The help of Elizabeth Case, associate ed.tor for th« series, ^j^J** at Cambridge University Pres., and Emily Loose editor at Cambr.dge Un.v'irv U b gratefully acknowledged Patty ^ P_,ded Visional editorial and production support that •mProvCdPthc quality of the manuscript. Her cheerful spirit has reheved pressures oil many occasions. Reflections on the commons Hardly a week goes by without a major news story about the threatened destruction of a valuable natural resource. In June of \^H9, for example, a New York Times article focused on the problem of overfishing in the Georges Bank about ISO miles off the New England coast. Catches of cod, flounder, and haddock arc now only a quarter of what they were during the 1960s. Everyone knows that the basic problem is overfishing; however, those concerned cannot agree how to solve the problem. Congressional representatives recommend new national legislation, even though the legislation already mi the hunks has been enforced only erratically. Representatives of the fishers argue that the fishing grounds would nor be in toch bad shape if the federal government had refrained from its sporadic attempts to regulate the fishery in the past. The issue in this case - and mam/ others - is how best to limit the use of natural resources so as to ensure their long-term economic viability. Advocates of centra] regulation, of privatisation, and of regulation by those involved have pressed their policy prescriptions in a variety of different arenas. Similar situations occur on diverse scales ranging from small neighborhoods to the entire planeT. The issues of how best to govern natural resources .used by many individuals in common are no more settled in acidemia than in the world of politics. Some scholarly arcicles about the *tragedy of the commons" recommend that "the state** control most natural resources to prevent their destruction; others recommend that privatizing those resources will resolve the problem. What one can ob^'i w- i;i the world, however, is that neither the state nor the market is uniformly successful in enabling individuals ro sustain long-term, productive use of natural resource systems. Further, communities of individuals have relied 0*1 institutions resembling neither the state nor the market to govern some resource systems with reasonable degrees of success over long periods of time. xviii Governing the commons We do not yet have the necessary intellectual tools or models to under* M.ind the array of problems thai arc associated with governing and managing natural resource systems and the reasons why some institutions seem to work in some settings and not others. This book is an effort to (1) critique the foundations of policy analysis as applied to many natural resources, (2) present empirical examples ol successful and unsuccessful efforts to govern and manage such resources, and (3) begin the effort to develop better intellectual tools to understand the capabilities and limitations of self-governing institutions for regulating many types of resources. To do this, 1 first describe the three models most frequently used to provide a foundation for recommending state or market solutions. 1 then pose theoretical and empirical alternatives to these models to begin to illustrate the diversity of solutions that go licyond state-, and markets. Using an institutional mode of analysis, I then attempt to explain how communities of individuals fashion different ways of governing the commons. THREE INFLUENTIAL MODELS The tragedy of the commons Since Garrett Hardin's challenging article in Science (1968), the expression "the tragedy of the commons'" has come to symbolize the degradation of the environment to be expected whenever many individuals use a scarce resource in common. To illustrate the logical structure of his model, Hardin asks the reader to envision a pasture "open to all." He then examines the structure of this situation from the perspective of a rational herder. Each herder receives a direct benefit from his own animals and suffers delayed costs from the deterioration of the commons when his and others' cattle overgraze, Each herder is motivated to add more and more animals because he receives the direct benefit of his own animals and bears only a share of the costs resulting from overgrazing. Hardin concludes: Therein i\ ihe tragedy. Each man is locked into a system th;it compels him to increa.se his herd without limit in a world that is limned. Ruin is the dcsriiurion toward which all men rush, each pursuing his own best interest in a society that believe* in the freedom of the common*, (Hardin 1968. p. 1,244) Hardin was not the first to notice the tragedy of the commons. Aristotle long ago observed that "what is common to the greatest number has the least care bestowed upon it, Everyone thinks chiefly of his own, hardly at all of the common interest" (Politics. Book II, ch. 3). Hobbes's parable of man in a state of nature is a prototype of the tragedy of the commons: Men Reflections on the commons seek their own good and end up fighting one another. In 1833, William Forster Lloyd (1977) sketched I theory oi the commons that predicted improvident use for property owned in common. More tlinn a decade before Hardin's article, H. Scott Gordon (1954) clearly expounded similar logic in another classic: "The Economic Theory of a Common-Property Research: I he fishery." Gordon described the same dynamic as Hardin: There appears then, to be some truth in the conservative dicrum that everybody's property is nobody's property. Wealth that is free for all is valued by no one because he who is foolhardy enough lo wait foi i(s proper lime of use will only find that tt has been taken by another. , . , The fish in the sea arc valueless to the fisherman, because there ts no assurance chat they will be there for him tomorrow if they arc left behind today. (Gordon 1954, p. 124) John H. Dales (1968, p, r>2) noted at the same time the perplexing problems related to resources "owned in common because there is no alternative!" Standard analyses in modern resource economics conclude that where a numl>cr of users have access to a common-pool rcsonn r, the total of resource units withdrawn from the resource will be greater than the optimal economic level of withdrawal (Clark 1976, 1980; Dasgupta and Heal 1979). If the only "commons" of importance were a few grazing areas or fisheries, the tragedy of the commons would be of little general interest. That is not the case. Hardin himself used the grazing commons as a metaphor for the general problem of overpopulation. The "tragedy of the commons" has been used to describe such diverse problems as the Saheltan famine of the 1970s (Picardi and Seifert 1977), firewood crises throughout the Third World (Norman 1984; Thomson 1977), the problem of acid rain (R. Wilson 1985}, the organization of the Mormon Church (Mullock and Baden 1977), the inability of the U.S. Congress to limit its capacity to overspend (Shcpsic and Weingast 1984), urban crime (Neher 1978), pub lic-scctor/privatc-sector relationships in modern economies (Scharpf 1985, 1987, 1988), the problems of international cooperation (Snidal 1985), and communal conflict in Cyprus (I.umsden 1973). Much of the world is dependent on resources that are sub|ect to the possibility of a tragedy of the commons. The prisoner's dilemma game Hardin's model has often been formalized as a prisoner's dilemma (PD) game (Dawes 1973, 1975).' Suppose we chink of the players in a game as being herders using a common grazing meadow. For this meadow, there is an upper limit ED the number of animals that can graze on the meadow for Governing the commons a season and be well ted at the end of the season. We call that number L. For a two-person game, the "cooperate" strategy can l>c thought of as grazing Ul animals for each herder. The "delect" strategy is for each herder to graze as many animals as he thinks he can sell at a profit {given his private costs), assuming that this number is greater than IJ2. If both herders limit their grazing to L/2, they will obtain 10 units ul profit, whereas if they both choose the defect strategy they will obtain zero profit. If one of them limits his number of animals to Ul, while the other grazes as many as he wants, the "defector" obtains 11 units of profit, and the "sucker" obtains -1. If each chooses independently without the capacity to engage in a binding contract, each chooses his dominant strategy, which is to defect. When they both defect, they obtain zero profit. Call this the Hardin herder game, or dame 1. Ii has the structure of a prisoner's dilemma game.1 The prisoner's dilemma game is conceptualized as a noncoopcrarive game in which all players possess complete information. In noncoopcrarive games, communication among the players is forbidden or impossible or simply irrelevant as long as it is not explicitly modeled as part of the game. If communication is possible, verbal agreements among players are presumed tO be nonbifldihg unless the possibility of binding agreements is explicitly incorporated in the game structure (I larsanyi and Selten 1988, p. 3). "Complete information" implies that all players know the full structure of the game tree and the payoffs attached to outcomes. Players cither know or do not know the current moves <>1 other players depending on whether or not they are observable. In a prisoner's dilemma game, each player has a dominant strategy in the sense that the player is always better off choosing this strategy - lo defect 10 11 0 10 11 -1 0 c\ /b /o < _ Figure 1.1, Game 1: I lie H»rd.n berder gamc- RrJ'lectioHi-, un the commoTis -no matter what the other player chooses. When both players choose their dominant strategy, given these assumptions, they produce an equilibrium that is the third-best result for both. Neither has an incentive to change that is independent of the strategy choice of the other, I he equilibrium resulting from each player ^electing his or her "best" individual strategy is, however, not a Parcto-optimal outcome. A Pareto-optimal outcome occurs when there is no other outcome strictly preferred by at least one player that is at least as good for the others. In the two-person prisoner's dilemma game, both players prefer the (cooperate, cooperate) outcome to the (defect, defect) outcome. Thus, the equilibrium outcome is Parcio inferior. The prisoner's dilemma game fascinates scholars. The paradox that individually rational strategies lead :o .> DecnveU irrarnnal outcomes seems to challenge a fundamental faith that rational human beings can achieve ration,ii results. In the introduction to a recently published book, Paradoxes of Rationality and Cooperation, Richmond Campbell explains the "deep attraction'* of the dilemma: Quite simply, these paradoxes cast in dnubt our understanding of rationality ami, in the case ot the Prisoner's Dilemma suggest that it is impossible for rational crcjrures to cooperate. Thus, they hear directly on fundamental issues in ethics and political philosophy and threaten the foundations of the social sciences, It is the Scope of these consequences that explains why these paradoxes Imvc drawn so much attention and why they command a central place in philosophical discussion. (Campbell 1985, p. 3) The deep attraction of the dilemma is further illustrated by the number of articles written about it. At one count, 15 years ago, more than 2,000 papers had been devoted to the prisoner's dilemma game (Grofman and Pool 1975). The logic of collective action A closely related view of the difficulty of getting individuals to pursue their joint welfare, as contrasted to individual welfare, was developed by Man-cur Olson (1965) in T/v Logic Collective Action. Olson specifically set out to challenge the grand optimism expressed in group theory: that individuals wiili common interests would voluntarily acr. so as to try to further those interests (Bentley 1949; Truman 1958). On the first page of his book, Olson summarized thai accepted view: The idea that groups tend to act in support ot their group interest?, is supposed lo follow logically from this widely accepted premise of rational, self-interested be-havinr, In other words, if the members of some group have a common interest or object, and if they would all he better off if that objective were achieved, it has been Governing the commons thought to follow logically that the individual* in that group would, if they were rational and self-interested, act to achieve that objective. (Olson 1965, p.!) Olson challenged the presumption that the possibility of a benefit for a group would be sufficient to generate collective action to achieve that benefit. In (lie most frequently quoted passage of hi* hook, Olson argued that unless the number of individuals is quite small, or unless there is coercion or some nihri special device to make individuals ail in (heir common interest, rational, self-interested individuals will not act to achieve their common or gfOHp intrr-ests (Olson 1965, p. 2; emphasis in original) Olson's argument rests largely on the premise that one who cannot be excluded from obtaining the benefits of a collective good once the good is produced has little incentive to contribute voluntarily to the provision of that good. His book is less pessimistic than it is asserted to be by many who cite this famous passage. Olson considers it an open question whether intermediate-size groups will or will not voluntarily provide collective benefits. His definition of an intermediate-size group depends not on the number of .u tors involved but on how noticeable each person's actions are. The tragedy of the commons, the prisoner's dilemma, and the logic of collective action arc closely related concepts in the models that have defined the accepted way of viewing many problems that individuals face when attempting to achieve collective hem-lils. At f he heart «>l each id i hrsc models is the free-rider problem. Whenever one person cannot be excluded from the benefits that others provide, each person is motivated not to contribute to the joint effort, but to free-ride on the efforts of others. If all participants choose to free-ride, the collective benefit will not be produced. The temptation to free-ride, however, may dominate the decision process, and thus all will end up where no one wanted to be. Alternatively, some may provide while others free-ride, leading to less than the optimal level of provision of the collective benefit. These models are thus extremely useful for explaining how perfectly rational individuals can produce, under some circumstances, outcomes that are not "rational" when viewed from the perspective of all those involved. What makes these models so interesting and so powerful is that they capture important aspects of many different problems that occur in diverse settings in all parts of the world. What makes these models so dangerous - when they are used metaphorically as the foundation for policy - is that the constraints that are assumed to be fixed for the purpose of analysis are taken on faith as being fixed in empirical settings, unless <■ sternal author- Reflections on the commons icics change them.1 The prisoners in the famous dilemma cannot change the constraints imposed on them by the district attorney; they are in jail. Not all users of natm.il icsourccs are similarly itu.ipablc <>| changing their constraints. As long as individuals are viewed as prisoners, policy prescriptions will address this metaphor. I would rather address the question of how to enhance the capabilities of those involved to change the constraining rules of the game to lead to outcomes other than remorseless tragedies. THH METAPHORICAL USE OF MODELS These three models and their many variants arc diverse representations of a broader and stilt-evolving theory of collective action. Much more work will be needed to develop the theory of collective action into a reliable and useful foundation for policy analysis. Considerable progress has been made during the past three decades by theorists and empirically oriented social scientists. The sweeping conclusions of the first variants of this theory have given way to a more qualified body of knowledge involving many more variables and explicit base conditions. As an evolving, rather than completed, theory, it provokes disagreement regarding the importance or insignificance of some variables and how best ro specify key relationships,4 The results from more recent work, particularly work focusing on the dynamic aspects of relevant empirical settings, have begun ro generate more optimistic predictions than did earlier models; see, in particular, the work of Axel rod (19S1, 1984) and Kreps and Wilson (14S2). This is one of the most exciting areas in the social sciences, for although considerable cumulation has already occurred, some deep questions remain unanswered. Some of these puzzles arc key to understanding how individuals jointly using a common pool resource might be able to achieve an effective form of governing and managing their own commons. These puzzles arc examined in Chapter 2. Much (hat has been written about common-pool resources, however, has uncritically accepted the earlier models and the presumption of a remorseless tragedy (Nebel 1987). Scholars have gone so far as to recommend thai "Hardin's 'Tragedy of the Commons' should be required reading for all students . .. and, if I had my way, for all human beings."1 Policy prescriptions have relied to a large extent on one of the three • r11i-■ a models, but those attempting to use these models as the basis for policy prescription frequently have achieved htile morr than a metaphorical use of the models. 'When models arc used as metaphors, an author usually points to the similarity berwecn one or two variables in a natural setting and one or two 7 Governing the commons variables in a model. If calling attention to similarities is all that is intended by the metaphor, it serves the usual purpose of rapidly conveying information in graphic form. These three models have frequently been used metaphorically, however, for another purpose. The similarity between the many individuals jointly using a resource in a natural setting and the many individuals jointly producing a suboptimal result in the model has been used to convey a sense that further similarities arc present. My referring to natural settings as "tragedies of the commons." "collective action problems," "prisoner's dilemmas," "open at cess resouiccs," or even "common-property resources," the observer frequently wishes to invoke an image of helpless individuals caught in an inexorable process of destroying their own resources. Ail article in the December 10, 1988, issue of Tht Fxon-nmist goes so far as to assert that fisheries can be managed successfully only if it is recognized that "left to their own devices, fisherman will overexploit stocks," and "to avoid disaster, managers must have effective hegemony over them." Public officials sometimes do no more than evoke grim images by briefly alluding to the popularized versions ot :hc models, presuming, as self-evident, that the same processes occur in all natural settings. The Canadian minister of fisheries and oceans, for example, captured the color of the models in a 1980 speech: If you let loose that kind of economic self-interest in fisheries, with everybody fishing as he wants, taking from a resource ih.it belongs to no individual, you end tip destroying your neighbour .mil yoursell. In free fisheries, good times create bad times, attracting more and more boats to chase fewer and fewer fish, producing less and less money to divide among more and more people. (Romeo l.cBlanc, speaking at the 50th anniversary meenng of the United Maritime l-ishermcti, March I 9, 1980; quoted by Matthews and Phync 1988) The implication, of course, was that Canadian fisheries universally met that description - an empirically incorrect inference." But many observers have come to assume that most resources are like those specified in the three models. As such, it has been assumed that the individuals have been caught in a grim trap. The resulting policy recommendation! have had an equally grim character. CURRENT POLICY PRESCRIPTIONS Leviathan as the "only" way Ophuls (1973, p. 228) argued, for example, that "because of the tragedy of the commons, environmental problems cannot be solved through cooperation ,.. and the rationale for government with major coercive 8 Reflections on the commons powers is overwhelming." Ophuls concluded that "even if we avoid the tragedy of the commons, it will only be by recourse to the tragic necessity of Leviathan' (!'' p. emphasis added). Carrcti I lardm argued a decade after his earlier article that we are enveloped in ■ "cloud of ignorance" about "the true nanire of the fundamental political systems and the effect at each on the preservation of the environment" (1978, p. 310). The "cloud ui ignorance" did not, however, prevent him from presuming chat the only alternatives to the commons dilemma were what he called "a private enterprise system," on the one hand, or "socialism," on the other (1978, p. 314). With the assurance of one convinced that "the alternative of the commons is too horrifying to i oriiemplale" (1 96H, y. 1,247), I l.irdin indicated that change would have to be instituted with "whatever force may be required to make the change stick" (1978, p. 314). In other words, "if ruin is to be avoided in a crowded world, people must be responsive to a coercive force outside their individual psyches, a '1 eviathan,' to use Hobbcs's term'" (Hardin 1978, p. 314). The presumption that an external leviathan is necessary to avoid tragedies of the commons leads to recommendations that central governments control most natural resource systems. Hc.lbroner (1974) opined that "iron governments," perhaps military governments, would be necessary to achieve control over ecological problems. In a less draco ni.in view, I'hrcn-feld (1972, p. 322) suggested that if "private interests cannot be expected to protect the public domain then external regulation by public agencies, governments, or international authorities is needed." In an analysis of the problems involved in water resource management in developing countries, Camifhrrs and Stoner (1981, p. 29) argued that without public control, "overgrazing and soil erosion of communal pastures, or less fish at higher average cost," would result. They concluded that "common property resources require public control if economic efficiency is to result from their development" (1981, p. 29; emphasis added).' The policy advice to centralize the control and regulation of natural resources, such as grazing lands, forests, and fisheries, has been followed extensively, particularly in Third World countries. One way to illustrate these proponents' image of centralized control is to modify the ILmlin herder game using the assumptions that underlie this policy advice. The proponents of centralized control want an external government agency to decide the specific herding strategy that the central authority considrrs best for the situation: The central authority will decide who can use the meadow, when they can use it, and how many animals can be grazed. Let us assume that the central authority decides to impose a penalty of 2 profit units on anyone who is considered by that authority to Governing the commons be using a defect strategy. Assuming that the central agency knows the sustainable yield of the meadow {L) and can unfailingly discover and penalize any herder using the defect strategy, The newly restructured game imposed by the central authority is represented in Game 2. Now, the solution to Game 2 is (cooperate, cooperate). Both players receive 10 profit units each, rather than the zero units they would have received in Game 1. If an external authority accurately determines the capacity of a common-pool resource, unambiguously assigns this capacity, monitors actions, and unfailingly sanctions noncompliance, then a centralized agency can transform the Hardin herder game to generate an optimally efficient equilibrium for the herders. Little consideration is given to the cost of creating and maintaining such an agency. This is seen as exogenous to the problem and is not included as a parameter of Game 2.* The optimal equilibrium achieved by following the advice to centralize control, however, is based on assumptions concerning the accuracy of information, monitoring capabilities, sanctioning reliability, and zero costs of administration. Without valid and reliable information, a central agency could make several errors, including setting the carrying capacity or the fine too high or too low, sanctioning herders who cooperate, or not sanctioning defectors. The implications of all forms of incomplete information arc interesting. However, as an example, I shall focus entirely on the implications arising from a central agency's incomplete information about the herders' strategies. The implicit assumption of Game 2 is that the central agency monitors all actions of the herders costle&sly and imposes sanctions correctly. In Game 3, we assume that the central agency has complete information about the carrying capacity of the meadow, b;it incomplete information about the particular actions of the herders. The central agency conse- 10 -1 9 -2 10 9 -1 -2 c\ c\ ( *i li Figure 12. Game 2: The central-authority game with complete information. Reflections on the commons .|iicndy makes errors in imposing punishments. Let us assume that the central agency punishes defections (the correct response) with probability y and fails to punish defections with probability 1 — y (the erroneous response). Let us also assume that the central agency punishes cooperative actions (tiw erroneous response) with probability x and dors not punish cooperative actions (the correct response) with probability I — jr. The payoff parameters arc illustrated in Figure 1.3. A central agency with complete information would make no errors in its punishment level; in that case, x = 0 and y = 1. Game 2 would then be a special case of Game 3 in which x = 0 andy = 1, However, if the central agency does not have complete information about the actions of the herders, it imposes both types of sanctions correctly with a probability of 0.7 U = 0.3, y = 0.7). An example of the specific payoffs for this game is shown as Game 4 in Figure 1.4. Given this payoif srructun, the herders again face A prisoner's dilemma game. They will defect (overgraze) rather than cooperate (graze within the carrying capacity), In Game 4, as in the original Game 1, the equilibrium outcomes for the herders were (0, 0). In a game in which a central agency sanctions correctly with a probability of 0.7, the equilibrium outcomes are (-1,6, -1.6). The equilibrium of the regulated game has a lower value than that of the unregulated game. Given the carrying capacity and profit possibilities of Game 1, the central agency must have sufficient information so that it can correctly impose sanctions with a probability greater than 0,75 to avoid pushing the herders to the (D. D) equilibrium.10 10-Zx - 1 -2k 11-2« >a-ix 11-2« - 1 - 2x -u /c i Figvirr I.J. Game }■ The central-authority tumt with irKomplcte intDfmatnin 1 1 Govern ing f ŕ; c common í 9 4 - 1 6 9 6 ■ 1 4 í « - 1,6 - 1.4 D Figure 1.4. Game 4; An example of the central-authority j>..ir ! v •••• n.. • variable. One set of advocates presumes that a central authority must assume continuing responsibility to nuke unitary decisions for a particular resource. The other presumes that a central authority should parcel out ownership rights to the resource and then allow individuals to pursue their own self-interests within a set of well-defined property rights, both cen-irali/aiiMM ti advocates accept as a central tend that institutional change must come from outside and he imposed on the individuals affected. Despite sharing a faith in the necessity and efficacy of "the state" to change institutions so as to increase efficiency, the institutional changes they recommend could hardly be further apart. If one recommendation is correct, the other cannot be. Contradictory positions cannot both be right. I do not argue for either of these positions. Rather, I argue thai both arc too sweeping in their claims. Instead of there being a single solution to a single problem, I argue that many solutions exist to cope with many different problems. Instead of presuming that optimal institutional solutions can be designed easily and imposed at low cost by external authorities, I argue that "petting the institution* right" is a difficult, time-consuming, conflict-invoking process. It is a process that requires reliable information about time and place variables as well as a broad repertoire of culturally acceptable rules. New institutional arrangements do not work in the field as they do in abstract models unless the models are well specified and empirically valid and rhe participants in a field setting understand how to make the new rules work. Instead of presuming that the individuals sharing a commons are inevitably caught in a trap from which they carui"t escape. I argue that the capacity of individuals to extricate themselves from various types of dilemma situations varies from situation to situation. The cases to be discussed in this book illustrate both successful and unsuccessful efforts to escape tragic outcomes. Instead of basing policy on the presumption that rhe individuals involved are helpless, ! wish to learn more from (he experience of individuals in field settings. Why have some efforts to solve commons problems failed, while others have succeeded? What can we learn from experience that will help stimulate the development and use of a better theory of collective action - one that will identify the key variables that can enhance or detract from the capabilities of individuals to solve problems? Institutions are rarely cither private or public - "the market" or "the state." Many successful CPR institutions are rich mixtures of "private-like™ and "public-like" institutions defying classification in a sterile dichotomy. Reflections- on the .omtnnm By "successful," I mean institutions that enable individuals to achieve productive outcomes in situations where temptations to free ride and shirk are ever present. A competitive market - the epitome of private institutions - is itself a public good. Once a competitive market is provided, individuals can enter and exit freely whether or not they contribute to the cost of providing and maintaining the market. No market can exist for long without underlying public institutions to support it. In field settings, public and private institutions frequently are intermeshed and depend on one another, rather than existing in isolated worlds, An alternative solution To open up the discussion of institutional options for solving commons dilemmas, I want now to present a fifth game in which thr herders themselves can make a binding contract to commit themselves to a cooperative strategy that they themselves will work out. To represent this arrangement withm a noncoopcrative framework, additional moves must be overtly included in the game structure. A binding contract is interpreted within noncoopcrative game theory as one that is unfailingly enforced by an 10 -1 ■ 1 0 10 - 1 1 1 : 1 0 -1 11 11 ■ 1 0 IG 1 1 - 1 0 10 11 -1 Ptem 15 Came 5: S«lf-financed contract-cnforceroent ^>i"« Governing the commons external actor - just as we interpreted the penalty posited earlier as being unfailingly enforced by the central authority, A simple way to represent this is to add one parameter to the payoffs and a strategy to both herders1 strategy sets.'^ The parameter is the cost of enforcing an agreement and will be denoted by e. The herders in Game S must now negotiate prior to placing animals on the meadow. During negotiations, they discuss various strategies for sharing the carrying capacity of the meadow and the costs of enforcing their agreement. Contracts are not enforceable, however, unless agreed to unanimously by the herders, Any proposal made by one herder that did not involve an equal sharing of the carrying capacity and of enforcement costs would be vetoed by the other herder in their negotiations. Consequently, the only feasible agreement - and the equilibrium of the resulting game - is for both herders to share equally the sustainable yield levels of the meadow and the costs of enforcing their agreement so long as each herder's share of the cost of enforcement is less than 10.14 Further, in Game 5, players can always guarantee that the worst they will do is the (defect, defect) outcome of Game 1. They are not dependent on the accuracy of the information obtained by a distant government official regarding their strategies. If one player suggests a contract based on incomplete or biased information, the other player can indicate an unwillingness to agree, They determine their own contract and ask the enforcer to enforce only that on which they have agreed. If the enforcer should decide to charge too much for its services [any number equal to or greater than P,{Q Q - Pt{D> D), i = 1, 2], neither player would agree to such a contract. The "solution" of a commons-dilemma game through instrumentalities similar to Game 5 is not presented as the "only way" to solve a commons dilemma. It is merely one way. But this way has been almost totally ignored in both the policy analysis literature and the formal-theory literature. Con-:e:np'..iting such an option raises numerous questions. First, might ,r be possible for the herders to hire a private agent to take on the role of enforcer? This is not as farfetched as it might seem at first. Many long-term business exchanges have the structure of a prisoner's dilemma,15 Businesses axe hesitant to accept promises of future performance rather than enforceable contracts, especially when beginning new business relationships. To reduce enforcement costs, however, a frequent practice is to use a private arbitrator rather than a civil court as the mechanism to achieve enforcement.11* In JV-person settings, all professional athletic leagues face problems similar to those illustrated here. During the play of a professional game, the temptation to cheat and break the rules is ever present. Further. fa-flections on the commons accidents do happen, and rules get broken, even by players who were intending to follow the rules. Athletic leagues typically employ private monitors to enforce their rules.1* As soon as we allow the possibility of a private party to take on the role of an external enforcer, the nature of the "solution" offered by Game 5 to the commons dilemma begins to generate a rich set of alternative applica-tidtis. A se!:'-:inancKii c>:iirract-rnforceir.cnt game allows the participants in the situation to exercise greater control over decisions about who will be allowed to graze and what limits will be placed on the number of animals, as compared with either Game 2 or Game 3. If the parties use a private arbitrator, they do not let the arbitrator impose an agreement on them. The arbitrator simply helps the parties find methods to resolve disputes that arise within the set of working rules to which the parties themselves have agreed. Arbitrators, courts, and other arrangements for enforcement and dispute resolution make it possible for individuals to initiate long-term arrangements that they could not otherwise undertake.18 Further, as soon as one thinks about a "solution" like Game 5, it is a small step to thinking about the possibility ol several arbitrators offering enforcement services at varying charges during the negotiation stage. The payoff-dominant equilibrium is to agree on that arbitrator who will enforce the contract at the lowest e. The key difference between Game 5 and Games 2 and 3 is that ihe participants themselves Jesign their own contracts in Game 5 in light of the information they have at hand. The herders, who use the same meadow year after year, have detailed and relatively accurate information about carrying capacity. They observe the behavior of other herders and have an incentive to report contractual infractions. Arbitrators may not need to hire monitors to observe the activities of the contracting parties. The self-interest of those who negotiated the contract will lead them to monitor each other and to report observed infractions so that the contract is enforced. A regulatory agency, on the other hand, always needs to hire its own monitors. The regulatory agency then faces the pnncipal-agent problem of how to ensure that its monitors do their own job. The proponents of the central-authority "solution" presume that such agencies have accurate information and arc able to change incentives to produce something like Game 2, It is difficult for a central authority to have sufficient rime-and-place information to estimate accurately both the carrying capacity of a CPR and the appropriate tines to induce cooperative behavior, I believe that situations like that in Game 3, in which incomplete information leads to sanctioning errors, occur more frequently than has been presumed in the policy literature. The need for external monitors and 17 Governing the commons enforcers is particularly acute when what is being enforced is a decision by an external agent who may impose excess costs on participants. A further problem for consideration is that games in which enforcers have been arranged for by mutual agreement nuy be mistaken by analysts and public officials for games in which there have been no agreements about how to cooperate and enforce agreements. In other words, some examples of a "Game 5" may be mistaken for a "Game l.**" These situations may be construed to be "informal," carrying a presumption that they are not lawful. This goes to fundamental presumptions about the nature of governments as external authorities governing over societies. As will l^e seen in the later discussion of empirical cases, users of CPRs have developed a wide diversity in their own agreements, which are enforced by many mechanisms, Some ol the enforcement mechanisms arc i \fernal governmental agencies. Some enforcement mechanisms involve members of the users' community who have been employed as monitors and enforcers. Some enforcement mechanisms involve the users themselves as their own monitors. When the enforcement mechanism is not an external governmental agency, some analysts presume that there is no enforcement. That is why Game 5 is mistaken for Game 1. A self-financed contract-enforcement game is no panacea. Such institutional arrangements have many weaknesses in many settings. The herders can overestimate or underestimate the carrying capacity of the meadow. I Their own monitoring system may break down, "I he external enforcer may not be able to enforce ex post, after promising to do so ex ante. A myriad of problems can occur in natural settings, as is also the case with the I idealized central regulation or private-property institutions. The structure of the institutional anangements that one finds in natural settings is, of course, far more complicated than the structure of any of the extremely simple games presented here for discussion. What I attempt to I do with these simple games is to generate different ways of thinking about I the mechanisms that individuals may use to extricate themselves from |j commons dilemmas - ways different from what one finds in much of the I policy literature. To challenge this mind-set, one needs only simple mechanisms that illustrate alternatives Co those that normally are presented as the dominant solutions. An empirical alternative Came S illustrated a theoretical alternative to centralization or privatiza- I tion as ways to solve CPU problems. Let us now briefly consider a solution I devised by participants in a field setting - Alanya, Turkey - that cannot be Reflections on the commons characterized as either central regulation or privatization. The inshore fishery at Alanya, as described by Fikret Berkcs (1986b), is a relatively small Operation. Many of the approximately 100 local fishers operate in two- or three-person boats using various types of nets. Half of the fishers belong to a local producers' cooperative. According to Berkes, the early 1970s were the "dark ages" for Alanya. The economic viability of the fishery was threatened by two factors: Hirst, unrestrained use of the fishery had led to hostility and, at times, violent conflict among the users. Second, competition among fishers for the better fishing spots had increased production costs, as well as rhe level of uncertainty regarding the harvest potential of any particular boat. Early in the 1970s, members of the local cooperative began experimenting with an ingenious system for allotting fishing sites to local fishers. After more than a decade of trial-and-crror efforts, the rules used by the Alanya inshore fishers arc as follows: • Each September, a list of eligible fishers is prepared, consisting of all licensed fishers in Alanya, regardless of co-op membership. • Within the area normally used by Alanya fishers, all usable fishing locations arc named and listed. These site are spaced so that the nets set in one site will not block the fish that should be available at the adjacent sites, • These named fishing locations and their assignments are in effect from September to May. • In September, the eligible fishers draw lots and are assigned to the named fishing locations. • From September to January, each day each fisher moves east to the next location. After January, the fishers move west. This gives the fishers equal opportunities at the stocks that migrate from east to west between September and January and reverse their migration through the area from January to May (Berkes 1986b, pp. 73-4), The system has the effect of spacing the fishers far enough apart on the fishing grounds that the production capabilities at each site are optimized. All fishing boats also have equal chances to fish at the oc-i spots. Resources are not wasted searching for or fighting over a sitc.^" No signs of overcapitalization arc apparent. The list of fishing locations is endorsed by each fisher and deposited with the mayor and local gendarme once a year at the time of the lottery. The process of monitoring and enforcing the system is, however, accomplished by the fishers themselves as a by-product of the incentive created by the 18 19 Governing the commons rotation system. On a day when a given fisher is assigned one of the more productive spots, that fisher will exercise that option with certainty (leaving aside last-minute breakdowns in equipment)- AH other fishers can expect that the assigned fisher will be at the spot bright and early. Consequently, an effort to cheat on the system by traveling to a good spot on a day when one is assigned CO a poor spot has little chance of remaining undetected. Cheating on the system will be observed by the very fishers who have rights to be in the best spots and will be willing to defend their rights using physical means if necessary. Their rights will be supported by everyone else in the system. 1 he others will want to ensure that their own rights will not be usurped on the days when they are assigned good sites. The few infractions that have occurred have been handled easily by the fishers at ihe local coffeehouse (Berkcs 1986b, p, 74). Although this is not a private-property system, rights to use fishing sites and duties to respect these rights are well defined. And though it is not a centralized system, national legislation that has given such cooperatives jurisdiction over "local arrangements" has been used by cooperative officials to legitimize their role in helping to devise a workable set of rules. That local officials accept the signed agreement each year also enhances legitimacy. The actual monm n ing and enforcing of the rules, however, are left to the fishers. Central-government officials could not have crafted such a set of rules without assigning a full-time staff to work (actually fish) in the area for an extended period. Fishing sites of varying economic value arc commonly associated with inshore fisheries (Christy 19H2; Forman 1967), but they are almost impossible to map without extensive on-site experience. Mapping this set of fishing sites, such that one boat's fishing activities would not reduce the migration of fish to other locations, would have been a daunting challenge had it not been for the extensive time-and-place information provided by the fishers and rheir willingness 10 experiment for a decade with various maps and systems. Alatiya provides an example of a self-governed common-property arrangement in which the rules have been devised and modified by the participants themselves and also arc monitored and enforced by them. The case of the Alanya inshore fishery is only one empirical example ol :hc i"',i:ii institutional arrangement* that have been devised, modified, monitored, and sustained by the users of renewable CTRs to constrain individual behavior that would, il unconstrained, reduce joint returns to the community of users. In addition to the case studies discussed in Chapters 3, 4, and 5, productive CPR institutional arrangements have been Reflections on the commons well documented for many farmer-managed irrigation systems, communal forests, inshore fisheries, and grazing and hunting territories.'1 Game S and empirical cases of successfully governed CPRs provide theoretical and empirical alternanves to the assertion that those involved cannot extricate themselves from the problems faced when multiple individuals use a given resource. The key to my argument is thai some individuals have broken out of the trap inherent in the commons dilemma, whereas others continue remorsefully trapped into destroying their own resources.21 Tin-, leads me to ask what differences exist between those who have broken the shackles of a commons dilemma and those who have not. The differences ma;- h.v-<- ' ■ Jo with factors internal to a given group. The participants may simply have no capacity to communicate with one another, no way to develop trust, and no sense that they must share a common future. Alternatively, powerful individuals who stand to gain from the current situation, while others lose, may block efforts by the less powerful to change the rules of the game. Such groups may need some form of external assistance to break out of the perverse logic of their situation. The differences between those who have and those who have not extricated themselves from commons dilemmas may also have to do with factors outside the domain of those affected. Some participants do not have the autonomy to change their own institutional structures and are pre vented from making constructive changes by external authorities who are indifferent to the perversities of the commons dilemma, or may even stand to gain from it. Also, there is the possibility that external changes may sweep rapidly over a group, giving them insufficient rime to adjust their internal structures to avoid the suboptimal outcomes. Some groups suffer from perverse incentive systems that arc themselves the results of policies pursued by central authorities. Many potential answers spring to mind regarding the question why some individuals do not achieve collective benefits for themselves, whereas others do, However, as long as analysts presume that individuals cannot change such situarions themselves, they do not ask what internal or external variables can enhance or impede the efforts of communities ol individuals to deal i reatively and constructively with perverse problems such as the tragedy of the commons. Policy prescriptions as ftictuphors Policy analysts who would recommend a single prescription for commons problems have paid little attention to how diverse institutional atrangc- 20 l : rot erning the commons ments operate in practice. The centrists presume that unified authorities will operate in the fieJd as they have been designed to do in the textbooks - determining the best policies to be adopted for a resource based on vaJid scientific theories and adequate information. Implementation of these policies without error is assumed. Monitoring and sanctioning activities are viewed as routine and nonproblematic. Those advocating the private-property approach presume that the most efficient use patterns for CPRs will actually result from dividing the rights to access and control such resources. Systematic empirical studies have shown that private organization of firms dealing in goods such as electricity, transport, and medical services tends io be mure efficient than governmental organization of such firms; for a review of this literature, see De Alessi (1980). Whether private or public forms arc more efficient in industries in which certain potential beneficiaries cannot be excluded is, however, a different question. We are concerned with the types of institutions that will be most efficient for governing and managing diverse CPRs for which at least some potential bcneticiarics cannot be excluded. Privatizing the ownership of CPRs need not have the same positive results as privatizing the ownership of an airline. Further, privatizing may not mean "dividing up" at all. Privatization can also mean assigning the exclusive right to harvest from a resource system to a single individual or firm. Many policy prescriptions are themselves no more than metaphors. Both the ccntralizers and the privatizers frequently advocate oversimplified, idealized institutions - paradoxically, almost "institution-free" institutions. An assertion that central regulation is necessary tells us nothing about the way a central agency should be constituted, what authority it should have, how the limits on its authority should be maintained, how it will obtain information, or how its agents should be selected, motivated to do their work, and have their peiiormance.s monitored and rewarded or sanctioned. An assertion that the imposition of private property rights is necessary tells us nothing about how that bundle of rights is to be defined, how the various attributes of the goods involved will be measured, who will pay for the costs of excluding nonowncrs from access, how conflicts over rights will be adjudicated, or how the residual interests of the right-holders in the rtsour. : ^ itc:ii itself will I t Organ , i d. An important lesson that one Learns by carefully studying the growing number of systematic studies by scholars associated with "the new institution alism" is that these "institutional details" are important,11 Whether or not any equilibria are possible and whether or not an equilibrium would be an improvement for the individuals involved (or for others who are in turn affected by these individuals) will depend on the particular structures Reflections on the commons of the institutions. In the most general sense, alt institutional arrangements can be thought of as games in extensive form. As such, the particular options available, the sequencing of those options, the information provided, and the relative rewards and punishments assigned to different sequences of moves can all change the partem of outcomes achieved, rurther, the particular structure of the physical environment invoked also will have a major impact on the structure of the game and its results. Thus, a set of rules used in one physical environment may have vastly different consequences if used in a different physical environment, Policies based on metaphors can be harmful Relying on metaphors as the foundation for policy advice can lead to results substantially different from those presumed to be likely. Nationalizing the ownership of forests in Third World countries, for example, has been advocated on the grounds that local villagers cannot manage forests so as to sustain their productivity and their value in reducing soil erosion. In countries where small villages had owned and regulated their local communal forests for generations, nationalization meant expropriation. In such localities, villagers had earlier exercised considerable restraint over the rate and manner of harvesting forest products. In some of these countries, national agencies issued elaborate regulations concerning the use of forests, but were unable to employ sufficient numbers of foresters to enforce those regulations. The foresters who were employed were paid such low salaries that accepting bribes became a common means of supplementing their income. The consequence was that nationalization created open-jeeess resources where limited-access common-property resources bad previously existed. The disastrous effects of nationalizing formerly communal forests have been well documented for Thailand (Fccny ]s»S8a), Niger (Thomson 1977; Thomson, Feeny, and Oakerson 1986). Nepal (Arnold and Campbell 1986; Messerschmidt 1986), and India (Cadgil and Iyer 1989). Similar problems occurred in regard to inshore fisheries when national agencies presumed that they had exclusive jurisdiction over all ■ i v. , (Cor - ' V, ' i- ' ■'■ ■ X t. i ..• I I ■ .....ir: . ' •1 -. • Panayoutou 1982; Pinkenon 1989a). A CHALLENGE An important challenge facing policy scientists is to develop theories of human organization based on realistic assessment of human capabilities and limitations in dealing with a variety of situations that initially share Governing the commons some or all aspects of a tragedy of the commons. Empirically validated theories of human organization will be essential ingredients of a policy science that can inform decisions about the likely consequence; of a multitude of ways of organizing human activities. Theoretical inquiry involves a search for regularities. It involves abstraction from the complexity of n field setting, followed by the positing of theoretical variables that underlie observed complexiries. Specific models of a theory involve further abstraction and simplification for the purpose of still finer analysis of the logical ■ekii unships among variables in a closed system. As a theorist, and at times a modeler, I see these efforts at the core of a policy science. One can, however, get trapped in ones own intellectual web. When years have been spent in the development of a theory with considerable power and elegance, analysts obviously will want to apply this tool to as many situations as possible. The power of a theory is exactly proportional to the diversity of situations it can explain. All theories, however, have limits. Models of a theory are limited still further because many parameters must be fixed in a model, rather than allowed to vary. Confusing a model - such as that of a perfectly competitive market - with the theory or which it is one representation can limit applicability still further. Scientific knowledge is as much an understanding of the divetsity of situations for which a theory or its models are relevant as an understanding of its limits. The conviction that all physical structures could be described in terms of a set of perfect forms - circles, squares, and triangles - limited the development of astronomy until Johannes Kepler broke the bonds of classical thought and discovered that the orbil of Mars was elliptical - a finding that Kepler himself initially considered to be no more than a pile of dung (Koestler 1959). Godwin and Shepard (1979) pointed out a decade ago that policy scientists were doing the equivalent of "Forcing Squares, Triangles and Ellipses into a Circular Paradigm'* by using the commons-dilemma model without serious attention to whether or not the variables m the empirical world conformed to the theoretical model. Many theoretical and empirical findings have been reported since Godwin and Shepard's article that should have made policy scientists even more skeptical about relying on a limited set of models to analyze the diversity of situations broadly referred to as CPR problems. Unfortunately, many analysts - in academia, special-interest groups, governments, and the press - still presume that common-pool problems arc all dilemmas in which the participants themselves cannot avoid producing suboptimal results, and in some cases disastrous results. Whar is missing from the policy analyst's tool kit - and from the set of accepted, well-developed theories of human organization - is an ade- Reflections on the common* quately specified theory of collective action whereby a group of principals can organize themselves voluntarily to retain the residuals of their own efforts. Examples of self-organized enterprises abound. Most law firms arc obvious examples: A group of lawyers will pool their assets to purchase a library and pay for joint secretarial and research assistance. They will develop their own internal governance mechanisms and formulas for allocating costs and benefits to the partners. Most cooperatives are also examples. The cases of self-organized and self-governed CPRs that we consider in Chapter 3 are also examples. But until a theoretical explanation -based on human choice - for self-organized and self-governed enterprises is fully developed and accepted, major policy decisions will continue to be undertaken with a presumption that individuals cannot organize themselves and always need to be organized by external authorities. Further, all organizational arrangements are subject to stresi, weakness, and failure. Without an adequate theory of self-organized collective action, one cannot predict or explain when individuals will be unable to solve a common problem through self-organization alone, nor can one begin to ascertain which of many intervention strategies might be effective in helping to solve particular problems. As discussed earlier, there is a considerable difference between the presumption that a regulatory agency should be established and the presumption that a reliable court system is needed lit monitor and enforce self negotiated contracts. If the theories being used in a policy science do not include the possibility of self-organized collective action, then the importance of a court system that can be used by self-organizing groups to monitor and enforce contracts will not be recognized.24 1 hope this inquiry will contribute to the development of an empirically supported theory of self-organizing and self-governing forms of collective action. What I attempt to do in this volume is to combine the strategy used by many scholars associated with the "new institutional ism" with the strategy used by biologists for conducting empirical work related to the development of a better theoretical understanding of the biological world As an instirutionalist studying empirical phenomena, ( presume that individual* try to solve problems as effectively as they can, That assumption imposes a discipline on me. Instead of presuming that some individuals are incompetent, evil, or irrational, and others are omniscient, I presume that individuals have very similar limited capabilities to reason and figure out the structure of complex environments, It is my responsibility as a =>cir:ir:sc to ascertain what problems individuals arc trying to solve and what factors help or hinder them in these efforts. When the problems that t observe involve lack of predictability, information, and trust, as well as high levels Governing the commons of complexity and transactional difficulties, then my efforts to explain must take these problems overtly into account rather than assuming them away. In developing an explanation for observed behavior, 1 draw on a rich literature written by other scholars interested in institutions and their effects on individual incentives and behaviors in field settings. Biologists also face the problem of studying complex processes that are poorly understood. Their scientific strategy frequently has involved identifying for empirical observation the simplest possible organism in which a process occurs in a clarified, or even exaggerated, form. The organism is not chosen because it is representative of all organisms. Rather, the organism is chosen because particular processes can be studied more effectively using this organism than using another. My "organism'' is a type of human situation, I call this situation a CPR situation and define exactly what I mean by this and othct key terms in Chapter 2. In this volume, I do not include all potential ( 1'R situations within the frame of reference. I focus entirely on small-scale CPRs, where the CPR is itself located within one country and rhr number u: individuals affected vanes from 50 to 15,000 persons who are heavily dependent on the CPR for economic returns, These CPRs are primarily inshore fisheries, smaller grazing areas, groundwater basins, irrigation systems, and communal forests. Because these are relatively small-scale situations, serious study is more likely to penetrate the .surface complexity to identify underlying similarities and processes. Because the individuals involved gain a major part of their economic return from the CPRs, they are strongly motivated to try to solve common problems to enhance their own productivity over time. The effort to self-organize in these situations may be somewhat exaggerated, but that is exactly why I want to study this process m these sellings. Further, when self-organ nation fails, 1 know that it is not because the collective benefits that could have been obtained were unimportant to the participants. There are limits on the types of CPRs studied here; (V) renewable rather than nonrenewable resources, (2) situations where substantial scarcity exists, rather than abundance, and (3) situations in which the users can substantially harm one another, but not situations in which participants can produce major external harm for others. Thus, ail asymmetrical pollution problems ate excluded, as is any situation in which a group can form a cartel and control a sufficient part ot the market to affect market price. In the empirical studies, I present a synopsis of important CPR cases that have aided my understanding of the processes of self-organization and self-govci nance. These cases arc in no sense a "random" sample of cases. Rather, these are cases that provide clear information about the processes Reflections on the commons involved in (1) governing long-enduring CPRs, (2) transforming existing institutional arrangements, and [3} failing to overcome continued CPR problems. These cases can thus be viewed as a collection of the most salient raw materials with which 1 have worked in my effort to understand how individuals organize mid govern themselves to obtain collective benefits in situations where the temptations to free-ride and to break commitments are substantial. Prom an examination and analysis of these cases, I attempt to develop a series of reasoned conjectures about how it is possible that some individuals organize themselves to govern and manage CPRs and others do not. I try to identify the underlying design principles of the institutions used by those who have successfully managed their own CPRs over extended periods of time and why these may affect the incentives for participants to continue investing time and effort in the governance and management ;>t their own CPRs. I compare the msti rations used in successful and unsuccessful cases, and 1 try to identify the internal and external factors that can impede or enhance the capabilities of individuals to use and govern CPRs. I hope these conjectures contribute to the development of an empirically valid theory of self-organization and self governance for at least one well-defined universe of problematical situations. That universe contains a substantial proportion of renewable resources heavily utilized by human beings in different parts of the world. It is estimated, for example, that 9(W of the world's fishermen and over half of the fish consumed each year are captured in the small-scale, inshore fisheries included within the frame of this study (Panayoutou 1982, p. 49). Further, my choice of the CPR environment for intensive study was based on a presumption that I could learn about the processes of sclf-organination and self-governance of relevance to a somewhat broader set of environments. Given the similarity between many CPR problems and the problems of providing small-scale collective goods, the findings from this volume should contribute to an understanding of the factors that can enhance or detract from the capabilities of individuals to organize collective action related to providing local public goods. All efforts to organize collective action, whether by an external ruler, an entrepreneur, or a set of principals who wish to gain collective benefits, must address a common set of problems. These have to do with coping with free riding, solving commitment problems, arranging for the supply of new institutions, and monitoring individual compliance with sets of rules. A study that focuses on how individuals avoid free-riding, achieve high levels of commitment, arrange for new institutions, and monitor conformity to a set of rules in CPR environments should contribute to an understanding of how in- 1.1 Governing the commons dividuals address these crucial problems in some other settings as well. Let mc now give a brief sketch of how this book is organized* In Chapter 2,1 define what I mean by a CPH situation and individual choice in a CPR situation. Then I examine a series of crucial questions that any theory of collective action must answer. To conclude the chapter, I examine two assumptions that have framed prior work and discuss the alternatives that frame my analysis. The empirical part of this volume is contained in Chapters 3, 4, arid 5, where I examine specific cases of long-enduring CPR institutions and resources, the origin and development of CPR institutions, and CPR failures and fragilities. At the end of each empirical chapter, I consider what can be learned from the cases in that chapter chat will contribute toward the development of a better theory of self-organination related to CPR environments. In Chapter 6, I pull together the theoretical reflections contained at the ends of Chapters 3, 4, and 5 and address the implications of these conjectures for the design of self-organizing and self-governing institutions. 28 An institutional approach to the study of self-organization and self-governance in CPR situations In Chapter 1,1 described my strategy as that of a "new instirutionalist" who has picked small-scale CPR situations to study because the processes of self-organization and self-governance are easier to observe in this type of situation than in many others. The central question in this study is how a group of principals who are in an interdependent situation can organize and govern themselves to obtain continuing joint benefits when all face temptations to free-ride, shirk, or otherwise act opportunistically. Parallel questions have to do with rhe combinations of variables that will (1) increase the initial likelihood of self-organization, {2) enhance the capabilities of individuals to continue sel f-organized efforts over time, or (3) exceed the capacity of self-organization to solve CPR problems without external assistance of some form. This chapter has several objectives. First, I define what I mean by CPRs and how 1 view individual behaviors in complex and uncertain CPR situations. Then I examine the general problem facing individuals in CPR situations: how to organize to avoid the adverse outcomes of independent action. This general problem is solved by external agents in two well-accepted theories: the theory of the firm and the theory of the state. These explain how new institutions are supplied, how commitments arc obtained, and how the actions of agents and subjects are monitored effectively, using in one case the firm, and in the other state, as an organizational device. How a group of principals - a community of citizens - can organize themselves to solve the problems of institutional supply, commitment, and monitoring is still a theoretical puzzle. Given that some individuals solve this puzzle, whereas others do not, a study of successful and unsuccessful efforts to solve CPR problems should address important issues related to the theory of collective action and the development of better policies related to CPRs. Many efforts to analyze collective-action prohlcms have 29