andersen (1985b) find strong evidence in favor of a working-class mobilization thesis, or when Schmidt (1982; 1983) finds support for a neocorporatist, and Cameron (1978) for an economic openness argument, it is without fully testing against the strongest alternative explanation.7 Most of these studies claim to explain the welfare state. Yet, their focus on spending may be irrelevant or, at best, misleading. Expenditures are epiphenomenal to the theoretical substance of welfare states. Moreover, the linear scoring approach (more or less power, democracy, or spending) contradicts the sociological notion that power, democracy, and welfare are relational and structured phenomena. By scoring welfare states on spending, we assume that all spending counts equally. But, some welfare states, Austria for example, spend a large share on benefits to privileged civil servants. This is normally not what we would consider a commitment to social citizenship and solidarity. 104 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY Other nations spend disproportionally on means-tested social assistance. Few contemporary analysts would agree that a reformed poor relief tradition qualifies as a welfare state commitment. Some nations spend enormous sums on fiscal welfare in the form of tax privileges to private insurance plans that mainly benefit the middle classes. But these tax expenditures do not show up on expenditure accounts. In the United Kingdom, total social expenditure has grown during the Thatcher period; yet, this is almost exclusively a function of very high unemployment. Low expenditures on some programs may signify a welfare state more seriously committed to full employment. Therbom (1983) is right when he holds that we must begin with a conception of state structure. What are the criteria with which we should judge whether, and when, a state is a welfare state? There are three approaches to this question. Therbom's proposal is to begin with the historical transformation of state activities. Minimally, the majority of a genuine welfare state's daily routine activities must be devoted to servicing the welfare needs of households. This criterion has farreaching consequences. If we simply measure routine activity in terms of spending and personnel, the result is that no state can be regarded as a real welfare state until the 1970s! And, some that we normally label as welfare states will still not qualify because the majority of their routine activities concern defense, law and order, administration, and the like (Therborn 1983). Social scientists have been too quick to accept nations' self-proclaimed welfare state status. They have also been too quick to conclude that the presence of the battery of typical social programs signifies the birth of a welfare state. The second conceptual approach derives from Richard Titmuss's (1958) classical distinction between residual and institutional welfare states. The former assumes that state responsibility begins only when the family or the market fails; its commitment is limited to marginal groups in society. The latter model addresses the entire population, is universalistic, and implants an institutionalized commitment to welfare. It will, in principle, extend welfare commitments to all areas of distribution vital for societal welfare. This approach has fertilized a variety of new developments in comparative welfare state research (Myles 1984; Korpi 1980; Esping-Andersen and Korpi 1984; 1986; Esping-Andersen 1985b; 1987). And it has forced researchers to move away from the black box of expenditures and toward the content of welfare states: targeted versus universalistic programs. the conditions FAlL 1990 105 of eligibility, the quality of benefits and services, and, perhaps most importantly, the extent to which employment and working life are encompassed in the state's extension of citizen rights. This shift to welfare state typologies makes simple linear welfare state rankings difficult to sustain. We might in fact be comparing categorically different types of states. The third approach is to select theoretically the criteria on which to judge types of welfare states. This can be done by measuring actual welfare states against some abstract model and then by scoring programs, or entire welfare states, accordingly (Day 1978; Myles 1984). The weakness of this approach is that it is ahistorical, and does not necessarily capture the ideals or designs that historical actors sought to realize in the struggles over the welfare state. If our aim is to test causal theories that involve actors, we should begin with the demands that were actually promoted by those actors that we deem critical in the history of welfare state development. It is difficult to imagine that anyone struggled for spending per se. A respecification of the welfare state Few people can disagree with T. H. Marshall's (1950) proposition that social citizenship constitutes the core idea of a welfare state. What, then, are the key principles involved in social citizenship? In our view, they must involve first and foremost the granting of social rights. This mainly entails a decommodification of the status of individuals vis-avis the market. Second, social citizenship involves social stratification; one's status as a citizen will compete with, or even replace, one's class position. Third, the welfare state must be understood in terms of the interface between the market, the family, and the state. These principles need to be fleshed out prior to any theoretical specification of the welfare state.8 Rights and decommodification As commodities in the market, workers depend for their welfare entirely on the cash-nexus. The question of social rights is thus one of decommodification, that is, of granting alternative means of welfare to that of the market. Decommodification may refer either to the service rendered, or to the status of a person, but in both cases it signifies the 106 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY degree to which distribution is detached from the market mechanism. This means that the mere presence of social assistance or insurance may not necessarily bring about significant decommodification if it does not substantially emancipate individuals from market dependence. Means-tested poor relief will possibly offer a security blanket as a last resort. But if benefits are low and attached with social stigma, the relief system will compel all but the most desperate to participate in the market. This was precisely the intent of tht! nineteenth-century poor laws. Similarly, most of the early social insurance programs were deliberately designed to maximize labor market performance (Ogus 1979). Benefits required long contribution periods and were tailored to prior work effort. In either case, the motive was to avert workdisincentive effects. There is no doubt that decommodification has been a hugely contested issue in welfare state development. For labor, it has always been a priority. When workers are completely market dependent, they are difficult to mobilize for solidaristic action. Since their resources mirror market inequalities, divisions emerge between the "ins" and the "outs," making labor movement formation difficult. Decommodification strengthens the worker and weakens the absolute authority of the employer. It is for exactly this reason that employers have historically opposed decommodification. Decommodified rights are differentially developed in contemporary welfare states. In welfare states dominated by social assistance, rights are not so much attached to work performance as to demonstrable need. Needs-tests and typically meager benefits, however, serve to curtail the decommodifying effect. Thus, in nations where this model is dominant (mainly in the Anglo-Saxon countries), the result is actually to strengthen the market since all but those who fail in the market will be encouraged to contract private sector welfare. A second dominant model espouses compulsory state social insurance with fairly strong entitlements. Yet, again, this may not automatically secure substantial decommodification, since this hinges very much on the fabric of eligibility and benefit rules. Germany was the pioneer of social insurance but over most of the twentieth century can hardly be said to have brought about much in the way of decommodification through its social programs. Benefits have depended almost entirely on contributions and, thus, work and employment. In fact, before World War II, average pensions in the German insurance sys- FALL 1990 107 tern for workers were lower than prevailing poverty assistance rates (Myles 1984). The consequence, as with the social assistance model, was that most workers chose to remain at work rather than retire. In other words, it is not the mere presence of a social right, but the corresponding rules and preconditions that dictate the extent to which welfare programs offer genuine alternatives to market dependence. The third dominant model of welfare, namely the Beveridge-type citizens' benefit, may, at first glance, appear the most decommodifying. It offers a basic, equal benefit to all irrespective of prior earnings, contributions, or work performance. It may indeed be a more solidaristic system, but not necessarily decommodifying since only rarely have such schemes been able to offer benefits of such a standard that they provide recipients with a genuine option to that of working. Decommodifying welfare states are, in practice, of very recent date. A minimalist definition must entail that citizens can freely, and without potential loss of jobs, income, or general welfare, opt out of work under conditions when they, themselves, consider it necessary for reasons of health, family, age, or even educational self-improvement; when, in short, they deem it necessary for participating adequately in the social community. With this definition in mind, we would, for example, require of sickness insurance that individuals have a guarantee of benefits equal to normal earnings, the right to absence with minimal proof of medical impairment and for the duration that the individual deems necessary. These conditions, it is worth noting, are those usually enjoyed by academics, civil servants, and higher echelon white-collar employees. Similar requirements would be made of pensions, maternity leave, parental leave, educational leave, and unemployment insurance. Some nations have moved toward this level of decommodification, but only recently and, in many cases, with significant exemptions. Thus, in almost all nations, benefits were upgraded to almost equal normal wages in the late 1960s and early 1970s. But, in some countries, for example, prompt medical certification in case of illness is still required; in others, entitlements depend on long waiting periods of up to two weeks; in others, the duration of entitlements is very short (in the United States, for example, unemployment benefit duration is maximally six months, compared to thirty months in Denmark). Overall. the Scandinavian welfare states tend to be the most decommodifying; the Anglo-Saxon ones the least. 108 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY The welfare stllte as a system ofstratification Despite the emphasis given to it in both classical political economy and in T. H. Marshall's pioneering work, the relationship between social citizenship and social class remains severely neglected, both theoretically and empirically. Generally speaking, the issue has either been assumed away (it has been taken for granted that the welfare state creates a more egalitarian society), or it has been approached narrowly in terms of income distribution or in terms of whether education promotes upward social mobility. A more basic question, it seems, is: What kind of stratification system is promoted by social policy? The welfare state is not just a mechanism that intervenes in, and possibly corrects, the structure of inequality; it is, in its own right, a system of stratification. It actively and directly orders social relations. Comparatively and historically, we can easily identify alternative systems of stratification embedded in welfare states. The poor relief tradition and its contemporary means-tested social assistance offshoot were conspicuously designed for purposes of stratification. By punishing and stigmatizing recipients, it promotes severe social dualisms, especially within the ranks of the working classes. It comes as no surprise that this model of welfare has been a chief target of labor movement attacks. The social insurance model promoted by conservative reformers such as Bismarck and von Taaffe was also explicitly a form of class politics. It sought, in fact, to achieve two simultaneous stratification results. The first goal was to consolidate divisions among wage earners by legislating distinct programs for different class and status groups, each with its own conspicuously unique set of rights and privileges designed to accentuate the individual's appropriate station in life. The second objective was to tie the loyalties of the individual directly to the monarchy, or central state authority. This was Bismarck's motive when he promoted a direct state supplement to the pension benefit. This state-corporativist model was pursued mainly in nations such as Germany, Austria. Italy, and France and often resulted in a labyrinth of status-specific insurance funds (in France and Italy. for example. there exist more than one hundred status-distinct pension schemes). Of special importance in this corporatist tradition was the establishment of particularly privileged welfare provisions for the civil service ("Beamten"). In part. Jlis was a means of rewarding loyalty to the FALL 1990 109 state and in part, a way of demarcating this group's uniquely exalted social status. We should, however, be careful to note that the corporatist status-differentiated model springs mainly from the old guild tradition. The neoabsolutist autocrats, such as Bismarck, saw in this tradition a means to combat the rising labor movements. The labor movements were as hostile to the corporatist model as they were to poor relief-in both cases for obvious reasons. Yet, the altematives first espoused by labor were no less problematic from the point of view of uniting the workers as one solidaristic class. Almost invariably, the model that labor first pursued was that of the self-organized friendly societies or equivalent union- or partysponsored fraternal welfare plan. This is not surprising. Workers were obviously suspicious of reforms sponsored by a hostile state, and saw their own organizations not only as the basis of class mobilization, but also as embryos of an alternative world of solidarity and justice, as a microcosm of the socialist haven to come. Nonetheless, these microsocialist societies often became problematic class ghettos that divided rather than united workers. Membership was typically restricted to the strongest strata of the working-class and the weakest-who needed protection most-were most likely outside. In brief, the fraternal society model contradicted the goal of working-class mobilization. The socialist ghetto approach was an additional obstacle when socialist parties found themselves forming governments and having to pass the social reforms they so long had demanded. For reasons of political coalition building and broader solidarity, their welfare model had to be recast as welfare for the "people." Hence, the socialists came to espouse the principle of universalism and, borrowing from the liberals. typically designed their welfare model on the lines of the democratic flat-rate. general revenue-financed. Beveridge model. As an alternative to means-tested assistance and corporatist social insurance. the universalistic system promotes status equality. All citizens are endowed with similar rights. irrespective of class or market position. In this sense. the system is meant to cultivate cross-class solidarity, a solidarity of the nation. But. the solidarity of flat-rate universalism presumes a historically peculiar class structure. one in which the vast majority of the population are the "little people" for whom a modest. albeit egalitarian. benefit may be considered adequate. Where this condition no longer exists. as occurs with growing working-class prosperity and the rise of the new middle classes. flat- 110 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY rate universalism inadvertently promotes dualism because the betteroff tum to private insurance and to fringe-benefit bargaining to supplement modest equality with their accustomed standards of welfare. Where this process unfolds (as in Canada or the United Kingdom), the result is that the wonderfully egalitarian spirit of universalism turns into a dualism similar to that of the social assistance state: the poor rely on the state, and the remaining groups on the market. It is not only the universalist, but in fact all historical welfare state models, that have faced the dilemma of class structural change. But, the response to prosperity and middle-class growth has been varied and, therefore, so has the stratificational outcome. The corporatist insurance tradition was, in a sense, best equipped to manage new and loftier welfare state expectations since the existing system could technically be upgraded quite easily to distribute more adequate benefits. Konrad Adenauer's 1957 pension reform in Germany was a pioneer in this respect. Its avowed purpose was to restore status differences that had eroded due to the old insurance system's incapacity to provide benefits tailored to expectations. This it did simply by moving from contribution- to earnings-graduated benefits without altering the framework of status-distinctiveness. In nations with either a social assistance- or a universalistic Beveridge-type system, the option was whether to allow the market or the state to furnish adequacy and satisfy middle-class aspirations. Two alternative models emerged from this political choice. The one typical of the United Kingdom and most of the Anglo-Saxon world was to preserve an essentially modest universalism in the state and allow the market to reign for the growing social strata demanding superior welfare. Due to the political power of such groups, the dualism that emerges is not merely one between state and market, but also between forms of welfare state transfers: in these nations, one of the fastest growing components of public expenditure is tax-subsidies for socalled private welfare plans. And the typical political effect is eroding middle-class support for what is less and less a universalistic public sector transfer system. Yet another alternative has been to seek a synthesis of universalism and adequacy outside the market. This road has been followed in the countries where. by mandate or legislation. the state includes the new middle classes by erecting a luxurious second-tier. universally inclusive. earnings-related insurance scheme on top of the flat-rate egalitar- FALL 1990 111 ian one. Notable examples are Sweden and Norway. By guaranteeing benefits tailored to expectations, this solution reintroduces benefit inequalities, but effectively blocks off the market. It thus succeeds in retaining universalism and, therefore, also the degree of political consensus required to preserve broad and solidaristic support for the high taxes that such a welfare state model demands. Welfare state regimes Welfare states vary considerably with respect to their principles of rights and stratification. This results in qualitatively different arrangements among state, market, and the family. The welfare state variations we find are therefore not linearly distributed, but clustered by regime types. In one cluster, we find the "liberal" welfare state, in which meanstested assistance, modest universal transfers, or modest social insurance plans predominate. These cater mainly to a clientele of low-income, usually working-class, state dependents. It is a model in which, implicitly or explicitly, the progress of social reform has been severely circumscribed by traditional, liberal work-ethic norms; one where the limits of welfare equal the marginal propensity to demand welfare instead of work. Entitlement rules are therefore strict and often associated with stigma; benefits are typically modest. In tum, the state encourages the market, either passively, by guaranteeing only a minimum, or actively, by subsidizing private welfare schemes. The consequence is that this welfare state regime minimizes decommodification effects, effectively contains the realm of social rights, and erects a stratification order that blends a relative equality of poverty among state welfare recipients. market-differentiated welfare among the majorities, and a class-political dualism between the two. The archetypical examples of this model are the United States, Canada, and Australia. Nations that approximate the model are Denmark, Switzerland, and the United Kingdom. A second regime cluster is composed of nations such as Austria, France, Germany, and Italy. Here, the historical corporatist-statist legacy was upgraded to cater to the new"postindustrial" class structure. In these "corporativist" welfare states, the liberal obsession with market efficiency and commodification was never preeminent and, as such, the granting of social rights was hardly ever a seriously contested 112 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY issue. What predominated was the preservation of status differentials; rights, therefore, were attached to class and status. This corporativism was subsumed under a state edifice perfectly ready to displace the market as a provider of welfare; hence, private insurance and occupational fringe benefits play a truly marginal role in this model. On the other hand, the state's emphasis on upholding status differences means that its redistributive effects are negligible. But, the corporativist regimes are also typically shaped by the church, and therefore influenced by a strong commitment to the preservation of traditional family patterns. Social insurance typically excludes nonworking wives and family benefits encourage motherhood. Day care, and similar family services, are conspicuously underdeveloped, and the "subsidiarity principle" serves to emphasize that the state will only interfere when the family's capacity to service its members is exhausted. An illustrative example is German unemployment assistance. Once a person has exhausted his or her entitlement to normal unemployment insurance, eligibility for continued assistance depends on whether one's family commands the financial capacity to aid the unfortunate; this applies to persons of any age. The third, and clearly smallest, regime cluster is composed of those countries in which the principles of universalism and decommodifying social rights were extended to the new middle classes. We may call it the "social democratic" regime type since, in these nations, social democracy clearly was the dominant force behind social reform. Norway and Sweden are the clearest cases, but we should also consider Denmark and Finland. Rather than tolerate a dualism between state and market, between working class and middle class, the social democrats pursued a welfare state that would promote an equality of the highest standards, rather than an equality of minimal needs as was pursued elsewhere. This implied, first, that services and benefits be upgraded to levels commensurable to even the most discriminate tastes of the new middle classes, and, second, that equality be furnished by guaranteeing workers full participation in the quality of rights enjoyed by the better-off. This formula translates into a mix of highly decommodifying and universalistic programs that, nonetheless. are tailored to differentiated expectations. Thus. manual workers come to enjoy rights identical to those of salaried white-collar employees or civil servants; all strata and classes are incorporated under one universal insurance system; yet, benefits are graduated according to accustomed earnings. This model FALL 1990 113 crowds out the market and, consequently, inculcates an essentially universal solidarity behind the welfare state. All benefit, all are dependent, and all will presumably feel obliged to pay. The social democratic regime's policy of emancipation addresses both the market and the traditional family. In contrast to the corporatistsubsidiarity model, the principle is not to wait until the family's capacity to aid is exhausted, but to preemptively socialize the costs of familyhood. The ideal is to maximize not dependence on the family, but capacities for individual independence. In this sense, the model is a peculiar fusion of liberalism and socialism. The result is a welfare state that grants transfers directly to the children, and takes direct caring responsibilities for children, the aged, and the helpless. It is, accordingly, committed to a heavy social service burden, not only to service family needs, but also to permit women to chose work outside the household. Perhaps the most salient characteristic of the social democratic regime is its fusion of welfare and work. It is, at once, a welfare state genuinely committed to a full employment guarantee and a welfare state entirely dependent on its attainment. On the one side, it is a model in which the right to work has status equal to the right of income protection. On the other side, the enormous costs of maintaining a solidaristic, universalistic, and decommodifying welfare system means {hal j{ must minimize social problems and maximize revenue. This is obviously best done with the most people working, and the fewest possible people living off social transfers. While it is empirically clear that welfare states cluster, we must recognize that no single case is pure. The social democratic regimes of Scandinavia blend crucial socialist and liberal elements. The Danish and Swedish unemployment insurance schemes, for example, are still essentially voluntarist. Denmark's labor movement has been chronically incapable of pursuing full employment policies due in part to trade union resistance to active labor market policy. And in both Denmark and Finland, the market has been allowed to playa decisive role in pensions. Nor are the liberal regimes pure. The U.S. social security system is redistributive, compUlsory, and far from actuarial. At least in its early formulation, the New Deal was as social democratic as was contemporary Scandinavian social democracy. In contrast, the Australian welfare state would appear exceedingly close to the bourgeois-liberal ideal type, but much of its edifice has the coresponsibility of Australian 114 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY labor. And, fmally, the European corporatist regimes have received both liberal and social democratic impulses. Social insurance schemes have been substantially destratified and unified in Austria, Germany, France, and Italy. Their extremely corporativist character has thus been reduced. Notwithstanding the lack of purity, if our essential criteria for defining welfare states have to do with the quality of social rights, social stratification, and the relationship between state, market, and family, the world is composed of distinct regime clusters. Comparing welfare states on scales based on more or less or, indeed, better or worse, will yield highly misleading results. The causes of welfare state regimes If welfare states cluster into three distinct regime types, we are confronted with a substantially more complex task of identifying the causes of welfare state differences. What is the explanatory power of industrialization, economic growth, capitalism, or working-class political power in accounting for regime types? A first superficial answer would be: very little. The nations we study are all more or less similar with regard to all but the working-class mobilization variable. And we find very powerful labor movements and parties in each of the three clusters. A theory of welfare state developments must clearly reconsider its causal assumptions if we wish to explain clusters. The hope to find one single powerful causal motor must be abandoned; the task is to identify salient interaction effects. Based on the preceding arguments, three factors in particular should be of importance: the nature of (especially working-) class mobilization; class-political coalition structures; and the historical legacy of regime institutionalization. As we have noted, there is absolutely no compelling reason to believe that workers will automatically and naturally forge a socialist class identity; nor is it plausible that their mobilization will look especially Swedish. The actual historical formation of working-class collectivities will diverge, and so also will their aims and political capacities. Fundamental differences appear both in trade unionism and party development. A key element in trade unionism is the mix of craft and industrial unions. The former is prone to particularism and corporativism; the latter is inclined to articulate broader, more universal objectives. This blend decisively affects the scope for labor party FALL 1990 115 action and also the nature of political demands. Thus, the dominance of the American Federation of Labor (AFL) in pre-World War II United States was a major impediment to social policy development. Likewise, the heavily craft-oriented Danish labor movement, compared to its Norwegian and Swedish counterparts, blocked social democracy's aspirations for an active labor market policy for full employment. In the United States, craft unions believed that negotiating occupational benefits was a superior strategy, given their privileged market position. In Denmark, craft unions jealously guarded their monopoly on training and labor mobility. Conversely, centralized industrial unionism tends to present a more unified and consolidated working-class clientele to the labor party, making policy consensus easier, and power mobilization more effective. It is clear, therefore, that a working-class mobilization thesis must pay attention to union structure. Equally decisive is political or denominational union fragmentation. In many nations, for example, Finland, France, and Italy, trade unionists are divided between socialist and communist parties; white-collar unions are politically unaffiliated or divide their affiliation among several parties. Denominational trade unionism has been a powerful feature in the Netherlands, Italy, and other nations. Since trade unionism is such a centrally important basis for party mobilization, such fragmentation will weaken the left and thus benefit the nonsocialist parties' chances of power. In addition, fragmentation may entail that welfare state demands will be directed to many parties at once. The result may be less party conflict over social policy, but it may also mean a plurality of competing welfare state principles. For example, the subsidiarity principle of Christian workers will conflict with the socialists' concern for the emancipation of women. The structure of trade unionism mayor may not be reflected in labor party formation. But, under what conditions are we likely to expect certain welfare state outcomes from specific party configurations? There are many factors that conspire to make it virtually impossible to assume that any labor or left party will ever be capable, singlehandedly, of structuring a welfare state. Denominational or other divisions aside, it will be only under extraordinary historical circumstances that a labor party alone will command a parliamentary majority long enough to impose its will. We have noted that the traditional working class has, nowhere, ever been an electoral majority. It follows that a theory of class mobilization must look beyond the major leftist party. It 116 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY is a historical fact that welfare state construction has depended on political coalition building. The structure of class coalitions is much more decisive than are the power resources of any single class. The emergence of alternative class coalitions is, in part, determined by class formation. In the earlier phases of industrialization, the rural classes usually constituted the single largest electorate. If social democrats wanted political majorities, it was here that they were forced to look for allies. Therefore, it was ironically the rural economy that was decisive for the future of socialism. Where the rural economy was dominated by small, capital-intensive family farmers, the potential for an alliance was greater than if it depended on large pools of cheap labor. And, where farmers were politically articulate and well organized (as in Scandinavia), the capacity to negotiate political deals was vastly superior. The role of the farmers in coalition formation and, hence, in welfare state development is clear. In the Nordic countries, the conditions provided for a broad red-green alliance for a full employment welfare state in return for farm price subsidies. This was especially true in Norway and Sweden. where farming was highly precarious and dependent on state aid. In the United States, the New Deal was premised on a similar coalition (forged by the Democratic party) but with the important difference that the labor-intensive South blocked a truly universalistic social security system and opposed further welfare state developments. In contrast. the rural economy of continental Europe was very inhospitable to red-green coalitions. Often, as in Germany and Italy. much of agriculture was labor-intensive and labor unions and left parties were seen as a threat. In addition. the conservative forces on the continent had succeeded in incorporating farmers into "reactionary" alliances, helping to consolidate the political isolation of labor. Political dominance was. before World War II. largely a question of rural class politics. The construction of welfare states in this period was, therefore. dictated by which force captured the farmers. The absence of a red-green alliance does not necessarily imply that no welfare state reforms were possible. On the contrary. it implies which political force came to dominate their design. The United Kingdom is an exception to this general rule because the political significance of the rural classes eroded before the turn of the nineteenth century. In this way. the United Kingdom's coalition logic showed at an early date FALL 1990 117 the dilemma that faced most other nations later, namely that the new white-collar middle classes constitute the linchpin for political majorities. The consolidation of welfare states after World War II came to depend fundamentally on the political alliances of the new middle classes. For social democracy, the challenge was to synthesize workingclass and white-collar demands without sacrificing the commitment to solidarity. Since the new middle classes have, historically, enjoyed a relatively privileged position in the market, they have also been quite successful in meeting their welfare demands outside the state or as civil servants by privileged state welfare. Their employment security has traditionally been such that full employment has been a peripheral concern. Finally, any program for drastic income equalization is likely to be met with great hostility among a middle-class clientele. On these grounds, it would appear that the rise of the new middle classes would abort the social democratic project and strengthen a liberal welfare state formula The political position of the new middle classes has, indeed, been decisive for welfare state consolidation. Their role in shaping the three welfare state regimes described earlier is clear. The Scandinavian, or social democratic, model relied almost entirely on social democracy's capacity to incorporate the middle class in a new kind of welfare state: one that provided benefits tailored to the tastes and expectations of the middle classes, but nonetheless retained universalism of rights. Indeed, by expanding social services and public employment, the welfare state participated directly in manufacturing a middle class instrumentally devoted to social democracy. In contrast, the Anglo-Saxon nations retained the residual liberal welfare state model precisely because the new middle classes were not wooed from the market into the state. In class terms, the consequence is dualism. The welfare state caters essentially to the working class and the poor. Private insurance and occupational fringe benefits cater to the middle classes. Given the electoral importance of the latter, it is quite logical that further extensions of welfare state activities are resisted. Indeed, the most powerful thrust in these countries is an accent on fiscal welfare; that is, on tax expenditures and deductions for private sector welfare plans. The third, or corporativist welfare regime of continental Europe, has also been patterned by the new middle classes, but in a different way. The cause is historical. Developed by conservative political forces, 118 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY these regimes institutionalized a middle-class loyalty to the preservation of both occupationally segregated social insurance programs and, ultimately, to the political forces that brought them into being. Adenauer's great pension reform in 1957 was explicitly designed to resurrect middle-class loyalties. Conclusion We have presented an alternative to a simple class mobilization theory of welfare state development. It is motivated by the analytical necessity of shifting from a linear to an interactive approach with regard to both welfare states and their historical foundations. If we wish to study welfare states, we must begin with a set of criteria that define their role in society. This role is certainly not to spend or tax, nor is it necessarily that of creating equality. We have presented a framework for comparing welfare states that takes into consideration the principles for which the historical actors willingly have struggled and mobilized. And, when we focus on the principles embedded in welfare states, we discover distinct regime clusters, not merely variations of "more" or "less" around a common denominator. The salient forces that explain the crystallization of regime differences are interactive. They involve, first, the pattern of working class political formation and, second, the structuralization of political coalitions with the historical shift from a rural economy to a middle-class society. The question of political coalition formation is decisive. Third, past reforms have contributed decisively to the institutionalization of class preferences and political behavior. In the corporatist regimes, hierarchical status-distinctive social insurance cemented middle-class loyalty to a peculiar type of welfare state. In the liberal regimes, the middle classes became institutionally wedded to the market. And, in Scandinavia, the fortunes of social democracy after World War II were closely tied to the establishment of a middle-class welfare state that benefited both its traditional working-class clientele and the new white-collar strata. In part, the Scandinavian social democrats were able to do so because the private welfare market was relatively undeveloped and, in part, because they were capable of building a welfare state with features of sufficient lUXUry to satisfy the tastes of a more discriminating pUblic. This also explains the extraordinarily high cost of Scandinavian welfare states. FALL 1990 119 But, a theory that seeks to explain welfare state growth should also be able to understand its retrenchment or decline. It is typically believed that welfare state backlash movements, tax revolts, and rollbacks are ignited when social expenditure burdens become too heavy. Paradoxically, the opposite is true. Anti-welfare state sentiments over the past decade have generally been weakest where welfare spending has been heaviest, and vice versa. Why? The risks of welfare state backlash depend not on spending, but on the class character of welfare states. Middle-class welfare states, be they social democratic (as in Scandinavia) or corporatist (as in Germany), forge middle-class loyalties. In contrast, liberal, residualist welfare states found in the United States, Canada, and, increasingly, the United Kingdom depend on the loyalties of a numerically weak, and often politically residual social stratum. In this sense, the class coalitions in which the three welfare states were founded explain not only their past evolution but also their future prospects. Notes I. Adam Smith is often cited but rarely read. A closer inspection of his writings reveals a degree of nuance and a battery of reservations that substantially qualify a delirious enthusiasm for the blessings of capitalism. 2. In the Wealth of Nations (Smith 1961, vol. 2, 236), Smith comments on states that uphold the privilege and security of the propertied as follows: " ... civil government, so far as it is instituted for the security of property, is in reality instituted for the defense of the rich against the poor, or of those who have some property against those who have none at all.·· 3. This tradition is virtually unknown to Anglo-Saxon readers. since so little has been translated into English. A key text. which greatly influenced public debate and later social legislation, is Adolph Wagner's Rede Uber die Soziale Frage (1872). For an English language overview of this tradition of political economy, see Schumpeter (1954), and especially Bower (1947). From the Catholic tradition, the fundamental texts are the two Papal Encycli· cals. Rerum Novarum (1891). see Rutter 1932. and Quadrogesimo Anno (Pius XI 1938). The social Catholic political economy's main advocacy is a social organization where a strong family is integrated in cross-class corporations. aided by the state in terms of the subsidiarity principle. For a recent discussion. see Richter (1987). Like the liberals. the conservative political economists also have their contemporary echoes. although they are substantially fewer in number. A revival occurred with Fascism's concept of the Corporative ("Standiche") state of Ottmar Spann in Germany. The subsidiary principle still guides much of German Christian Democratic politics (see Richter 1987). 120 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY 4. Chief proponents of this analysis are members of the German "state derivation" school (Milller and Neusilss 1973; Offe 1972; O'Connor 1973; Gough 1979; see also the work of Poulantzas (1973). As Skocpol and Amenta (1986) note in their excellent overview, the approach is far from one-dimensional. Thus, Offe, O'Connor, and Gough identify the function of social reforms as also being concessions to mass demands and as potentially contradictory. Historically, socialist opposition to parliamentary reforms was principled less by theory than by reality. August Bebel, the great leader of German social democracy, rejected Bismarck's pioneering social legislation, not because he did not favor social protection, but because of the blatantly anti-socialist and divisionary motives behind Bismarck's reforms. 5. This realization came from two types of experiences. One, typified by Swedish socialism in the 1920s, was the discovery that not even the working-class base showed much enthusiasm for socialization. In fact, when the Swedish socialists established a special commission to prepare plans for socialization, it concluded after ten years of exploration that it would be practically quite impossible to undertake. A second kind of experience, typified by the Norwegian socialists and Blum's Popular Front government in 1936, was the discovery that radical proposals could easily be sabotaged by the capitalists' capacity to withhold investments and export their capital abroad. 6. This is obviously not a problem for the parliamentary class hypothesis alone; structural Marxism faces the same problem of specifying the class character of the new middle classes. If such a specification fails to demonstrate that it constitutes a new working class, both varieties of Marxist theory face severe (although not identical) problems. 7. This literature has been reviewed in great detail by a number of authors. See. for example. Wilensky et al. (1985). For excellent and more critical evaluations. see Uusitalo (1984), Shalev (1983). and Skocpol and Amenta (1986). 8. This section derives much of its material from earlier writings (see. especially Esping-Andersen (1985a; 1985b; 1987). References Bell. D. 1978. The Cultural Contradictions of Capitalism. New York: Basic Books. Bendix. R. 1964. Nation-Building and Citizenship. New York: Wiley. Block. F. 1977. "The Ruling Class does not Rule." Socialist Revolution 7 (May- lune):6-28. Bower. R. H. 1947. German Theories of the Corporate State. New York: Russel and Russel. Bowles. S. and Gintis. H. 1986. Democracy and Capitalism. New York: Basic Books. Cameron. D. 1978. "The Expansion of the Public Economy: A Comparative Analysis." American Political Science Re\'iew 72: 124HI. Castles. F. 1978. The Social Democratic Image of Society. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. ---. ed. 1982. Thclmpact ofPanies. London: Sage. FALL 1990 121 Cutright, P. 1965. "Political Structure, Economic Development, and National Social Security Programs." American Journal ofSociology 70:537-50. Day, L. 1978. "Government Pensions for the Aged in 19 Industrialized Countries." In R. Tomasson, ed., Comparative Studies in Sociology. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. Dich, 1. 1973. Den Herskende Klasse. Copenhagen: Borgen. Dobb, M. 1946. Studies in the Development of Capitalism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Esping-Andersen, G. 1985a. Politics against Markets. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ---. 1985b. "Power and Distributional Regimes." Politics and Society 14:223-56. ---. 1987. "Citizenship and Socialism: De-commodification and Solidarity in the Welfare State." In M. Rein, G. Esping-Andersen, and L. Rainwater, eds., Stagnation and Renewal. Annonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe. Esping-Andersen, G., and Friedland, R. 1982. "Class Coalitions in the Making of West European Economies." Political Power and Social Theory 3: I-52. Esping-Andersen, G., and Korpi, W. 1984. "Social Policy as Class Politics in Postwar Capitalism." In J. Goldthorpe, ed., Order and Conflict in Contemporary Capitalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. ---. 1986. "From Poor Relief to Institutional Welfare States." In R. Erikson et aI., eds., The Scandinavian Model. Annonk, NY: M. E. Sharpe. Flora, P., and Alber, J. 1981. "Modernization, Democratization and the Development of Welfare States in Europe." In P. Flora and A. Heidenheimer, eds., The Development of Welfare States in Europe and America. London: Transaction Books. Flora, P., and Heidenheimer, A., eds. 1981. The Development ofWelfare States in Europe and America. London: Transaction Books. Gough, I. 1979. The Political Economy ofthe Welfare State. London: Macmillan. Gourevitch, P. 1986. Politics in Hard Times. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Heimann, E. 1929. Soziale Theorie des Kapitalismus. Reprint 1980. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp. Hewitt, C. 1977. "The Effect of Political Democracy and Social Democracy on Equality in Industrial Societies." American Sociological Review 42:450-64. Jessop, B. 1982. The Capitalist State. Oxford: Martin Robertson. Katzenstein, P. 1985. Small States in World Markets. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Korpi, W. 1980. "Social Policy and Distributional Conflict in the Capitalist Democracies. " West European Politics 3:296-316. ---. 1983. The Democratic Class Struggle. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Marshall, A. 1920. Principles ofEconomics. 8th ed. London: Macmillan. Marshall, T. H. 1950. Citi:enship and Social Class. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Myles, 1. 1984. Old Age in Ihe Welfare State. Boston: Little, Brown, and Co. Myrdal, A., and Myrdal. G. 1936. Kris i Befolkningsfragan. Stockholm: Tiden. O'Connor, 1. 1973. Tile Fiscal Crisis oflile Slale. New York: St. Martin's Press. 122 INTERNATIONAL JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY Offe, C. 1972. "Advanced Capitalism and the Welfare State." Politics and Society 2, no. 4:479-88. ---. 1985. Disorganized Capitalism. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Ogus, A. 1979. "Social Insurance, Legal Development and Legal History." In H. F. Zacher ed, Bedingungen fur die Entstehung von Sozialversicherung. Berlin: Duncker and Humboldt. Okun, A. 1975. Equality and Efficiency: The Big Trade-Off. Washington DC: Brookings Institute. Pius XI. 1938. On Reconstruction of the Social Order (QA.) Encyclical of His Holiness Pope Pius XI. New York: The America Press. Polanyi, K. 1944. The Great Transformation. New York: Rhinehart. Poulantzas, N. 1973. Political Power and Social Classes. London: New Left Books. Pryor, F. 1969. Public Expenditures in Communist and Capitalist Nations. London: Allen and Unwin. Przworski, A. 1980. "Material Bases of Consent: Politics and Economics in a Hegemonic System." Political Power and Social Theory 1:21-66. ---. 1985. Capitalism and Social Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Richter, E. 1987. "Subsidiaritat und Neoconservatismus." Politische Vierteljahresschrift 28 (September):293-3 14. Robbins, L. 1976. Political Economy Past and Present. London: Macmillan. Rokkan, S. 1970. Citizens, Elections, Parties. Oslo: Universitetsforlaget. Rutten, G. 1932. La doctrine sociale de /'Eglise resumee dans les ensycliques Rerum novarum et Quadragesimo anno. Paris: Editiones du Cerf. Schmidt, M. 1982. "The Role of Parties in Shaping Macro-economic Policies." In F. Castles, ed., The Impact of Parties. London: Sage. ---. 1983. "The Welfare State and the Economy in Periods of Economic Crisis." European Journal ofPolitical Research II: 1-26. Schmitter, P., and Lembruch, G. 1979. Trends Toward Corporatist Intermediation. London: Sage. Schumpeter, 1. 1954. History of Economic Analysis. New York: Oxford University Press. Shalev, M. 1983. "The Social Democratic Model and Beyond." Comparative Social Research 6:315-51. Shonfield, A. 1965. Modern Capitalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Skocpol, T., and Amenta, E. 1986. "States and Social Policies." Annual Review ofSociology 12:131-57. Smith, A. 1961. The Wealth ofNations. Edited by E. Cannan. London: Methuen. Stephens, 1. 1979. The Transition from Capitalism to Socialism. London: Mac- millan. Therbom, G. 1983. "When. How and Why does a Welfare State become a Welfare State?" Paper presented at the European Consortium for Political Research (ECPR) Workshops. Freiburg. March. ---. 1986. "Karl Marx Returning. The Welfare State and Neo-Marxist. Corporatist and Statist Theories." International Political Science Rel'iew 7. no. 2: 131-{)4. Titmuss. R. 1958. Essays 011 the WC'lfare State. London: Allen and Unwin. FALL 1990 123 Tufte, E. 1978. Political Control of the Economy. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Uusitalo, H. 1984. "Comparative Research on the Detenninants of the Welfare State: The State of the Art." European Journal of Political Research 12, no. 4:403-22. Wagner, A. 1872. Rede uber die Soziale Frage. Berlin: Wiegandt und Grieben. ---. 1962. Finanzwissenschaft (1883). Reproduced partly in R. A. Musgrave and A. Peacock, eds., Classics in the Theory of Public Finance. London: Macmillan. Weir, M., and Skocpol, T. 1985. "State Structures and the Possibilities for Keynesean Responses to the Great Depression in Sweden, Britain, and the United States." In P. Evans et aI., eds., Bringing the State Back In. New York: Cambridge University Press. Wilensky, H. 1975. The Welfare State and Equality. Berkeley: University of California Press. ---. 1981. " Leftism, Catholicism, and Democratic Corporatism." In P. Aora and A. Heidenheimer, eds., The Development of Welfare States in Europe and America. London: Transaction Books. Wilensky, H., and Lebeaux, C. 1958. Industrial Society and Social Welfare. New York: Russel Sage. Wilensky. H., et al. 1985. " Comparative Social Policy: Theory, Methods, Findings." Research Series no. 62. Berkeley: International Studies.