Trade and Market in the Early Empires ECONOMIES IN HISTORY AND THEORY Edited by KARL POLANYI, CONRAD M. ARENSBERG, and HARRY W. PEARSON THE FREE PRESS CLENCOE, ILLINOIS THE FALCON'S WIM P&ESS TRADE AND MARKET IN THE EARLY EMPIRES I copyright 1957 by the free press, a corporation printed in the united states of america designed by sidney solomon library of congress catalog card number: 57-6745 Preface the senior editors hope to be forgiven for a somewhat lengthy preface. Close cooperation in genuine freedom allowed the present book to take shape as work in progress. Manifold factors, each on its own level, influenced the interdisciplinary plan, structure and form. There were, in the first place, the initiators and their former students who together largely wrote the book, one of the latter, Professor Harry W. Pearson of Adelphi College, acting also as co-editor; the institutions, internal and external to the University, which supported over a decade the various ventures in their overlapping phases; the personal scholarly aims of the editors which they endeavored to bring to fruition on converging lines. The undersigned will therefore speak here in three voices: each for himself, and together for both. In Spring 1947 Karl Polanyi was appointed Visiting Professor of Economics at Columbia University. Until his retirement in 1953 he taught General Economic History in the Graduate Faculty, redefining the subject in the yearly announcement as "the place occupied by economic life in society." In 1948, the Council for Research in the Social Sciences at Columbia University (C. R. S. Sc.) endowed a research project on the originsjoj^conon^.uis^tations, under his direction. Having retired, at the age of sixty-seven, he was given the honorary appointment of Adjunct Professor of Economics. Jointly with Professor Conrad M. Arensberg he then applied to the Ford Foundation, Behavioral Sciences Division, for a grant in support of an Interdisciplinary F vi Preface Project on the economic aspects of institutional growth, to be administered by Columbia University. In accepting the gift, Columbia University pointed to the continuity of effort which linked the C. R. S. Sc. project with the new grant. But while the charter of the C. R. S. Sc. barred students engaged in project work from making use of results towards the attainment of an academic degree, no such restrictions applied to the Interdisciplinary Project; rather it was intended as a center of research benefiting the study purposes both of the senior proponents and of their associates. Polanyi has been serving full-time since 1953 on the Interdisciplinary Project, which in 1956 was continued by the Ford Foundation for another two years. Harry W. Pearson was appointed Executive Secretary. A university Seminar, at faculty level, on the institutionalization of the economic process set up at Columbia University discussed the same general topic from 1953 to 1955. One by one a number of his 1947 students had joined Polanyi in his inquiries. Theoretical stimulation came from Harry W. Pearson and Rosemary Arnold (Barnard), both also giving valuable literary help; empirical applications were contributed by Charles S. Silberman (Columbia University) and Walter C. Neale (Yale University); George Woodard (Goddard College) uncovered Old Testament data relevant to the Mesopotamian field; Daniel B. Fusfeld (Michigan State University) provided a methodological link with economic anthropology; Roxane Eberlein created an invaluable card index for the total research effort; Laura P. Striker, Ph. D. (History), a guest student, volunteered assistance over several years with the German translations of cuneiform texts. Among later students Terence K. Hopkins (Columbia University) brought to bear a much needed sociological approach to the concept of a substantive economy; Professor Murray C. Polakoff (University of Texas) contributed in the same direction; Abe Rotstein (Sir George Williams College, Montreal) who assisted Polanyi's work in many ways, also wrote the Introductory Note to the present book. By 1953 definite progress had been made. The distinction between trade and market institutions was proving a potent instrument in rectifying serious misreadings of economic data in early societies. Building on the works of earlier scholars, we had largely solved the problem of money uses in primitive and archaic societies. In regard to prices, the existence of the complex institution of "equivalencies" was revealed. The consequences for our understanding of the manner in which the Preface vii economic process was instituted in Mesopotamia and classical Greece began to take shape. At this point Arensberg, whose parallel endeavors at an institutional approach to the problems of sociology and anthropology were laid down in publications reaching back over a period of years, joined forces with Polanyi. Professor A. L. Oppenheim of the Oriental Institute, Chicago agreed to act as consultant in Assyriology. The undersigned then initiated the study of anthropology, economic history, and Assyriology from which this book sprang. In Arensberg's case, such joint study gave a welcome opportunity to show that anthropology could serve economic history as more than a storehouse of odd data. The approach by which he thinks anthropologists in close collaboration with himself have reached some new understanding jaf the regularities to be found both in ethnographic and substantive economic data is an operational method recently referred to as "interaction theory." A few paragraphs may well be devoted to this linking of social arrangements and culture traits on the one hand, institutions on the other. It consists of the systematic use of three operations upon the immediate observations and the generalization of the resultant records —in the form of answers to the question: Who did what to whom, in what order, how often, where? The operations are (1) the specification of the persons acting on one another, (2) the discrimination of the order of the action (initiative and response), (3) the comparison of the events so described in time, as frequencies or rates of recurrence. Economic institutions then take on the appearance of goods-handling and goods-receiving, while ethnographic data may be expected to reveal who passed on goods to whom, in what order, how often, with what response among those listed under "whom." This should, for instance, enable us to link ethnographical data with such a purely empirical classification of parts of the goods-handling and goods-receiving process as are indicated by the terms reciprocative, redistributive, and marketing, as Polanyi has suggested. The reciprocative sequence among fixed partners AB/BA or AB/BC/CA C indicated similar social arrangements and culture traits whether the institutions formed otherwise part of prestige, kinship, community, religious, or other activities of the peoples who live by reciprocative human action in similar sequence. I viii Preface In a redistributive world we find only few, if any, simple or complex chains of action and their reversals, or circles of action back upon themselves. Action is instead centripetal movement of many upon one central figure followed by an initiative of that central figure upon the same many. Formally, BA/CA/DA/EA/FA are followed by an event A/BCDEF in unison or repartition. Central authority or focus in human organization has been invented, and it is now a frequent form in which human action occurs. The economics of redistribution, again, has common elements with the other institutions of the epochs in which central authority, the elaboration of "set events," is developing. But the identity of A, the centralizing figure, is still a fixed feature. His identity is not reversible: Temple-god or high priest, or king, or emperor, or even, in republican cases, citizen office-holder in rotation of office still fixed for a day or a year, is a fixed point, round which the others are also bound, liege, and fixed. We asked the same type of question of the market. Here we asked it, in detail, and again our questioning, which resulted in what we think to be common denominator social arrangements and culture traits, led us to a slightly different pattern of observations than those our economists made. We asked, abstractly and analytically, what social action does the free market entail, and also where in the ethnographic record, can we find such forms of social action prior to modern times. The economists of our project had difficulty with our question. To them free or moving prices were the earmark of the free market; and production for sale at such prices, fluctuating in its turn against market supply and demand, was the earmark of a market economy. But to the anthropologist that is not enough, since he must connect the specific, developed details of a culture trait, particularly the outward and spectacular features which win it human recognition and acclaim, with the inner features, its social arrangements, its past history, and its functions for men, society, and the maintenance of other institutions than itself. But they finally agreed with us upon the following tentative formulation: In the free market of supply and demand, a man can reverse roles, being supplier or demander as he can or wills. A man can go to this market or that as he sees his advantage; he is free of fixed and static obligation to one center or one partner, he moves at will and at random, or as prices beckon. He can offer to all and any comers, dole or divide among them, "corner the market" so that they all pay his price and so dance to his tune. At another turn of prices, or in a next Preface ix transaction or market, formally, he is one of a similar "crowd" and dances in unison to the tune called by another who may in his turn have "cornered the market" from them all. Thus the action, judged by our operations, is random as to persons, at the free initiative of any one, formally, and the position of central "authority" in the market goes now to this competitor or cornerer—, now to that. The personal identity of the center, unlike that in redistributions, is fluctuant, moving, reversible, and random, too, a function not of other institutions but of the market itself. Nowhere in the ethnographic record should we find another such fluid randomizing, so different a pattern of social arrangements to compare with those of reciprocity and redistribution. Here was a pattern reckoned from the will of the actor, giving him only the role he should achieve, not that ascribed to him from outside, forming and reforming the positions of others about him as he himself changed behavior and motive. Now, formally, A/BCDEF took place no oftener than B/ACDEF or F/ABCDE, and somehow human beings had learned, presumably, to accept roles as the movement of the institution itself, the market, dictated, together with a freedom to try to bend the others to their advantage. In the Western world, where this institution had come to emerge and to blossom into extreme elaboration in a Manchester-School England of the 19th century, was it historical accident alone that a "free enterprise," a free and equal democracy, an "open" class system, a free choice of religious and associational membership, and a free choice of mate in a small, ego-reckoned family structure, should all have historically coincided? In our particular project we could not decide such large matters of history and sociology, but we could ask the second question already mentioned above, Where outside the recent Western world, in the ethnographic record, would we find anything resembling or parallel to this? If it did exist elsewhere, did any parallel connections unite economic behavior and social arrangements and institutions? To get an answer to the second question we might have turned to several places, perhaps to Japan, Mexico, Melanesia or ancient Greece. For all of them some reporters have claimed free or near-free markets. But we turned instead to Barbary, where the Berber hill tribes have markets that may well be free and where mutatis mutandis other free, not to say anarchic, institutions mark a very ancient and interesting civilization of perhaps some common origins with our own but certainly I x Preface outside it today. A chapter of this book records what seems to be another case of near-free markets there. Let the reader judge for himself, as he will judge the joint efforts of institutional economist and anthropologist in the other treatments of problems in different or alternative economic behaviors, motives, and systems in this book, if we have rightly or wrongly discovered the connections between culture trait, economic institution, and common denominator social arrangement in this case as in the others. The present work reflects research carried on by the undersigned collectively, in free cooperation, during the 1953-1955 period. The manuscript of a previous work of Polanyi—summing up his 1948-1952 results in a more personal vein—should, however, be mentioned here. It was prepared by him in collaboration with his students, Charles S. Silberman and Rosemary Arnold, then research assistants on the staff of the C. R. S. Sc. project; his wife Mrs. Ilona Polanyi acted as editorial assistant. On leave during the Winter Term 1949-1950, aided by the C. R. S. Sc., Polanyi made studies on Dahomey in the British Museum. In chapters VIII and IX on this subject, by Rosemary Arnold, particular indebtedness to the C. R. S. Sc. has been acknowledged. Chapter VIII consists of passages assembled from previous texts for submission to the University Seminar in 1953; Chapter IX, as it stands, was written by her for the C. R. S. Sc. project. In her case, as in that of Charles S. Silberman, Polanyi welcomes the opportunity to acknowledge the vital contribution of his collaborators in his as yet unpublished work. We wish to acknowledge our debt to the institutions which made our work possible. We can single out, in grateful memory, the officers of the Behavioral Sciences Division of the Ford' Foundation, of the Columbia University Council for Research in the Social Sciences and those of the University administration and of our respective departments of Economics and Anthropology, together with the administration of the University Seminars, particularly Professors Frank Tannen-baum and Arthur R. Burns, all at Columbia University, who gave both material support for the complicated interdisciplinary work of our project and platforms for our many hours of discussion and conference. Vital encouragement came from Professors Robert M. Maclver, Paul F. Lazarsfeld and Robert K. Merton of the Sociology Department; steadfast support from Professors John M. Clark, Joseph Dorfman, Preface xi Carter Goodrich, David S. Landes, and William Vickrey of the Eco^ nomics Department, all at Columbia. Many others contributed ideas and ideals; moral, intellectual, and technical assistance, running the gamut from the dedicated fellow-scholar to the interested observer; from the authority in his field to the challenging student. Amongst these were Dr. M. I. Finley, Fellow of Jesus College, Cambridge; the Rev. Professor R. J. Williams, University of Toronto; Professor Julius Lewy, Union Hebrew Seminary, Cincinnati; Professor Gregory Vlastos, Princeton University; Professor John Mum, Vassar College; Professor Albrecht Götze, Yale University; Professor Bert F. Hoselitz, University of Chicago, together with Rivkah Harris and R. F. G. Sweet of the Oriental Institute of the University of Chicago; Professor Peter F. Drucker, New York University; Professors Isaac Mendelsohn and Martin Ostwald of Columbia University; Professors Morton Fried and Margaret Mead, together with Sidney Greenfield, Thomas Hazard, Dr. Marshall Sahlins, Donna Chrablow Taylor and Dr. Andrew Peter Vayda, all of the Department of Anthropology, Columbia University; also Drs. Robert Hennion and Cohn-Haft, while at Columbia. Miss Lucy Lowe's able professional services in the way of technical editing also deserve acknowledgement. Thanks are also due to the Carnegie Institution of Washington for permission to adapt the map from The Maya Chontal Indians of Acalan-Tixchel: A Contribution to the History and Ethnography of the Yucatan Peninsula, by France V. Scholes and Ralph L. Roys. We are also indebted to Lee Hunt for his expert assistance in adapting this map and for his beautiful execution of the endpaper maps. We owe a debt of another kind to Professor Talcott Parsons of Harvard University. If his work is the subject, in essence, of two of our chapters, it is because that work is important and will certainly live in future social science in much of its contribution to our knowledge of institutions and social process. It was possible here to discuss Economy and Society, forthcoming almost at the same time as our own book, only because he sent us the manuscript graciously and fore-bearingly. Karl Polanyi Conrad M. Arensberg Novembers, 1956 New York I The Authors Conrad M. Arensberg professor of anthropology co-director: interdisciplinary project columbia university Rosemary Arnold instructor in economics barnard college Francisco Benet research associate in anthropology interdisciplinary project columbia university Anne G. Chapman research associate in anthropology interdisciplinary project columbia university Daniel B.Fusfeld assistant professor of economics michigan state university Terence K. Hopkins instructor in sociology columbia university Walter C.Neale instructor in economics yale university A. L. Oppenheim professor of assyriology oriental institute university of chicago Harry W. Pearson assistant professor of economics executive secretary: interdisciplinary project adelphicollege Karl Polanyi visiting professor of economics 1947-1953 director: interdisciplinary project columbia university Robert B. Revere research assistant in history interdisciplinary project columbia university Qontcnts Editors Preface Introductory Note v xix Part One: BIRTH OF THE ECONOMY I. The Secular Debate on Economic Primitivism by Harry W. Pearson 3 the "oikos" theorem: karl rodbertus \jjJ/l bücher and eduard meyer max weber and michael rostovtzeff II. Marketless Trading in Hammurabi's Time by Karl Polanyi 12 pseudo-economy and inverted perspective problems of the babylonian economy an early assyrian trading post risk-free trading transactions and dispositions the tamkarum III. A Bird's-Eye View of Mesopotamian Economic History by A. L. Oppenheim 27 IV. 'No Man's Coast': Ports of Trade in The Eastern Mediterranean by Roheit B. Revere 38 mesopotamia and egypt the hittites port of trade policies symbiosis V. Aristotle Discovers The Economy by Karl Polanyi 64 the anonymity of the economy in early society Aristotle's probings the sociological bent xiv Contents natural trade and just price exchange of equivalencies the texts Part Two: AZTEC-MAYA; DAHOMEY; BERBER; INDIA VI. Anthropology As History by Conrad M. Arensberg 97 the empirical approach methodological conclusions VII. Port of Trade Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations by Anne C. Chapman the problem of aztec-maya trade the aztec of the basin of mexico the maya of yucatan gulf of mexico-xicalango pacific coast—xoconusco inland-acalan gulf of honduras 114 VIII. A Port of Trade: Whydah on the Guinea Coast by Rosemary Arnold 154 war and trade in native dahomey remote control of whydah foreigners' enclave administered trade IX. Separation of Trade and Market: Great Market of Whydah by Rosemary Arnold zobeme, the native market administered trade and local food distribution X. Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands by Francisco Benet siba and makhzen the market in the siba safe conduct explosive markets rigor of market law segmental anarchy and "free*' prices conclusions 177 188 Contents xv XI. Reciprocity and Redistribution in The Indian Village: Sequel to Some Notable Discussions by Walter C. Neale 218 the village economy the nature of land revenue Part Three: INSTITUTION ANALYSIS XII. The Place of Economics in Societies by Karl Polanyi, Coniad M. Arensberg, and Harry W. Pearson 239 XIII. The Economy As Instituted Process / by KarJ Po/anyi 243 the formal and substantive meanings of "economic" reciprocity, redistribution, and exchange forms of trade, money uses and market elements XIV. Sociology and The Substantive View of The Economy by Terence K. Hopkins 270 criticism of current sociological conceptions of the economy 1. the division-of-labor conception 2. the rational action position a. the market model view b. the "scarcity" defined economy c. conclusion of part i the substantive view of the economy 1. the economic process and society 2. the instituting of the economic process 3. locational and appropriational types of economic action 4. conclusion XV. Parsons and Smelser on The Economy by Hairy W. Pearson 307 XVI. The Economy Has No Surplus: Critique of A Theory of Development by Harry W. Pearson 320 a rationalistic construct reifying the profit concept surplus-the economic aspect of institutional change xvi Contents XVII. Economic Theory Misplaced: Livelihood In Primitive Society by Daniel B. Fusfeld 342 economic anthropology the societal approach the use of economic theory a cross cultural economics XVIII. The Market in Theory and History by Walter C.Neale 357 price-making markets types of markets: the economist's view markets in economic history Concluding Note Index of Authors Index of Topics 373 375 377 Introductory Jsjotc most of us have been accustomed to think that the hallmark of the economy is the market—an institution quite familiar to us. Similarly, our inquiries into general economic history have usually been concerned with market activities or their antecedents. What is to be done, though, when it appears that some economies have operated on altogether different principles, showing a widespread use of money, and far-flung trading activities, yet no evidence of markets or gain made on buying and selling? It is then that we must reexamine our notions of the economy. The conceptual problem arises in marketless economies where there is no "economizing," i.e., no institutional framework to compel the individual to "rational" and "efficient" economic activity, or "optimum" allocation of his resources. Economizing action may be present in various aspects of behavior, e.g., in regard to one's time, energy, or one's theoretical assumptions, but the economy need contain no institutions of exchange to reflect these principles in the individual's daily life as they have done in our own day. In that case the economy would not be subject to economic analysis since this presumes economizing behavior with supporting institutional paraphernalia, e.g., price-making markets, all-purpose money and market trade. Thus the main task of this book is conceptual: it argues that only a small number of alternative patterns for organizing man's livelihood exist and it provides us with tools for the examination of nonmarket xvii if! I xviii Introductory Note economies. These tools are applied in a series of empirical researches, although the underlying theory transcends them. The aim is not to reject economic analysis, but to set its historical and institutional limitations, namely, to the economies where price-making markets have sway, and to transcend these limitations in a general theory of economic organization. It is particularly as economists and as economic historians that we may have to revise our traditional assumptions. Some will be inclined to reject as of no interest economies which do not "economize," i.e., have no institutions for economizing action. They may regard the empirical and conceptual work advanced here as presenting no more than unimportant and irrational shards on the fringes of history. Others may even maintain that nothing is advanced here that is not amenable to treatment by economic analysis or some variation of the maximization theorem. However, many unfortunate consequences follow from an approach that restricts our view of the economy to market activity. It is an impoverished economic history that narrows its concern to markets or market antecedents, for these may be only fragmentary aspects of the economy. The economy would then falsely seem to be in unilineal evolution to our own day, whereas in fact other economies need not be miniatures or early specimens of our own, but may be sharply at variance with it, both as to individual motives and organization. Technological progress is cumulative and unbounded, but economic organization is not. There are only a few general ways in which the economy may be organized. It is this limitation of the possible patterns of economic organization and their effective combinations which gives to the thoughts and data offered here some topicality. In the receding rule of the market in the modern world, shapes reminiscent of the economic organization of earlier times make their appearance. Of course we stand firmly committed to the progress and freedoms which are the promise of modern society. But a purposeful use of the past may help us to meet our present overconcern with economic matters and to achieve a level of human integration, that comprises the economy, without being absorbed in it. It is this which makes economic history come alive and throw light on the changing roles of economies in history and society. PART I ^irth of the economy I The Secular QDebate on &conomic ^nmitivism for more than sixty years a debate has been raging in the field of economic history. Many features have faded out, some were irrelevant from the start. Yet it contained—and still contains—the elements of one of the most significant divergencies in the human sciences. It would not be easy to find a more suitable introduction than this controversy to the interpretive problems involved in the study of archaic economic institutions. The theorem about which the storm of discussion ultimately centered was first propounded by Rodbertus in the middle 1860's. The actual controversy started some thirty years later between Karl Biicher and Eduard Meyer; it was at its height about the turn of the century. Subsequently Max Weber and Michael Rostovtzeff took their stand. Several others made important contributions.1 No more illuminating introduction to this conflict of views could be found than Friedrich Oertel's oft-quoted statement of the issues as he summed them up in 1925: Are we to conceive of the economy of antiquity as having reached a high level of development, or, on the contrary, as essentially primitive? Should the 5th and 4th centuries b.c. be regarded as an age of national and international business, a receding agriculture, an advancing industry, large scale manufacturing managed on capitalistic lines and growing in scope, with fac- 3 ■IIP*"" 4 Birth of the Economy tories working for export and competing with one another for sales in the world market? Or should we assume, on the contrary, that the stage of the closed "household economy" had not yet passed; that economic activity had not attained a national, even less an international scale; that no organized commerce involving long-distance trading was carried on and that, consequently, no large-scale industry producing for foreign markets existed? In brief, was the character of economic life still agrarian rather than industrial? Was commerce still restricted to a peddling of particular wares, the work of craftsmen producing without the aid of machinery and using the raw materials that were locally available to them?2 Oertel termed the first the positive, the latter the negative theory. Johannes Hasebroek, more appropriately, called the first the modernizing, the latter the primitivist view. But careful examination of the terms employed by Oertel to describe the issues involved in the dispute as well as the various attempts to characterize the opposing positions serves well to indicate the lack of conceptual clarity which has dogged the controversy from the beginning. Debates such as this are resolved either by the appearance of new evidence or by the conceptual clarification of the problem so that the previously existing evidence falls into new perspective. In this case, the facts, on what we will call the operational level, can no longer be in dispute. It is, rather, the interpretation of these facts at the institutional level which remains unsettled. The oikos Theorem: Karl Rodbertus The origins of this controversy go back to Rodbertus' essay on Economic Life in Classical Antiquity, which appeared over the years 1864-1867. The second part of this essay dealt with the "History of Roman Tributes from the Time of Augustus."3 Here Rodbertus contrasted sharply modern and ancient taxation systems. His approach was highly suggestive. Modern taxation, he wrote, differentiates between personal and property taxes; these latter are either taxes on landed property or taxes on capital; capital, again, is either industrial or commercial, and the latter is invested either in goods or in money (i.e., either in industry or in finance). All these types of property appear as distinct from one another; indeed they appertain to different social classes. Distinctions analogous to those regarding property are also made in regard to incomes. We distinguish purely personal incomes, The Secular Debate on Economic Piimitivism $ such as wages or salaries, which are due to the use of labor power, from income that derives from impersonal property, or title to ownership, such as rent; this latter may be either rent from land or profit; profit, again, is split up into interest and entrepreneurial profit. "This state of affairs," Rodbertus concluded, "resulted in a modern expanding economy."4 The various stages of production are here linked with one another through the process of buying and selling. In this fashion varying claims to a share in the national dividend are created which take the form of money incomes. This remarkably modern view of the social function of money has not been sufficiently appreciated. Rodbertus realized that the transition from a "natural economy" to a "money economy" was not simply a technical matter, which resulted from a substitution of money purchase for barter. He insisted instead that a monetarized economy involved a social structure entirely different from that which went with an economy in kind. It was this change in the social structure accompanying the use of money rather than the technical fact of its use which ought to be emphasized, he thought. Had this point been expanded to include the varying social structures accompanying trading activity in the ancient world the controversy might have been resolved before it began. Instead the "household" or "oikos" held the center of the stage. With Rodbertus the oikos was no more than a logical construct, a kind of anticipation of a Weberian "Ideal type." He invented the term, "lord of the oikos"5 to designate the owner of all the various titles to property and the corresponding incomes listed above. All this was designed to illustrate how, instead of a multitude of differentiated taxes, the ancient Romans knew only one tax, the tributum paid by the lord of the oikos whose revenue was a compound of all those various kinds of incomes which had been fragmented by the modern "money economy." For Rodbertus the oikos Was typified by the vast Roman slave-worked domain, but historical confusion is apparent in a tendency to speak of the oikos without reference to any definite period. The term oikos thus became merely a peg upon which to hang the concept of economy in kind under which money, markets, and exchange were at a discount, in spite of the existence of an elaborate organization of production. The essential element in this speculative theory upon which controversy later hinged was Rodbertus' statement that in this oikos economy 6 Birth of the Economy Nowhere does buying and selling intervene, nowhere do goods change hands. Since the national dividend never changes hands, it nowhere splits up into various income categories as in modern times. ... All this necessitated economy-in-kind. No money was needed to make the national dividend pass from one phase of production to the other, since no change of ownership was involved.6 Karl Bücher and Eduard Meyer Here the matter might have rested had it not been for Karl Biicher's path-breaking work, Die Entstehung der Volkswirtschaft, first published in 1893. The great achievement of Bücher was to link the study of economic life in the ancient world with primitive economics. His aim was to establish a general theory of economic development from primitive to modern times. He did not equate classical antiquity with primitive society, but by emphasizing the relatively recent tribal origins of ancient Greek and Roman society, he suggested that ancient economic life might better be understood if viewed from the perspective of primitive rather than modern society. Regarding our specific interest his thesis was that not before the emergence of the modern state do we find a Volkswirtschaft, i.e., a complex economic life on larger than a city scale. Up to the year 1000 a.d. the economy never passed beyond the stage of closed domestic economy (geschlossene Hauswirtschaft) where production was solely for one's own needs, involving no exchange between the household units. The economic life of the Greeks, Carthaginians and Romans, he said, was typified by this oikos economy. (Here he referred to Rod-bertus.)7 Bücher later conceded that before the development of a large scale slave economy, there was a much larger amount of free wage labor, professional services, and exchange in general. However he still maintained his thesis in the following form: Complex economic life of a territorial character on a large scale (Volkswirtschaft) is the result of a development covering a period of thousands of years, and is no older than the modern state. Prior to this, mankind existed over long stretches of time without any system of exchange of goods and services that deserves the name of a complex economic life on a national scale.8 By settling on the self-sufficient oikos as the central unit of ancient society and placing this construct in a speculative theory of economic The Secular Debate on Economic Pnmitivism 7 development, Bücher forced himself into the position of having to deny the significance of trade and money in ancient society. Thus the unfortunate oikos theorem cast the die of the controversy which was to ensue, and provided an easy target for Eduard Meyer who vigorously challenged Bücher's position in 1895.9 Meyer summed up his opposing thesis in the dictum that, "... the later period of antiquity was in essence entirely modern."10 In support of this he adduced evidence on a number of points which seemed decisive: "The ancient world possessed an articulated economic life with a highly developed system of transportation and an intensive exchange of commodities."11 "In the ancient Orient we meet from the earliest recorded time with a highly developed manufacturing industry, a general system of commerce, and the use of precious metals as the means of exchange."12 Here he went on to say that since 2500 b.c. Babylonia produced numerous documents referring to private business transactions in regard to slaves, land and buildings, dividing of property at death, etc. There we find a developed system of accountancy in terms of gold and silver, which spread all over the civilized world and served as a basis for coinage. The central point which seemed to prove the economic modernity of the ancient world was that, "Trade and money were of fundamental importance in the economic life of the ancients."13 Meyer's position is what Hasebroek has called the "modernizing" attitude, what Oertel described as the "positive" approach, while Sal-violi termed it the historians' view. A more precise designation for this position might be "the market-oriented" view. Our modern world is indeed characterized by an unprecedented development of productive power, an international trade network, and the use of money as a universal means of exchange. By suggesting that the ancient world had begun on the same line Meyer was, of course, adopting a "modernizing" attitude. It was also "positive" in the sense that it attributed these elements to ancient civilization; and it did represent the nineteenth-century historians' traditional view. But these terms do not convey the central feature of Meyer's position. The pivotal institution of the modern economy is the market. It is under its aegis that production, trade and money are integrated into a self-contained economic system. And the crucial point in regard to the position of Meyer and the "modernists" is that in asserting the existence of large scale manufacturing, trade and money, they also assumed their organization to follow the market p 8 Birth of the Economy pattern. But whether or not these elements of any specific economy are so organized is a point for investigation at least equally as important as the fact of their existence. The fact that the debate turned so much upon the exclusive importance of the oikos obscured this point and thereby weakened the position of the "primitivists." The "evidence" clearly turned against them. The long-distance carrying and exchange of goods and the use of money objects were indeed widely spread features of ancient economic life, and in 1932 Michael Rostovtzeff was able to state that the oikos position was then held by almost no one.14 But this was a pyrrhic victory for the market-oriented position. The oikos had been a spurious issue from the start. Once that thesis was thoroughly discredited the argument could move to the level on which it should have begun. On this level there is no disputing the "facts" regarding the physical movements of slaves, grain, wine, oil, pottery; their changing hands between distant peoples, nor can one deny some local exchanges between city and countryside. There is likewise no question of the use of money objects. The question is, how were these elements of economic life institutionalized to produce the continuous goods and person movements essential to a stable economy? Max Weber and Michael Rostovtzeff It was the genius of Max Weber which eventually permitted the debate to reach this level. Accepting neither the "primitive" nor the "modern" approach to the problem, Weber admitted that there were some similarities between the economy of the European ancient world at the height of its development and that of the later medieval period, but he emphasized the unique characteristics of ancient culture which for him made all the difference.15 The force which moved the Greek and Roman economies in their special direction, according to Weber, was the general military-political orientation of ancient culture. War in ancient times was the hunt for men and economic advantages were won through the ceaseless wars and, in peace, by political means. Even the cities, although superficially like those of the Middle Ages in economic outline, were essentially different in total outlook and organization. The Secular Debate on Economic Primitivism 9 Taken in its entirety ... the city democracy of antiquity is a political guild. Tribute, booty, the payments of confederate cities, were merely distributed among the citizens. . . . The monopoly of the political guild included cleruchy, the distribution of conquered land among the citizens, and the distribution of the spoils of war; and at the last the city paid out of the proceeds of its political activity theater admissions, allotments of grain, and payments for jury service and for participation in religious rites.16 Weber thus opened the way to a new interpretation of the "facts," over which there was now little dispute. No victim of a preconceived stage theory of economic development, his approach showed the possibility of a relatively high level of economic organization existing in a societal framework basically different from that of the modern market system. It can hardly be said, however, that Weber resolved the issues in this secular debate, for while he sketched in the outlines of a new approach, he did not provide the conceptual tools with which to answer specific questions regarding trade organization, money uses, and methods of exchange. And although Johannes Hasebroek's detailed and masterful elaboration of Weber's thesis in 1931" secured an important victory for the so-called "primitivist" side, Michael Rostovtzeff's questioning opposition proved that all the issues had not thereby been resolved. Rostovtzeff conceded that the class warfare and revolutions which created the democracy of the Greek city states were of a different character than those which established capitalism in the modern western world, and that the ideals of the new society retained the color of the chieftain's society which had preceded it.18 But in effect this merely moved forward the time setting of the controversy. Rostovtzeff argued that the debate should focus on the high point of ancient economic development, that is, the Hellenistic and early Roman period. And regarding this period, Rostovtzeff stood firm: "As far as I am concerned, the difference between the economic life of this period and that of the modern world is only quantitative, not qualitative."19 To deny this, Rostovtzeff declared, would be to deny that the ancient world had achieved any economic development over four thousand years. Like Oertel, Rostovtzeff maintained that the controversy was made up of this dilemma: did the ancient world in its long existence go through a development similar to that of the modern world or was the whole ancient world based upon a primitive stage of economic life? He labeled the closed household theorem an ideal construction which I 10 Birth of the Economy never existed, above all not in Greece where there was an active trade with the highly developed Oriental empires. And did the Ionian Greeks gain nothing from the cities of the Near East where they settled? "Surely something must have happened!"20 This statement of Rostovtzeff's view of the issues in the oikos controversy appeared in 1932, and thus represented the culmination of nearly forty years of debate since the publication of Biicher's book in 1893. Yet it is remarkable how little clarification of the issues had been achieved; opposing sides still clashed in a conceptual twilight. The source of the confusion now appears obvious. Both sides, with the partial exception of Weber, were unable to conceive of an elaborate economy with trade, money, and market places being organized in any manner other than that of the market system. The "primitivists," who insisted that the ancient world was different from the modern, sought their support in the oikos, which to them represented an earlier stage in the development of the self-same market system. The "modernists" saw Greece and Rome resting on a foundation four thousand years in the building, which included the high economic and cultural life of the ancient Near East. Meyer emphasized the high economic development of this area and Rostovtzeff the contact between it and Greek and Roman culture. To them it was inconceivable that such a long period, full of cultural achievement, would not produce an economy at least up to the level of the later medieval period. As Rostovtzeff declared, "Something must have happened!" But what if those four thousand years of development had moved along different lines than those of the modern world? Then the perspective from which Greece and Rome should be viewed would have to be shifted. Not capitalism, then, but a different organization of economic life would be the model from which to judge the high period of ancient economy. Biicher's primitivist perspective and Weber's military-political approach had suggested this view of the question. But neither Bücher nor Weber had provided adequate conceptual tools for recognizing what had happened, i.e., the institutional foundations of this different sort of economic development. The following chapters of this work are devoted to this task. Exploring anew the position of trade, money, and market in the Mediterranean empires, a radically new perspective is gained from which to view the economic life of the people of the Old World. This perspective gives a much broader range to the issues of the oikos debate. For The Secular Debate on Economic Primirivism 11 now the elements of markets and commercial trade which appear in the Greek classical and Hellenistic periods are seen not as the heritage of over four thousand years of Mesopotamian development, but as portentous new inventions seeking a place in Greek culture. Harry W.Pearson Notes to Chapter I 1. No attempt has been made in this chapter to summarize all of the contributions to this debate; the intent here is to present only the essential outlines. The best bibliographies are to be found in M. I. Rostovtzeff, Social and Economic History of the Hellenistic World, III (Oxford, 1941), 1327-28, fn. 25; and, more recently in Eduard Will, "Trois quarts de siede de recherches sur 1'economie grecque antique," Annales, IX (January-March, 1954). 2. Friedrich Oertel, Supplement and comments appended to Robert Pöhlmann, Geschichte der sozialen Frage und des Sozialismus in der antiken Welt, 3d ed., III (Munich, 1925), 516-17. 3. Karl Rodbertus, "Zur Geschichte der römischen Tributsteuern," Jahrbücher für Nationalökonomie und Statistik, IV (1865), 339 and passim. 4. Ibid.,p. 342. 5. Ibid., p. 344. 6. Ibid., pp. 345-6. 7. Karl Bücher, Industrial Evolution, English translation (New York, 1912), pp. 96-97. 8. Ibid., p. 88. 9. This challenge was delivered in Meyer's address to the third meeting of the German historians at Frankfort in 1895. The address, "Die wirtschaftliche Entwicklung des Altertums," is published in Eduard Meyer, Kleine Schriften (Halle, 1924), pp. 79 ff. 10. Ibid., p. 89. 11. Ibid., p. 88. 12. Ibid., p. 90. 13. Ibid., p. 88. 14. Cf. his review of T. Hasebroek, Zeitschrift für die Gesammte Staatswissen-schalt, 92 (1932), 334. 15. "Die sozialen Griinde des Untergangs der antiken Kultur," Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Sozial-und Wirtschaftsgeschichte (Tübingen, 1924), pp. 289-311. See also Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft, ch. 8 (Tübingen, 1922). 16. Max Weber, General Economic Histoiy (Glencoe, Illinois, 1950), p. 331. 17. Griechische Wirtschafts-und Gesellschaftsgeschichte (Tübingen, 1931). 18. Op.cit.p. 337. 19. Ibid., p. 335, n. 1. 20. Ibid., p. 338. II JAarhtlcss Trading in Hammurahis Time at one stage or another in the history of almost any field of study, the condition may obtain that the more ample the facts that come to our cognizance the less do they appear to fit into a pattern. In regard to the Babylonian economy, Max Weber showed himself conscious of deep-seated difficulties as early as 1909, but never returned to the issue. Among the Assyriologists themselves symptoms of malaise were noticeable only comparatively late, but then all the more significantly. Paul Koschaker, who time and again warned against some of the assumptions made by the earlier pioneers, eventually complained that his own efforts had reached a dead end. His study on economic administration in the Old Babylonian state (1942) closed, in his own words, "on a discordant and sceptical note." It had not been found possible, he intimated, satisfactorily to apply transactional terms to the process of governmental trading as it was recorded in the documents of Larsa; we might, he added, for the time being have to resign ourselves to the inadequacy of rational concepts to cope with the administrative irrationalities of what he arraigned as hyperbureaucratic trading methods. In this particular phrasing, a policy bias may be deemed to have interfered with that great scholar's clarity of vision. However such a view would bypass the heart of the matter. The anything but anti-socialist V. Gordon Childe also failed to disperse the obscurities surrounding Markerless Trading in Hammurabi's Time 13 the early form of economic life in that area. His theory of an "urban revolution," reflecting the results of the spectacular advance of the archaeology of prehistory, nevertheless, offers no answer to the question how production and trade were organized. It should be assumed, therefore, that the obstacles to a deeper insight transcended any preferences of historical philosophy or economic policy. Indeed, there may be strong reasons to believe that the frustration with which the inquiring mind has met in the field of the Babylonian economy is only the latest phase of that secular perplexity which for almost a century went under the name of oikos controversy, as presented in the previous chapter. The issue was roughly, whether at the highest point of its development the society of classical Greece and Rome in its economic aspects was essentially modern or primitive. Pseudo-economy and Inverted Perspective In retrospect it is not too difficult to see why, even where there was broad agreement on the facts, interpretation remained elusive. Actually, the question at issue was the extent to which the economy, in its various spheres, was organized through markets. Evidence of functioning markets is not so readily available as might be supposed. Even under modern conditions it is often a delicate matter to ascertain whether at a definite time and place a supply-demand-price mechanism for a definite good or service is in operation or not. For the distant past direct evidence may not be at hand. We are then forced back to relying on such indirect evidence as those culture traits that commonly denote the presence of markets and market activities in a society. But this type of evidence is deceptive. Traits superficially recalling a business men's culture may occur independently of markets and even of the economy altogether. Famous instances of pseudo-economies, such as the potlatch or the Kula trade, details of which sometimes are almost a mimicry of stock-jobbers' activities, abound with the Manus of the Great Admiralty Islands, the Tolowa-Tututni of California or the Kwakiutl of the North West Coast. Habits not intrinsically economic, such as the urge of gambling, competition in auctioneering, rigid accountancy, the lure of risk, pride in a public turnover, which occur in modern business life, also play a vital part in the social fabric of primitive communities. Obviously, the presence of such pseudo-economic 12 f 14 Birth of the Economy traits is not proof of functioning markets. Moreover—yet another ambiguity—some genuine economic institutions that in their elaborate form we justly regard as having arisen only in modern times are found to have occurred under archaic conditions as well. However, while as to its structure the institution may be similar, its function may be very different. In its early, premarket form it acted as a substitute for markets; in its market form it is, on the contrary, supplementary to the existing market. Examples: In recent centuries business life produced complex credit structures and clearing systems, elaborate forms of brokerage, and special purpose moneys. All of these must be regarded as new. Yet, in much less complex forms similar institutions had existed before, in early societies. The explanation is simple. Where barter is widespread, credit, brokerage, clearing or money used as a standard help to carry on barter and thus make up for the absence of exchange-money and markets. To use modern terms, it may be said that in these cases the lack of functioning markets calls for a substitute for markets. In the absence of money employed as a means of exchange there is often a large-scale public storage of staples with the concomitant practice of carrying debt accounts of individuals, and accompanying clearing practices. Though money is not used as a means of exchange, it may well be employed as a standard as well as a means of payment, different goods being used for the different purposes. Brokerage and auction are then the usual devices of arranging for exchange. With the development of markets such practices, of course, become superfluous and tend to disappear, until much later they reappear again, only this time in a sophisticated form and in the new role of assisting the functioning of highly developed markets. Typical of such a recurrence of institutional traits and operational devices which made their reappearance in our days, is the field which we call banking. Historically the appearance of money-changers, these earliest bankers, preceded the general use of coined money. Even branch banking reached a high development in Ptolemaic Egypt, where it served as a means of running an advanced planned economy in kind, without markets or money as a means of exchange. Actually, the clearing of obligations between traders' accounts appears to have been general fifteen hundred years prior to Ptolemaic Egypt, in the "early Assyrian" trade, in the absence not only of price-making markets, but even of coined money. To sum up: The elusive element in the oikos controversy was the Marketless Trading in Hammurabi's Time 15 role of the market on which in reality the issues centered even though with no sufficient awareness of this circumstance on the part of the disputants. Translated into these terms, Rodbertus stressed that in the absence of a market system taxation in the Late Roman Empire would naturally be based on a general property tax put on the practically self-sufficient households of the big slave-owning landowners. Biicher, again in these terms, recognized that modern economies were integrated through national markets, themselves largely creations of the state, a development that had never occurred before. Finally, Weber's position on capitalism in antiquity as well as that of Rostovtzeff boiled down to the factual question to what extent, large or small, was the economic process in ancient Rome at other times and in its other aspects instituted through markets. But in asserting the presence of markets we must carefully avoid a dangerous pitfall. Economic acitivi-ties under advanced market conditions may resemble similar activities under premarket conditions while their function is quite different. The distinction between pre- and postmarket should help to avoid that "inverted perspective," as it might be called, which sometimes induced historians to see strikingly "modern" phenomena in antiquity where in fact they were faced by typically primitive or archaic ones. Problems of the Babylonian Economy Paul Koschaker in 1942 was indeed much less confident of our grasp of the Babylonian economy than Eduard Meyer had been in 1895. The underlying reasons will now become apparent. Shortly after Biicher's and Meyer's clash of views, the find was made of the obsidian stele on which the Code of Hammurabi was displayed. To all intents and purposes it contained a commercial code of law which was (at the time) dated about twenty-five centuries before our era.* The significance of the sheaves of clay tablets relating to business matters that had been previously unearthed now stood revealed. Civilization, so much seemed evident, had been born from man's commercial instincts; and the cradle of our own world, that of a businessmen's culture, had been uncovered in Babylonia; to argue the primitive character of the economic life of antiquity in the face of these facts was no more than a fad. A series of scholars whose critical faculties * More recently dated around the second half of the XVII century b.c 16 Birth of the Economy have been rarely surpassed in any field of learning testified to the collective findings. There was no lack of differences between them on detail, nor of the recognition of important lacunae—but as to the general character of the economy, the ethos of the participants, the attitudes and value scales on which they oriented their behavior, no doubt could prevail. We had here before us the very essence of a capitalistically minded business community, in which king and god alike engaged in profiteering, making the best of their chances in lending money at usury and imbuing a whole civilization with the spirit of money-making over millennia. It is against this climate of opinion that the doubts here voiced in regard to the actual organization of the economic life of the ancient Near East should be viewed. In terms of our interpretation of the oikos controversy the impasse can be succinctly formulated. Babylonian economic life had necessarily appeared as a complex of activities ultimately depending on the functioning of an underlying market system. Markets were the rock bottom on which rested with axiomatic assurance the determination of forms of trade, money uses, prices, commercial transactions, profit and loss accounts, insolvency, partnership, in short, the essentials of business life. It follows that in the absence of such markets these explanations of the economic institutions and their way of functioning must fall to the ground. We submit that this precisely is the case. Babylonia, as a matter of fact, possessed neither market places nor a functioning market system of any description. This recognition, which supplies the main thesis of this chapter arises out of a number of mutually supporting groups of facts: (1) Herodotus, who visited Babylon some time between 470 and 460 b.c, asserted with the greatest possible emphasis that "the Persians do not frequent market places and in effect, do not possess in their country a single market place." (Her. I, 153.) This passage was consistently ignored by economic historians of Mesopotamia. (2) Even a superficial survey of the legal character of economic transactions from the Old Babylonian period down to Persian times showed the soundness of the accepted view that in spite of the intervening "Dark Ages" no striking change in the nature and character of these transactions had ever occurred. (3) It appeared as a matter of common sense that market places, had they been present to any extent in Hammurabi's time, would Marketless Trading in Hammurabi's Time 17 * hardly have disappeared so thoroughly as to be beyond reviving during that upsurge of business activities which took place a thousand years later, and in the wake of which Herodotus was visiting Babylon. (4) According to reliable archaeological evidence the walled towns of Palestine (with the single exception of Hellenistic Jerusalem) possessed right down to their destruction no open spaces whatsoever. (5) The chief market place of Babylon would offer a landmark not easily overlooked. Yet contemporary literary records of the names, sites and layout of temples and avenues of that city which were discovered in the library of Ashur-banipal indicated no open space of this kind. (6) Some half dozen different words occurring in various cuneiform documents and translated in different contexts as "market" turned out on closer inquiry either not to mean "market place" at all or at least to be doubtful. (7) Eventually, partial confirmation was received in February, 1953, from A. L. Oppenheim, in these terms: "As to your specific questions: Archaeological evidence speaks against the existence of 'market places' within the cities of the Ancient Near East."* An Early Assyrian Trading Post ^ A rough outline of accounts of an early Assyrian trading post that existed over a century in the period of Hammurabi in the center of Asia Minor shall provide us with a generalized version of how Assyri-ologists only a few decades ago conceived of the organization of trade in this admittedly specific case. Such a broad survey shall throw into relief the problems that must arise if the traditional view—based on the assumption of markets is to be replaced by another resting on the same data yet barring that assumption. It will hardly be possible to avoid some repetitiousness, when contrasting the composite scene as it emerges from our sources—the two main publications, that of Landsberger in 1925, and Eisser-J. Lewy in 1935—with the tentative picture we here suggest as an alternative. The first publication was admittedly conjectural—unavoidably so, in view of the gaps in the evidence; also it justly claimed the right to a free rendering of the selected illustrative material, so as to round off the original texts where meticulous precision could have produced but inarticulate fragments. The * See below, pp. 30-31. I 18 Birth of the Economy second publication, a decade later, comprised the bulk of the then transliterated tablets, and was roughly in accordance with the first, from which it differed, apart from detail, mainly in literal accuracy and legal elaboration. Landsberger had offered a brilliant sequence of lifelike scenes, suggestive of the drama of business; Eisser-J. Lewy supplied philological comment and juridical systematization. We will keep this brief and inevitably elliptic sketch of their presentations to three points: personnel and incentives; the nature of the goods; the character of the activities. Near Kanish, on the river Halys, we have a settlement of Assyrian merchants, members of the so-called karum, businessmen who make profit on buying and selling, partnership, loaning and investing. The records are ample; they cover some three generations and end abruptly. The merchants act as middlemen between the distant city of Assur, to which they themselves belong by race, religion and language, and between the subjects of a native prince (or princes) of central Anatolia. Whatever its origin, the rationale of the trading post as actually organized is the procurement of copper for the City. Profit is made on the sale-purchase of goods, on loans—short or long—on participations and as between the members of the firm, on a share in the profit. The firm is a family affair, though not exclusively so. Frequently a journeyman or junior partner, in reward for his services as a traveler, is accorded an interest-free loan, in money or goods, which he is permitted to use for trading on his own account (be'ulatum). The main driving force in business is the big man in Ashshur (ummeanum), who provides the goods, lends the money, invests sums over a long term against interest or participation or both. However, some of the more successful gild merchants in Kanish may be doing likewise. Transportation is organized through a special group of carriers, on a commercial basis. Besides these, the anonymous figure of the tamkarum is in evidence, whose function, interests and activities are not clear, but evidently important. The goods are, primarily, copper, as we said, which is handled as a monopoly by the karum as such. Second, consignment ware such as lead (tin?) and fine cloths from the capital. From Kanish, native cloth and other goods are exported. Silver bars move both ways. Third, "free" goods are mentioned, which are neither subject to "monopoly" nor to consignment. The main activity is sale-purchase, mostly in regard to goods on consignment, on which the merchant can claim a commission. For the rest, his job is to find a customer for the goods and to Marketless Trading in Hammurabi's Time 19 make the best of the chances of the market. Prices and interest rates fluctuate almost in the stock-exchange manner, so he must keep an eye on them. Dealings amongst the merchants give rise to disputes, often brought to a head by arbitration. In other cases, severe penalties, moral as well as physical, seem to threaten the defaulter at the hand of the authorities. All this would accord well with a system of market trading before coined money was invented and executive organs were set up capable of enforcing court decisions. Other points appeared to fit in less well with these assumptions. Landsberger did not fail to remark that profits are hardly ever explicitly mentioned, losses practically never, prices are not the center of interest, and dealings amongst merchants are not secured by surety or pledge, as usual in archaic trade. Also the data implied that there was a prohibition on other than cash transactions, at least in regard to consigned goods. Moreover, it was noted that rules were sometimes enforceable under the threat of the death penalty. So far, the bare outline of the traditional presentation. Risk-fiee Trading It is unavoidable, then, that we take another look at the Assyrian trade settlement and suggest methods of trading suitable in the general circumstances as we see them. Yet in the main we will be merely reinterpreting the above data. Nonmarket trade—this is the crucial point—is in all essentials different from market trade. This applies to personnel, goods, prices, but perhaps most emphatically to the nature of the trading activity itself. The traders of the karum of Kanish were not merchants in the sense of persons making a living out of the profit derived from buying and selling, i.e., price differentials in regard to the transaction in hand. They were traders by status, as a rule by virtue of descent or early apprenticeship, in other cases maybe, by appointment. Unless the appointment was accompanied by a substantial land grant—as we may assume in the case of the tamkarum, but not in that of the members of the gild— their revenue derived from the turnover of goods on which a commission was earned. This was the original source of all "profit," i.e., that pool of goods, including silver, in which eventually the internal mem- 20 Birth of the Economy bers of the firm as well as the external ones, i.e., creditors and partners shared. The goods were trade goods—storable, interchangeable and standardized, or, as Roman law has it, quae numero, pondere ac mensura consistunt. Apart from standard cloths, the chief staples were metals —probably silver, copper, lead and tin, all goods reckoned according to their silver equivalent. Silver, besides functioning as standard, was also, up to a point, a means of payment. The role of gold was much more restricted in both these uses. "Prices" took the form of equivalencies established by authority of custom, statute or proclamation.* The necessaries of life were supposed to be subject to permanent equivalencies; actually they were subject to long-range changes by the same methods by which they had been established. This need not have affected the trader's revenue, which did not depend on price differentials. In principle there was always a "price," i.e., the equivalency at which the trader both bought and sold. But rules regarding the application of equivalencies were hardly the same for monopoly goods, consignment ware and "free" goods. The numerous qualifying adjectives which accompany the term equivalency refer to the various rules and their effects. The equivalency for copper, "a monopoly," was fixed by treaty over a long term. Copper mining, as organized by the natives, would involve assurances by their chiefs that at least a part of the equivalencies, presumably in goods coveted by the people, would be forthcoming in definite amounts. As to consignment ware, mainly fine cloths manufactured in Assur and imported lead (or tin?), "prices" were similarly fixed and the goods bought and sold at that "price." "Prices" for free goods are especially important, for eventual departures towards market trading were likely to originate from here; in other words, the present meaning of "price" might have developed from equivalencies for "free" goods. The many different adjectives attaching to equivalencies in the Sumerian formulary (also found in Ugarit) as well as the peculiar terminology of Larsa documents indicate that the handling of "equivalencies" must have been subject to administrative rules of an intricate kind. In the twentieth century a.d., this should surprise no one. However, the chief difference between administrative or treaty trade on the one hand and market trade on the other lies in the trader's activities themselves. In contrast to market trade, those activities are here * See below, p. 32. Ms&etless Trading in Hammurabi's Time 21 risk-free, both in regard to price expectation and debtor's insolvency. Price risk is excluded by the absence of price-making markets with * . their fluctuating prices, and the general organization of trade which does not depend for profit on price differentials, but rather on turnover, r* Hence that relative lack of concern with prices; absence of the mention » of profits on the business in hand; and even more important, mention ► of losses. In effect, participation in business is participation in profits. This has far-reaching consequences for the forms of trade partnership, , which cannot be understood at all unless the discounting of loss on f prices, as a general rule, is kept in mind. *■ There is no risk of debtor's insolvency, and consequently hardly i anv mention of losses on bad debts. This fact is as incisive in regard to 4 the organization of trade as the absence of risk on prices. ] In contrast with modern society, the archaic state makes obligations 4 towards the public hand stricti juris, while obligations toward the private need not always be so. He to whom public goods are entrusted must unfailingly be able to produce either the goods themselves or their * equivalent. This fits in well with the practice of in rem transactions (Zug um Zug, didontes kai labontes) and the exclusion of credit. Several known features of Karum-trading follow: (1) No sale except for cash. (2) The Kanish trader receives his consignment of goods against security to the value of the goods. (3) Obligations against third parties must be registered with the competent authority, City, Karum or Palace (in the case of natives); hence, in principle, all obligations are guaranteed by I the public hand. Under treaty trade this rule is widely attested. (4) The public hand assumes here no risks, since it would refuse to guarantee obligations beyond the security in hand. U In case of fraud or the infringement of the rules of law, the severest penalties are applied. Taken together all this explains why apparently no default on debt occurs; why arbitration awards are self-executing; how it comes about that the account-keeping authority can simply charge the defaulter's account with the amount awarded to the other party; why membership of the Karum and a good standing with the City is a precondition of trading; why no pledges to ensure payment are met with; why the interest-free loan employed by the journeyman for trading on his own account, the be'ulatum, is never lost; why business knows only profit, not loss. 22 Birth of the Economy Under such circumstances of no-risk business along administrative lines, the term "transaction" hardly applies; we will therefore designate this type of activity as "dispositional." The traders' activities were manifold: copper procurement desig-volved a mining of the ore; its collection and transportation; refinement; storage and payment. The trader's job was to stimulate native mining activity through advances and, perhaps, long-term investments, up to several years duration; to ensure delivery and deposit the copper with the gild office in Kanish. But his main job was to make payment for the copper or whatever else he had bought. Some may have been paid for in refining the copper, some in silver, tin or imported high-grade cloth. The rest of the copper and native cloth were exported, the latter maybe, after having been finished on the spot. All that which was bought with consignment goods went to Assur. Although the principles of "fixed price," "cash delivery," "legal surety," and "commission on turnover" obtained throughout, the trader's job was far from simple: to make the right contacts among the natives; correctly to judge their requirement of goods; make his financial arrangements in time; conform strictly to rule and regulation; dispose with precision the goods entrusted to him; see to the quality of the wares, either way; procure funds with which to make advances to prospective suppliers, and for deposit with the government; as well as many other matters. Mistakes or omissions meant delay; difficulty in raising loans; small procurement; unnecessary expense; domestic unpleasantness; loss of authority in the family firm; trouble with colleagues and authorities; a reduced turnover. Yet, in this marketless trade there was no loss on prices, no speculation, no failure of debtors. It was exciting as an occupation, but risk-free as a business. Transactions and Dispositions This dispositional mode of dealing was the main characteristic of early Assyrian trade. The essential element in the trader's behavior was not a two-sided act resulting in a negotiated contract but a sequence of one-sided declarations of will, to which definite effects were attached under rules of law which governed the administrative organization of the treaty trade he was engaged in. It is easy to deduce from this the criteria of dispositional trading. (1) Acquisition of goods from a distance—the criterion of all au- Marketless Trading in Hammurabi's Time 23 thentic trade—was the constitutive element. The procurement of useful objects ran in a peaceful way, goods going in both directions. There was a large professional personnel employed in the acquisitional activities and the actual physical carrying of the wares. The traders derived a revenue from their activities, in which they had a direct financial interest. (2) Although acting within the frame of a governmental organization and a network of official and semi-official institutions, the trader remained an independent agent. He was in no one's employ, under the orders of no superior, free to expand and contract his business at will, or to discontinue it altogether. If unskilled, lazy or unwise, his earnings would drop. But he need not fear the summons of any employer or higher authority—as long as he kept within the law. The principle of rule of law was paramount. (3) Nevertheless, not even in principle could transactions or private deals be banned. The rationale of "rule of law" therefore was the institutional separation of the trader's dispositions relating to public business from his private transactions. The trader needed capital to be provided in the form of short or long term loans, or of partnerships; associates, as members of the firm; employees to travel for him and do the neighborhood carrying; he was free to buy and sell non-consigned ware; to loan money to firms and to participate in their profits. Yet at no time was there to be any doubt about the "public" as distinguished from the "private" character of the deal—whether the trader had acted in his public capacity in the course of the copper procurement involving consignments of government ware or apart from this public business, that is, privately. In the former sphere, his steps were formalized and his acts were phrased as dispositions; in the latter sphere, they were informal and could be described as transactions. But of what kind the institutions were, which in the various fields of economic activity permitted such a separation to become effective, is still largely hidden from our view. Did the separation run on the lines of the different kinds of goods in question, the quantities involved, or rather according to the origin of the funds employed, or maybe combinations of these criteria? We do not yet know. (4) Documents were recorded by public scribes, made out under the supervision of public officials, a copy of the document presumably filed in the official archives, under readily identifiable headings. The state of affairs in regard to any item of business could then at all times 24 Birth of the Economy be ascertained at headquarters. The documents themselves were set out with a brevity and precision which enabled the public trustee— the tamkarum—to take action at all times if enjoined by an interested party in legitimate possession of a copy of the relevant document. The Tamkarum The key to the functions of the tamkarum lies in the methods and organization of trading. And vice versa: the key to the understanding of those methods lies in the office of the tamkarum. His figure and function are sui generis. His primary duties are those of a public trustee; he takes action under the law as soon as an authorized person produces (or rather has read out to him) the appropriate clay tablet, probably leaving a copy; according to the case and the situation, his duty is to advance fares or other small expenses; to accept pledges, as, e.g., of a slave that may have been handed to the gild merchant on the default of his native debtor; to be instrumental in having goods from the City purchased by the gild merchant and (although this does not clearly appear) to deliver on the trader's behalf goods to the City; to facilitate transportation by accepting responsibility for money and goods entrusted to carriers, and also for the safety of the goods bought in. the City for the account of the gild trader (in these latter cases a document was made out, addressed to the tamkarum, which the creditor could transfer to another gild merchant if he happened to be in need of cash); to have goods auctioned at the trader's request, crediting him with the sum thus recovered, whether it happened to be "more or less" than the equivalency. Other minor services were in the nature of legal advice and legal intervention with the karum especially if differences with the natives arose. Also, in case of sudden death of an important gild trader the sequestration of goods and monies as well as liquidation of the firm was done through his immediate intervention. The tamkarum derived no revenue from the business in hand, although he may have charged small service fees to the traders according to some fixed scale. His living was ensured through the landed property with which he was invested at his appointment. If the figure of the tamkarum can be outlined only conjecturally, that of the ummeanum must frankly be described as obscure. The suggestion made here is no more than a tentative construction that might pbrketless Trading in Hammurabi's Time 2 5 J!! the pattern of risk-free marketless trading, organized in the public interest, primarily on behalf of governmental war material procure-''. inent. The financing of such imports would be a public service. While • the trade aspects of the matter may be left to the karum and the tam-H - Jarum, respectively, who between them would take care of its efficient -.I ,.. performance, the financial side would be seen to by the ummeanum. There is, first, the handling of the accounts of the gild traders, including transfers from debtor's to creditor's accounts; secondly, direct in-> vestments into this branch of foreign trade so as to increase supply and ■* - make it more regular. The ummeanum—that much should be taken for |p * granted—was a public figure similar to the tamkarum. His investments * J and partnerships are what we might call treasury advances; these are I usually made in round sums of gold ounces (employing units of two f ' ounces) which may indicate the prestige character of the transaction, r since gold was treasure. Whether the "big men" of the land were given * a chance to invest into this privileged business and thus benefit from t the manufactures of dependent labor (particularly female) we cannot be sure. Much speaks for such an extension of palace business to the favored few. Cleomenes of Naukratis compensated the big landholders :: of Egypt for his introducing of the corn export monopoly by allowing them a profitable share in the governmental syndicate. The King of i Dahomey treated his environment with a similar liberality in matters of the royal slave trade, of which he remained, of course, the chief beneficiary!* When all is said, this type of organization of trade and business was probably unique in history. To what extent it may have served as a model for the port of trade** of late Ugarit, and eventually Sidon, r Tyre and Carthage can as yet only be conjectured. So much already ; appears certain: contrary to traditional notions, Babylonian trade ; and business activities were not originally market activities. ; The next chapter offers a bird's-eye view of Mesopotamian eco- nomic history which in more than one regard brings unexpected simpli-I fications. The absence of marketplaces from this picture provided by I an expert may be taken as supporting at a vital point the tentative 1 assumptions that underlie our presentation. Admittedly, in no detail does the new prospectus support the many conjectures that were drawn upon in this chapter to give life and plausibility to the views presented here. 26 Birth of the Economy If our interpretation is borne out by the facts, the question arises, How, when and where did market trade, fluctuating prices, profit and loss accounts, commercial methods of business, commercial classes and all the paraphernalia of a market organized economy originate? The history of market trade may be found to have shifted by a thousand years downwards and several degrees of longitude westwards, to the Ionia and Greece of the first millenium b.c. Karl Polanyi * See bebw,Ch. VIII. ** Seebelow,Ch.IV. Ill Jí 6Bird,s-&ye View of G]\Aeso^otamian &conomic History brevis esse laboro, obscurus fio; sectantem levia nervi deficiunt animique; professus grandia turget ArsPoetica, 25-27 if ample documentary evidence alone sufficed to serve as a basis for the writing of the economic history of a dead and distant civilization, the very number of cuneiform texts dealing with all aspects of the economic life of Mesopotamia should certainly enable the historian to accomplish this task. Few if any periods of history prior to the flowering of the European Middle Ages are as well documented with regard to private business activities and the dealings of the administrative offices of temples and palaces as certain eras of the history of Babylonia and Assyria. Nowhere else—China and India perhaps excepted— can the rise and development of economic institutions be observed for far more than two millennia. The number of clay tablets dealing with these matters increases by the thousands every year, and the number of published and unpublished documents approaches the hundred thousand mark with no end in sight. The practically imperishable nature of the writing material combines with the custom of recording administrative as well as private transactions in writing to yield as bountiful a harvest as any economic historian might hope for. What, then, are the reasons for the 27 28 Birth of the Economy failure of Assyriologists and economic historians alike to make the utmost of this source of information? There is, for one, the very number of texts available, with which only a few scholars are willing and able to deal adequately. More important an obstacle, however, is the conceptual barrier which hampers full understanding of both the real nature of a recorded transaction and its many-sided institutional background. Steeped in the economic theories of the nineteenth century, which affect even the Assyriologist most naive in matters of economic theory, we are bound to locate every economic situation within the traditional coordinates of money, market, price, etc., as these have been defined and have found acceptance within the last hundred years of our civilization. We constantly apply this frame of reference without even realizing that we distort the Mesopotamian picture in its most essential aspects, by basing our analysis on a set of assumptions which we take for granted are universally applicable. But this barrier is by no means insuperable. The few students of the legal institutions and of the religion of Mesopotamia came to realize some time ago—even if they have not always been able to achieve this goal—that any attempt at understanding the complex and basically alien phenomena in an archaic civilization must be oriented along the lines in which this civilization itself conceived of them. In dealing with a literate civilization, the most efficient means of reaching this understanding is to study the semantics of selected key terms rather than to use modern categories of organization as the avenues of approach. This is admittedly extremely difficult when one has to handle a dead language whose full utilization by the historian is restricted by the nature of the accidentally preserved text material. The reaction against the thought patterns evolved in the nineteenth century in the fields of history of religion, linguistics, sociology, etc., have taught us to respect alien civilizations and sharpened our faculties for self-observation in those areas; but this, unfortunately, is not the case with regard to economics. There, epistemological discussions, traditional or otherwise, have created an atmosphere in which there is no understanding of any economic pattern beyond that which has grown out of the spectacular economic development of Western Europe since the eighteenth century. The resulting attitude of the economic historians, be their background that of historic materialism or of traditional liberalism, is characterized by a markedly inadequate A Bird's-Eye View of Mesopotamian Economic History 29 treatment of the economies of so-called primitive peoples as well as by p complete disregard for the essentials of the economics of the ancient great civilizations. ■*» $ > A new approach to this problem has been opened up by the Inter-* ^ disciplinary Project at Columbia University, and has been tested in ' f several areas with considerable success. j * . The basic advantage of this approach is that it provides us with a \ \ new set of concepts which can be used to describe large sections of the complex and varied array of data which the Assyriologist culls from the economic texts. These concepts serve primarily descriptive purposes and succeed in revealing certain structurally relevant features of Mesopotamian economics. They provide adequate categories in which to organize and present a number of important observations which would otherwise remain meaningless; the most important of these concepts is that of "redistribution." This is not meant to imply that any given period or area attested in cuneiform documents can be fully or even adequately characterized by this term; in fact, the entire develop / ment of Mesopotamian economy is marked by continuous shifts in emphasis which bring now one and now another form of economic * integration to the foreground without the others completely disappearing at any time. The investigation of the exact relationship between the concept of "redistribution" and others, such as "reciprocity," consequently becomes the primary task of research, which has to extend, * moreover, into the realm of social history, since such forms of economic integration are deeply imbedded in the social fabric of the country. Of course the new approach will multiply the problems rather than offer easy solutions, but under its impact the line of investigation is bound to shift to new points of attack, and may even compel the Assyriologist to abandon the convenient excuse that lack of evidence hampers his chances to solve the problems. Under these circumstances the necessity of a re-evaluation and re-examination of the entire evidence bearing on matters economic becomes imperative. This process, moreover, should not only be applied to all text material directly concerned with the problem but also to historical, religious and literary documents. Obviously such a project is too far-reaching to be dealt with adequately by one individual, and too novel and difficult to promise easy success. For this reason the following pages represent solely an attempt to point out the possibilities of the new interpretation and are 30 Birth of the Economy meant to illustrate the approach rather than to demonstrate its effectiveness. Three main factors will be singled out here as having contributed towards the shaping of the unique socio-economic basis of Mesopo-tamian civilization as it emerges into the limelight of the literary period. Each of them recurs severally or in different combinations in other civilizations of the ancient Near East, but nowhere else appears the specific constellation which arose in Southern Babylonia. There is, first, cereal agriculture based on irrigation, able to produce reliable harvests independent of rain and capable of extension in space to support an ever-increasing population. The advantages of this type of agriculture—a crop that can easily be stored and exactly divided for distribution, yielding the greatest amount in return for the effort required under the given climatic and technological conditions—coincide with the second factor: a unique settlement pattern. Thus a situation is created which differs unmistakably from Egypt, where under apparently similar circumstances the relatively primitive type of integration that characterizes a storage-economy can be observed. The decisive difference seems to lie in the nature of the urbanization which materialized in Mesopotamia quite early, producing a city concept sui generis. In these cities, however small they be, a communal bond had so completely replaced all loyalties of the inhabitants beyond those toward the immediate family that not even their traces can be found. This relationship between individuals finds expression in the way in which the city administers itself and acts towards its own citizens, other cities, and centra] authority. The essential and unique feature of urbanization in Southern Mesopotamia is the fact that a city could grow there into a center of cultural activity without the stimulus or the presence of social conditions inherent in political power. The internal economic organization of these cities is still quite obscure, but it seems admissible to posit that it did not differ essentially from that of the village communities which we find all over the ancient Near East including those regions where agriculture relied on rain. Within a compass of fields in a commons near the city where the harvest ripened for the farmers and the few essential craftsmen, such villages could offer their populations an adequate living, necessitating but few contacts with other cities and only marginal money uses. It is essential to note that each of these towns consisted of the town proper (u r u), the suburb (u r u . b a r . r a) and the port (k a r). The absence A Biid's-Eye View of Mesopotamian Economic History 31 "* the ports of trade were bound me political factors. Part of the reason for this, again, may lie strategic importance of iron, the flow of which they controlled. i° , . n0 direct evidence is available to us. There is ample proof, how-^ * 0f the increasing importance of navies as a military factor. Com-e^er', oava]-land operations were on record since the Peoples of the D1°ea0(j continued to grow in the first millennium. In the seventh Se3 we find the Ionian amphibious troops hired by Psamtik acting CC\ catatyst in the overthrow of the power of Assyria in Egypt. Allied h the Lydians, the Phoenician cities also engaged in similar politico-lL,ty intrigues. 111 Thus one of the vital attributes of the ports of trade—their neu-trality as iS uu"------ -------------- — — L 1tv__tended to disappear, not as if they had lost their independence ^the hinterland powers; rather, they themselves had become powers m be reckoned with. This change of role was reflected in the attitude of the inland ^ers. Warily and reluctantly, they saw themselves compelled to move P° . st the ports of trade. Straight conquest and subjugation was out 3fthe quesuon' ^s would have altogether done away with their value 0 channel of entry for foreign goods. Other responses had to be as a devised jsea. Qae answer was demilitarization. This interpretation may be put the poucv °* Assyna towards Sidon, when that city was transferred f°m a tee* t0 ^e mam"and, and resettled with Assyrian colonists; ■ ilarly? on tne policies of Lydia against the Ionian cities, when the S1 Us of Smyrna were torn down. In a milder form, the Lydian policy , making annual raids against the coastal cities had the same purport. TTiese moves appear to have been as nondestructive as possible, while rthekss rendering those cities militarily helpless on land. A basic change of role was taking place which combined a more rive p^^y of the empires towards the coast with maintenance of 3 uch °^ ^e tracuuonal continental bias. Often this manifested itself •n a show of force, even in transitory control, followed by a withdrawal. Ports of Trade in the Eastern Mediterranean 57 Sometimes this led to a symbiotic relationship (as Rostovtzeff called it) growing into a closer cooperation between coast and continent than ever before. Again, we are forced to ignore the important differences \lrfiich subsisted between the simple emporia of a local range, and the elaborate organizations of foreign trade we called ports of trade. The situation, in somewhat greater detail, was this: In the northern Black Sea area, Scythia and the Greek colonies achieved a firm symbiosis, avoiding overt military pressure. Rostovtzeff describes how the Scythians exchanged their surplus goods for products of Greece and Ionia: . . . the Scythians favoured the Greek colonies, left them unmolested, entered into personal relations with them, and probably contented themselves with levying a nominal tribute as a sign of sovereignty. Neither from Herodotus nor from other 6th or 5th century sources do we hear of any conflict between the Greek colonies and the Scythians.38 In Lydia, Gyges moved against Miletus (ca. 663), Colophon, and Magnesia ad Siplum.39 That this was merely a military demonstration and an assertion of nominal suzerainty is apparent, since Gyges did not seem to aim at capturing citadels. He raided only the fields of Miletus and did not attack the two nearest coastal cities, Cyme and Ephesus. Eventually, his military activities against the coastal cities came to a halt. In a significant move, Lydia permitted Miletus to colonize Abydos on the Hellespont, on plainly Lydian soil. Gyges, himself, in the latter part of his reign, turned openly philhellene. The coastal cities and Lydia later cooperated in the face of the Cimmerian invasion. Gyges' successors, too, followed a policy of mild pressure, essentially aiming at a symbiosis. Alyattes devastated the Milesian fields every year, but left farmsteads unmolested. He destroyed the walls of Smyrna in an evident attempt at demilitarizing the city, yet did not occupy it. He concluded a treaty favorable to Miletus and, in the second half of his reign, a mutually advantageous relationship was fostered by the strong cultural affinity that was springing up between Lydia and Ionia. Jierodotus declared there was but little difference between them. Croesus, following in the traditions of Alyattes, had the hill forts of Ephesus destroyed. The other cities were left unmolested after they allowed peaceful entry to his troops. While they had to pledge annual payments, and military aid in extraordinary cases, they were not garrisoned, nor were their domestic affairs interfered with. Croesus was 58 Birth of the Economy out and out friendly towards the Greek ports of trade. Last of the Lydian monarchs, he was the most thoroughly hellenized of them all. So far, in talking about the symbiosis of empire and port of trade, we had in mind the region of the northern Black Sea and Western Asia Minor, directing our attention to the Scythian and the Lydian empires respectively. In either instance the Greek ports of trade such as Miletus, Ephesus, or Theodosia were in the center of interest. In turning south toward the Syrian coast where history started more than a thousand years earlier, two periods compete. Al Mina and Ugarit, the first ports of trade, had been faced by the inland empires of Assyria, Babylon, the Hittites, and Egypt. Their successors, Sidon and Tyre, had to deal with the Neo-Assyrian Empire, Chaldean Babylonia, and the Persians. In following up the changes that occurred in the first millennium in the policies of these latter continental powers we will have to substitute for Kanaanite Al Mina and Ugarit, their much later successors, the Phoenician cities of Sidon and Tyre. At first sight there is a striking change in Assyrian policy. The western military escapades of the Mesopotamian rulers of the third and second millennium now turn into regular warfare, which seems to aim at the permanent conquest of the West with a Mediterranean coast as its ultimate object. In this move Assyria, with its almost yearly campaigns, has the lead. The inhuman cruelties committed against their prisoners reveal a deliberate policy of intimidation. Delving deeper it seems doubtful whether in regard to the coast the change is really as big as it appears on the surface. Up to about 782, though Assyria collected tribute from the coastal cities, her interference was tentative in character. Shamshi-Adad V visited the Mediterranean region only twice during his reign. These visits were booty raids and military demonstrations rather than campaigns of conquest. Adad-Nirari also assured himself of the tribute of Tyre, Sidon, Israel and Philistia, but did not repeat his visit to the coast. Shalmaneser III and Tiglath-pileser III both exacted annual tribute while otherwise leaving the Phoenician cities alone except for Philistia, which was raided though not then incorporated. A policy of fierce aggression starts with Sennacherib who occupied Phoenicia in 701, with the sole exception of Tyre. Esarhaddon and Ashurbanipal following in his footsteps destroyed Sidon and exacted heavy tribute from Tyre. No doubt, the end of the eighth century saw a new Assyrian policy, much more reminis- I* Ports of Trade in the Eastern Mediterranean 59 . cent of the nineteenth century a.d. than of the nineteenth century b.c. Military pressure against the coastal cities was now constant. Nevertheless, it would be easy to exaggerate the "modernness" of the neo-Assyrian drive toward the coast. Tyre was made to pay tribute and some attempt was made to subject her foreign policy. Yet her relationship with Assyria was for the most part one of cooperation. V Assyrians had right of entry into Tyrian territories, but Tyrian traders -j were granted full reciprocity by Esarhaddon.40 Though Tyre had an Assyrian resident magistrate watching her rulers she was otherwise independent. Later, Nebuchadnezzar kept Phoenicia under subjection, and tried to take Tyre, but was defeated. Neo-Assyrian and neo-Baby-lonian policies broadly amounted to an economic activation of the ~ coast through the ports of trade, which, however, were not incorporated, pressure being mostly exerted by methods of remote control. Persia represented entirely new principles of empire building. To use a minimum of coercion was among its tenets. Herodotus credited its rulers with professing a remarkable principle of empire government, according to which their interest in peoples diminished in proportion to the distance from the center of the country.41 This may well have held out to the coastal towns a promise of autonomy. Its fulfillment seems to have depended on whether or not the cities were willing to accept Persian suzerainty. Miletus was treated mildly, other Ionian Icities harshly—obligation of military service, payment of tribute and native rulers chosen by the Persians were imposed. To call these rulers tyrants is essentially misleading. Over the whole of the Hellenic Iworld the fashionable monarchy of the nontraditional type went under the name of tyrannis. But the sinister overtones that the term later acquired are thoroughly anachronistic. Seventh and sixth century tyrannies were anything but unpopular; the typical self-made ruler arose from the ranks of the aristocracy with the help of the populace to rid them of oppression from oligarchic class rule. In metropolitan Greece, by the middle of the fifth century the new monarchy had been generally superseded by free forms of popular rule and the tyrannis was now under a cloud. Yet the ambiguity is still apparent in Herodotus. The [Ionian tyrants of his grandfathers' time often owed their positions to the Persians who preferred to deal with monarchs rather than with assemblies, and to that extent the Ionian "tyrants" were justly dubbed Persian puppets. Herodotus mentioned that the Ionian kings during 60 Biith of the Economy the Scythian wars did not cut the bridge on the Danube which Darius had entrusted to their care because they felt they would only be in power as long as the Persians were present. Persian tyrannis was then often merely a method by which popular but sympathetic satellite governments were established. In preparation for the second invasion of Greece the Persians, who nourished no ideological preferences, replaced the fyrannis in all Ionian cities by democratic regimes. When the wars were over, a return to the old policy of almost complete political independence occurred, yet with a closer approximation to a symbiotic relationship between coast and continent. The Phoenician cities did not go through the same sharp fluctuations of Persian policies as those of Ionia. They retained their native Icings, free to join or refuse to join Persian expeditions. There was a break in the mutual good-will when Xerxes beheaded some Phoenician officers for poor conduct. The Phoenicians thereupon withdrew their fleet from Persian service for approximately fifteen years. The bitter revolt of 352 in which many Sidonians immolated themselves in their city was not severely punished: the city was rebuilt and Phoenicia continued to enjoy a fair measure of independence and prosperity under Persia, which seemed to be tolerant of all but open rebellion. Co-operation was based on a smoothly functioning trade organization of the coast which the Persians implemented by contributing a metallic standard, an efficient road system, and a secure hinterland. When in the last third of the first millennium, Macedonia cut across Europe, Asia, and Africa to create a world empire, the demise of the port of trade seemed imminent. Both the strategic and the cultural perils of the coast had lost substance and actuality. The coastlines, now lying for the first time within the boundaries of the all-inclusive empire, were left without political and military significance, and the helleniza-tion of the oecumene was the order of the day. Symbolic of the change was the defeat of Tyre at the hands of Alexander the Great. The man who embodied the novel idea of a universal civilization, had possessed himself of the impregnable rock which harbored Ezekiel's admired and hated Mistress of the Seas, and which had braved the might of Assur and Babylon. A vast expansion of peaceful trade was on, fusing the hitherto separated continents and transforming the Eastern Mediterranean into an Hellenic lake. It is all the more remarkable to find instead a revival of the early port of trade almost in its classic form. For a long time to come, the Ports of Trade in the Eastern Mediterranean 61 port of trade with its neutral administration of transactions between many foreign peoples proved indispensable. To channel the commerce of the Orient which would flow through the Indian Ocean and the Red Sea, Cleomenes of Naucratis was commissioned by Alexander the Great to plan a city at the point of entry to the west. The outcome was the port of trade par excellence, Alexandria. Neutrality was its raison (f e'fcre.42 Although situated on Egyptian soil, and erected under a Greek government, neither the Egyptians, nor even the Greeks themselves were to wield power in it. It was built outside the administrative boun-daiy of the Egyptian chora and its autonomy was to prove indestructible. Its neutrality was guaranteed by settling there Jews and Egyptians in large numbers, so as to reduce the preponderance of the Greeks themselves. The security of trade under the municipal authority was assured by business transactions being sworn to before the altar of Ilophaestion,43 the defied friend of Alexander. The great king who bestowed his genius on these details had ordered two temples to be erected to Hephaestion, and all business documents to invoke the sanction of the guardian god. Alexandria was the model to which, in Hellenistic times, many other ports of trade conformed, whether on the Phoenician coast, in Greece, or in Asia Minor. Ports of trade now had an informal status of their own. Tyre, Byblus, Sidon enjoyed the same independence as did the Greek cities of the coast; but the same independence was not granted to the Greek poleis of inland Babylonia.44 Thus the transcontinental empires of the Hellenistic age, far from discarding the concept of the port of trade, rather strengthened and renewed it. But the shunning of the coast that the ancient world had known was now overcome. And the time was near when, in the Western Mediterranean an utterly novel constellation of power in relation to coast and continent would arise to revolve around the Roman axis. Robert B. Revere Notes to Chapter TV 1. A. T. Olmstead, History of Assyria (New York, 1923), p. 28,—CAH, I, 568. 2. Ibid., p. 54. m->m G,i; barton, The Royal Inscriptions of Sumer and Afclcad (New Haven, 1VZ9), p. 181 ff. v ' 62 Birth of the Economy 4. H. R. Hall, The Ancient History of the Near East (London, 1913), p. 97 ff. 5. Robert Engberg, The HyJcsos Reconsidered (Chicago, 1939), p. 10. 6. Breasted, CAH, II, 192. "As Wenamon was obliged to pass through the territory of Nesubeneded, who now ruled the Delta, Hrihor supplied him with letters to the Delta prince, and in this way secured him passage in a ship. . . 7. Ibid., p. 167. 8. H.R. Hall, CAH, III, 295. 9. Breasted, op. cit., p. 193. 10. Cook, CAH, II, 306. 11. Breasted, op. cit., p. 78. 12. In this section we closely follow J. Friedrich's and A. Goetze's translations. Cf. "Hittite Policies in Regard to Coastal Areas," by Karl Polanyi, Columbia University, March, 1955. (Mimeographed.) 13. Polanyi, op. cit., J. Friedrich, Aus den hettitischen Schriften, A. O. 24, 3 (1925), The Telepinush Text, op. cit. (trans, into English). 14. Ibid. 15. Ibid., Art. 2, Line 5. 16. Ibid., Art. 3, Line 7. 17. Ibid., Art. 3, Line 8. 18. A. Goetze, "Madduwattash," MVAeG, 32, 1 (1928), Accusations Against Madduwattash. 19. A. Goetze, "Hattushilish," MVAeG (1925). 20. Ibid., Ill (28). 21. A. Goetze, Kizzuwatna and the Problem of Hittite Geography (New Haven, 1940), "The Shunashshura Treaty," p. 36 ff. 22. Ibid. 23. R. Dussaud, Pretydiens, Hittites et Acheens (Paris, 1953), fig. I. 24. Ibid., p. 62. 25. A. Goetze, Klein Asien (1936), p. 168. 26. Dussaud, op. cit., p. 59. 27. A. Goetze, op. cit., p. 168, "The old border line that separated the West from the East remained all through the Hittite period, that is, almost through the whole of the second millennium." 28. Ibid., p. 31. 29. M. Rostovtzeff, Social and Economic History of the Hellenistic World (Oxford, 1941), I, 81. "These cities, though subjects of Persia in the 4th century b.c., in fact belonged not to the Oriental but to the Greek world. They were, so to speak, fragments of the Western world on the fringe of the Eastern, serving as connecting links between the two. Behind them, however, the interior of Anatolia and the adjoining parts of north Syria remained essentially Oriental." 30. Lehmann-Hartleben, Die antiken Hafenanlagen des Mittelmeeres (Leipzig, 1923), p. 24. 31. Sir Leonard Woolley, A Forgotten Kingdom (Harmondsworth, 1953), p. 151. 32. Claude Schaeffer, Cuneiform Texts, p. 38. 33. Claude Schaeffer, "Reconstructing an Ancient Civilization," The Listener, Vol. 53 (June 30, 1955), 1162. "And here were sets of weights based on the shekel, that is one-third of an ounce. There are many small weights for fractions of a shekel, probably for the silversmith, and others for two, three, five, ten, twenty, thirty and fifty shekels. These are in bronze or in haematite. The heavy stone weights for 300, 500 and 1,000 shekels are in stone. One, which is cut with particular Potts of Trade in the Eastern Mediterranean mmm 63 Jeare in hardstone, corresponds to one talent, that is, 3,000 shekels. These weights . show that at Ugarit a decimal system was in use different from the system in vogue ^in Mesopotamia or in Egypt at the same time, which was based on multiples of % sixty." ,,, 34. Ibid., p. 1163. ~ 35. Claude Schaeffer, Cuneiform Texts, p. 25. This letter is confirmed by the - extraordinary lack of objects from Anatolia on the site of Ugarit. There are a • sufficient number to indicate that there was trade, but an insufficient number to postulate an occupation. 36. Claude Schaeffer, The Listener, op. cit., p. 1163. 37. O. R. Gurney, The Hittites (Harmondsworth, 1952), p. 97. "It is curious that the only case which we should describe as wilful murder is mentioned in connection with a merchant, who seems to be treated rather in a class by himself, and is associated with the motive of robbery." 38. M. Rostovtzeff, Iranians and Greeks in South Russia (Oxford, 1922), p. 41. 39. Hogarth, CAH, II, whom we follow for this period. 40. Olmstead, op. cit., p. 375 ff. 41. Herodotus, 1,134. See also Rostovtzeff, Social and Economic History of the Hellenistic World, I, 83. 42. CI. Preaux, Ueconomic royale des Lagides (1939), p. 432 ff. 43. Arrian, Anabasis, XXIII. "Hephaestion's name was to be engraved on all the legal documents with which the merchants entered into bargains with each other." 44. M. Cary, A History of the Greek World from 323 to 146 b.c. (London, 1951), p. 268. Aristotle Discovers the Economy 65 V Aristotle ^Discovers the &conomy in perusing the preceding chapters the reader may have sensed that some significant conclusion was pending. The oikos debate and our discussion of the Assyrian trading methods together with that of the ports of trade in the Eastern Mediterranean seemed to suggest that the study of the Old World, out of which civilization broke forth into the radiance of Greece, had a surprise in store. Such an expectation would not have been quite unjustified in view of the weighty, implications that the recognition of the absence of markets from Hammurabi's Babylonia obviously holds for the appraisal of Greek economic history. The familiar picture of classical Athens will have to absorb what might appear as a criss-cross of contradictions. The dominant conclusion must be that Attica was not, as we firmly believed, heir to commercial techniques that were supposed to have developed in the East; rather, she may herself have been a pioneer of the novel method of market trading. For if Babylon and Tyre were not, as it now appears, the ancient homes of the price-making market, then the elements of that seminal institution must have come from the Hellenic sphere, some time in the first millennium b.c. Sixth and fifth century Greece was, therefore, in essential respects, economically more naive than even the extreme "primitivist" would have it, while in the fourth century these very Greeks initiated the gainful business practices that in much later days developed into the dynamo of market competition. This brings into focus an aspect of the oikos controversy which only now becomes apparent. The "primitivists" asserted no more than tliat, up to the time of the Persian Wars, Attica was not a mercantile community. They did not deny that by the fourth century the Phoenicians had been ousted from their former maritime preeminence by the Hellenic seafarers, whose enterprising spirit backed by sea-loans gjve them the lead over their erstwhile masters. For the rest, it was taken for granted that the Lydians had passed on to their Hellenic pupils the arts of gainful trading which they themselves had acquired from their Mesopotamian neighbors of the East. All this falls to the ground if, as seems beyond dispute, Sumeria, Babylonia and Assyria as well as their Hittite and Tyrian successors practiced trade primarily through the dispositional actions of status tr.iders. But whence then did the Hellenes, or for that matter the Lvdians, derive their arts of individual business initiative, risky and gainful, which they hence certainly began to apply to some extent in their proceedings? And if, as it appears almost impossible not to conclude, they drew mainly upon themselves for the new attitudes, what c\ idence does the Greek literary record offer of the inevitable crisis of values which must have resulted? To dramatize the cultural event of Greece at the climactic point of her awakening from a heroic to a semi-commercial economy, would be beyond our capacity, even if the attempt were not barred by the scope of this work. Yet it appears appropriate, indeed, it is imperative to follow up in the light of our newly gained knowledge the peripety in the social thinking of that encyclopaedic mind in the Greek orbit, Aristotle, when he first encountered the phenomenon we have become used to calling the "economy." The contempt into which Aristotle's "Economics" has fallen in our day is a portent. Very few thinkers have been listened to on a greater diversity of subjects over so many centuries as he. Yet on a matter to which he devoted a signal effort and which happens also to be reckoned among the issues vital to our own generation, the economy, his teachings are judged inadequate by the leading spirits of the time to the point of irrelevance.1 Aristotle's influence on medieval city economy exerted through Thomas Aquinas was as great as later that of Adam Smith and David Ricardo on nineteenth century world economy. Naturally, one might say, with the actual establishment of the market system and the subsequent rise of the classical schools, Aristotle's doctrines on the subject went into eclipse. But the matter does not rest here. The more out- 64 r 66 Birth of the Economy spoken among modern economists seem to feel as though almost everything he had written on questions of man's livelihood suffered from some baneful weakness. Of his two broad topics—the nature of the economy and the issues of commercial trade and just price—neither had been carried to any clear conclusion. Man, like any other animal, was presented by him as naturally self-sufficient. The human economy did not, therefore, stem from the boundlessness of man's wants and needs, or, as it is phrased today, from the fact of scarcity. As to those two policy issues, commercial trade sprang according to Aristotle from the unnatural urge of money-making, which was of course unlimited, while prices should conform to the rules of justice (the actual formula remaining quite obscure). There were also his illuminating, if not altogether consistent remarks on money and that puzzling outburst against the taking of interest. This meager and fragmentary outcome was mostly attributed to an unscientific bias—the preference for that which ought to be over that which is. That prices, for instance, should depend upon the relative standing in the community of partners in the exchange seemed indeed an almost absurd view to take. This sharply circumscribed breaking away from the body of thought inherited from classical Greece deserves more attention than it has hitherto received. The stature of the thinker and the dignity of the subject should make us hesitate to accept as final the erasing of Aristotle's teaching on the economy. A very different appreciation of his position will be sustained here. He will be seen as attacking the problem of man's livelihood with a radicalism of which no later writer on the subject was capable—none has ever penetrated deeper into the material organization of man's life. In effect, he posed, in all its breadth, the question of the place occupied by the economy in society. We will have to reach far back to explain why Aristotle thought as he did of what we call "the economy," or what impelled him to regard money-making in trade and the just price as the chief policy questions. Also we agree that economic theory cannot expect to benefit from Book I of Politics and Book V of the Nichomachian Ethics. Economic analysis, in the last resort, aims at elucidating the functions of the market mechanism, an institution that was still unknown to Aristotle. Aristotle Discovers the Economy 67 To go to the root of our approach, classical antiquity was altogether wrongly placed by economic historians along the time scale which led up to market trade. In spite of intensive trading activities and fairly advanced money uses, Greek business life as a whole was still in the very first beginnings of market trade in Aristotle's time. His occasional vagueness and obscurities, not to speak of his alleged philosopher's remoteness from life, should be put down to difficulties of expression in regard to what actually were recent developments, rather than to the supposed insufficient penetration by him of practices allegedly current in contemporary Greece and nourished by a millennial tradition of the civilizations of the East. This leaves classical Greece, however definitely some of her eastern States were already advancing towards the market habit, still considerably below the level of commercial trading with which she was later credited. Thus the Greeks may not have been, as was so confidently assumed, simply latecomers picking up the commercial practices developed by the Oriental empires. Rather, they were latecomers in a civilized marketless world, and compelled by circumstances to become pioneers in the development of the novel trading methods which were at most on the point of turning towards market trade. All this, far from diminishing, as might superficially appear, the significance of Aristotle's thought on economic questions must, on the contrary, very greatly enhance their importance. For if our "non-rnarket" reading of the Mesopotamian scene is true to fact, which we have no more cause to doubt, we have every reason to believe that in Aristotle's writings we possess an eye witness account of some of the pristine features of incipient market trading at its very first appearance in the history of civilization. The Anonymity of the Economy in Early Society Aristotle was trying to master theoretically the elements of a new complex social phenomenon in statu nascendi. The economy, when it first attracted the conscious awareness of the philosopher in the shape of commercial trading and price differentials, was already destined to run its variegated course toward its 68 Birth of the Economy fulfilment some twenty centuries later. Aristotle divined the full-fledged specimen from the embryo.2 The conceptual tool with which to tackle this transition from name-lessness to a separate existence we submit, is the distinction between the embedded and the disembedded condition of the economy in relation to society. The disembedded economy of the nineteenth century stood apart from the rest of society, more especially from the political and governmental system. In a market economy the production and distribution of material goods in principle is carried on through a self-regulating system of price-making markets. It is governed by laws of its own, the so-called laws of supply and demand, and motivated by fear of hunger and hope of gain. Not blood-tie, legal compulsion, religious obligation, fealty or magic creates the sociological situations which make individuals partake in economic life but specifically economic institutions such as private enterprise and the wage system. With such a state of affairs we are of course fairly conversant. Under a market system men's livelihood is secured by way of institutions, that are activated by economic motives, and governed by laws which are specifically economic. The vast comprehensive mechanism of the economy can be conceived of working without the conscious intervention of human authority, state or government; no other motives than dread of destitution and desire for legitimate profit need be invoked; no other juridical requirement is set than that of the protection of property and the enforcement of contract; given the distribution of resources, of purchasing power as well as of the individual scales of preference the result will be an optimum of want satisfaction for all. This, then, is the nineteenth century version of an independent economic sphere in society. It is motivationally distinct, for it receives its impulse from the urge of monetary gain. It is institutionally separated from the political and governmental center. It attains to an autonomy that invests it with laws of its own. In it we possess that extreme case of a disembedded economy which takes its start from the widespread use of money as a means of exchange. In the nature of things the development from embedded to disembedded economies is a matter of degree. Nevertheless the distinction is fundamental to the understanding of modern society. Its sociological background was first mooted by Hegel in the 1820's and developed by Karl Marx in the 1840's. Its empirical discovery in terms of Aristotle Discovers the Economy 69 history was made by Sir Henry Sumner Maine in the Roman law categories of status and contractus, in the 1860's; finally, in the more comprehensive terms of economic anthropology, the position was restated by Bronislaw Malinowski in the 1920's. Sir Henry Sumner Maine undertook to prove that modern society was built on contractus, while ancient society rested on status. Status is set by birth—a man's position in the family—and determines the rights and duties of a person. It derives from kinship and adoption; it persists under feudalism and, with some qualifications, right up to the age of equal citizenship as established in the nineteenth century. But already under Roman law status was gradually replaced by contractus, i.e., by rights and duties derived from bilateral arrangements. Later, Maine revealed the universality of status organization in the case of the village communities of India. In Germany, Maine found a disciple in Ferdinand Toennies. His conception was epitomised in the title of his work Community and Society (Gemeinschaft und Gesellschaft), 1888. "Community" corresponded to "status," "society" to "contractus." Max Weber frequently employed "Gesellschaft" in the sense of contract-type group, and "Gemeinschaft" in that of status-type group. Thus his own analysis of the place of the economy in society, though at times influenced by Mises, was molded by the thought of Marx, Maine and Toennies. The emotional connotation, however, given to status and contractus as well as to the corresponding "community" and "society," was widely different with Maine and Toennies. To Maine the pre-contractus condition of mankind stood merely for the dark ages of tribalism. The introduction of contract, so he felt, had emancipated the individual from the bondage of status. Toennies' sympathies were for the intimacy of the community as against the impersonalness of organized society. "Community" was idealized by him as a condition where the lives of men were embedded in a tissue of common experience, while "society" was never to him far removed from the cash nexus, as Thomas Carlyle called the relationship of persons connected by market ties alone. Toennies' policy ideal was the restoration of community, not, however, by returning to the pre-society stage of authority and paternalism, but by advancing to a higher form of community of a postsociety stage, which would follow upon our present civilization. He envisaged this community as a co-operative phase of 70 Birth of the Economy human existence, which would retain the advantages of technological progress and individual freedom while restoring the wholeness of life. Hegel's and Marx's, Maine's and Toennies' treatment of the evolution of human civilization was accepted by many continental scholars as an epitome of the history of society. For a long time no advance was made on the trails they blazed. Maine had dealt with the subject chiefly as pertaining to the history of law, including its corporate forms as in rural India; Toennies' sociology revived the outlines of medieval civilization. Not before Malinowski's fundamental stand on the nature of primitive society was that antithesis applied to the economy. It is now possible to say that status or gemeinschaft dominate where the economy is embedded in noneconomic institutions; contractus or gesellschaft is characteristic of the existence of a motivationally distinct economy in society. In terms of integration we can easily see the reason for this. Contractus is the legal aspect of exchange. It is not surprising, therefore, that a society based on contractus should possess an institutionally separate and motivationally distinct economic sphere of exchange, namely, that of the market. Status, on the other hand, corresponds to an earlier condition which roughly goes with reciprocity and redistribution. As long as these latter forms of integration prevail, no concept of an economy need arise. The elements of the economy are here embedded in noneconomic institutions, the economic process itself being instituted through kinship, marriage, age-groups, secret societies, to-temic associations, and public solemnities. The term "economic life" would here have no obvious meaning. This state of affairs, so puzzling to the modern mind, is often strikingly exhibited in primitive communities. It is often almost impossible for the observer to collect the fragments of the economic process and piece them together. To the individual his emotions fail to convey any experience that he could identify as "economic." He is simply not aware of any pervading interest in regard to his livelihood which he could recognize as such. Yet the lack of such a concept does not appear to hamper him in the performance of his everyday tasks. Rather, it is doubtful whether awareness of an economic sphere would not tend to reduce his capacity of spontaneous response to the needs of livelihood, organized as they are mainly through other than economic channels. Jjjtistotle Discovers the Economy 71 f>~ All this is an outcome of the manner in which the economy is here y iristituted. The individual's motives, named and articulated, spring as a f-iole from situations set by facts of a noneconomic—familial, political OT religious—order; the site of the small family's economy is hardly more than a point of intersection between lines of activities carried on by larger kinship groups in various localities; land is either used in common as pasture or its various uses may be appropriated to members ' of different groups; labor is a mere abstraction from the "solicited" ■ assistance offered by different teams of helpers, at definite occasions; as a result, the process itself runs in the grooves of different structures. Accordingly, before modern times the forms of man's livelihood attracted much less of his conscious attention than did most other parts of his organized existence. In contrast to kinship, magic or etiquette with their powerful keywords, the economy as such remained nameless. There existed, as a rule, no term to designate the concept of economic. Accordingly, as far as one can judge, this concept was absent. Clan and totem, sex and age-group, the power of the mind and the ceremonial practices, custom and ritual were instituted through highly elaborate systems of symbols, while the economy was not designated by any one word conveying the significance of food supply for man's animal survival. It can not be merely a matter of chance that until very recent times no name to sum up the organization of the material conditions of life existed in the languages even of civilized peoples. Only two hundred years ago did an esoteric sect of French thinkers coin the term and call themselves e'eonomistes. Their claim was to have discovered the economy. The prime reason for the absence of any concept of the economy is the difficulty of identifying the economic process under conditions where it is embedded in noneconomic institutions. Only the concept of the economy, not the economy itself, is in abeyance, of course. Nature and society abound in locational and ap-propriational movements that form the body of man's livelihood. The seasons bring around harvest time with its strain and its relaxation; long-distance trade has its rhythm of preparation and foregathering with the concluding solemnity of the return of the venturers; and all kinds of artifacts, whether canoes or fine ornaments are produced, and eventually used by various groups of persons; every day of the week food is prepared at the family hearth. Each single event contains necessarily a bundle of economic items. Yet for all that, the unity and co- 72 Birth of the Economy herence of those facts is not reflected in men's consciousness. For the series of interactions between men and their natural surroundings will, as a rule, carry various significances, of which economic dependence is only one. Other dependences, more vivid, more dramatic, or more emotionalized may be at work, which prevent the economic movements of forming a meaningful whole. Where these other forces are embodied in permanent institutions the concept of the economic would be more confusing than clarifying to the individual. Anthropology offers many examples: 1. Where the physical site of a man's life is not identifiable with any ostensible part of the economy, his habitat—the household with its tangible environment—has but little economic relevance. This will be so, as a rule, when movements belonging to different economic processes intersect in one site, while the movements forming part of one and the same process are distributed over a number of disconnected sites. j Margaret Mead described how a Papuan-speaking Arapesh of New | Guinea would envisage his physical surroundings: I A typical Arapesh man, therefore is living for at least part of the time j (for each man lives in two or more hamlets, as well as in the garden huts,' huts near the hunting bush, and huts near his sago palm) on land which J does not belong to him. Around the house are pigs which his wife" is feeding, but which belong either to one of her relatives or to one of his. Beside the house are coconut and betel palms which belong to still other people, and the fruit of which he will never touch without the permission of the owner, or someone who has been accorded the disposal of the fruit by the owner. He hunts on the bushland belonging to a brother-in-law or a cousin at least part of his hunting time, and the rest of the time he is joined by others on his bush, if he has some. He works his sago in others' sago clumps as welf as in his own. Of the personal property in his house that which is of any permanent value, like large pots, well carved plates, good spears, has already been assigned to his sons, even though they are only toddling children. His own pig or pigs are far away in other hamlets: his palm trees are scattered three miles in one direction, two in another: his sago palms are still furthei scattered, and his garden patches lie here and there, mostly on the lands of others. If there is meat on his smoking rack over the fire, it is either meat which was killed by another, a brother, a brother-in-law, a sister's son, etc.— and has been given to him, in which case he and his family may eat it, or it is meat which he himself killed and which he is smoking to give away to someone else, for to eat one's own kill, even though it be only a small bird, is a crime to which only the morally, which usually means with the Arapesh mentally, deficient would stoop. If the house in which he is, is nominally Motle Discovers the Economy 73 lit will have been constructed in part at least from the posts and planks fpher people's houses, which have been dismantled or temporarily feted, and from which he has borrowed timber. He will not cut his jfcrs to fit his house, if they are too long, because they may be needed ir for someone else's house which is of a different shape or size. . . . (p then is the picture of a man's ordinary economic affiliations.3 ItiThe complexity of the social relations that account for these every-jfc items, is staggering. Yet it is only at the hand of such relations, jjlpiiliar to him, articulated and meaningfully deployed in the course of own personal experience, that the Arapesh is able to find his bear-5 in an economic situation, the elements of which are jigsawed into Eens of different social relationships of a non-economic character. So much for the locational aspect of the economic process where procity prevails. 2. Another broad reason for the absence in primitive society of an pegrating effect of the economy is its lack of quanritativity. He who isesses ten dollars does not, as a rule, call each by a separate name, t conceives of them rather as interchangeable units that can be substituted one for another, added up or subtracted. Short of such an Operational facility on which terms like fund or balance of profit and loss depend for a meaning, the notion of an economy would mostly be devoid of any practical purpose. It would fail to discipline behavior, to ■■^ganize and sustain effort. Yet the economic process does not naturally offer such a facility; that matters of livelihood are subject to reckoning is merely a result of the manner in which they are instituted. Trobriand economy, for instance, is organized as a continuous give-and-take, yet there is no possibility of setting up a balance, or of employing the concept of a fund. Reciprocity demands adequacy of response, not mathematical equality. Consequently, transactions and decisions cannot be grouped with any precision from the economic point of view, i.e., according to the manner in which they affect material want satisfaction. Figures, if any, do not correspond to facts. 1 hough the economic significance of an act may be great, there is no way of assessing its relative importance. Malinowski listed the different kinds of give-and-take, from free gps at the one extreme, to plain commercial barter at the other. His grouping of "gifts, payments, and transactions" came under seven headings, which he correlated with the sociological relationships with- 74 Biith of the Economy I in which each occurred. These numbered eight. The results of his I analysis were revealing: I (a) The category of "free gifts" was exceptional, since charity was neither needed nor encouraged, and the notion of gift was always associated with the idea of adequate counter-gift (but not, of course, of equivalency). Even actual "free gifts" were construed as counter-gifts, given in return for some fictitious service rendered to the giver. Mali-nowski found that "the natives would undoubtedly not think of free gifts as being all of the same nature." Where the notion of "dead loss" is lacking, the operation of balancing a fund is not feasible. (b) In the group of transaction, where the gift is expected to be returned in an economically equivalent manner, we meet another confusing fact. This is the category which according to our notions ought to be practically indistinguishable from trade. Far from it. Occasionally the identically same object is exchanged back and forth between the partners, thus depriving the transaction of any conceivable economic purpose or meaning! By the simple device of handing back, though in a roundabout way, the pig to its donor, the exchange of equivalencies instead of being a step in the direction of economic rationality proves a safeguard against the intrusion of utilitarian considerations. The sole purpose of the exchange is to draw relationships closer by strengthening the ties of reciprocity. (c) Utilitarian barter is distinct from any other type of mutual gift giving. While in ceremonial exchange of fish for yam there is, in principle, adequacy between the two sides, a poor haul or a failure of crops, e.g., reducing the amount offered, in barter exchange of fish and yam there is at least a pretence of higgling and haggling. It is further characterized by an absence of special partnerships, and, if artifacts enter, by a restriction to newly manufactured goods—second-hand ones might have a personal value attached to them. (d) Within the sociologically defined relationships—of which there • are many—the exchange is usually unequal, as befits the relationship. Appropriational movements of goods and services are thus often instituted in a manner that renders some transactions irreversible and many . goods noninterchangeable. j Thus quantitativity can hardly be expected to operate in that wide ? domain of livelihood which comes under the heading of "gifts, pay- I ments and transactions." I 3. Another familiar concept that is inapplicable in primitive con- Aristotle Discovers the Economy 75 ditions is that of property as a right of disposing of definite objects. Consequently, no straight inventory of possessions is practicable. We have here a variety of rights of different persons in regard to the same object. By this fragmentation, the unity of the object under its property aspect is destroyed. The appropriational movement does not as a rule have the complete object, for instance a piece of land, as its referent, but only its discrete uses, thus depriving the concept of property of its effectiveness in regard to objects. 4. Economic transactions proper hardly crop up in kinship-organized communities. Transactions in early times are public acts performed in regard to the status of persons and other self-propelling things: the bride, the wife, the son, the slave, the ox, the boat. With settled peoples changes in the status of a plot of land, too, were publicly attested. Such status transactions would naturally carry important economic implications. Wooing, betrothal and marriage, adoption and emancipation are accompanied by movements of goods, some of them immediate, some to follow in the long run. Great as the economic significance of such transactions was, it ranked second to their importance in establishing the position of the persons in the social context. How, then, did transactions in regard to goods eventually separate off from the typical kinship transactions in regard to persons? As long as only a few status goods, such as land, cattle, slaves were alienable there was no need for separate economic transactions since the transfer of such goods accompanied the change in status, while a transfer of the goods without such a change would not have been approved Of by the collectivity. Incidentally, no economic valuation could easily attach to goods the fate of which was inseparably linked with that of their owners. Separate transactions in regard to goods were in early times restricted to the two most important ones, namely, land and labor. Thus precisely the "goods," which were the last to become freely alienable were the first to become objects of limited transactions. Limited, since land and labor for a long time to come remained part of the social tissue and could not be arbitrarily mobilized without destroying it. Neither land nor freemen could be sold outright. Their transfer was conditional and temporary. Alienation stopped short of an unrestricted transference of ownership. Amongst the economic transactions in fourteenth century tribal-feudal Arrapha on the Tigris, those which refer to land and labor illustrate the point. Property, both in land and per- 76 Birth of the Economy sons, belonged with the Nuzi to collectivities—clans, families, villages. Use alone was transferred. How exceptional in tribal times the transfer of property in land was, may be seen from the dramatic scenario of the episode of Abraham purchasing a family vault from the Hittite. It is a peculiar fact that the transfer of "use alone" is rather more "economic" than would be the transfer of ownership. In the exchange of ownership, considerations of prestige and emotional factors may weigh heavily; in the alienation of use the utilitarian element prevails. In modern terms: interest, which is the price of use over time, may be said to have been one of the earliest economic quantities to be insti-1 tuted. Eventually, the thin economic layer may "peel off" from the status 1 transaction, the referent of which is a person. The economic element 1 may then change hands alone, the transaction being camouflaged as a status transaction which, however, is to be fictitious. Sale of land to 1 non-clan members being prohibited, the residual rights of the clan tIe, since he held on to the autarchy postulate which was pointless &t$ide of a naturalistic interpretation of wealth. The signal error in rendering metadosis as "exchange" in the jjiee crucial passages of the Politics and the Ethics cut deeper still.15 the case of metadosis Aristotle kept to the common meaning of the Ofd. It was the translators who brought in an arbitrary interpretation, an archaic society of common feasts, raiding parties, and other acts ; mutual help and practical reciprocity the term metadosis possessed g specific operational connotation—it signified "giving a share," espe-■ cially to the common pool of food, whether a religious festivity, a ceremonial meal, or other public venture was in question. That is the dictionary meaning of metadosis. Its etymology underlines the unilateral character of the giving, contributing, or sharing operation. Yet we are faced with the astonishing fact that in the translation of these passages in which Aristotle insisted on the derivation of exchange from metadosis, this term was rendered as "exchange" or "barter," which turned it into its opposite. This practice was sanctioned by the leading dictionary, which recorded s. v. metadosis those crucial three passages as exceptions! Such a deviation from the plain text is understandable only as an expression of the marketing bias of latter-day translators, who at this point were unable to follow the meaning of the text. Exchange to them was a natural propensity of men and stood in no need of explanation. But even assuming it did, it certainly could not have sprung from metadosis in its accepted meaning of "giving a share." Accordingly, they rendered metadosis by "exchange," and thus turned Aristotle's statement into an empty truism. This mistake endangered the whole edifice of Aristotle's economic thought at the pivotal point. By his derivation of exchange from "giving one's share" Aristotle provided a logical link between his theory of the economy in general and the practical questions at issue. Commercial trade, we recall, he regarded as an unnatural form of trade; natural trade was gainless since it merely maintained self-sufficiency. In support of this he could effectively appeal to the circumstance that, to the limited amount needed to ni.untain self-sufficiency, and only to that amount, exchange in kind was still widely practiced by some barbarian peoples in regard to the necessaries of life, at set equivalences, benefiting at one time the one, at another time the other, as chance would have it. Thus the derivation ■ Hl h 94 Biríh of the Economy of exchange from contributing one's share to the common pool of food was the linchpin that held together a theory of the economy based on the postulate of self-sufficiency of the community and the distinction between natural and unnatural trade. But all this appeared so foreign to the marketing mind that translators took refuge in turning the text upside down, eventually losing their hold of the argument. Perhaps the most daring thesis of Aristotle, which up to this day must stagger the thinking mind by sheer force of originality, was in this manner reduced to a platitude that, had it carried any definite meaning at all, would have been rejected by him as a shallow view of the ultimate forces on which the human economy rested. Karl Polanyi Notes to Chapter V 1. J. A. Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis (New York, 1954), p. 57, "Aristotle's performance is . . . decorous, pedestrian, slightly mediocre and more than slightly pompous common sense." Schumpeter had no doubt that Aristotle was engaged in "analyzing actual market mechanisms. Several passages show . . . that Aristotle tried to do so and failed" (p. 60). The latest detailed study is no less negative on the merits of the case. Cf. C. J. Soudek, "Aristotle's Theory of Exchange," Proceedings of American Philosophical Society, V, 96, NR, 1 (1952). Joseph J. Spengler's "Aristotle on Economic Imputation and Related Matters," Southern Economics Journal, XXI (April, 1955), 386, fn. 59, is the lone exception: "Aristotle did not concern himself with how prices are formed in the market." 2. Cf. Karl Polanyi, The Great Transformation (New York, 1943), p. 64. 3. Cooperation and Competition (New York and London, 1937), p. 31. 4. Aristotle, EN 1132b 21, 35. 5. Aristotle, Pol. 1257a 24. 6. Ibid., 1257a 19. 7. Ibid., 1257a 25. 8. Aristotle, EN 1133b 16,1133b 8. 9. Ibid., 1133b 29. 10. Ibid., 1133a 8. 11. Ibid., 1133a 10. 12. Ibid., 1133b 15. 13. Aristotle, Pol., 1257a 24-31. 14. Aristotle, EN 1133a 3-6. 15. Ps.-Arist., Oec. II, 1353a 24-28. 16. Ibid., 1133a 2; Pol. 1257a 24; 1280b 20. Aztec-^JVlaya; ^Dahomey; Verier; India .1 ■ I ■ I Anthropology as History fx a book on the economy in early societies must call upon the data of cultural and social anthropology along with those of history. In both fields man's experience with substantive economies finds its record. The varied and often strange patterns of economic action described in Part One of this book have already suggested rethinking of some concepts and definitions in economic theory, signaling as they do the in-appropriateness of that theory outside the marketing system of the classical Western nineteenth century. The Empirical Approach For its part, but without the written documents of history, anthropology has amassed an immense record of scattered and haphazard data about man's behavior with things for use, subsistence and consumption and about his relationships with his fellows over such things. It is well to know something of the lessons that the field work of anthropologists teaches and to explore the implications of that work for any new economic discipline which should analyze and generalize their data. Gathering of empirical data in the field, picking up economic facts without separation from other information, treating them in the technical or social context in which they were met, covers a hundred years or more of experience in anthropology. Its theorizing, busy with the processes, the similarities and differences among cultures, addressed 97 98 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India itself thus to what it found rather than to deducible consequences of any first principles of human nature. Anthropology, as we learn in another chapter of this book,* felt no need for economic theory and did not seek to discover any of those principles of human action such as economic theory's rationalizing, or economizing, to establish them as central. It turned instead to the dynamics of the emergence of cultural content. This experience of first recording and next trying to understand man's endlessly multifarious behavior and his many systems of motives, products of his various cultures and civilizations, confirms anthropology in its kinship with such an empirical discipline as history. Empiricism continues to separate them among the social sciences from such eminently conceptualizing disciplines as economics, political science or sociology. It means for both anthropology and history that the burden of proof is shouldered by him—a Kroeber, a Darwin, a Toynbee—who should assert a comparison or identify a common process or claim discovery of a universally unfolding law working out many times in the record. It has made further them kin in that both disciplines must deal in time sequences, must treat past and present, must seek recurrences, parallels, convergences. Both deal with events and occurrences, not with man's nature or the timeless necessities. The comparative, temporal, empirical and processual bent of modern anthropology makes it nevertheless complementary to a comparative sociology and social psychology of the world's peoples, past and present. It is pressing upon its neighbor disciplines the recognition of the sweeping force and pervasive results of cultural process and thereby transcending traditional sociology's and psychology's concentration on contemporary Western man and his society. The same empirical bent also nourished anthropology's essential kinship with history and prehistory. Anthropology's great archeological branch treats trends and processes in the cultural record of peoples whose achievements lie not in writing but in the mute artifacts of the ruins they have left behind. That elder branch of the subject still continues today to extend backward the so-called "ethnographic present," the time of first European contact with the world's non-Western peoples, and so to join the present to the past history of all mankind. Anthropology, indeed, maintains its original three branches intact even today. Cultural anthropology, archeology, and physical anthropology—the original interest in man's * See below, Ch. XVII. thropoiogy as History 99 lotion up from the animals—still interfertilize. It is this very proces-»1 and temporal concern, this comparison of past and present, which •fffceps them together. '.; This triple experience of the three branches of anthropology, scan-:;>Vfáng processes in past and contemporary peoples for parallels, differ-ces and convergences in the record of man's cultural achievement, Jfeds to be connected to the difficulties for economic theory to which Jpnmarket systems give rise. Much already partly tested theory is to be Won from the work of anthropologists to date on this record of man's behavior. If it mostly does not distinguish man's "economic" activity '■ from his action in other fields, nevertheless it is specifically relevant, Since it touches upon those alternate substantively economic patterns wjjpch concern us in this book. Much of what anthropologists have dfeovered about man's culture apart from economic institutions is directly in point when we turn to the particular questions which arise oat of his many different ways of treating goods and goods-handlers and receivers. * Admittedly, there is as yet no body of generalizations that treats economic" behavior from the specifically anthropological point of iew. Instead, we possess a vast body of diverse data about the various lehaviors and motives with which non-Western peoples' livelihood is ade and in which goods pass from hand to hand, move into distribu-on among new persons, and in new modes of consumption. Kari íolanyi has already devised an at least tentative classification of these verse ways of goods-handling; in broad outline, reciprocative, redis-ibutive, and marketing systems can be distinguished.* They are by no jneans mutually exclusive, nor do they claim to be exhaustive. Yet ttis empirical classification for descriptive purposes is useful; it is a first breakthrough from nonempirical and a priori interpretations, and "ts implications and ramifications, as well as its limitations, will occupy us in many sections of this book. Were anthropologists in their turn to attempt even the first step in conceptualizing the data, they too would probably turn to consideration of social arrangements, forms of interpersonal relationship, and self-contained logics based on them. In this lies a most important convergence among the empirically-minded social sciences of the present day. And if anthropologists were to move in this direction, they too would be forced to read those "economic" patterns of behavior and ♦See below, Ch. XIII. 100 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India motive against the same general view of society that another chapter of this book has elevated to a central tenet of modern sociology.* They would start with society as a system in which "the units ... are not individuals, but patterns of interaction"** of persons with one another. Not free human nature, nor free individuals, nor even any hard and fast psychological attributes of man, within his biological and physic-logical limits as an animal, give the anthropologist his starting point. In treating any culture patterns, even those of economic institutions, q the anthropologist selects these "patterns of interaction" to begin with, J not because they are logically prior, but because they are empirically decisive in those comparisons of present and past to which he subjects his data. Not many anthropologists have yet begun to take this step explicitly in regard to economic data. Chappie and Coon in Principles of Anthropology, 1942, seem to be the first to attempt it. Firth seems to sense its \ necessity, as it is implicit in the efforts of British social anthropology. "Economic anthropology," to date, is not yet a reality. It is still freeing J itself from the belief that other chapters in this book demolish, that I economic theory itself already has something to offer for an easy explanation of other economic systems than the market system of the recent West. The first generalizer, Herskovits, now asserts allegiance to formal economic theory and has tried a reduction of the data in that direction, away from the attempts of Mauss, after Durkheim, in whicli the early French ethnologists discovered empirical regularities in the reciprocities of gift-giving. But even Herskovits must continually stop to point out how little the categories of economic theory and the concerns of rationalizing and economizing which it follows out to their logical end help with ordering the ethnographers' data and how different, deviant, and quite outside the motivational categories of rational action in the market are the behaviors and motives with which he must deal.*** Yet anthropology is deeply committed to this priority of social patterns in any scheme for the understanding of the substantive economies of the human record. Our discipline is preconditioned to derive specific motivations, whether "economic" or otherwise, from such arrangements rather than from abstract human nature or needs. But it also sees these patterns and arrangements as historically achieved * See below, Ch. XIV. * * See ibid., p. 279. * * * See below, pp. 348 ff. kaopology as History 101 j|r than as consequences of the play of general forces of human Jjjle or circumstance, as the economist might view them. Anthro-Jlgy expects the social arrangements underlying economic behaviors i motives to be particular human inventions of historical times and ices. It expects social and economic inventions, like technical and tstic ones (of which we have a better record so far), to have spread 1 combined in diffusions, evolutions and convergences and to con-lie to do so today and in the future, rather than simply to prove jjtonsive to the effects of universal processes of association, as soci-Ijgy sees them. This processual bent of anthropology has substantial ^plications, as we shall see. It makes of the interpretation of non-'estern economic data a vitally historical, even "culturological" pur-lt rather than a psychological, economic, or sociological one. For the anthropologist must not only identify the social arrange-jjit of human interaction and organization as invented and patterned a culture that explains economic behaviors and motives, but he must account for its presence. For him a common denominator of gnonomic action, such as reciprocations or redistributions, with their Hitendant mechanisms of trade or forms of money use, is both an ar-tngement of human interactions and an institutional import of a new ^mergence among the people where he happens to find it. He must ■account for its being there, historically and geographically. He must £ account for it functionally, that is, for its connection with the other ' patterns of the people's culture of that time and place. He must add to the reasons for its presence the functions it performs and the values fc embodies for those who act it out and by which it is kept alive, sanctioned as custom, and transmitted as Kulturgut of their cultural ™ inheritance. He must account for its continuation then and there, as S^ll. £ He cannot always do the first accounting, of course. Ethnographic *f records are haphazard and even written history must be finely sifted before our knowledge of the presence of any particular institution or « culture pattern grows firm. For many of the inventions and institutions vhich interest us today, "origins" are lost in the mists of time and in the endless successions and transformations of cultural evolution. But the anthropologist must try. For a culture pattern is a concrete thing, whose presence or absence is an historical fact and whose emergence is an historical event. He cannot always do the second thing either; but he can try to spell 102 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India out its contemporary functions. For a culture pattern coexists with others and it supports or opposes the others in some sort of integration or lack of it. Such integration possesses details and has a structure that 3 is important for the continuation of a culture and society and the 4 integration has form and laws of being which the social sciences are uncertainly exploring. An imperative rests upon an anthropologisl, whether or not he is explicitly a social anthropologist committed to f unctionalism or other special theories of cultural or social integration, I to spell out in faithful, empirical detail all observable and checkable dovetailing of transmitted action, interaction, meaning and contest which makes up any culture pattern, social, lingual, or technical. j And he cannot always do the third thing: account historically for the continuation of a pattern he has identified and interpreted. Ye I here again he must continue to try, for human culture, like other animals' behavior, is adaptive, functional for survival, and presumably f even rewarding. Its continuance rests upon its successful transmission j to the new generations who must use it and pass it on in turn. Its further J elaboration seems at least in good part to come from the further gains I it yields. The anthropologist exploring culture patterns, including those behind variant non-Western economic behaviors, must treat the rise and fall of his subject matter as an historian accounts in his field for the growth and decline of institutions and empires. To see social arrangements, then, as prior to economic actions, institutions, and value and motive schemes, and to see them specifically as culture patterns, that is, as contrivances and devices man has achieved with the human material given by the existence and the characteristics of his fellow human beings, is not merely the bias with which anthropology will take its next steps into the explanation of the record of substantive economics. It is not merely the occupational bias which anthropologists bring to any experience, as one might perhaps surmise. It is one grand view imposed on all social science analysts, from the discovery of the three first categories of substantive economies prior to this book,1 through the sociologists here, to the work of others here and yet to come. It may well be, moreover, the view to which empirical discoveries are impelling us all. Note that sociologists often write as if the priority of the presence or absence of particular social arrangements over economic actions and motivations of a particular kind were a matter of logical premise in the world-view of their discipline. So it is, of course, when a theory HMWrthropoIogy as History 103 nSmgthe social system, or of the economic system, "embedded" in the BBycial system, is under construction. In another view, however, particu-papfef social arrangements are the empirical controlling elements, and their 7 jT prionty is one of relevance, perhaps even of causation. The real issue jPSPjetween the deductive theories deriving economic action from man's ^i&jltional or gain-seeking faculties and the findings of the newer social KSfjjcience is only half stated when the sociologist limits himself to insist-Ewfefag that his science has taught him to see economic behaviors depend-ijekttit upon the social systems in which they are "embedded." For anthro-J»^ology finds these systems in turn dependent upon, and serving to i integrate, particular patterns or inventions of human interactional and ▼ social arrangement and its symbolization, achieved in time and place, A in the way that technology or science also depend upon and unite the • T'other particular inventions of mankind's variously unfolding develop-ffpment. Using social arrangements as a frame of reference, then, and seeking , ^them out by an operational method that extracts them as common •rffi denominators in the data of action and motive, are not merely biases or \ philosophical premises in anthropology and the newer social science f^ji now turning to the comparative record. They are discoveries already ^ 1 achieved about the relevant priorities of phenomena in our science. ■ The institutionally operational method working with nonmarket eco-pPiibomic data is very much akin, as we shall see, to other contemporary j v analyses in social science. It makes the same path as has anthropology ' to a discovery of the common-denominator patterns of arrangement, L - structure, and form in human interpersonal action. In other branches of social science today these patterns seem to turn out to be the things controlling human motives and human institutional action. I have tried elsewhere to show their force in the small group and short-term attitude and behavior of industrial relations,2 while George Homans has documented their determination of group behavior and attitude in the wide range of studies of social behavior t already accomplished by observational and empirical methods,3 and Hopkins* reminds us of the central place of these arrangements in current social system theory with Parsons and its other formulators. It is a confirmatory discovery, indeed, that in the non-Western economic data we have before us here the same priority of relevance faces us. * See below, Ch. XIV. 104 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India In the Berber markets, in the Indian redistributions, in the African and American "ports of trade" which find review here, we have had again and again to seek out these patterns and to dig down into the arrangements of action between persons before we could go on to search for an explanation of the motives of our actors, the values which prompt them, the circumstances they cope with, or the gains they win. We had again and again to connect these backward to common-denominator patterns of action before we could structure all these things into a representation and interpretation of the institutions the record gives us. And we have had to do all this comparatively. Our common, emerging social science is not an endless excavation of particular details alone, but like all science, a generalizing of probes, propositions, and proofs. If Arnold, Revere, and Chapman here find a common form of early trade in "the port of trade," in "weak hands" (to use Polanyi's apt phrases), in eighteenth century Dahomey, in Asia Minor three thousand years earlier, and pre-conquest Mesoamerica, or if Benet finds elements of "free markets" in an anarchic Barbary, we can be sure of these findings only because we can, in the end, demonstrate that common patterns exist behind these things our authors describe and because we can check the record for the known and specified arrangement of interpersonal action applying to any two of them despite their differences of setting and detail. Priority of one kind of datum over another is not a matter of disciplinary or philosophical affection for one kind of phenomenon over another. It is a matter of just such comparison, discovery and check among the observers of the run of cases. Just such comparison pushes us to the "scientific fact." Stated baldly thus, and if our proofs are accepted and our "facts" are "true," there seems little to argue with in the discovery that social arrangements serve as a frame of reference to economic actions and motives. But to see these arrangements as culture, as human inventions, with anthropology, presents continuing difficulties, even in sociology. It finds it sometimes difficult to decide between the claims for prior relevance between these arrangements and "values" in the scheme of social system theory. We touch here on a great debate still raging everywhere in social science as it did once in philosophy. But the view of common denominator, social arrangements as culture patterns, derived from the experience of anthropology, comes to our rescue. In that view social arrangements make their own values in the process of be- Anthropology as History 105 coming culture patterns, or "instituted." The evolution of a culture pattern is just such an emergence of summary and symbolizing values, meaning, vocabulary and concept about a new pattern of action, making it ready for recognition, sanction, and transmission. Action comes first, in anthropology's view of culture, whether it be the wheel, or divine monarchy, or parallel cousin marriage, and values come second in the usual evolutionary or diffusionary problems with which the science has had to deal. In this anthropology repeats the discoveries of small group and industrial studies, where new group norms and new shared attitudes likewise arise out of changes in interpersonal and group action. And a culture pattern is not complete, any more than an "institution" is fully emerged, until the summarization, symbolization, and evaluation which crystallizes the connection between the new action and its resultant values is achieved in a configuration which has won the instant recognition and the long term habit of the human actors who "carry the culture trait." Read properly, then, social science's experience with "culture" and with "institutionalizing" a process, here the substantive goods-handlings of the "economic process," offers no difficulties in giving both historical and methodological priority to action over values. Much of the trouble with this discovery lies in our semantic training (we say we "act out" a value) and in our philosophical tradition of idealism ("In the beginning was the Word."). The long squabble of idealism and realism haunts us unnecessarily. Anthropological experience with culture shows the same phenomena of emergence as does sociological experience with group process, though the data are different. What stands in the way of acceptance of the common finding seems to be a tendency to read the anthropologist's term "culture" as a synonym for the sociologists' own word "values." Thus it is easy for sociologists, often assuming out of philosophic tradition that values ("common meanings" they sometimes call them) are prior to social action—a tautology of long standing since "social" action is in turn the action based on "common meanings"—4 to think the anthropologist is also claiming values to rule action when he speaks of "culture" and the "cultural determination" of a bit of behavior. By the same route it is easy for sociologists—and many anthropologists as well—to take another finding of our common social science, one equally important to our understanding of the nonmarket economies under examination here, for an obstacle to following the his- 106 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India torical and evolutionary emergence of culture patterns out of common-denominator arrangements in the determination of economic (and other) institutions and values. Anthropology has discovered in its record of man's doings the process of cultural diffusion, by which two peoples come to share a trait or institution out of their contact with each other, and its counterpart, the process of cultural convergence or cultural parallelism, in which two peoples, in no contact, come to share a very like trait, too, but by a quite different route. Comparison of traits and patterns from people to people and time to time and place to place, the very comparison which yields us similar social arrangements behind widely separated civilizations in these pages, like the common "ports of trade" in distant Mesoamerica and Syria, has led us to these discoveries in dealing with all sorts of doings of man. It is not surprising that comparison has led to analogous discoveries once again when we have turned to explore the record of his economic acts. But too often both sociologists and anthropologists forget these processes of culture and jump logically from the specificity of particular culture patterns to the uniqueness and integration of cultures as wholes. They read the discoveries of anthropology about "culture" or "values" to bar comparison or to license neglect of it, and to reify integrated "cultural wholes" and "social systems" into unique entities whose essences and consequences have no parallels anywhere. To some of them, then, in this context to say that the prior social arrangements behind economic motive and behavior are culture patterns is tantamount, erroneously, to saying that no connections can be drawn at all between one people's institutions and the next. There seems to be a tendency in social science today to condemn as idealistic and to impute to anthropologists a view according to which whole cultures are unique and the economic arrangements springing up in them without parallel. This is the reading of culture which we are presently expounding as fallacious. We have already described how anthropology must of course explore the instant case and unravel the functional and other interconnections and integrations of traits within a culture, just as sociologists must always look from particular norms or processes to the whole social system before them. But to work out the place of a phenomenon in situ is another thing than to compare it with others; both things must be done in science and both yield knowledge. The experience of anthropology has always comprised both. The discoveries of convergent evolution and diffusion in 11111 m ill ,';AnthropoIogy as History 107 Bn's doings could not have taken place without ethnographic and torical comparisons. Now the main point of anthropology, and of the work which has taught us to handle economic action and value as culture patterns, lies in this comparison of the common-denominator social arrangements and this discovery of the processes leading to the evolution of institutions from out of them. It is not any finding that economic institutions, whether market ones or nonmarket ones, are culture traits (which they are), or that culture traits are expressions of values (a happy tautology which delights some anthropologists still), or that patterns of social action are prior to values (which they are), or that social arrangements and culture traits are the independent variables (Which is true). It is rather that each term of the analysis leading to these findings must have particular, empirical, historical documentation. Moreover, once this proof can be provided we can at once go on farther to depicting the processes which have given us the actual events of the past emergence of these institutions. It is in this way alone, in treating them as culture traits, that we can legitimately spell out the cultural dynamics and reconstruct the true history of economic institutions. This dynamics and this rewon history is the best account we will ever have of their "origins." Methodological Conclusions The usefulness of the historical bent of anthropology and its experience with culture traits and processes is easy enough to see when *e treat institutional origins and history. Its insistence that action is prior to values is perhaps easier to accept in that context than is the comparable discovery in social and group dynamics. Examples come readily enough from well-known history, where the painful searches required here are in the long past. After all, a use of gold for personal enrichment rather than for collective worship had to exist in Europe and in Spain before conquistadores should sack the New World for it and should corrupt "innocent" Indians to their gold lust. The course of historical civilization and the diffusion of pecuniary values ran from East to West, not the other way, as we all know. But the consequences of this historical bent and the cultural experience for methods of research, indeed in the very analysis and comparison of diverse data of 108 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India behavior and motive which fills the ethnographic and historical record, is not so easy to grasp or to accept. Nevertheless, a temporal, processual view of social arrangements, culture traits, and resultant institutions pervades the most basic operations of anthropological research and dominates the methods which have brought ethnographic data into accord with those of substantive economic analysis in these pages. In their most basic methods both anthropology and historical-institutional or substantive economics, at least as developed here, are processual and operational. They share a realization that their comparison, their synthesis, their structuring of their data must always reflect the particular observations of persons, times, and actions which their data-gatherers actually make. To demonstrate the existence of an economic institution of nonmarket kind, for example, Polanyi here and elsewhere must show both what was done and when and with and by whom. He must also show explicitly what was not there and when and by whom an action we might expect to take place did not occur, as he does in showing that "sales" are not made to random demanders but only to recognized trading partners in reciprocal systems and that reciprocity exchanges involve merely appropriate and worthy, not equivalent unit-reckoned returns.* And he must show that these specifics of time, place, person, action, and quantification recur, repeat, grow standard, or come to be supplanted by others. Anthropology's method with culture traits is equally specific, observational, operational and processual. For traits of human social organization it must also specify who and who not does a thing, where and when, and where and when not, with what and without what else, at what rates of occurrence. It must also establish the regularities, the limits, and the restoring sanctions upon deviations, in order to demonstrate patterns of existence. And when it treats changes, it must touch the changes in these particulars as they arise, in new time and new circumstance. This careful documentation of detail of observation and this empirical handling of events in time and this painful documentation of regularities of recurrence reflects not only the kinship of anthropology and institutional history but it also marks as well their common divergence from the formal and often timeless logic of economic theory and sociology alike. The doctrine of culture trait, like the concept of institution, rests upon experience which asks questions about function, gain, conformity to man's nature, powers or needs, after and not before Anthropology as History 109 ' the details of observation about man's behavior have been taken up, compared, ordered, synthesized, classified and recognized. This is an especially important theoretic and methodological point. When we come to the problem of functional equivalency among traits and institutions in different societies and cultures, it may become crucial. To the anthropologist a social arrangement ("real culture," e.g., de facto polygyny), a culture pattern (i.e., one of "ideal" culture, e.g., •de jure but not rigorously observed monogamy), an institution (e.g., sororate, bride-price, usury) exists in its own right and has form, structure, and characteristics independent of functions and relationships amrng other social or cultural data. Such real things—concrete inventions ordering persons, acts, symbols, etc., into patterns of unique existence—change in function, take on or lose functions from time to time, people to people, just as they accrete or slough off their other defining elements. A social arrangement, a culture trait, an institution is not defined exclusively or even primarily by its function, and the first thing to know about it is not what it does for men or society. The first thing to know is how it operates within itself and how it came to be. Only then can one ask what its functions are now, were once, and may yet be in the future. Moreover, of course, not its functions but its forms give it the character by which the observers (ourselves) and the actors ("the natives") recognize and value it, and the question of just what function it performs is an empirical one to be solved by further research, not an answer deduced from the essence of the thing. Thus in anthropology and history to analyze an institution as a concrete event rather than—as in economics or sociology—to explore it in general terms as a functional equivalent for doing what is done by something else in another society or other circumstances is to ask different questions and to work toward different answers however complementary the ultimate knowledge may prove to be. For the anthropological view of the evolution of traits, like the historical view of institutions, is that the functions they perform and the rewards they bring do not in themselves call these things into being or account for their continuance. Necessity is not the mother of invention, nor is reward its father. The two together may remain childless. Inventions are rather events of discovery or creation, whether they he technical or institutional, and they make good their new trending or trial arrangement of persons, materials, and actions per saltum into the new configurations of achieved form which make of culture traits 110 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India new emergences. Once the jump is made, and the new form attained, then functional serviceability and sometimes unexpectedly huge gain confirm the existence of the new trait and work strongly to elaborate and to extend it. But the record is replete with trends not so consummated and with jumps approached but never made. Consciousness of emergence, and the combination of temporal and formal observations which have yielded it out of ethnographic data, is another of the empirical discoveries of anthropology which make it different from the system-building disciplines of sociology and economics. It is a discovery, too, which enforces, as we shall see presently, the quite other than simply functional method which the research of this book on the ethnographic record of man's substantive economic behavior has had to carry out. Thus the search for the ordering similarities in economic matters of ethnographic and historical record which is the latter-day equivalent of the old-fashioned study of the origins of economic institutions, and which has motivated our studies is not by any means merely a search for alternate ways in which man has solved his universal problems. It is not a study of the functional equivalents of our economic institutions in other cultures and societies. It is doubtful indeed whether beyond subsistence man has had any universal economic problems; rather his problems arise, like his values, from his institutions and their evolutions. To restrict a study of economic institutions to the functional equivalents among societies, and to neglect the discovery that they are also in part culture patterns and behave like these, would be to falsify the facts. Rather, the facts of economic evolution resemble in great measure the facts of cultural evolution. The facts of cultural evolution are not, as it may seem, that most cultures and most societies have developed alternate ways of doing much the same thing and that different economic institutions are nothing but different cultural devices for winning a livelihood, meeting scarcities, spreading goods about, effecting necessary exchanges. There is danger here of meekly surrendering to empty truisms, since all cultures survive for a time in an environment and most of their people stay alive on the goods somehow brought to them. The facts of cultural evolution instead tell us that some peoples in some real past events by chance and hard thought have combined specific prior actions and relationships in new ways or experimented with new ones. Their new combination of old ways, their new invention out of former materials tropology as History i il bequeathed or diffused to them, was not independent of their old .- jsostom, but it was nevertheless a jump into the unknown. Culture patterns, like all inventions, recombine both old and new; they have both a history which is specific and limited, and a future of uncharted dimensions and promises. A new pattern, newly emergent, of course, soon takes on functions, established connections with the older social and cultural order, brings gains and rewards which confirm its discovers in its use. Each new advance in mastery of it, each rewarded further use, brings greater and greater reward, for a time, and in this sense culture is functional in the adaptive sense as well as in the integrative one. The people among whom our innovation spreads soon come to experience and value unexpected consequences in greater and greater rewards as they also begin to encounter unexpected pains and restrictions in their expanding use of a new technique, a new art or ceremonial device, a new social or economic institution. Who could foresee that domesticating grains and herd animals would bring first a many-fold increase of population and then a desiccation and destruction of the land? Who could see that sacrificial blood-offering would lead to human sacrifice and brittle empires of warfare and hate, or harnessing machines to mine pumps and clothmill looms in England would lead to an industrial and technical revolution over the whole globe? The history and ethnography of human culture is full of examples of such emergence, elaboration, and revolution. A people evolving a new culture, or inventing a new culture trait or a complex of them, from minor technique to major economic institution, has often found heady riches in its hand. Such peoples have often entered upon long and deep elaborations of such a new pattern. They have often flourished with it as it has flourished for them. They have built upon it, explored it and embroidered it, mined and exhausted its resources. We need not animize the process with a Spengler for whole civilizations, or hypos-tatize the resources into motive forces with such cliches as ascribe England's nineteenth century glory to her coal and iron or Plains Indians' riches to the horse. Here again what cultural innovation gives command over what absolute or relative new riches and power is a question of empirical discovery and exploration, a something to be learned both by the men on the spot and by the commentators who come afterwards palely to record the accidents of history. Suffice it to say that the story of culture is also the story of man. Man is the animal (maybe 112 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India the chief animal) who has hit upon the device of culture for achieving mastery of the environment by freeing himself of slavish dependency on it. He is one animal, perhaps the chief one, who explores and exploits his habitat by a device, the cultural one, which creates for him successive environments both natural and artificial. And he is no fool; he can quickly see and use up his advantage while it lasts. Certainly the concept of functional equivalents among culture patterns and institutions is useful. But its usefulness ceases where the sweep of cultural evolution and variation starts. Certainly, in these pages and in others, we can find that gift-giving does the same things for human individual and social life as does the market. Both are mechanisms of distribution and survival. But they are different mechanisms, based on very different social arrangements, in many ways opposite cultural and institutional elaborations. Presumably as well they have very different antecedants, advantages, and limitations. Certainly they have very different distributions among the world's times, places, and peoples. To understand them we must know not only these circumstances, but also the relative order of their historical emergence, and the necessary precursors and preconditions they must have had. The experience of anthropology with culture patterns, then, teaches us not only this processual thinking which extends beyond functional-ism and system-building relyings on putative needs of individual or society. It commits us as well to a humble descent to operational methods in which both analysis and synthesis are bound to consistency with the observations, descriptions, and eliminations shown by the record. Where, as with both culture patterns and social arrangements, specificities of time occurrence and recurrence go into the data-gathering and data-ordering, the operations treating these must be reflected in the models and the definitions we construct for what we find. Where specification of persons, listing who acts and who does not, is a necessary part of the recording of the behaviors we are examining, this operation, too, must continue to appear in the classifications of data we erect and the building of alternate institutions or systems we carry out. Where determining the order of action or initiative between persons is part of the observation which goes into discriminations of status and relationship, that operation also must carry over into our models of institution, social arrangement, economic system, etc. In this way, if we find, as we do in some of them, that common-denominator social arrangements underlie convergences and parallelisms of economic in- biopology as History 113 Stations, then we must be very clear that we derive these comparisons om regularities in the data themselves and not from an a priori bias four own. It is the consistent use of these operations basic to so many ; the modern social sciences5 that give us this power of control and ity. Conrad M. Arensberg /ores to Chapter VI 1. Cf. Karl Polanyi, The Great Transformation (New York, 1943). 2. Conrad M. Arensberg, "Behavior and Organization: Industrial Studies," ch. CIV in Muzafer Sherif and John Rohrer, eds., Social Psychology at the Crossroads Jew York, 1952), and in Conrad M. Arensberg and Geoffrey Tootall, "Plant jciology: Real Discoveries and New Problems" in Paul Lazarsfeld and Mirra Komarovsky, eds., Common Frontiers of Social Research (Glencoe, 111., forth-orning). 3. George Homans, The Human Group (New York, 1952). 4. As opposed to symbiosis or physical collision, for example. 5. See E. D. Chappie and Conrad M. Arensberg, Measuring Human Relations, Genetic Psychology Monographs (Provincetown, 1940). Also, E. D. Chappie and Carleton S. Coon, Principles of Anthropology (New York, 1942). Also, Conrad M. Arensberg in Rohrer and Sherif, eds., Social Psychology at the Crossroads, op. cit. VII ^Port of Trade Enclaves in Aztec and GJAaya Qivilizations The Problem of Aztec-Maya Trade much of the obscurity that has veiled the contacts of the Aztec and the Maya and prevented an understanding of the economic relations obtaining among the peoples of Mesoamerica now appears to be lifting.1 Trade carried on over long distances, more than any other activity, bound together the two great culture areas of Mesoamerica. Yet this trade that so intimately linked the Aztecs of the Basin of Mexico and the Maya of Yucatan had to overcome very considerable physical and perhaps even more formidable organizational obstacles. The distance between the centers of these metropolitan areas was great. As the crow flies, Tenochtitlan (on the site of Mexico City) was more than 500 miles removed from the Maya heartlands in the Yucatan peninsula. The length of the traject over high mountains and primeval forest may have been almost twice as much. Yet over most of this area not only the empires, but also numerous tribes and tribal confederacies were frequently at war with one another; slave raiding was constant; feuds, massacres and border violence the rule. How, then, were these difficulties surmounted? What was the operational nature of this trade between the different and distinct cultures? These are the questions to which this chapter is devoted. 114 frsde Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 115 Our subject is restricted geographically to the Aztec empire and j&Maya states; institutionally it comprises only long distance trade distinguished from market institutions, from which trade was to a Ktnarkable degree separate. | To the modern mind this may sound paradoxical. But long-distance Me was an institution apart: geographically, it was trade beyond the ders; its personnel formed a distinct social group; its members only ptionally made their appearance in markets; both the organizing caravans and the negotiating of exchange in foreign countries formed Jjjfert of this specialized occupation. This particular form of adminis-||§ed trade should not then be confused with any other form of exchange, such as the important local market complex itself, corner food-nils, peddlers, the sale of services, or the variants of neighborhood lade. | To return to the long-distance trade between Aztec and Maya, three ■tctors will recur in our analysis: the commodities imported and ex-^j§orted; the personnel engaged in the foreign economy; and the geographical locations where the meetings of the long-distance traders .' took place. Luxury wares and their raw materials formed the main items of ^trade. It did not as a rule directly concern the common people as consumers. This was an added reason why the democratic exchanges of [ t the home market places, where everyone with a few cacao beans in his pocket was welcome, had no room in a trading system reserved to the fete, and the needs of the state. "t Even more significant was the person of the trader. At no time does the trade over these vast areas appear as random activity of individuals; certainly it is not simply an extension of the face to face exchanges common in the metropolitan market places. Rather it was the highly structured occupation of persons dedicated to performing their duties under the authority of their professional organizations. It emerges, especially among the Aztecs, as an institution of characteristic social, economic, and ecological configuration. To a large extent this trade determined the type of contact maintained between civilizations across Ideographical and political boundaries. I The locational focus of the exchange transactions was the "port of trade," the name introduced in this book to denote those towns or cities frhose specific function was to serve as a meeting place of foreign |raders. The word "port" as employed here, need not imply a coastal 116 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India or riverain site, although ports of trade were usually thus situated. Transshipments naturally developed from the earliest times on the borders of ecological regions, such as highland and plain, desert and jungle, forest and savannah. Prior to modern days, the port of trade should therefore be regarded as the main organ of long-distance commerce. Trade was here treaty-based, administered, as a rule, by special organs of the native authorities, competition was excluded, prices were arranged over long terms. Ports of trade usually developed in politically weak spots, such as small kingdoms near the coast, or chieftains' confederacies, since, under archaic conditions, strangers shunned territories that were incorporated in military empires. To the hinterland empires the "ports" served as a "bread basket," that is, as a source of supply.* Even powerful rulers were wary of laying their hands on the "port," lest foreign traders and strangers shy off and trade suddenly dry up. Independent trade areas of this kind, harboring numbers of warehouses, storing the goods of distant trading peoples, while the local population of the area itself did not engage in trading expeditions have been found to exist in widely different parts of the globe. We submit that the key to the volume and intensity of long-distance trading between Aztec and Maya should be sought in the existence of such port of trade territories—whether enclaves or buffer states—which served as intermediaries to the trade of militarily powerful metropolitan units. To such areas outside of their political boundaries both the Aztecs of Mexico and Maya of Yucatan traveled to exchange goods. The ports of trade had their setting mainly on the lagoons and rivers of gulf areas. Situated to the south of the Aztec Empire and beyond the cultural province of Yucatan Maya, these areas extended westward from Yucatan on the Gulf of Mexico as well as eastward to the Gulf of Honduras, and even to points further south. It happened that these were also the regions where cacao cultivation was predominant, a significant fact, since the cacao bean was the universal money in the Mesoamerican and Central American regions. Port of trade areas (see map, p. 118) probably benefitted from their relative neutrality and enjoyed a fair measure of independence. Admittedly, they were occasionally to some extent controlled by Aztec colonists or factors, that is, by Nahuatl-speaking people who had established themselves in a ward or quarter of the neutral trading towns; the Yucatan Maya also had their factors living in some of the ports of * See below, p. 160. iTiade Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 117 tjade; moreover various ports had their own agents in other ports. Such ..fesident agents or factors did undoubtedly wield considerable power, fltipi" and may often have been, wholly or partly, rulers of the port towns or provinces. However, with the exception of Xoconusco, none of the ports of trade paid tribute to the Aztec state or to the Maya. For the piost part the port of trade areas were autonomous, i Another notable fact appears to be that no traders native to these ■pjrts of trade traveled to the Basin of Mexico to trade, although some may have visited Yucatan. The documents indicate that the active fe.de ran from the metropolitan centers to the ports of trade, the ex-flange taking place in the ports of trade themselves, of which a dozen i so existed in the neutral enclaves. The Aztec of the Basin of Mexico The Aztec Empire2 at the beginning of the Spanish conquest, exknded from northern Veracruz on the Gulf coast to the state of Guerrero, on the Pacific; and south, above the Isthmus of Tehuante-pec. It can be loosely described as a wide belt stretching across central Mexico, with the capital lying well in the north.3 The seat of the Empire was the Basin of Mexico, in the southernmost part of the Central Mexican Plateau. Its floor in this area reaches an altitude of some 7,400 feet. At the time of the conquest the Basin of Mexico comprised a number of cities and towns on the edge and on islands of several connecting salt and fresh water lakes, which have since almost entirely dried up. The capital of the Empire—ruins of its ceremonial buildings can still be seen in the central plaza or zocalo of Mexico City—was Tenochtitlan. Its "twin city" to the north on the same island was Tlatelolco. Together they had a population of about one million, while in the entire valley there lived perhaps as many as two million people.* Here, in Tenochtitlan and Tlatelolco, lived the Culhua-Mexica.8 The less precise but more familiar name Aztec will be used to refer to the Nahua-speaking inhabitants of Tenochtitlan. Their culture was an ancient heritage, parts of which can be traced back to the classical period of Teotihuacan (300 to 900 a.d.). Its great pyramids still look down on the northern part of the Basin of Mexico. The structure of Aztec society has baffled historians and ethnologists for generations.8-10 The Aztecs, Nahuatl speakers, were in a po- I le Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 119 historical sense a new people. Their empire, which, most likely, a state structure, was less than a hundred years old at the time of ^conquest. Theirs was a highly stratified and complex society, based agriculture. Intense religiosity was expressed in the pageantry of r rituals. Almost every public act was sanctified by an appeal to the fe^pds, an appeal which sometimes culminated in human sacrifice and " " ' ■ 1 cannibalism. The splendor of its capital, Tenochtitlan, was de-|bed by its conqueror, Herman Cortes, in these terms: \ This great city of Temistitan is built on a salt lake, and from the main-]Jfict to the city is a distance of two leagues, from any side from which you |er. . . . The city has many squares where markets are held, and trading ferried on. There is one square, twice as large as that of Salamanca, all founded by arcades, where there are daily more than sixty thousand fouls, buying and selling, and where are found all the kinds of merchandise produced in these countries.11 ■The metropolis fell to the Spaniards in August of 1521 after nearly uee months of siege; then it was "a vast charnel-house, in which all was hastening to decay and decomposition."12 The basis of the regime of the Spanish conquest was the usurpation of political power and economic control achieved through military .\vyictory. Deliberately, the Spaniards utilized those of the aboriginal institutions that would further their own ends, attempted to destroy those which opposed their objectives, and let those disintegrate for which they had no need. Accordingly, they utilized such aboriginal institutions as the ancient system of tributes and status, slavery, forced labor, tenantry and cacao bean money. However, temples were demolished, idols smashed and religious codices burned. As to longdistance trade, they had no use for it and allowed it to disintegrate. Tliey had other means of acquiring goods; during the conquest by ' plunder and confiscation, later by tribute and in the markets. The Aztec long-distance traders were an anomaly in them. Their trade goods were different from the Spanish, and so were their ports, their methods of transportation, and motivations. Markets were another matter. The Spaniards were highly dependent upon the markets during the early years, principally for food. These circumstances taken together explain the striking paucity of data, in the writing of the conquistadores and in later reports to the Spanish Crown, on an institution of enormous importance in the aboriginal society, namely, the system of long-distance trade.13 120 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India For the purpose at hand the different fate of trade and markets is in itself significant. The fact that the markets remained in existence and, even though in modified form, continued to be a major focus of interest to the Spaniards, while the whole system of long-distance trade suffered rapid disintegration, goes to show that even prior to the conquest trade and markets were separate institutions, for had they been closely interdependent it would have been hardly possible for the Spaniards to continue one without the other. The long-distance trader among the Aztecs was called pochteca. This term will be used generically to refer to the various types of full-time professional traders who carried on trading relations exclusively with peoples beyond the frontier of the Aztec Empire.14 The only exception to this was the trade with the isolated province of the Empire, the enclave of Xoconusco in the Guatemala region. Although Xoco-nusco definitely formed part of the empire, goods flowed to the center not only as tribute or tax, but also were traded by the pochteca. Precisely where the pochteca fit into the Aztec status structure is not easy to determine. They did not belong to the "nobles" (pilli) nor to the commoners (macehualh) but neither do they appear to have constituted somehow a "middle class." Actually, they were closely associated with the piffi. Sahagun, referring to some honored pochteca, calls them "nobility by fantasy."16 They invited the pilli to their sumptuous feasts as honored guests. There is a reference to individual pochteca as having been granted private ownership of a piece of land, traditionally a prerogative of the pilli, although it was not extensively practiced at the time of the conquest.16 Some of the pochteca, the top ranking officers and especially the slave traders, are repeatedly referred to as persons of great wealth and as highly esteemed by the sovereign. Certain of the pochteca traded in distant ports on behalf of the sovereign for the coveted elite goods. On the other hand, they were obliged to present gifts and pay tribute in kind, although not in service,17 thus differing from the piffi who may be economically classed as receivers of tribute.18 Also the sovereign cautioned the pochteca not to appear too haughty in presumption of their wealth, lest they lose the esteem in which he held them, have them killed, and their goods confiscated.19 For the rest, their status seems most nearly to approximate that of some skilled craftworkers. The latter paid tribute with their finished product; the pochteca, with their wares. Alike they were exempt from personal services or labor for the state and from service in the army, f", ■ tsade Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 121 :. ■ except in times of emergency. Also both groups dealt largely in luxury jfoems. The pochteca brought the raw materials from the distant tropics wl>- juch as quetzal and macaw feathers, animal skins, and precious stones I"-— jrjth which the craftsmen made their wares, and then carried some of the finished products back to the foreign ports. Yet there was no close linkage between this trade and the crafts, for just as the pochteca also . exported other commodities, such as slaves and fine fabrics, craftsmen ? ?F were probably often directly commissioned for some of their work by fjy the sovereign and the pilli.20 Nevertheless, it is significant that of all the I -:; craftworkers, the pochteca were most closely identified with the feather f.. workers, the amanteca, whose status was comparable in Western terms 1" to that of jewelers. Sahagun states that their barrios (quarters) were toll gether, their principal gods coupled, that they reciprocated at feasts | • and were almost equal in wealth.21 *' Apparently the pochteca of the Aztec domain formed a definite • ■ type of organization through which they were in association. The • traders of at least eighteen towns, most of which were in the Basin of Mexico, were known to have traveled together. They also jointly organized for war from various towns.22 Their occupation was hereditary. Sahagun states repeatedly that the pochteca of Tenochtitlan and Tlatelolco, twin towns of the capital, live in their own barrios. Again, the term needs explanation. In common parlance, it means simply quarter or ward of a town. The Spaniards, however, used it also to refer not only to a quarter, but also to an entire town, in still other cases to a subdivision of a quarter, termed, in Nahuatl, calpulli, i.e., clan owned land; sometimes even only a subdivision of clan land, i.e., land owned by a lineage or extended family, Tlaxilacaffi. One ethnologist (A. Mon-zon) maintains that in this context they (barrios) were clan lands and that the pochteca were organized as a kin unit.23 Others have interpreted it simply as a quarter and held that the pochteca were organized as guilds or even only as a socio-economic class.24 Again, the pochteca structure has been thought to contain elements of both clan and class.25 Whatever their barrios were, and they might well have been the territory of stratified clans as Monzon believes, there are on record names for seven of them dispersed and repeated over a wide area of the Aztec Empire. And often more than one of these barrios existed in the same town. Be this as it may, the pochteca possessed a tight-knit structure, with their own hierarchy, special gods, distinctive rites, particular feasts and 122 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India religious celebrations, unique insignia and a strict moral code, as well as an ethical point of view on the hazards and rewards of the profession, and a high regard for honesty and group solidarity.26 They had courts to judge their own members. Yet, as we know, the pochteca were not a separate, autonomous body, rather they formed part of the community very close to the piJIi, and had strong ties with the craftsmen, especially the feather workers. They also sacrificed and ate slaves in honor of the main god of Tenochtitlan-Tlatelolco, the so-called Aztec tribal god, Huitzilopochtli.27 Nor, indeed, was their role in Aztec society confined to trading. As they pushed beyond the political frontiers into enemy, that is non-tribute-paying territory, they were frequently assaulted, robbed, imprisoned or slaughtered, whereupon in retaliation the Aztecs declared war on the offenders.28 Once a territory was conquered and thereby subjected to tribute payments, the pochteca ceased to trade there.29 The exception to this rule, as we noted, was the geographically isolated province of Xoconusco, far to the south on the Pacific coast. It is significant, if true, that the pochteca themselves conquered this province.30 In most cases where trade preceded tribute, once a province had been conquered and began to pay its tribute, longdistance trading ceased. In this sense, then, trade was followed by tribute; commerce by administration. For an example of the type of goods paid in tribute, these were paid by Quiauteopan and its five towns, as recorded in the Codex Mendoza. Admittedly, this province is not typical because the list does not include the usual quota of maize, beans, and other foods. Every six months the following was paid to Tenochtitlan: 400 large mantles, 40 large copper bells, 80 copper axe blades, 100 jars of bees' honey; and yearly, 1 war dress with its shield of rich feathers and 1 pan of turquoise stones. As we shall see, most of these items were exported by the pochteca, which suggests that trade preceded tribute.31 There is no doubt that the pochteca differed in rank; also, as stated, the profession was hereditary.32 Yet it called for considerable ability, courage, and training. Young men making their first expedition were counseled and admonished by their elders. The top-ranking officers were old men who no longer went on expeditions.33 But whether age-grading was basic to the ranking system is another question. The interrelationship of the different status groups remains a problem, as does that of the different towns and barrios in which the pochteca lived. If, as has been suggested, the pochteca were organized in stratified clans jfjjjf *|rade Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 123 f^Ci-t&en the various ranks may have constituted separate clans or sub-clans.34 It has been possible to discern the following four or five ranks, some of which may have been localized, that is, may have existed only in a few barrios or towns of the pochteca. 1. Top-ranking officers. For the highest rank there are several terms, one of which is pochtecatlatoque, literally, a senior or principal person of the pochteca.35 Sahagun implies that such persons were appointed by s. , t&e sovereign; if so, undoubtedly from among the old pochteca of '■ prestige. They inhabited one or several of the barrios of Tenochtitlan and Tlatelolco. These were highly esteemed old traders who stayed at home, bidding farewell to the outgoing expeditions with words of encouragement and admonishment. They commissioned the expeditionary pochteca with goods to be exchanged for them in the ports of trade, and upon whose return the gain would be shared by both parties. There is even a mention of women commissioning goods, this case being the only reference known to the writer to women as pochteca.36 The pochtecatlatoque presided at the important feasts and ceremonies and probably provided also the judges among the pochteca.37 2. Slave traders. This group ranked very high, but just what their relationship was to the pochtecatlatoque is not clear. Sahagun says that they were, "the major and most principal of all the merchants, their wealth being in men themselves." Slave traders domiciled in Tlatelolco actually resided also in Tochtepec, in Oaxaca near the southern frontier of the Empire. These frontier residents were so important that the pochteca from Tenochtitlan and Tlatelolco made special visits there to take part in certain of their rituals and to extend to these members among the slave traders their personal invitations to attend the yearly celebration in the capital.38 3. King's traders. These were called the teucunenenque (teuctli —lord, noble, person of quality; nenenqui—traveler, passenger). They were dearly loved by the sovereign. It is clear from the data given by Sahagun that these were royal administrative trade officials. He describes them as going to the Gulf coast area and exchanging goods there on behalf of the sovereign and also for themselves with the lords of Xicalango (also Coatzocoalcos and Cimatan) 39 He also tells us that they were honored for having conquered the outlaying province of Ayotla, in which was located the trading port of Xoconusco, mentioned earlier.40 However, Hernando Alvarado Tezozomoc, 124 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India writing at the close of the sixteenth century, gives credit for the conquest to the emperor Ahuizotl and his troops.41 This same chronicler relates that Moctezuma the Younger summoned the Teucunen-enque and ordered them to go with other principle sefiores to collect tribute from the Gulf coast towns of Ahuilizapan and Cuetlaxtlan. Upon their arrival they were attacked, smothered with chile smoke, disemboweled, stuffed with straw, seated upon handsome benches and cursed in farcical obsequiousness by their slayers. When Moctezuma received news of this affront, he was incensed. He declared war and the towns were reconquered in quick order.42 Significantly, in all of these varied activities there is a very close relationship between the Teucunenenque and the emperor, while at the same time there is no mention of them as top officers, nor slave traders, nor spies.43 4. Trader-spies. These, the naualoztomeca, were described by Sahagun as "not so principal." He mentions them only in the role of trader-spies and this may well have been their exclusive function. In this capacity they are described as entering enemy territory with a knowledge of the local dialect or language, disguised as natives, to seat themselves in the market place, ostensibly to exchange their wares, but really listening, observing and inquiring for vital information. Upon their return they reported all to the emperor. As would be expected, these "trader spies" did not trade in luxury goods for which the other pochteca were famous, but in common goods such as knives and combs of flint.44 The Nahuatl-Spanish dictionary of Molina written in the sixteenth century gives further evidence for the existence of this rank. In it naualcalaquini is defined: to enter a place in dissimulation with caution and in secret, while oztomeca is defined as harriero and in derivations as walking merchant.48 5. Oztomeca or "walking merchants" are mentioned by Tezozo-moc and may have been the same as the naualoztomeca, although he does not describe them as trader-spies but rather in two instances as the traders whose slaughter was motive for war.46 But it may have been merely a general term for trader, synonymous with pochteca.47 The caravan or expedition was led by a "captain" pochteca, and included non-pochteca, the slaves and tamemes or porters. The parents of young men on their first trip were solicitous that the captain look after their boys. Certainly the slave traders and king's traders also went on expeditions and it is probable that all kinds of pochteca \e Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 125 tured out jointly, as it was always a perilous journey. Thus there itild be among the usual expeditionary crew both age grading and ■ Inferences of rank 48 How did the pochteca obtain the commodities which they ex-:ed? Sahagun describes a trip in which the king supplied them pi 1600 quachtli (cotton cloths) which they took to Tlatelolco and bided there equally with the Tlatelolcan pochteca. Thereupon both «ps took the cloths to the market in Tlatelolco and purchased rich *■ nothing with which to trade on behalf of the sovereign as well as i tewelry and finery "for their own trading."48* Upon arriving in the ports of trade of the Xicalango area, they exchanged these goods again pith the local rulers.49 In another instance Sahagun quotes a trader Is saying that he had purchased stone knives, bells, needles, cochineal and piedra de Iumbre with which to trade.60 This same source gives several accounts of the slave traders buying slaves in the market of '^neighboring Azcapotzalco for the purpose of ceremonial sacrifice, a 'part of the pochteca yearly celebration.51 They may also have purchased slaves for export. Slaves were sold in various markets, one of the most important being that of the just mentioned Azcapotzalco. But the home of the slave traders was, as we may recall, Tlatelolco. Masters certainly sold their slaves in the market and a person could |ell his children and even himself. A slave could even purchase a slave. |}ut there is no mention of the pochteca selling slaves in the markets M the Basin of Mexico.52 Evidently those who sold slaves in the piarket were not the pochteca who traded slaves over long distances. But as to exports in general, a comparison of the items sold in the markets of the Basin of Mexico with the goods exported by the pochteca reveals that all of the latter goods were available in the local markets.53 Thus is can be asserted that some pochteca did purchase goods in the markets of Tenochtitlan-Tlatelelco which they traded in foreign ports. However, they may also have had other sources, one of them being the royal cloths supplied by the palace, and other treasures. The most frequently mentioned types of goods exported are: slaves (men, women and children); richly worked garments for men and women (there is one reference to clothes "for the common people"); ornaments of gold and precious stones; skeins of rabbit fur; copper bells. Copper and obsidian ornaments, needles, combs and 126 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India knives of obsidian, red ochre and cochineal dyes, sweet smelling herbs and piedra de lumbre are also mentioned. Garments and ornaments seem to be by far the most important items as they are frequently mentioned and many different kinds are described.64 It is significant that most of these goods are manufactured articles, and most of the raw materials out of which they were marie were not found in the Basin of Mexico but came in partly as tribute from outlying provinces, perhaps also with local vendors and certainly with the pochteca on their return trips. The extent to which exports relied on markets is not yet clear. The commodities most frequently described as imported by the pochteca are: rich feathers; precious and semi-precious stones. Cacao, cacao stirrers, gold, animal skins and fans are also mentioned.55 Thus in contrast to exports, imports mostly consisted of raw materials. This is qualified by "mostly" not because of the fans or stirrers which probably were not very important, but because there is occasional mention of some of the imported precious stones and animal skins as having been "worked." This undoubtedly means polished and tanned as there is no account of actual manufactured objects in either case.56 Given the great importance of gold and copper objects in the Aztec society, absence of the mention of copper and the infrequent references to gold as imported would seem to indicate that most of it was obtained either in the local markets or through tribute payment. The present states of Oaxaca and Guerrero were known sources of gold and most of this region had been conquered by the Aztecs.57 However, the pochteca are known to have traveled as far south as the present Costa Rica-Panama border for gold.58 We can only suggest, however, that the question of gold, its sources, forms, and uses merits a study in itself. Here attention should be drawn to the extraordinary importance of feather objects. Feather working was an ancient and, as we have seen, a highly respected craft. There were numerous types of feathers. The most highly prized came from birds of the highlands of the south, those of the quetzal bird being outstanding. Apparently it was an extremely arduous task to hunt or capture these birds. Some conservation of the species was practiced; sometimes the captured bird was carefully held while its best feathers were plucked and the bird then set free in order to give another supply.59 Among the amazing ie Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 127 ■Mety of objects made or adorned with the feathers were head gear, sics on shields and helmets used in ceremonies, garments and Ihs, ornaments, standards and banners.80 Surprisingly, there are only a few mentions of cacao as having been Iported by the pochteca. This is baffling because cacao was very Important as the principal money of the various cultures and as the ■pin ingredient of the people's favorite chocolate drinks. Cacao beans, png with other objects, were used both in exchange and for payment fines, debts and tribute.61 It was cultivated or in use all the way *vls ?from the Basin of Mexico to Costa Rica, although it may not have 'f£ been employed throughout this entire area. A recent dissertation entitled "When Money Grew On Trees" shows that its principal areas of ^scaltivation were central Veracruz, northern Oaxaca and the Xoconusco itclave far to the south, yet forming part of the empire. Beyond the frontiers it was grown in the Xicalango region of the Gulf coast, southwestern Guatemala and the Gulf of Honduras.62 It will be noted that two of these areas were the central regions of the great ports of trade. ^ Among the Aztecs, then, if cacao was not a principal trade import, it ' -may have been because the 900 loads received annually in tribute payment supplied most of their needs.63 Should this be so, the importance of Xicalango and the Gulf of Honduras as Aztec ports of trade may have indirectly been due to cacao production. Indirectly, since wealth * in cacao might well have attracted from the hinterlands and regions inaccessible to the pochteca, the fine feathers and precious stones which they sought. Other money in use with the Aztecs were a particular kind of small Ibotton cloth, gold dust in transparent quill containers, "rich feathers" i and perhaps small copper axes and pieces of tin.64 Just how these moneys circulated and what might be paid for with each will necessitate special research. Although barter also obtained, the various money objects, and especially cacao, were extensively used in the markets. Like cacao, some were also used in payment. It is not possible to say with ^assurance whether cacao served as a standard, that is, whether all other moneys had established equivalencies in relation to cacao. This writer is acquainted with only one reference which definitely stipulates an Ipxchange equivalency between cacao and cloth. Sahagun writes that a canoe was worth one quachtli (cloth, and presumably money) or one hundred cacao beans.65 This equivalency need not have obtained uni-versally, of course, as the exchange values of the moneys were known 128 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India to vary in different regions. Nevertheless, the existence of equivalencies between objects used as money appears established and of money objects cacao was certainly the most widely spread, and thus, practically, must have served as a standard. For the relation between long-distance hade and the markets, it is a most suggestive fact that we have not come across any mention of the pochteca using money of any description in the ports of trade. Money as a means of exchange was employed, of course, primarily in the market. Trade, as carried on by the pochteca was directed towards ports of trade in which transactions were performed in kind, whether with the intervention of the administration of the store houses where the staples were deposited, or through direct acts of exchange in kind. In principle, all foreign trade was barter, and the method of operation was barter. The description referred to above of the pochteca teucunenenque receiving cloths from the emperor and going to Tlatel-olco where they shared them with other pochteca "and spoke of the business which the king had entrusted them with" is evidence of administered trade, that is, trade between politically independent entities. This is further substantiated by this same chronicler's account of their arrival at the ports of trade: When the traders arrived at the province of Anahuac Xicalango, they gave the rulers that which the ruler of Mexico had sent them and they greeted them on his behalf, and the ruler of rulers of this same province, of the town of Xicalanco, and the town of Cimatecatl (Cimatan), and Quatzaqualco (Coatzacoalco) gave them large polished green stones, and other long polished chalchiuites (turquoise), and red stones and other emeralds . . . and other stones. .. . They also gave them shells and red and yellow fans, and cacao stirrers . . . rich feathers . . . tanned skins of wild beasts ... all these things were brought back by the traders from that province of Xicalanco for the ruler of Mexico; and when they returned and arrived at Mexico they immediately presented them to the ruler.66 Sahagun further says that the traders took goods to Xicalanco "for the common people" consisting of earnings of copper and flint, flint combs, small knives, bells, needles, cochineal and sweet smelling herbs. He does not say how this ware was exchanged. However, in the entire account by Sahagun of the pochteca trading in these foreign provinces there is no mention of prices or markets or of their exchanging with anyone but the rulers. The only exception is the spy traders, the naua- Trade Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 129 loztomeca, who went, not to the ports of trade, but into enemy territory where they sat in the markets disguised as natives—a strong indication of the local ethnic character of markets, as contrasted with trade. There are no data on how the slave traders carried on exchange. The rulers and other nobles who bought slaves in the ports of trade must have either sacrificed them, or put them to work as domestics or in the cacao fields. The pochteca also exchanged the goods which had been commissioned by the pochtecatlaloque with whom they shared the "gain" upon return. There is no direct indication of what this gain consisted in, but, as will be evident from the passage cited below, it must have been in goods.67 Where barter prevails gain must necessarily take that form. Just how the pochteca returned with their precious ware is of great interest. The crucial point is that their goods were not destined for the market. They made sure of returning on a good luck day. They waited until night-time before entering the capital and came in secretly so that no one should notice them. They did not go directly to their houses, but to that of a relative or some person of confidence where they deposited their goods. If anyone inquired there about what they had brought back they would say: . . . this wealth that I bring, take care of it for me but don't think I entrust it with you because it is mine, it belongs to the senores, the principal merchants, they recommended that I bring it here.'8 And only after reporting to the pochteca officers did they go home to sleep. The Maya of Yucatan We now enter the world of the Maya. The paucity of data on trade is striking. Yet the little that the Spanish documents reveal is suggestive. By taking advantage of modern research on related subjects, in particular the organization of the pochteca and the use of cacao money and comparing them with accounts of the Basin of Mexico we can piece together a fragmentary image of the preconquest situation. The degree to which it has been possible to attain some clarity is due chiefly to the excellent studies of Roys, Scholes, and Chamberlain. 130 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India The absence of the mention of trade in the Spanish eye witnesses' accounts on Yucatan after its discovery, in 1517, has two very different reasons: The one was the indifference of the conquistadores to this obviously non-gold-bearing area. Once the Spaniards were resigned to the lack of gold in a region, they were little interested in observing native trading customs. The other was the almost immediate disappearance of the native trading system after the conquest of the Aztec capital in the north, in 1521. Actually, the entire area under consideration had had a very active and tightly knit trade organization, based on regional ecology, agricultural specialization and localized manufacture. Consequently, the entire network of trading relationships, from the Basin of Mexico south to Yucatan and Honduras and even to Panama, was drastically affected by the fall of Tenochtitlan, the center of economic and political power. A few years after that event the basis of the Indian societies had shifted and the delicate web of trade relations had become torn or tangled; by the 1540's it had all but disappeared. The accounts of some of the participants of the first three expeditions directed towards the western mainland (1517-1519) and of later entradas into the unexplored inland regions deserve close scrutiny for what they may reveal of trade and markets. We will enumerate certain isolated facts in regard to trade in Yucatan taken from these records, mostly written by the conquistadores and early missionaries, and compare them with accounts of the Basin of Mexico and other areas. By coincidence the very spot where the Spaniards first touched the mainland, the northeastern corner of Yucatan, was one of the few commercial centers of the entire peninsula. The conquerors were much impressed with the richly dressed Indians who greeted them at Ecab (Belma), in northeastern Yucatan. In their enthusiasm they called it "el Gran Cairo." Ecab and the neighboring inland towns of Cachi and Cahuacha were described as having large markets.72 At Cachi there was a market court on one corner of the square, where disputes were settled by certain officials.73 In 1527 the Adelantado of Yucatan, Francisco de Montejo, sailed down the eastern coast to the Bay of Chetumal. Here he found the town of Chetumal two leagues inland from the bay. He described it as having two thousand houses, stone walls facing the coast for defense(!), fertile lands, highly developed bee culture and as being an important trading center. It was also the only extensive cacao-producing area of ■%tde Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 131 ig entire peninsula. Later his lieutenant Alonso Dávila came to the jlpe area and was so favorably impressed with the many maize fields, »|Jie populous settlements and the strategic location that he established Igjte Spanish town of Salamanca there. This was one of the few places, 'fte other being the northeastern tip, where the Spaniards found gold ejects. In this same bay region was the town of Bacalar. It was also jgjjgported to have had a thriving commerce. Situated on a lake of the tóne name, it was joined by a river to the Bay of Chetumal.74 The land around the Bay of Chetumal region, in some essential Aspects, appears closely comparable to the coastal strips of the Gulf df Mexico and the Gulf of Honduras. This point of embarkation for iperseas trading and for receiving goods from the hinterland was, like (the Xicalango-Gulf of Mexico, a land of bays, lagoons, rivers, lakes and marshes, all of which made for extensive canoe travel. It also had cacao cultivation. But the similarity to the other two areas becomes even jl more striking when we see that, despite several eye witness reports, W there is no mention of markets or market places. (See map, p. 118) r In contrast to the Basin of Mexico with its unified imperial governor ment, Yucatan at the time of the conquest, according to Roys, was I? divided into eighteen politically autonomous entities, which he de-' scribes as follows: Certainly each of these subdivisions was independent of its neighbors. Some of them possessed a well-organized political system headed by a single ruler: others were more or less closely knit confederacies of towns or groups of towns; still others seem to have been merely collections of towns in a given area, whose relations with one another are largely a matter of con-.- jecture.75 The greater part of the northern peninsula was limestone with only a thin layer of humus on top and it was covered with a shrub or thick brush growth. Only the northeast had sufficient rainfall to permit of forest growth. The center of the peninsula was traversed from sast to west by a low mountain range. This country would have presented great difficulties for living were it not that the underground water table was sufficiently near the surface to make water accessible through natural or artificial wells, called cenotes. It was therefore around these cenotes that the farming communities were located. Maize, beans, squash, cotton and cassava were the most important crops. There were settlements along the coast dedicated exclusively to 132 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India fishing. Here salt gathering was also important. Apiculture was extensively practiced. Game, and especially deer, was plentiful. But metals were entirely lacking, although flint was to be found, and apparently it was even mined along the foothills of the sierra. Flint was the material used for cutting implements and weapons.76 Notwithstanding the apparent simplicity of its basic neolithic pattern, the Maya-Yucatecan society was highly stratified, ritualistic and commercial. The long-distance trader in Yucatan was a person of noble status and wealth. He trafficked mainly in slaves, cloth and salt, to a lesser extent in honey and flint, i.e., mostly in raw materials. His principal ports of trade were about Xicalango in the Gulf of Mexico to the southwest, and on the Gulf of Honduras to the southeast. In the latter area he had warehouses and factors (agents). There apparently was a manner of distinction among the traders, between what Roys calls the "professional merchant," the ppolom, and "those who traveled," the ah ppolom yoc.77 There does not seem to have existed in Yucatan the same sharp definition of the traders as a group which obtained among the Aztecs. Nor is there any mention of their occupation of a special section of a town or city. Nor is there evidence, as we saw, of a comparable degree of internal ranking and differentiation of types of traders. Nor do we find any such complex ritual and ceremonial activities as characterize the Aztec traders. It is not by any means suggested, however, that Yucatecan-Maya trading institutions represented simply a watered down version of the Aztec, or a simpler commercial system than was theirs. Trade in Yucatan was a vitally important activity. The Maya social and political stratification, internecine warfare, as well as the economics of production and consumption, was to a large extent dependent on the maintenance of trade relations beyond their ethnic frontiers. Indeed, the Yucatecan trader was apparently much more closely identified with his political rulers than was the Aztec trader. In at least one case, dating back to the middle of the fifteenth century, the son of the ruler of Cocom is referred to as a trader.78 A close connection of, if not identity with, the rulers and traders, coupled with the absence of any indication of trading in the market places of foreign ports, points towards the practice of administered trade carried on by chieftain's clans through warehouses in the ports of trade. H&rade Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 133 HgF As we have noted, the main export commodities at the time of the Hraecmquest were slaves, cloth and salt. Flint and honey ranked second. R9oh contrast to the Mexican exports, none required specialized labor in F-s% manufacture. Nearly every woman wove cloth. Anyone living near the Pjjf -c09St c0u^ genera% obtain permission to gather salt. Flint was readily available and easily made into tools or weapons; and most families pos-jessed bee hives. Slaves, of course, are a special case. Their acquisition for trade both within Yucatan and abroad was a primary cause for IjK' taids and wars between the provinces. They were also bought and sold fr? in Yucatan.79 I Because the cultivation of cotton and its spinning and weaving were rH. universal in Yucatan, cloth may not have been an important item of Bfc trade within Yucatan proper. The same may have been true of honey. ■Hjpertainly slaves, salt and flint were traded internally. Many other Ev articles were also traded "domestically," such as fish, pottery, canoes, f d\es, copal gum for incense, maize, game, fruit, wooden idols and small | - amounts of native cacao.80 Im It is clear, then, that long-distance trade dealt only in certain spe-cific goods. At the time of the conquest, only a relatively few types of f articles were being exported. JJJjl Turning now to the imports, we will recall that the Spaniards were never weary of complaining of and continually disheartened by the i small amounts of gold to be had in Yucatan and that all of it had been imported. The lure of richer plunder from the various regions of the | Aztec Empire was an important factor in the relatively late conquest L of the peninsula. Yucatan was not definitely conquered until after the 4 suppression of the Great Maya Revolt of 1546-47. For our purposes 1' ". it is significant that the largest amounts of gold objects acquired by the I Spaniards were from the region of the large market towns on the northeastern coast and from the important trading area of the Bay of Chetu-mal on the East coast. About the time of the conquest gold articles were imported from the Xicalango region, having been brought there by pochteca from the Basin of Mexico where the ornaments and ritual paraphernalia were made. Bells, axes or celts, plates and thin sheets of copper and skeins of dyed rabbit hair seem to have followed the same route. Precious and semiprecious stones including jade and jadite turquoise, crystalline green stones, yellow topaz, obsidian and the fine quetzal and macaw feathers that originated in the southern highlands and were traded in via the Gulf of Honduras as well as the Gulf of Mex- 134 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India ico. A type of red shell, Spondylus princeps, was relayed to Yucatan via Honduras from the Pacific coast of Nicaragua. Cacao was also imported in large quantities. Of all the above-mentioned items only cacao was native to the two main ports of trade areas, the Gulf of Mexico and the Gulf of Honduras.81 Money, in the sense of quantifiable objects used in exchange, was common in Yucatan. Cacao was the most important, but cotton cloths of a standard size, strings of red shells (spondylus princeps), copper hatchets, and bells as well as jade beads and salt were also used as money. Of these, only the cotton cloth and salt were native to Yucatan. As in the case of the Nahua area, this matter calls for further research. However, as suggested above, in view of the extensive use of the cacao money and its predominance over other money, it may well have been a standard against which all other commodities were equated throughout the entire area of central and southern Mexico and Central America. As among the Aztecs, it was also used to make a kind of chocolate drink.82 The long-distance traders used only the cacao bean as money. The traders carried a kind of pocketbook filled with cacao beans. These may have been used as cash to pay for lodgings on the journey. One of the early chroniclers, Gasper Antonio Chi, asserts that the Yucatecans, being a hospitable people, gave shelter to all traveling strangers, except the traders, who had to pay.83 The goods were transported by human caravans and canoe fleets. Overland the noble ah ppolom yac led his slave porters single file along the foot trails through the underbrush and forest, which had been cleared just enough to allow the passage of one man with a pack. The mounted Spaniards later complained of these trails that they had not been cleared for a man on a horse and that consequently a rider often got himself entangled in the overhanging vegetation. The traders led, the porters followed. The porters were slaves, destined to be sold in the foreign ports. This was a convenient arrangement for the traders, because the goods which they exported were bulkier than those which they brought back. At their destinations they exchanged all of their goods, including their slaves, mostly for manufactured items, and so simplified the problem of portage on the return trip. Apparently the Maya did not pay their porters as did the Aztecs their tamemes. The Maya may have had a corps of slaves who always accompanied them ||e Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 135 X-m trading expeditions and simply augmented the number of this corps 'gf porters going out with the slaves to be sold. Like the pochteca, how-Bet, they stopped along the trails at shrines, in this case those of their Jj|d Ekchuan, who was also the god of cacao.84 But by no means did all their travel go overland. From the Bay of jfccencion on the east coast they journeyed by canoe to the Gulf of ■pduras and perhaps around the peninsula and down the west coast jjtwell. The porters then became rowers. The canoes were made from (hollowed out tree trunk and were traded from the Chetumal Bay |*ea. Some were reported to be very large, holding as many as forty to prtyrnen.85 Aztec pochteca, Mayan ppolom, in either case persons of the upper class, enter on a long-distance carrying service on behalf of the community. The pochteca of the Nahua are a highly elaborated gild, probably of communally settled clan origin; the ppolom, though perhaps of even higher rank, are less specialized because their exports are not ■ luxury wares but raw materials. We know their gods, their porters, their routes, their military and political status, but what was the journey's aim? How would the pochteca and the ppolom trade in the absence of markets? Obviously nothing but barter in kind was feasible, and it would be transacted even while their respective countries may have been engaged in hostilities. Pochteca as well as ppolom were moving toward definite geographical areas organized to serve just that purpose. The actual exchange of goods took place in ports of trade. We now turn to the discussion of their locations. Gulf of Mexico—Xicalango The ports of trade on the Gulf of Mexico extended from a point in the State of Veracruz to the westernmost section of the Laguna de Terminos, i.e., the "lagoon at the border," the town of Xicalango pioper.86 (See map, end pages) This was (and is) a hot alluvial plain covered by a network of rivers, lagoons, swamps and bogs interspersed with tropical rain forests and grassy savannahs. From the lagoon of Tupilco, just east of the Coatzal-coalcos River through this entire region there predominated a people of Maya stock, the Chontal. It was, as we have noted, one of the principal cacao-producing areas. Within the region there were a num- 136 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India ber of small senorios, politically autonomous entities, each with its lords and nobles, working population and a varying number of subject tributary towns.87 Neither politically nor militarily was there any strong concentration of power present. Many and far-flung routes come together here at the various ports of trade. People and goods traveled by canoe, almost exclusively. From the north came the famous pochteca of the Aztec with their luxury wares. Inland, down from the southern and eastern sierras came people with precious stones and feathers, from the Zoque and Tzeltal-Tzotzil towns and mines. Traders following other riverain routes west came down the Candelaria River from Acalan and across the base of Yucatan from the Gulf of Honduras as well. Up the Gulf Coast towards the east the canoes traveled at least as far as the town of Campeche. There is no direct evidence that the traders spanned the entire distance around the Yucatecan peninsula by canoe to the east coast. Roys assumes that they did so because it is known that traders from Xicalango made pilgrimages to the shrine of the merchant god on the Island of Cozu-mel. He admits, however, they may have traveled up the eastern coast from the Gulf of Honduras instead.88 As we have seen, this Xicalango enclave was perhaps most important for Aztecs in their long distance trade. Sahagun documents the journey of the pochteca to this region. Cargoes of richly worked fabrics and clothing, ornaments and spindle whorls of gold, copper bells, obsidian knives and combs, and skeins of dyed rabbit hair all firmly secured on the backs of their porters, which the pochteca of the various cities of the Basin of Mexico assembled, in making ready for their departure overland, were destined for these two main ports of trade: Xicalango on the Gulf coast and Xoconusco on the Pacific.89 Some of the pochteca, perhaps each one of them, carried a black wooden staff, symbol of their god, Yiacatecutli. They also carried fans, corn mash and other dried foods for the journey. Some of the porters were slaves and others the lowly tamemes, clothed in rags and subsisted as human beasts of burden.90 Writing some hundred odd years after the conquest, the English missionary, Thomas Gage, made notes on this same rank of men, now working for the Spaniards: . . . they will make those wretches to carry on their backs a whole day, nay some two or three days together, which they do by tying the chest on jde Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 137 jpside with ropes, having a broad leather in the middle, which they P$ over the forepart of their head, or over their forehead, hanging thus t weight upon their heads and brows, which at their journey's end hath pfe the blood stick in the foreheads of some, galling and pulling off the Tj; and marking them in the fore-top of their heads, who as they are |d tamemes, so are easily known in a town by their baldness, that leather pth having worn off all their hair.91 Each porter and slave carried approximately fifty pounds. There is indication of how much the pochteca themselves may have carried, ley trotted single file over mountain trails. If, as Bernal Diaz reported, they averaged five leagues a day, it must have taken many days to cover f the first lap.92 At night they stopped to sleep in any cave, gorge or ^-■gavine, beside a large boulder or under a tree. Each night they tied their black staffs together, thus improvising the image of their god Yiacatecutli. To it they offered their blood by piercing their tongues, i-V tars, legs or arms, and in burning incense in its honor they felt assured of a safe journey. Sometimes also they worshipped at shrines of their god along the trail. A strange proscription was laid upon them: during the entire journey until the return home, they could not bathe nor wash nor cut their hair. It was, however, permissible to wash the neck.93 The first lap of the journey was terminated in the town of Tochtepec, near the southern border of the Empire, in the northeastern section of the present state of Oaxaca. Tochtepec was the chief frontier trading center and the home of a colony of rich slave traders who had originally come from Tlatelolco. It was the gateway into the enemy teiritory through which the pochteca passed to reach those two great trading centers to the south,94 that of Xicalango, to the east, Xoconusco, to the west. At Tochtepec the caravan split, some going over the sierra to the isolated Aztec province of Xoconusco, that Aztec exclave on the Pacific coast. The others went instead down the sierra to the marshy swamp lands of the Gulf coast. As enemy territory lay ahead, upon departing the pochteca took to swords and shields, and even armed their slaves, marching cautiously and only at night.95 Those headed towards the Pacific had the protection of a line of Aztec garrisons along the sierra trail until they reached Xoconusco. Those headed toward Xicalango, on the Gulf, did not have so far to go and although they had no garrisons to protect them, the local rulers of the ports of trade would send emissaries to greet them and give them safe conduct at the final part of their journey. Upon arrival, as has been 138 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India described, the pochteca presented themselves to the rulers of Coatzal-coalco, Cimatan and Xicalango.96 There were apparently five major groups of ports of trade in this Gulf of Mexico area; (1) the settlements at the mouth of the Coatzal-coalco River, (2) the inland towns of Cimatan and (3) those of the Chontalpa, (4) the town of Potonchan at the mouth of the Grijalva River and (5) the famous Xicalango at the western end of the Laguna de Terminos. 1. Coatzalcoalco was a coastal town just beyond the frontiers of the Aztec Empire but in the vicinity of an Aztec garrison. The pochteca arrived here bearing greetings and goods from their ruler. At the time of the conquest it was known to have been Nahuatl-speaking. The Spaniards described this country as rich and populous.97 2. Inland from the coast, further east, lay the Nahuatl town of Cimatan with its two closely allied neighboring towns. Cimatan controlled vital trade routes from both the inland sierras and the Basin of Mexico due to its strategic position near the great rivers which flowed down from the highlands and its accessibility to the Aztec traders coming from Tochtepec. It was the most powerful of the eight Mexican or Nahua speaking towns in Tabasco. It had conquered several Zoque towns to the south.98 Scholes and Roys write that, There can be little doubt that the temples of a town of such importanci were set on pyramids, and the more important buildings, on raised platforms, presumably of earth in this locality.99 Bernal Diaz described the palisades which surrounded it for defense but made no mention of a market.100 3. To the east of Cimatan and nearer the coast lay the Chontalpa, a thickly populated region and rich in cacao. In the lowlands between the Rio de Dos Bocas (present Rio Seco) and the Rio Nuevo 6 Gonzales lay at least twenty-three Chontal speaking towns. According to a document recently discovered, there were five other towns to the west of the Rio de Dos Bocas and five more to the east of the main group of twenty-three. This entire group of towns was called the Chontalpa. Here the Aztecs had factors and warehouses in the towns of Mecoacan, Chila-teupa and Teutitlan Copilco (modern Copilco). Scholes and Roys say the Aztecs sold their goods to local traders. Nevertheless, they infer that this region was not a commercial center because, according to a document of 1541, there was no market, although as the presence of Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 139 |s and warehouses testify, it was an important trading center.101 point is of eminent importance for a clearer understanding of the ire of long-distance trading. As we shall see, it is precisely the ration of markets and trading in the ports of trade, that seems to long-distance trading among the Nahua and Maya. || Next in order was Potonchan, near the mouth of the Grijalva . Like its neighbor to the east, Xicalango, it had traffic with ||n, the Usumacinta Valley and the Gulf of Honduras and hence ||e east coast of the peninsula of Yucatan. Although there is no |t evidence, Scholes and Roys believe the traders also went up the I coast and across to the island of Cozumel and the trading towns pat area. Potonchan was inhabited by Chontal speakers and thus Ifasted with Xicalango where there were at least some Nahua kers. As Sahagiin and other sources fail to mention Potonchan as Tjprt of trade for the pochteca and as it was inhabited by a Maya pie, this writer suggests that it traded exclusively with Mayas and jjpt with the pochteca at all. Although the town is described at some gth in the sixteenth century sources, there is no record of a mar-[Jt102. 5. The port of trade of Xicalango was the leading commercial site Br the Aztecs. As we know, they called this entire Gulf area, Anahuac-Kcalango. The town itself was situated near an inlet on the western K of the Laguna de Terminos. Scholes and Roys suggest that "the Mexican merchants with their employees and slaves occupied a quarter of the town. . . ." The ruling class, including the important local merchants, spoke Nahuatl while the native inhabitants spoke Chontal.103 This is a situation which was quite common, if not typical, in the Aztec ports of trade. It raises in a concrete way the question of the ^ relationship between the Nahua colonists-traders and the local rulers. Given a Nahua ruling class which included the traders and given the vital importance of trade for the community, it can be surmised that the Nahua traders were the actual rulers. The close tie if not identity between the traders and rulers was described for Yucatan and will be seen even more clearly in the province of Acalan and Naco on the Gulf of Honduras. Therefore this pattern may perhaps tell us something of an ethno-historical interest. Xicalango differs from both Yucatan and Acalan but is similar to Naco in that the trader-rulers were foreigners, that is, Nahua colonists. The chronicler Ixtlilxochitl men' 140 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India tions a "feria" (fair) in Xicalango but does not describe it nor associate it with the pochteca.104 Scholes and Roys recognize that just as Cimatan was favorably situated to handle long-distance trade from the highlands to the south and west, Xicalango enjoyed a similar advantage in regard to Acalan, the Usumacintla Valley and hence the Gulf of Honduras up to Yucatan. As we know, they may also have taken the coastal route to northeastern Yucatan. Xicalango shared all this traffic with its neighbor, Potonchan. But it contrasted to Potonchan not only on account of Nahua residents, but also because it was the preferred port of trade for the pochteca. It is for Xicalango, that Sahagun gives his most detailed description of administered trade.105 Some features of its concrete organization emerge. Hence our knowledge that no local traders from Xicalango went north to the Basin of Mexico. This trade was apparently handled exclusively by the pochteca. The Xicalango traders did however travel southward, to Acalan and the various ports of the Gulf of Honduras. They also may have gone to Yucatan as noted since there is indication that they went to the island of Cozumel to worship at the shrine of a merchant god. Cortes, in 1524, during his march to Honduras acquired a cloth map from the traders of Xicalango which he is said to have followed as far as Acalan.106 The inland sierras to which we have referred were also inhabited by peoples of the Maya linguistic stock; among them the Zoque, and the Tzeltal-Tzotzil. The other large group, the Chiapaneca, were an Otomangue speaking people. The foothills and sierra of the present states of Tabasco and Chiapas were the home of the Zoque. Here the people are described in the sixteenth century, some years after the conquest, as wearing tufts of feathers and skeins of green birds for ornaments, with necklaces and nose and ear plugs of wood, gold, topaz and other stones. Roys comments: "We know little of their political or social organization, except that there was among them an upper class which prided itself on its noble status."107 At least four of its principal towns were subject to Cimatan, while others were subject to the Chiapanec (the Otomangue group) and there were many independent towns and villages. This province, too, produced some cacao in the lowlands towards the Gulf coast, and manufactured cloth. It had mines of amber or so-called yellow topaz and produced cochineal which was used to make a red de Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 141 ||to8 The English missionary, Thomas Gage, visiting in 1625, de-jpes it as the richest part of Chiapas and comments on its important pnections with Tabasco and Yucatan. He names the chief com-idities as silk, which was certainly post-hispanic, and cochineal which, Siough used in pre-hispanic times, may have increased in production er the conquest.109 In the Tzeltal-Tzotzil region lay the town of Zinacantan, in the ghlands of Chiapas. Amber was obtained in trade by the Aztecs from js area. This product was much desired by the Culhua as well as the tiya for lip and nose beads. It was probably exported to the Gulf of exico and hence to Yucatan as well as the Basin of Mexico.110 To the Aztecs, to whom this was enemy territory, Zinacantan was P known as a town of "merchants." Sahagun reports that spy traders tie here to sit in the market place disguised as natives. We have »ady noted that their wares were not the luxury goods for which the chteca were famous, but rather goods which the common people gHtld buy.111 This is the only mention by Sahagun of pochtecas actually Jading in a market. It took place in unfriendly territory, in a town ^ hich, despite it being a trading town, cannot be called a port of trade. ' In other words, a port of trade, although located in a foreign territory, must be a friendly site, that is, safe for the traders. In some cases the friendliness of the Culhua ports of trade consisted in the circumstance that by some means Nahua traders had usurped political and economic . power from the local inhabitants. ;jf. Zinacantan, site of a Mexican garrison, was one of the strong points ; that protected the Culhua traders as they passed through enemy terri-lory and along the sierra down to the outlying Culhua province of f Xoconusco, near the present-day frontier between Mexico and Guatemala.112 Pacific Coast—Xoconusco The province of Xoconusco—an enclave on the Pacific coast_was conquered by the Aztecs about I486.113 Just how this conquest was carried out is not clear. While Sahagun states that pochteca conquered it. Tezozomoc names Aztec troops as the victors. He connects the traders with the conquest only in the sense that their slaughter in Xoconusco was the cause for an Aztec reprisal.114 In any event the 142 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India fertile cacao fields, for which Xoconusco was renowned, must have exerted a great attraction on the Aztecs.115 There is very little information on trade with this region. Sahagun mentions the pochteca setting out for Xoconusco, called Anahuac-Ayotlan, but proffers no description of their arrival nor of what was J traded.116 The cacao and perhaps quetzal feathers and other products of the 1 inland sierras offered a sufficiently rich reward for the Aztecs to warrant their passing through enemy territory.117 Nevertheless this area appears not to have been comparable in importance to either the Gulf of i Mexico or that of Honduras; it had very few navigable rivers, so that | trade movements were of necessity restricted.118 As in the ports of trade on the Gulf coast, this region was inhabited by some Nahua elements. Yet there is no evidence of the role they may have played as traders.119 In general, Xoconusco presents a problem. It is the only known area where long-distance trade was continued after subjugation to the Aztecs as a tribute-paying province. In all other instances long-distance trade was carried on outside the Aztec empire as well as beyond the provinces of the Mayan confederacies. Inland—Acalan Of first importance for the study of the region of Acalan is the discovery of a sixteenth century Chontal text in the Archives of Seville by Scholes. It has been recently published in a study by the finder and Roys. They have definitely located this province on the upper Cande-laria River, draining into the Laguna de Terminos. The Chontal text names seventy-six towns belonging to the province but Scholes and Roys found it impossible to locate or identify most of them. Concerning the capital, Itzamkanac, however, we know that it was situated south of the Candelaria near the junction of the Arroyo Caribe and the San Pedro tributaries in the present state of Campeche.120 Situated on the main river routes between the Gulf of Mexico and the Gulf of Honduras, Acalan was a focal point of trading. Its very name, derived from the Nahuatl acalli, means "the place of canoes." Since travel was mostly by canoe its settlements were probably near navigable waters.121 mm de Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 143 There is clear evidence here of the trader-ruler pattern. Scholes and Roys say in so many words that Acalan was ruled by "merchants," that |jř by what we have termed traders. They go on to say that the wealthiest of them, a lord named Poxbolonacha, was the supreme ruler of the entire province.122 The Acalan traders occupied a ward or quarter in Nito, on the ulf of Honduras, where they also had factors and warehouses. They likewise traded inland to the northeast with the Cehache and to the southeast in the region of the Itzas. Our authors write that Itzamkanae, the capital of Acalan, seems to have been an outlet for the commerce of the Sarstoon, Polochic and Montagua valleys, all of which were rich in cacao; and from its location n-e may well infer that there was also much trade with Chetumal and the v commercial centers of Northeastern Yucatan.123 It will be recalled that Cortés followed a map to Acalan which was given to him by traders of Xicalango. Itzamkanac witnessed a tragic episode, the execution of Cuauhtemoc. Cortés considered it perilous to leave Cuauhtemoc in Tenochtitlan in his absence, fearing that he would become the rallying point of an Indian insurrection. He thus took him and other Aztec rulers as prisoners on the march to Honduras in 1524 only to have them beheaded in Acalan. On approaching Itzamkanac, hungry and destitute on the march, Cortés and his men received canoes loaded with food from the Acalans. Upon his arriving at the town the ruler greeted him bearing gifts of honey, turkeys, maize, copal and fruit. Cortés described Itzamkanac is a large place with many temples, a rich and flourishing town. Yet he, as well as Bernal Dias and the later Dávila, fails to mention any market or market place. As we have seen from examining the ports Df trade, this is no longer surprising. Although markets may have been held for the local inhabitants, they were not necessary for the long distance trading and therefore they were probably either quite small or infrequently held. It was largely because of the enthusiastic reports of Cortés and other of his conquistadores praising Acalan as a prosperous and populous region, that the Adelantado of Yucatan, Montejo, planned in 1529 to use Acalan as a military base for his attack on the still unconquered peninsula of Yucatan. This same year, only five years after Cortés had passed through, Montejo sent his lieutenant Dávila to inspect the 144 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India region with this plan in mind. However, although Dávila describes Itzamkanac as having from nine hundred to a thousand very good buildings of stone and white stucco, he considered that it could not be used as a basis for military operations. His reasons were, in effect, that it was not as prosperous as both he and Montejo had been led to believe. Not only was it lacking in gold but the agricultural products were limited and its former thriving commerce had fallen away.124 In a lapse of only five years, from 1524 to 1529, Acalan had suffered a marked decline in its prosperity. Yet the Spaniards had not as yet attempted to subject the region to tribute. Nor had they, until Davila's arrival, established encomiendas. It is quite probable that the decline was due to the very rapid disintegration of the pre-hispanic trade structure. Even as an important trading center, Acalan may well have been merely a point of transit with little besides agriculture, copal gum and perhaps dyes of its own. The town must have been drastically affected by any lessening of the flow of goods from the far richer areas of Honduras and the Gulf of Mexico. The wealth of Acalan depended upon its strategic trade position between the two Gulfs. Once the network of trading relations was disturbed, its location made it highly vulnerable.125 As traders, the Acalans depended on the port. On their route to the Gulf of Honduras the traders of Acalan passed through the swampy region of the Itzas, who inhabited five islands in Lake Peten in what is now northern Guatemala. Their territory extended west to the Cehache and southward perhaps to the Rio de la Pasión. Here among the Itzas and in contrast to Acalan, the ruler was not a merchant or trader, rather he shared his rule with the high priests.126 The Itzas undoubtedly traded with Acalan and probably also with the Cehache, and the ports of trade on the Gulf of Honduras. Here, however, we can surmise that the lack of mention of the importance of traders is related to the fact that the ruler was closely allied to the priest. This obviously was not a port of trade area. Another province, known as Verapaz during the colonial period, and situated in western central Guatemala, was described by the chronicler Ximénez as having many markets and as being particularly important because it was a habitat of wild animals and birds, whose skins and feathers were a very important trade item. Despite these economic resources and the considerable commercial activity, there is no mention of native long-distance traders nor of any localities which might have been ports of trade.127 lie Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 145 The Mesoamerican ports of trade were specific localities, of typical Urganization and trade relations such as those of the two Gulf areas, li this context Acalan was not only a port of trade but also a com-munity of traders. polf of Honduras i The role of the Gulf of Honduras, to the south east of the broad gese of Yucatan, shows a startling functional similarity to the Xica-lango area on the Gulf of Mexico, described above (see map p. 118). Mven topographically the two coastal areas, left and right of the penin-lia present a symmetrical picture: in the Xicalango region there were, ||s we have seen, at least four long distance trading centers: Cimatan, He Chontalpa, Pontonchan and Xicalango, each closely related to riv-' eiain routes. In the Honduras region there were likewise at least four Bding centers, each in close proximity to the four large rivers: the Barstoon, the Rio Dulce and the inland Lake Izabal, the Montagua psd the Ulua. • Instead of a detailed presentation of the Honduran trading centers, jpe will conclude this chapter by listing significant resemblances between the two coastal regions, east and west of Yucatan, i.e., the Gulf of Honduras and the Gulf of Mexico. While this latter lay between Iffe Maya and Aztec main areas, the Gulf of Honduras represented a Jpk in the opposite direction, i.e., a trading bridge connecting Meso-jfjnerica with Central America. In either case—to conclude the argument—the essential resemblance of topographical traits and economic organization is apparent: 1. Topographically they are similar in that both are tropical coastal regions watered by a number of rivers whose basins lie in the inland sierras. Although the Gulf of Mexico area is more swampy, both were traveled almost exclusively, in pre-hispanic times, by canoe. This fact is relevant to trade and may also have been an important source of a demand for slaves as rowers. There was a need in both regions for slaves irhported from the Basin of Mexico and Yucatan. Slaves were probably $Iso used in the cacao "plantations." Scholes and Roys insist that cacao is unusually suited to slave labor in that it demands year round care.128 2. Both regions were among the largest cacao producers of the entire area under consideration. Alike, they lacked precious metals, Stones, feathers and obsidian. Yet they exported (i.e., re-exported) most 146 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India of these items, and all their exports, with the exception of their cacao, were brought down by canoe from the sierras. 3. Both Xicalango and Honduras imported not only slaves but also cloth, garments and ornaments of precious stones and metals from the Basin of Mexico and cloth as well as salt, honey and flint from Yucatan. 4. According to various authorities, a basic Maya linguistic and cultural affinity existed among the non-Nahua population all the way from the Copilco River on the Gulf of Mexico across to the Ulua River on the Gulf of Honduras.129 5. Of great interest is the parallel in the trading activities of the two regions under consideration. There are references stemming from the conquistadores testifying to the existence of factors and warehouses, both of which were notably lacking within the Aztec Empire proper as well as in Yucatan. In this context, the scattered Nahua settlements were undoubtedly very important for long distance trading with the Basin of Mexico. As in the Gulf of Mexico region, so likewise here in Honduras, did the trading routes converge from distant areas. The two regions were moreover linked through the Acalan and the Usuma-cintla river routes. 6. The Spaniards described both these regions as rich and populous during the first years of the conquest period. But their initial enthusiasms for them faded as little gold was found. The prosperity of either region was quickly undermined, as trade ceased. The early encomen-deros, harassed by insurrections, attacks, mute refusal of the Indians to pay tribute responded with cruel reprisals, and the flight of the natives into the as yet unconquered regions of the interior set in.130 Anne M. Chapman Notes to Chapter VII 1. The anthropologist Paul Kirchhoff (1952) first used the term Mesoamerica to define a culture area of central and southern Mexico and northern Central America. On the north it is bounded by the mouth of the Panuco River on the Gulf of Mexico, the Sinaloa River through to the mouth of the Lerma on the Pacific; to the south by the Montagua River on the Gulf of Honduras and extends further to the south to the Gulf of Nicoya on the Pacific. It refers to Indian cultures as they existed just prior to the Spanish conquest. The area is defined by the prevalence of certain diagnostic traits of high culture such as step pyramids, hieroglyphic writing, calendars of 365 and 260 days, specialized markets, trader spies and so forth. The "Viade Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 147 validity of Mesoamerica as a culture area has been amply confirmed by specialists in the fields of archaeology and ethnology. 2. The data on the Aztecs have been drawn principally from the great work of pay Bernardino de Sahagún, a Franciscan monk who arrived in New Spain in 1529. ► Versed in Nahuatl and a scholar of extraordinary merit, Sahagún may be described gs the first American ethnologist. Beginning in 1538 and for a period of several decades he wrote, in collaboration with Indian informants, the twelve books of the Jíistoria de las Cosas de Nueva Espana (Jimenez Moreno, 1938). Other early sources have been consulted but not exhausted. The.directly descriptive data have been given precedence over general statements. Modern studies ' ve been extensively used; outstanding among these is that of Acosta Saignes. 3. Barlow, 1949. 4. Cook and Simpson, 1948, pp. 27-28. 5. Barlow, 1949. 6-10. Until Bandelier published his three famous studies on the Aztecs in the 1870's (Bandelier, 1877, 1878, 1878a) their society had been, even in the empirical descriptions by very competent historians, considered comparable to feudal Europe. Randelier provoked a controversy which still has not ended by contending that here was a democratic egalitarian tribal society similar not to feudal Europe, but to the Iroquois of aboriginal North America. Since Bandelier, and especially in the last few decades, the Aztec society has been characterized as having a class structure iMoreno, 1931), as being a "tribal" society (Vaillant, 1950, ch. 6), as based on kinship relations in the from of stratified clans (Monzón, 1949, ch. 10), or, as seems most likely, as having a state structure (Caso, 1954). 11. Cortes, 1908, Second Letter, passim. 12. Prescott, n. d., p. 599. 13. McBryde, 1933, p. 110; Hendrichs, 1940-41, p. 193; Scholes and Roys, 1948, p. 165; Borah, 1951, p. 2; Tax and others, 1952, ch. 12. Gibson, 1952, pp. 190-194; Zavala and Miranda, 1954, passim; Borah, 1954, passim. 14. Cunow, 1926, Vol. I, pp. 275-78; Acosta Saignes, 1945, pp. 9-10. 15. Sahagún, 1946, Book 9, ch. 2. 16. Acosta Saignes (1945, p. 16) quotes Gonzalo Fernandez de Oviedo y Valdés, História general y natural de las índias, islas y tierra-firme del Mar Océano, 4 vols. Madrid, 1851-55). 17. Herrera y Tordesillas, n. d., decade 3, bk. 4, ch. 17; Veytia, 1826, pp. 227, 230, 232; Zurita, 1941, pp. 142,147-148. 18. Monzón, 1949, ch. 2. 19. Sahagún, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 6. 20. Herrera y Tordesillas, n. d., decade 3, bk. 4, ch. 17; Veytia, 1826, pp. 227, 230, 234; Suarez de Peralta, 1878, p. 21; Torquemada, 1943, Vol. 2, bk. 13, ch. 34; Sahagún, 1946, bk. 9, chs. 15-21; Caso, 1954, p. 24. 21. Sahagún, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 19. 22. Acosta Saignes, 1945, passim; Dahlgren de Jordan, 1954, pp. 246-49; Caso, 1954, p. 23. 23. Monzón, 1949, passim. 24. Cunow, 1926, Vol. 1, p. 278; Moreno, 1931, pp. 43-44; Vaillant, 1950, p. 122; Caso, 1954, p. 21. 25. Acosta Saignes, 1945, p. 21. 26. Herrera y Tordesillas, n. d., decade 3, bk. 2, ch. 17; Sahagún, 1946, bk. 9, chs. 3,6. 27. Sahagún, 1946, bk. 4, chs. 17-18; bk. 9, chs. 5,10-14. 148 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India \ JTrade Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 149 28. Ixtlilxochitl, 1891-92, Vol. 2, pp. 272, 279-81; Tezozomoc, 1944, chs. 27 23, 31, 33, 34, 37,75,78,88-92. 29. Acosta Saignes, 1945, pp. 10-11. 30. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 2. 31. Codex Mendoza, 1938, vol. I, p. 75. 32. Zurita, 1941, p. 142. 33. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 3. 34. Monz6n, 1949, passim. 35. Sime6n, 1885. 36. Sahagun, 1946, Bk 9, Ch. 3. 37. Ibid, bk. 9, chs. 3,10. 38. Ibid, bk. 9, chs. 4, 10. In one passage Sahagun calls them tealtianime and tecoanime, but otherwise refers to them simply as slave traders. These Nahuatl words are not found in Molina (1585) while Simeon (1885) defines them in the context of Sahagun. 39. Sime6n, 1885; Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 4. 40. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 2. 41. Tezozomoc, 1944, ch. 75. 42. Ibid, ch. 34. 43. Ibid., chs. 89-91. 44. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 5. 45. Molina, 1585. 46. Tezozomoc, 1944, chs. 75, 78. 47. Sime6n, 1885; Acosta Saignes, 1945, p. 13. 48. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 3. 48a. One of the few indications of how private profit splits off public service in trade. 49. Ibid, bk. 9, ch. 2. 50. Ibid,bk.9,ch. 3. 51. Ibid., bk. 9, ch. 10. 52. Torquemada, 1943, Vol. 2, bk. 14, ch. 17; Bosch Garcia, 1944, passim. 53. Cortds, 1908, Second Letter, passim; Conquistador An6nimo, 1941, pp. 43-44; Diaz del Castillo, 1947, ch. 92. 54. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, passim. 55. Ibid. 56. Ibid,bk.9,ch. 1. 57. Saville, 1920, pp. 102-3, 143, 187; Aguilar Piedra, 1946, passim; Lothrop, 1950, p. 76; Dahlgren de Jordan, 1954, pp. 138-140. 58. Lothrop, 1950, p. 87. 59. Herrera y Toresillas, n. d, decade 4, bk. 10, ch. 11. 60. Cervantes de Salazar, 1914, Vol. 1, p. 19; Torquemada, 1943, Vol. II, bk. 13, ch. 34; McBryde, 1945, p. 72, note 115; Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, chs. 18-21. 61. Suarez de Peralta, 1878, pp. 21, 166-67; Bastow, 1897, passim; Codex Mendoza, 1938, Vol. I, passim; Acosta, 1940, bk. 4, ch. 22; Torquemada, 1943, Vol. II, bk. 14, chs. 24, 33; Clavijero, 1945, Vol. I, bk. 1, ch. 9; Vol. II, bk. 7, ch. 36; Vol. 4, disertacion 6, no. 1. Clavijero is the only early source known to this writer who states that of the four known species of cacao, the smallest bean, the tlalcahuatl, was commonly used as ingredient for the drink while the other species were more often used as money. See also Bastow, 1897, p. 51. 62. Millon, 1955,ch. 10. 63. Ibid,ch.6. 64. Bastow, 1897, pp. 50-51; Acosta Saignes, 1945, p. 11; Clavijero, 1945, Vol. 2,bk. 7,ch. 36. 65. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 10. 66. Ibid, bk. 9, ch. 4. Translation A.M.C. 67. Ibid., bk. 9, ch. 3. 68-71. Ibid., bk. 9, ch. 6. Translation A. M. C. 72. Roys, 1939, pp. 60-1; Roys, 1943, p. 51; Chamberlain, 1948, pp. 47, 50-2. 73. Roys, 1943, pp. 51-2. 74. Tozzer, 1941, note 26; Chamberlain, 1948, pp. 47, 60-1, 100-1; Scholes and Roys, 1948, pp. 83-6. 75. Roys, 1943, p. 11. 76. Ibid,ch. 1. 77. Roys, 1939, p. 61. 78. Landa, 1941, p. 39. 79. Mendizabal, 1946-7, Vol. I, pp. 296-302, 317; Roys, 1943, ch. 8. 80. Roys, 1943, ch. 8. 81. Boekelman, 1935; Landa, 1941, pp. 94-7; Tozzer, 1941, notes 19, 23, 171, 415, 433; Roys, 1943, ch. 8; Thompson, 1954, pp. 21-2, 183-5. 82. Blom, 1932; Tozzer, 1941, notes 417, 418, 421; Chi, 1941, p. 231; McBryde, 1945, p. 84. 83. Chi, 1941, p. 231. 84. Blom, 1932; Thompson, 1929; Roys, 1943, ch. 8. 85. Roys, 1943, ch. 8. 86. Roys, 1943, p. 57; Scholes and Roys, 1948, p. 31. 87. Scholes and Roys, 1948, ch. 2. 88. Ibid., pp. 33-4. 89. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 4. 90. Ibid., bk. 9, chs. 4, 6. 91. Gage, 1929, p. 233. 92. Diaz del Castillo, 1947, ch. 45. 93. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 3. 94. Cooper Clark, 1938, Vol. 1, note on p. 95; Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 11; Barlow, 1949. 95. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 4. 96. Ibid.; Barlow, 1949, map. 97. Blom and LaFarge, 1926-27, Vol. 1, p. 68; Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 4; Scholes and Roys, 1948, p. 91. 98. Scholes and Roys, 1948, pp. 31-3, 318. 99. Ibid., p. 32. 100. Ibid., p. 32. 101. Ibid, pp. 24, 31-2. 102. Ibid, pp. 33-4, 36. 103. Ibid., 34-6. 104. Ixtlilxochitl, 1891-92, Vol. 2, p. 345; Cortes, 1908, Fifth Letter. 105. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 4. 106. Scholes and Roys, 1948, pp. 3, 57,93. 107. Roys, 1943, pp. 110-11. 108. Scholes and Roys, 1948, pp. 32, 39. 109. Gage, 1929, p. 167. 110. Roys, 1943, p. 107. 150 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India 111. Sahagun, 1946,bk. 9, ch. 5. 112. Barlow, 1949, map. 113. Kelly and Palerm, 1950, pp. 275-76. 114. Tezozomoc, 1944, ch. 78; Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 2. 115. Millon, 1955, chs. 3,10. 116. Sahagun, 1946, bk. 9, ch. 4. 117. Ibid., bk. 9, ch. 2. 118. Relación de Soconusco, 1882, pp. 426-27. 119. Lothrop, 1939, p. 44. 120. Scholes and Roys, 1948, p. 48. 121. Ibid, pp. 50-1. 122. Ibid, p. 4. 123. Ibid, p. 58. 124. Chamberlain, 1948, p. 88. 125. Scholes and Roys, 1948, p. 165. 126. Thompson, 1951. 127. Herrera y Tordesillas, n. d, decade 4, bk. 10, ch. 13; Relaciones ... de America Central, 1908, pp. 447-48; Ximenez, 1929-31, Vol. I, pp. 93-4. 128. Scholes and Roys, 1948, p. 29. 129. Ibid, pp. 3, 316-17; Chamberlain, 1948, p. 151; Stone, 1941, p. 15. 130. Scholes and Roys, 1948, ch. 5; Chamberlain, 1953, ch. 1. Bibliography to Chapter VII Acosta, José de, História natural y moral de las Indias. Mexico, 1940. Acosta Saignes, M, "Los Pochteca." Acta Antropológica, Vol. 1, no. 1, Mexico, 1945. Aguilar Piedra, C. H, "La orfebrería en el Mexico precortesiano." Acta Antropológica, Vol. 2, no. 2. Mexico, 1946. Bandelier, A. F, "On the art and mode of warfare of the ancient Mexicans." Peabody Museum. Harvard University, 10th Annual Report, 95-161. Cambridge, 1877. -, "On the distribution and tenure of lands, and customs of with respect to inheritance, among the ancient Mexicans." Peabody Museum, Harvard University, Uth Annual Report, 385^148. Cambridge, 1878. _, "On the social organization and mode of government of the ancient Mexicans." Peabody Museum, Harvard University, 11th Annual Report, 557-669. Cambridge, 1878a. Barlow, R. H, "The Extent of the Empire of the Culhua Mexica." Ibero-Ameri-cana, 28. Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1949. Bastow, J. W, "Comercio, moneda y cambio de los antiguos pueblos de Mexico." Congreso Internacionál de Americanistas, XI reunion; 47-63. Mexico, 1897. Berlin, H, "Relaciones precolombinas entre Cuba y Yucatan." Revista Mexičana de Estudios Antropologicas, nos. 1-2: 140-160. Mexico, 1940. Blom, F, and O. La Farge, Tribes and temples. A record of the expedition to Middle America conducted by Tulane University of Louisiana in 1925. 2 Vols. New Orleans, 1926-27. Blom, F, "Commerce, trade and montary units of the Maya." Middle American Research Series, No. 4: 531-566. Tulane University of Louisiana, New Orleans, 1932. Trade Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 151 Boekelman, H. J, "Ethno- and archeo-conchological notes on four Middle American shells." Maya Research, 2: 255-277. New Orleans, 1935. Borah, W, "New Spain's century of depression." Ibero-Americana, 35. Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1951. --, "Early colonial trade and navigation between Mexico and Peru." Ibero-Americana, 38. Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1954. Bosch Garcia, C, La esclavitud prehispanica entre los Aztecas. Mexico, 1944. Cjso, A, "Instituciones indigenas precortesianas." Memorias del Institute Nacional Indigenista, VI; 13-27. Mexico, 1954. Cervantes de Salazar, Francisco, Crönica de Nueva Espana. Madrid, 1914. Chamberlain, R. S, The conquest and colonization of Yucatan. 1517-1550. Carnegie Institute of Washington, Publication 582. Washington, 1948. --, The conquest and colonization of Honduras: 1502-1550. Carnegie Institute of Washington. Publication 598. Washington, 1953. ("hi, Gaspar Antonio, Relacidn. In Landa's Relacidn de las cosas de Yucatan. A translation edited with notes by A. M. Tozzer. Papers Peabody Museum. Harvard University, Vol. 18: 230-232. Cambridge, 1941. Clavigero, Francisco Javier, Historia antigua de Mexico. 4 Vols. Mexico, 1945. Codex Mendoza, A translation edited with notes by J. Cooper Clark. 3 Vols. London, 1938. Columbus, Ferdinand, The history of the life and actions of Admiral Christopher Colon. A General Collection of . . . Voyages and Travels. John Pinkerton edition, Vol. 12. London, 1812. Conquistador Anönimo, El, Rehciön de algunas cosas de la Nueva Espana y de la gran ciudad de Temestitan Mexico. Escrita por un companero de Hernan Cortes. Mexico, 1941. Cook, S. F. and L. B. Simpson, "The population of central Mexico in the sixteenth century." Ibero-Americana, 31. Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1948. Cooper Clark, J, See Codex Mendoza, 1938. Cortes, Hernan, Letters of Cortes; the five letters of relation to the Emperor Charles V. Translated and edited by F. A. MacNutt. 2 Vols. New York, 1908. Cunow, H, Allgemeine Wirtschaftsgeschichte. 4 Vols. Berlin, 1926. Dahlgren de Jordan, B, La Mixteca. Su cultura e historia prehispanicas. Mexico, 1954. Diaz del Castillo, Bernal, "Verdadera historia de los sucesos de la conquista de la Nueva-Espana." Historiadores primitivos de Indias. Vol. 2. Madrid, 1947. Gage, Thomas, A New Survey of the West Indies. 1648. New York, 1929. Gibson, C, "Tlaxcala in the sixteenth century." Yale Historical Publications, Miscellany LVI. New Haven, 1952. Hendrichs, P. R, "Datos sobre la tecnica minera prehispänica. Continuation." EI Mexico Antiguo, Vol. 5: 179-194. 1940-41. Herrera y Tordesillas, Antonio de, Historia general de Jos hechos de hs castillanos en las islas y tierra-ßrme del mar oceano. 10 Vols, recent re-issue of the 1726-30 edition. Editorial Guarania. Ascunciön del Paraguay, [n.d.] Ixtlilxochitl, Fernando del Alva, Obras histöricas de don Fernando del Alva Ixtlilxochitl. Edited by Alfredo Chavero. 2 Vols. Mexico, 1891-92. Jimenez Moreno, W, Fray Bernardino de Sahagun y su obra. Mexico, 1938. Kelly, I. and A. Palerm, The Ta/in Totonac. Part I. History, subsistance, shelter and technology. Smithsonian Institute, Institute of Social Anthropology, no. 13. Washington, 1950. 1 152 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India Kirchhoff, P., "Meso-America." In Heritage of Conquest. Edited by S. Tax: 17- 30. Glencoe, Illinois, 1952. Landa, Diego de, Landa's Relation de las cosas de Yucatan. A translation edited with notes by A. M. Tozzer. Papers, Peabody Museum, Harvard University, Vol. 18. Cambridge, 1941. Lothrop, S. K., "The Southeastern Frontier of the Maya." American Anthropologist, Vol. 41:42-45 (1939). -, Archaeology or Southern Veraguas, Panama. Memoirs, Peabody Museum, Harvard University, Vol. 9, no. 3. Cambridge, 1950. McBryde, F. W., SoloM. A Guatemalan town and Cakchiquel market-center. Middle American Research Series, no. 3 of pub. no. 5. Tulane University of Louisiana. New Orleans, 1933. -, Cultural and historical geography of southwest Guatemala. Smithsonian Institute, Institute of Social Anthropology, no. 4. Washington, 1945. Mendizábal, M. O. de, Obras completas. 6 Vols. Mexico, 1946-47. Milión, R. F., When money grew on trees. A study of cacao in ancient Mesoamerica. Ph.D. dissertation, unpublished. Columbia University. New York, 1955. Molina, Alonso de, Vocabulario de la lengua castellana y mexicana. Madrid, 1585. Monzón, A., El calpulli en la organization social de los Tenochca. Mexico, 1949. Moreno, M. M., La organization política y social de los Aztecas. Mexico, 1931. Morison, S. E., Admiral of the ocean sea. A life of Christopher Columbus. 2 Vols. Boston, 1942. Prescott, W. H., History of the conquest of Mexico and history of the conquest of Peru. The Modern Library. New York, n.d. Polanyi, K., Semantics of general economic history (revised). Council for Research in the Social Sciences, Columbia University. New York, 1953. Reíaciones históricas y geográficas de America Central. Edited by V. Suárez. Madrid, 1908. Relación de Soconusco. "(1574) Carta de D. Luis Ponce de León, gobernador de Soconusco...." In Fuentes y Guzman, História de Guatemala ó recordation florida. Vol. 1,423-428. Madrid, 1882. Roys, R. L., The titles of Ebtun. Carnegie Institute of Washington, Pub. 505. Washington, 1939. -, The Indian background of colonial Yucatan. Carnegie Institute of Washington, Pub. 548. Washington, 1943. -, See Scholes, F. V. and Roys, R. L. 1948. Sahagun, Bernardino de, História general de las cosas de Nueva Espana. Notes by M. Acosta Saignes, 3 Vols. Mexico, 1946. Saville, M. H., The Goldsmith's art in ancient Mexico. Indian Notes and Monographs. Museum of the American Indian, Heye Foundation. New York, 1920. Scholes, F. V. and R. L. Roys, The Maya Chontal Indians of Acalan-Tixchel: a contribution to the history and ethnography of the Yucatan Peninsula. Carnegie Institute of Washington. Pub. 560. Washington, 1948. Simeon, R., Dictionnaire de la langue Nahuatl ou Mexicaine. Paris, 1885. Stone, D. Z., "The Ulua Valley and Lake Yojoa." In The Maya and their Neighbors: 386-94. New York, 1940. -, Archaeology of the north coast of Honduras. Memoirs Peabody Museum, Harvard University, Vol. 9, no. 1. Cambridge, 1941. --, "Los grupos Mexicanos en la America Central y su importancia." Antropológia e História de Guatemala, Vol. 1, no. 1:43-46. Guatemala, 1949. í Ii í ff"rade Enclaves in Aztec and Maya Civilizations 153 [It.—-, "Una definition de dos culturas distintas vistas en la antropológia de la K. America Central." In Homenaje al Dr. Alfonso Caso: 3 5 3-61. Mexico, 1951. Katrong, W. D., "Anthropological problems in Central America." In The Maya and Ij their Neighbors: 377-85. New York, 1940. jjISoarez de Peralta, Juan, Noticias históricas de la Nueva Espana. Madrid, 1878. .Kax, S., And others, Heritage of Conquest, Glencoe, 111., 1952. ■p^Tezozomoc, Hernando Alvarado, Cronica Mexicana. Mexico, 1944. l- Thompson, J. E. S., "Comunicaciones y Comercio de los Antiguos Mayas." Anales de la Sociedad de Geografia e História de Guatemala, Vol. 6, no. 1: 40-44 'Vi (1929). I „-, "The Itza of Tayasal. Peten." In Homenaje al Dr. Alfonso Caso: 389-400. t Mexico, 1951. í —, The Rise and Fall of Maya Civilization. Norman, Oklahoma, 1954. I flrorquemada, Juan de, Veintíún libros rituales y monarquía Indiana. 3 Vols. Mexico, ft 194?- íjTozzer, A. M., See Landa, D. de. 1941. f'pullant, G. C, The Aztecs of Mexico. Penguin Books. 1950. M^eytia, Mariano, Tezcoco en los Ultimos tiempos de sus antiguos reyes 6 sea relación tornáda de los manuscritos inéditos de Boturini. Edited by Mariano Veytia. Mexico, 1826. Ximénez, Francisco, História de la provincia de San Vicente de Chiapa y Guatemala f de la orden predicadores. 3 Vols. Guatemala, 1929-31. Zavala, S. and J. Miranda, "Instituciones indígenas en la colonia." Memorias del Institute National índigenista, Vol. VI: 29-112. Mexico, 1954. Zurita, Alonso de, "Breve y sumaria relación de los senores ... en la Nueva Espaňa." In Relaciones de Texcoco y la Nueva Espaňa: 65-206. Mexico, 1941. VIII A Wort of Trade: Whydah on the Quinea Qoast it was in the course of inquiring into the commercial organization of eighteenth-century Whydah, historically known as the slave port of the Negro kingdom of Dahomey, that attention was first drawn to the subject of this chapter—the port of trade.1 Whydah was an organ of administered trade, a way of trading which appears as general from antiquity almost to the threshold of modern times.* The capacity of the port of trade for outlasting the millennia reflected the positive role played by that institution in resolving some of the less obvious problems of statecraft under archaic conditions, such as military requirements and protection against undesirable culture contact. In the institution of the port of trade, therefore, many strands meet, some deriving from the early state, some from even earlier primitive conditions. Apart from the military and cultural considerations which made the inland empires shun the coast, there was the position of the foreign trader, who refused to venture for the sake of commerce onto a strange and distant shore unless the safety of his person and goods was fairly assured. No one but the armed pirate could feel secure on a beach. Hence the combination of pirate and trader famed from the Odyssey. It was a long time before the neutrality of the trading place was ensured not by native weakness, as in silent trade, or around the mariners' altars on secluded beaches, but by the deliberate neutrality with which 154 Whydah, A Port of Trade on the Guinea Coast 155 f -v" ■ law and order enforced equal justice to all comers at the hand of port ■•V* authorities. Fear would drive out traffic. ife? The international status of the port of trade thus ran the gamut Rs. from a free port "in weak hands," as Whydah originally was, to a mere ■& port-town of an inland power administered from the distant capital as Eg* Whydah became under Dahoman rule after the conquest, in 1727. K& Since the last quarter of the seventeenth century Whydah was EC famed in the Western world as the port of call of the African slave |£» trade. In the beginning of the eighteenth century the small coastal .' kingdom that formed Whydah's immediate neighborhood was overrun [?.';• by the powerful inland state of Dahomey, which thus appeared in the hmelight of history. Whydah was incorporated in Dahomey, the capital p -f of which, Abomey, was some 150 miles removed from the coast. While | -" Whydah was frequented by the crews of the White slavers of many If nations, Abomey, secluded in the Dark Continent, remained inacces-(•;. sible to foreigners. Whydah, a flourishing port town, renowned in I distant countries, was never deemed worthy of the King of Daho-V mey's personal presence. Although a commercial emporium, no native I class interested in trade was in evidence. European observers were f sometimes baffled by the ambiguous status which this trading place held in Dahomey. An inquiry into the organization of trade in Whydah may then well start from the history of Dahomey, and the reasons which made it seize Whydah, and having done so, keep it at arm's length. Dahomey was one of the great Negro states of West Africa, an inland kingdom of some 300,000 population, heir to a political tradition k stemming from the empire-builders of the Western Sudan. For several hundred years, from the foundation of the kingdom, which legend places around 1625, until its conquest by the French in 1892, Dahomey was governed by the same dynasty of Negro kings and maintained its independence until borne down by overwhelming military forces. Eighteenth-century Dahomey had produced a planned economy of an advanced type, using trade, money and markets with sophistication. Viewed in historical perspective, this planned economy was a method of coping with the massive pressures which the external situation, the danger of foreign conquest, brought to bear upon Dahomey. Planning was a technique for survival, and the monarchy, the central planning organ, performed functions without which the society could not have 156 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India maintained its independent existence. Given Dahomey's situation, the organs of a tribal society would have been powerless. No loose tribal formation could have organized a sustained military effort on the scale required nor dealt effectively with the outside world through trade nor assured internal peace under the stresses and strains of permanent mobilization. A power transcending the tribal organs had to be called into being to meet the threat to the communal existence. The kings of the Alladoxonou dynasty created such a power and succeeded in welding the Dahoman peoples into an empire. Out of disunity and impotence, a military organization was created which Dahomey's neighbors were compelled to respect. Despite the strain which an annual war placed upon the resources of the country and its institutions, the well-being of the population was assured by an unquestionably efficient administration of the economy. And out of diverse traditions, a common tradition was forged, so deeprooted that it lives on among the people of Dahomey even today despite military conquest and a couple of generations of foreign rule.2 Yet Dahomey under the monarchy retained its tribal base—it was an empire built on tribal foundations. The traditions of the clan were the core values of Dahoman life, constitutive of the political community as of the tribal community. Far from disintegrating under the pressure of the throne, the clans of Dahomey remained as the basic social units and exercised indispensable functions in economic and political life. Even the monarchy appeared in the guise of the clan. The royal house ranked as the highest of the clans and the ancestors of the royal house were regarded as the ancestors of all Dahomans. As mediator between the living and the dead, the king's relationship to his people was that of head of a clan to its members—he was the link with the ancestors, high priest and chief magistrate, first among warriors, and guardian of the people's livelihood. While the king embodied the aristocratic virtues of a tribal chief, the democratic traditions of the tribal society were likewise perpetuated in the rights enjoyed by the clans, the villages, the gilds, and the innumerable voluntary associations—a charter of freedoms which was the keystone of Dahoman society. In adapting tribal institutions and traditions to the new circumstances created by political expansion, Dahomey produced that singular combination of centralization and decentralization, of authority and i^hydah, A Port of Trade on the Guinea Coast 157 lexibility, of controls and freedoms, which characterized its redistribu-tfve economy. War and Trade in Native Dahomey If a military policy was forced upon Dahomey in self-defense, this was no less true of its trade policy. The Dahomans were anything but a trading people. Their geographical position isolated them from trade. A glance at the map reveals that Dahomey stood well below the 12th parallel which marks the southernmost extension of the great trade routes of Africa. These well-worn tracks link the west-east flow of the middle Niger exclusively with the Moorish north and the Haussa country in the east. No roads whatsoever lead from the middle Niger to the western or southern coast.3 Though sheltered from the main approaches of trade, the Niger to the north and Guinea coast to the south, Dahomey could not remain entirely aloof from trade. Like the other Negro peoples of the interior, Dahomey was accustomed to fight only with bow and arrow. But once the Moors from the north had introduced firearms into the Sudan, and once the Europeans on the Guinea Coast were arming the coastal natives of the south with European muskets, those who knew only the bow and arrow were doomed to extinction or unending flight. Dahomey was caught between two fires. Trade with the Europeans at Whydah had become essential since it was this trade, as the Dahomans themselves said, which "brings guns and powder to Dahomey." So crucial was the control of the trade that Dahomey permitted guns and powder to move inland only to those border peoples who had certified their friendship by alliance with Dahomey. "The Mahee," Duncan says of the northern neighbors of Dahomey, "use the bow and arrow, the King of Dahomey forbidding the transport of firearms through his kingdom from the coast."4 Yet trade with the Europeans at Whydah—literally a condition for survival—raised at the same time the gravest threat to Dahomey's security. Dahomey was a passive trader, maintaining, herself, no organization for active trade over long distances. While there are a few reports of trading parties sent into the interior, the meagerness of these reports suggests that active trade was the exception rather than the rule. As a passive trader, however, dependent upon supplies brought by others 158 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India from afar, Dahomey would be exposed to all the dangers involved in letting down the gates to the foreigner. Without a counter-organization for trade, by which the movements of foreigners and their goods could be regulated in conformity with the requirements of state, Dahomey would stand defenseless before a dual enemy: her hostile neighbors, and the strangers come to trade. Herein lies the explanation of Dahomey's policy toward Whydah. So long as Dahomey's access to the port was secure, Dahomey was content to leave Whydah in the hands of the Whydasians. Dahoman traders, it seems, had been accustomed to come freely to Whydah for some time before 1727 when Whydah passed to Dahomey.5 Such a relationship permitted Dahomey to secure the essential trade goods and yet remain aloof from the foreigner in her inland retreat. What, then, prompted Dahomey to change her policy and take Whydah by force in 1727? This question was the subject of considerable controversy among the Europeans who witnessed the event. Norris, upholding the viewpoint that Dahomey's commercial interests were the motivating factor, commented as follows: I knew many of the old Whydasians as well as Dahomans who were present when Trudo attacked that kingdom. They attributed his enterprize solely to the desire of extending his dominions, and of enjoying at first hand, those commodities which he had been used to purchase of the Whydasians. . . .6 Herskovits follows this interpretation, affirming that the principal reason why Agadja was eager to conquer his way to the sea-coast was that... the transportation of goods through the kingdoms of Whydah and Ardra took from him a large proportion of his profits from slaving, and greatly increased the price of European goods which he received in exchange for the proceeds from slaves.7 And, further, that the conquest of Whydah gained for Agadja the right to sell his slaves directly to the captains of the slave vessels who called at the port, and from them to get, without paying the duties imposed by an intervening power, the European goods he valued so highly.8 These views are hardly consistent with the. facts. Whatever their varying interpretations of the event, contemporary witnesses agreed as to the facts, and the most significant fact was that the king of Whydah 6 7hydah, A Port of Trade on the Guinea Coast 159 ?Jad closed the port to traders from Dahomey. Norris says that the Dahoman king, Trudo, liad solicited permission from the king of Whydah to enjoy free commercial ^passage through his country to the sea side, on condition of paying the usual Icustom upon slaves exported; this was peremptorily refused by the king of 'AVhydah; and in consequence of this refusal, Trudo determined to obtain his purpose by force of arms... .9 Likewise, Snelgrave confirms that Dahomey ' sent an Ambasasdor to the King of Whidaw, requesting to have an open ■ Traffick to the Sea side, and offering to pay him his usual Customs on Negroes exported: which being refused, he from that time resolved to resent it, when Opportunity offered. Furthermore, the king of Whydah, after refusing Dahomey's request, told Snelgrave that if the King of Dahome should offer to invade him, he would not use him when taken according to their Custom, that is, cut off his Head, but would keep him for a Slave to do the vilest Offices.10 Atkins suggests that there were further provocations against Dahomey. "The king of Dahomey," he says, was probably incited to the Conquest from the generous Motive of redeeming his own, and the neighbouring Country People from those cruel Wars, and Slavery that was continually imposed on them by these Snakes (Whydasians) and the King of Ardra; ... against those in particular, his Resentments were fired: First, on account of their public Robberies, and Man-stealing, even to his Dominions; and Secondly, That Contempt the King , of Whydah had expressed towards him... .n There is, then, no question of Dahomey's attempting to evade payment of the duties upon the trade since the king offers to pay Whydah "his usual Customs on Negroes exported." And indeed, the first step taken by Dahomey after its capture of Whydah was to reduce the customs to one half those fixed previously by the king of Whydah.12 Instead, there was a security problem of the first order. Dahomey was being denied access to the Coast and the opportunity to secure firearms, while the public insult to Dahomey proffered by the king of Whydah could not be overlooked without grave damage to Dahomey's position. We may recall, moreover, that Dahomey was at this time under tremendous pressure from the Oyo, having suffered one invasion and standing in dread of another. Indeed, it seems likely that the taking 160 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India of Whydah was regarded by Dahomey as a counter-move against the Oyo. During the first Oyo invasion, according to Snelgrave, the Daho-mans had "comforted themselves with this Thought," that, in the event of a second invasion they might save their Persons, by flying to the Sea Coast, to which the J-oes durst not follow them. For as their national Fetiche was the Sea, they were prohibited by their Priests from ever seeing it, under no less a Penalty than Death.13 It may well be, then, that an outlet to the seaside was contemplated as an avenue of retreat from the Oyo. For the ultimate preserve of the "fugitive" peoples were the lagoons of the tropical coast. Under these circumstances, it was only by placing Whydah in its own hands that Dahomey could secure access to the coast and guarantee the neutrality of the place of trade. The compelling urgency of such a move is underlined by the subsequent difficulties which it encountered in holding the port. The intrigues of the coastal peoples, spurred on intermittently by various European governors, were, for a time, a recurring threat to Dahomey's hold upon the trade—all the more since Oyo was also seeking to establish trade relationships with the coast. At any rate, by the end of the century, Oyo had succeeded in wresting control from Dahomey of the neighboring kingdom of Ardra and its port, Jaquin, or Porto Novo, so that the Oyo were in a position to close off the coast entirely unless Dahomey was securely in possession of its own port. The threat was a very real one. At one time, Dalzel says, The King of Ardrah . . . stopped all communication with Whydah. The messengers from Porto Novo were no longer seen at the King of Dahomey's Customs; and the Dahoman traders, who had been accustomed to visit Ardrah, were no more allowed that liberty.14 When Dahomey protested this action, even sending an expedition against Porto Novo, the king of Oyo replied with the warning that Dahomey should undertake no further offensive actions against Ardra, since "Ardra was Eyeo's callabash, out of which nobody should be permitted to eat but himself.15 Far from looking upon Whydah as a source of commercial gain, then, Dahomey regarded the acquisition of Whydah as a security measure. The Dahoman attitude toward Whydah was that of an inland people who abhor the foreigner-infected coast and its cosmopolitan activities, but who are forced to maintain contact because of im- TWhydah, A Port of Trade on the Guinea Coast 161 stive military considerations.16 In short, the port of trade was a tbility, not a source of profit. Only this interpretation is consistent with the well attested massive fact that Dahomey, on more than one occasion, offered to cede Why-- dah to the British. The most complete account of such negotiations is that given by Duncan to whom the king expressed his earnest desire to give up Whydah to the English Government, with full powers to exercise our own laws and customs; . . . [and] to afford us every necessary assistance and protection, and to give us any ... quantity : of land in the vicinity of that settlement we might require for agricultural s jtirposes.17 [ Nothing could more definitely indicate Dahomey's noncommercial interests in Whydah than this offer to turn it over to the English crown. Moreover, this offer explicitly commits the king to the abolition of the slave traffic as well. "When we (i.e., the English) should have obtained possession of Whydah," the king goes on to say to Duncan, "we should have power to use our own discretion respecting the Slave-trade; and that ... we could with much more propriety exert our authority to prevent slave traffic than he himself." And again, "He said he should be ready and very glad to make any reasonable arrangement with the English Government for the abolition of slavery, and the establishment of another trade."18 The king is evidently concerned to place the port of trade in the lunds of a superlatively strong power. "He had, he said, refused possession of Whydah to the Prince de Joinville, stating his determination ti) treat with none but the Queen of England, who was the greatest of all white sovereigns."19 The port of trade must be in the hands of a power strong enough to guarantee its neutrality even against the other powers and itself a power that is friendly to Dahomey and committed by treaty to respect her interests. This would be a solution to the vexing problem of the port of trade. There can be no doubt that the king regarded such a solution as preferable to continued possession of the port by Dahomey herself. This offer, surprising as it may seem, represents Dahoman policy at the highest level. When the discussion with Duncan is concluded, Duncan reports, the king himself "dictated to me a letter to the Secretary of State for the Colonies, in which he formally ceded Whydah to the English Government... and when he found it satisfactory, he held the upper end of the pen while I signed his name."20 162 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India Again, some twenty years later, Commander Wilmot, meeting with the king in 1863, remarks "the friendly disposition evinced by the King towards the English," and quotes the monarch as saying: "From hence forth the King of Dahomey and the Queen of England are one; you shall hold the tail of the kingdom, and I will take the head"; meaning that we should have possession of Whydah for trading purposes, and supply him with everything.21 For Dahomey, then, war and trade were not commercial activities but conditions for survival. It is only in these terms that the economv and the society become intelligible. To misread war and trade as commercial activities is to distort beyond recognition the organs and techniques which Dahomey developed to cope with the conditions of existence imposed by its environment. Remote Control of Whydah For Dahomey, the creation of the port of trade at Whydah was the solution to a problem that might well have seemed insoluble. Here was Aristotle's dilemma concerning the Piraeus aggravated by manifold complications.22 If neutrality demanded the admittance of all comers to the port of trade, it also demanded the isolation of the por. else how were the foreigners, both European and African, to be pr< -vented from intriguing against Dahomey and interfering in Dahoman affairs? At the same time isolation could not signify a hands-off policy. There was need for a strong hand at Whydah to keep the flotsam and jetsam population of a port town in check and to compel respect for life and property so that trade would be secure. Yet how was Dahomey, supremely indifferent as she was to maritime commerce and its concerns, to exercise a strong hand and achieve an efficient administration of the port without shifting the very axis of her existence? The dilemma was all the more complex in that trade and war imposed incompatible conditions, yet both were essential to Dahomey's survival. A regular trade was impossible except under peaceful conditions, yet war was no less a necessary condition for trade, since it provided the captives without which Dahomey could not trade at all. One aspect of the matter is revealed in the comments of those experienced Guinea traders, Snelgrave and Barbot. Snelgrave observes that for some 1 w fflhydah, A Port of Trade on the Guinea Coast 163 i&ne after the capture of Whydah by Dahomey, "the Trade ... is almost ruined; for the far Inland People having now no Markets to carry ' fheir Slaves to, as formerly, and the Dahomes using no Trade but that B War, few Negroes are now brought down to be sold to the Euro-fans." This war between Dahomey and Whydah had not only dis-3j[ organized the ordinary channels of trade and closed off the trade routes, fifcut there was as well a "great Destruction of the Inhabitants of the neighbouring Countries, who used to carry on a regular Trade with the ma Inland People."23 Obviously, trade could not operate under such Ksturbed conditions. On the other hand, peace might be equally dis-iprptive of trade in so far as it cut off the supply of slaves. As Barbot ■omplains: "In the year 1682,1 could get but very few (slaves) because there was at that time almost a general peace among the Blacks along Í0' the coast."24 Certainly Dahomey would have to find a way of separating "■' war and trade so that the captives could be supplied to Whydah with-y©ut embroiling the traders in military affairs and disrupting the peace pf the port of trade. I Small wonder that Dahomey desired to avoid the problem of Why-jjjah altogether. It was this attitude which explains, as we have seen, She repeated offers by the kings of Dahomey to cede Whydah to the English and thus to be relieved of the responsibility for its administration. Certainly it is striking that none of the kings of Dahomey was ever known to set foot in Whydah, even the conquest of Whydah |§eing accomplished with the king remaining at a distance, in war encampment some miles outside of the town. Whydah was beyond the pale, and the Whydasians themselves an irritant in the body politic. On numerous occasions, the king displayed his contempt for these coastal people—a people of different stock, professing a strange religion, and worst of all, corrupted by trade with the foreigner.25 To Norris, who pleaded with the king to spare the lives of the Whydasians taken by the Dahomans, in the assault upon Whydah, the king replied as follows: |,.. it would be setting a bad example, and keeping people in the country, who might hold seditious language; that his was a peculiar government, and that these strangers [my italics] might prejudice his people against it, and infect them with sentiments incompatible with it.28 And, Duncan, setting off for the Kong Mountains, found that his Whydah carriers were put under the Dahoman captain of the guard, to 164 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India whom the king had given "strict orders to watch them narrowly, on account of their thievish propensities." Yet the problem of Whydah could not be avoided. The trade was essential to Dahomey and the hostility of the Whydasians left no alternative but to take over the port. Dahomey's conflict of interests was reconciled by an indirect administration of the port, a system of remote control as it were, which protected the trade while keeping trade and traders at a safe distance. Foreigners' Enclave It was the distinctive characteristic of the port of trade that trade was open to all comers from the European side. It was an alien enclave. In contrast with the trading settlements of the European companies which sought to exclude the interlopers, Whydah "... was a free Port of all the Guinea Coast for the Slave Trade."27 While the French, Portuguese, and English maintained permanent factories at Whydah, the king gave permission to trade to all ships: "Chaque navire qui arrive ici pour faire le commerce, ouvre une factorie et fait ses affaires lui-meme. Pour ce privilege, il paie au roi. . . ."28 Such a policy of "free trade" would seem to serve Dahomey's trade advantage, yet there was more than this involved. A grant of exclusive privileges to one European nation carried grave risks, as is hinted in Barbot's remarks about Bissos: I took notice of a grant made by the Black king of Bissos to the Portuguese, to trade and settle there, exclusive of all other Europeans; but not long after, the natives observing, that the Portuguese had built a fort with eight guns, oppos'd their design of ingrossing the whole trade of their island, and laid it open to all strangers resorting to their ports; who may carry on their commerce there with all imaginable safety, and without apprehending any insult, if they offer none.29 Opening the port to all comers was thus the only way to keep the peace and void the disastrous trade rivalries among the Europeans which, at other points along the Coast where the Europeans were settled, had ruined the trade and involved the natives in sanguinary wars.29 From the standpoint of Dahomey's strategic political interests, the neutrality of the port of trade had to be assured, and Dahomey sought safety in numbers. ydah, A Port of Trade on the Guinea Coast 165 The inland position of Whydah made it possible to regulate the Te more effectively than at other places on the Guinea Coast where ;de was conducted in the coastal settlements of the chartered complies or on board ship. With the first sighting of a vessel off Whydah, the port authorities ipt into action. As soon as ships were sighted in the road, porters re sent from the town to assist in the landing. No goods or men juld be disembarked in that forbidding surf without assistance, and t a move could be made by the traders without the full glare of blicity. As each ship arrived, an official party from the town, consist-ag of the Viceroy of Whydah, the local lords, and their armed escort, eeted the traders at the famous place of reception outside the town, "Captain's Tree." Since the town of Whydah was some two miles m the beach, goods were stored temporarily in buildings on the ach and porters were appointed by the authorities to haul the goods land to the factories or to other places in town set aside for the foreigners. Carrying was completely in the hands of the natives and no goods moved inland until the terms of trade were negotiated with the authorities—"This regulation being agreed on by the king and the factors," as Barbot relates, "the goods are brought ashore, and carried on men's backs to the French house____"31 While residing in the town, the traders were provided with servants, carriers, and other attendants by the native "head men" who had the disposal over labor. Fresh provisions for ships' crews and the daily table were procured on the local market at Whydah; at other places along the Coast provisions might likewise be secured in the markets, or, as was often the case, supplied to the traders by the natives under treaty arrangements. These physical facilities provided for the foreigners by the port authority served a dual purpose: they safeguarded the traders' person and property, while at the same time making any evasion of the regulations well-nigh impossible. Whydah was administered as a "White Man's Town," sealed off from Dahomey proper, and under the jurisdiction of resident officials. The immediate administration of Whydah was left in the hands of the Viceroy of Whydah appointed by the king—the Yevogan or "White Man's Captain," a title stemming from the pre-Dahoman period. In accordance with the customary Dahoman policy toward territories incorporated into the kingdom, Whydah was permitted to retain many of its previous customs, including the indigenous snake worship, and 166 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India -1 the traditions of administration stemming from the days of Whydasian rule were carried over under the Dahoman regime. The administrative personnel was changed, however, since the Whydasians had resisted Dahoman authority, although in other cases where submission to Dahomey was voluntarily tendered, local rulers were permitted to continue in power. The affairs of Whydah were conducted by the Viceroy \ and his staff, with trade matters directly under the supervision of the Chacha and the other trade officials appointed by the king. The Europeans at Whydah enjoyed certain extraterritorial privileges. Each of the European factories, with its surrounding nati\e settlement, constituted a separate quarter of Whydah. Each quarter had its own governor, usually of European nationality, though under the general supervision of the Viceroy of Whydah, and the natives of the settlement were placed at the service of the Europeans. In Burton s time, there were four such European quarters: French Town; Brazilian Town; English Town; and Portuguese Town.32 The European traders at Whydah were the "King's Men" and their factories the "King's Houses" so that any offense against the person of the traders or their places of trade constituted an affront lo the monarch himself. Any native caught stealing from them would be put to death. If the king "were requested to take cognizance of any case of robbery of a white man, the robber would certainly lose his head," Duncan comments, adding, however, that ". . . the King of Dahomey not wishing to interfere with white people's affairs, and the merchants being too humane to urge the King's interference," the law might not be strictly enforced.33 While the Europeans enjoyed the rights to practice their own religion, their factories were protected by native fetishes, the English fort, as Burton observed, having two fetishes, called the "Defenders of White Men."34 While Burton was scandalized that native fetish ceremonies were performed at the factory, it is obvious that the fetish put the peace of the place of trade under sacral sanctions. The purpose to be served was the same that made Alexander the Great enjoin Cleomenes to have two temples to deified Hephaistion erected in the confines of the future Alexandria, prospective port of trade of the Hellenic oecumene.* Whydah enjoyed considerable autonomy so long as the law was observed. The king rarely interfered with the local administration, yet * See above, pp. 60-1. fhydah, A Port of Trade on the Guinea Coast 167 pay bad report should reach the capital, a royal messenger forthwith |cended upon the town and the local authorities trembled. While | Viceroy was "judge and jury" in Whydah, only the king wielded % power of life and death, and all cases involving the death penalty are handled by the king's court at Abomey. The dual sets of officials, Bete as elsewhere throughout Dahomey, provided a check upon il-Bgitimate extensions of power. The Chacha and the superintendents Hp trade "attended all conferences," Forbes says, "reporting directly to Wme king any infringement of the royal prerogative," and acting as apolitical spies" upon the Viceroy and the local administration.35 if- The Europeans were left to their own affairs so long as they did not " violate the regulations, but the king's justice was swiftly visited upon ■hose who infringed the law. Twice, the governors of the French forts prere expelled from Whydah, in one case "upon the charge of having Bold contraband articles to the enemies of Dahomey," and the governor m the English fort, in the days of Trudo, was put to death by the king jbr insults to Dahomey.36 I. The royal justice, severe as it might be, was effective in maintaining jjaw and order in Whydah. In pre-Dahoman Whydah, the white traders Iliad often complained of the "impositions of great Men" and the ffhievery of the natives, while the common people of Whydah, as elsewhere throughout the kingdom, might find the king their only succor against the oppression of their native lords or the Europeans. Upon *. first meeting with the king of Dahomey immediately after the conquest of Whydah, Snelgrave urged the king That the best way to make Trade flourish, was to impose easy Customs, and to protect us from the Thievery of the Natives, and the impositions of great Men which the King of Whidaw not doing, greatly hurt the Trade. For the ill usage the Europeans had met with of late from him and his People, had caused them to send fewer Ships than formerly they did. The king responded sympathetically, saying that He designed to make Trade flourish; and I might depend upon it, he would prevent all Impositions, and Thievery, and protect the Europeans that came '. to his Country. . . ,37 Duncan testifies to the king's justice when he remarks that During my stay at Abomey, I was never asked by any individual for an article of even the most trifling value, nor ever lost anything, except what was stolen by my people from the coast. The Dahoman laws are certainly severe, but they have the desired effect.38 168 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India How necessary these safeguards were to the security of the realm and how real the threat of oppression by upstart local lords is illustrated by the story of Tanga, Viceroy of Whydah, which is related by N< irn\ »• Tanga, appointed by the king to his post, was an ambitious man and sought to make himself king of Whydah. He acquired a large body of retainers, "attached to his person by his liberality" and by the protection he afforded them "in their villainies" against the king's law. "] ]js oppressions rendered him odious to the garrison at the fort" as well, Norris adds. The European governors at Whydah, on the way to Abomey to lodge a protest with the king against the exactions of ■ he Viceroy, were intercepted by Tanga and imprisoned. Learning of Tanga's attempt to take the English fort by stratagem, the king declared him a traitor, set a price upon his head, and sent troops against him. Besieged in the house, which he had fortified against the king's troops, and surrounded by his hundreds of wives and the retainers whose loyalty he had secured by a reckless distribution of treasure, Tanga finally met his death. Administered Trade In pre-Dahoman Whydah, prices, as well as all other terms, had been negotiated with the king before any transactions could take place. The king "fixes the price of every sort of European goods, as also of slaves," Barbot tells us, "which is to stand betwixt his subjects and foreigners; and therefore no European must go there to trade, without waiting on him before he presumes to buy or sell." After the terms were agreed upon and the king's customs paid, Barbot goes on to say, "the factor has full liberty to trade, which is proclaimed throughout the country by the king's cryer."40 Under Dahoman rule, the same principles applied but general administrative regulations replaced separate treaty negotiations. Equivalencies were fixed by law and administered by the king's officials resident at Whydah. "The cha-cha is the principal agent to the king in all matters of trade," Forbes says, and to him must be subjected all commerce, whether in slaves or palm-oil, that he may have the refusal. The price is laid down by law, subject to his alteration if concurred in by the viceroy and six traders or superintendents of trade appointed by the king. . . . One or the other of these must be present at all sales to take the royal duty. . . dah, A Port of Trade on the Guinea Coast 169 This indirect administration of Whydah provided the necessary rds for trade while at the same time serving to isolate Whydah Its affairs from Dahomey proper. The policy of isolation was carried her in a series of measures which barred foreigners and their trade the interior of the country and placed the organization of in-1 trade exclusively in Dahoman hands. In laying drastic restrictions upon the movements of the Euro-,n traders, Dahoman policy was animated by considerations similar those reported of the neighboring kingdom of Ardra: "... we com-ly travel only by night," Barbot says of Ardra, Jess we be in company of the prince, or of some very notable men of the jrt, when we can travel by day; but the political Blacks carry us then ng by-roads, and never through any town or village . . . and alledge, that s a positive order from the government so to do, that no strangers may erve the disposition of the country, and the nature and situation of s.42 leaders, of course, were always regarded as spies, and it was standard procedure for a native kingdom, contemplating a military operation, to tend spies into the territory of the enemy disguised as traders. Even jpithout these policy deterrents, however, the Europeans could not get ' very far inland. Of the Gold Coast, Barbot says: > None of the Europeans dwelling along the coast [have] even ventured far ' up the land . . . what account can be given of it, is taken from the most intelligent Blacks, particularly as to the remotest countries, it being extraordinarily difficult and dangerous, if not altogether impossible, for Europeans to venture so far into such wild savage countries.43 As for Whydah, no movements outside the town could be made without the permission of the authorities. Along the lagoons which ring the town, ferrymen were stationed, as Duncan reports, to inspect all passes or permits obtained from the [king's minister] of Whydah to persons leaving the port, specifying the number of people wishing to proceed by canoe for any other place on the lagoon.44 The efficiency of the system was remarkable; in one instance, a whole party was turned back because one person had been included for whom no authorization had been received from the Viceroy. Europeans might go inland only with the permission of the king—"I say permission," Forbes remarks, "for such it is, as travelling is not allowed in Dahomey without a passport, in the shape of his Majesty's stick." Such permis- 170 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; In$u: sion was usually granted on state occasions, as for example, when th* invitations were issued to the Europeans to attend the Annual Customs at Abomey. All travelers moved under escorts provided by the king and under the protection of the "King's Stick."45 As the "King's Strangers," they were isolated from the local population and hosteled in special way-stations provided for travelers along the road to Abomey. There was another reason, of course, for the safeguards surrounding the traveler. As a foreigner, he stood under the protection of the king, and any accident would be a fateful matter, as Burton suggests in the following comment: The late king relaxed the usual Dahoman severity in matter of ingress, giving escorts to Dr. Dickson . . . and to Mr. Duncan. . . . His son, on the contrary, has shut up all the roads.... He promised that, on my return, I should penetrate into the mountain-land; pleaded want of time and troops, and consoled me by the suggestion that I was too important a personage to be risked in the bush. This was not wholly "blarney"; any accident to the "King's Stranger" would be looked upon as a dire and portentous occur- rence. 46 If the Europeans were barred from the interior as a security measure, similar considerations prompted restrictions on the movements ol native traders from neighboring states. While the king of Whydah in pre-Dahoman times had admitted the Mahee, Nagoes, Oyo, and other traders from inland countries to the port, Dahomey apparently reversed this policy. Under the Dahoman regime, these traders from inland were refused passage through Dahoman territory, the port of trade was closed to them, and the European traders at Whydah wen-permitted to deal directly only with the Dahomans themselves. Snel-grave visited Whydah immediately after its capture by Dahomey and observed that "the far Inland People [have] now no Markets to carry their Slaves to, as formerly."47 And Norris remarks that the slaves offered for sale by the Mahee and other inland traders "are disposed of to the factors of Dahomey."48 The reasons for such a policy are implied in the account given by Dalzel of the actions of Adahoonzou: In consequence of the failure of some of his expeditions, the King took it into his head, that it was owing to the intrigues of aliens residing in his dominions. He therefore ordered the Gongong to be beat; giving warning to all strangers, Eyeos excepted, immediately to quit the kingdom; alledging, that whenever any expedition was on foot, his designs were by them communicated to the enemy. ... Hah, A Port of Trade on the Guinea Coast 171 additional reason for precautionary measures against foreigners of Se was the danger of military supplies falling into their hands, Ids, powder, and iron [being] articles forbidden to be dealt in by lagers in Dahomey." As a result of the king's decree, Dalzel adds, |e Mahees, Nagoes, and other inland merchants .. . [came] no more augh the Dahoman dominions."48 iThe interior was thus closed off, both to the native traders on iomey's borders and to the Europeans at Whydah. In contrast with . situation elsewhere along the Coast, Dahomey did not permit the Ipuropeans settled on the Coast to send agents to inland places of trade, Kjr even to meet face-to-face with caravans of traders from the interior jjfcoming to the Coast to trade, as was the case on the Gold Coast. The Igi^opeans were completely excluded from trade within Dahomey gSfroper and from any direct trade relations with the countries farther 'Finland. They were permitted to meet face-to-face in trade only with the iSPahoman traders and within the confines of the port of trade at Why-^&h. IBy such measures, Dahomey was sealed off from the foreigner and je handling of trade goods within the country was kept entirely in ahoman hands. Such a policy was clearly not dictated by considerations of "monopoly profit" but by vital political interests. If we take a look at the character of Dahomey's trade goods, we see clearly the political interest which motivated trade policy and made necessary the rigorous restrictions on the movement of goods in trade. Dahomey's exports were slaves and palm-oil, the latter becoming of importance, however, only with the decline of the slave trade in the nineteenth century. Since slaves were enemies taken captive in war or criminals condemned by law, they constituted a menace to domestic security and it was inconceivable that they should be permitted to move throughout the country without adequate safeguards. As the king protested to Governor Abson, should these enemies be left free "to cut the throats of my subjects?" Slaves were elite goods, moreover, and their movements were restricted on this account as well. In principle, all slaves belonged to the king, as was the case with all property in Dahomey, and the king's subjects held slaves only by his leave. To own slaves was a privilege limited to persons of rank, and to trade in slaves was a prerogative of status, "licence to trade" being in effect contingent upon receiving an endowment in slaves from the hand of the king. As elite goods, slaves carried high political significance. Da- 172 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; IndM homey paid tribute in slaves to the king of Oyo, and slaves were tre-1 quently presented by the king of Dahomey to visiting foreign emiV I saries as a matter of diplomatic etiquette, as well as to the nobles of his own court. From start to finish, then, the handling of slaves was an operation subject to meticulous controls and one from which outsiders were I completely barred. Slaves were "collected" in war, obviously an opera-1 tion at the highest levels of state in which strangers had no part. Or, if I slaves were "collected" by purchase from inland merchants, they passed I at once into Dahoman custody, as we have seen. All dispositions or I transfers of slaves were matters of public record. The captives taken in I war were ceremonially presented to the king at the Annual Customs, a I count being kept in cowries of the number of captives thus presented, I and thereafter the king might make a ceremonial award of some of I lie \ captives to the nobles of his court or to soldiers who had distinguished ' themselves in combat. Such awards were acts of state and immediafclv ! publicized. A witness who was present when the Dahoman army returned from a campaign with prisoners of war reports that: As soon as any person had a Slave presented to them, a proper Officer made Proclamation of it, which was immediately echoed by the Populace, who i were waiting in great numbers at the King's Gate for the Sacrifices.50 The slaves received as gifts from the king's hand could be disposed of thereafter by the owners only with the royal permission. While the caboceers who led their own armies into the field were entitled to keep the captives taken by their soldiers, "the caboceers always pay a nominal duty upon all slaves taken in war when sold."51 Such a tax must have served as a device for keeping record as well as a source of revenue for the king. When the slaves were turned over to the Europeans at Whydah, the transfer was subject to rigorous supervision. The confinement of the Europeans to Whydah made it easier to exercise control since all transactions between natives and Europeans could take place only in the authorized trading places in the European quarters where full publicity attended transactions and a close watch was kept on the handling of goods. Here is how the slaves passed from native hands to European hands: When these slaves come to Fida, they are put in Prison all together, and when we treat concerning buying them, they are all brought out together ydah, A Port of Trade on the Guinea Coast 173 fL ]zige Plain; .. . When we have agreed with the Owners of the Slaves, |y are returned to their Prison; where from that time forwards they are j|--at our charge. ... So that to save Charges we send them on Board p Ships with the very first Opportunity.52 cedures had changed somewhat a hundred years later but the safe-rds were no less rigorous: is courtiers, vont tous les matins par toute la ville, demander a chaque mgociant, s'il lui est arrive des esclaves. lis le font savoir au facteur qui va iSp/ec eux, la measure a la main, dans la maison de ces negocians noirs, voi «|§ esclaves, & s'ils lui conviennent, il les achete, donne une specification £•$ marchandises d'^change dont ils sont convenus, & imprime sa marque bu sur le corps des esclaves. Ceux-ci, s'ils ne sont point esclaves du roi, int transporti des le soir meme au fort ou dans la factorie; mais si ce sont s Negres du roi, il doivent demeurer chez le marchand, jusqu'a ce qu'ils issent 6tre transported de suite a bord.53 l$Vith trading carried on only at these specified places of trade and un-jiet official scrutiny, it is clear that any private "street-corner" dealings *fwere out of the question. As for imports, they were similarly affected with a public interest. Goods imported were for the most part war material or elite goods »1lich circulated only among the dignitaries of the kingdom. Foreign cloth, umbrellas, shoes, and other imported goods were regarded as attributes of status; special safeguards surrounded dealings in such goods and sumptuary laws banned their possession by the common people. Guns, powder, iron, and coral could not be sold except to the king or his officials, and the king forbade the transit of firearms through his kingdom, in order to prevent war material from falling into the hands of his enemies. That coral should be included in this list seems at first glance strange, but coral was treasure, and clearly a "security" item sii ice it was demanded of Dahomey as tribute by the neighboring kings of Oyo. Dalzel relates an incident involving a woman trader at Whydah, by the name of Paussie, who had sold coral illicitly to the French traders.54 This action precipitated a diplomatic crisis. When word of tins reached the king of Oyo, he lodged official protest with the king of Dahomey, accusing Dahomey of deception in withholding the customary tribute of coral on the false plea that no ships had brought coral to Whydah recently. The woman Paussie, was seized by the king's messengers and taken to Abomey for punishment as a traitor, 174 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; Jnd« "•: butcher's. Instead it is purchased cooked, seasoned and prepared to be eaten. The feeding of the poorer subjects, clients or followers of a chief or sovereign is an unavoidable necessity which is sometimes resolved in the cooked-food markets. A chief, qaid or sayyid keeps "maison et table ouvertes,"17 especially when on the rise to power. At other times he may try to ensure a cheap supply of staples which may be directly distributed, e.g., at the "gates." % I Generally speaking the Bled es Siba has no such proletariat because it has not suffered detribalization, and division of labor remains primitive. The need to feed the poor is absent in a society over which no sovereign rules and where everyone is the equal of everyone else. The appearance of an internal proletariat in the Siba is a sure sign that it is developing an oligarchic tyranny of local character and a Makhzen of its own. Reciprocity produces an important form of assistance in the muna,19 a dole of food given to a needy stranger or neighbor, taking place in a public reunion, usually at night so that the occasion is called "the night of succor (Iaila el muna). In its ancient Arabic form the muna was simply a gift of food to the hungry or, rather, a first-fruit of alms owed to the needy or to God. A Berber who desires the benefit of a muna appeals to the chief of the notables of the group in the bustle of a market day. The following night, as soon as the group has returned 196 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India 9 home, food is collected from the households and served to the needy 1 person and his family. The muna obliges the other villagers to do like- 1 wise. The village itself is devoid of shops. Everything that is not domestically produced has, therefore, to be obtained from the market, through market transactions, and no exchanges or commercial activities of any kind are attempted outside of these times and places. The market place has a monopoly of exchange transactions. Itinerant traders, again, do not visit the villages, but only the markets. This does not, of course, apply to travelling craftsmen who repair saddles, ploughs, or other bulky objects which cannot be taken to the distant market, nor to the doctor (tubfb al-muslimfn) who pays irregular visits and carries and sells his own drugs and medicines. Nor does it apply, by a remarkable exception, to a class of peddlers who visit the villages when the men are away, for the women are their only clients. In return for the foodstuffs, spices, small manufactured articles, jewelry, cosmetics, charms or whatever their all-purpose bags may contain, they receive eggs, wool rags or fleeces or small quantities of oil filched by the housewives from home supplies. This uncommercial form of trade is undisputed women's prerogative; no money is used, barter is the governing principle. In the face of such an exception, restriction of all other commerce to the suq is all the more striking. The physical equipment of the market may be simple enough. It is held on a flat surface, sandy where possible, so as to avoid dust in summer and mud in winter. Essential to a market site is a good source of water, often connected with a shrine, so that at least in the big places of pilgrimage (mussem) marketing is combined with religious practices and ritual bathing. At the shrine oaths are taken in litigation cases. The shrines possess a holy perimeter (haran), serving as a refuge in case of need, and where people in danger (blood-feud, etc.) may take shelter. All this contributes to the security conferred on this turbulent area by the covenant of the market. The correlation between shrines and markets is too close to be of very recent origin. If the shrine of the spring or of the mosque is a famed one (siyyid) the yearly pilgrimage will most likely coincide with an increase of the merchandise offered in the market.21 According to the volume of business transacted in the markets and the number of persons who attend, we may divide suqs into two classes. HpExplosive Markets: The Berber Highlands 197 Wm. The first kind are small and held in the territory of a mountain canton w or at the boundary limits of two or three cantons; some crude remov-W able shelters forming shops (tahanout) provide room for the few dozen Hp -persons who visit the market (a hundred at the most). The notables of Ik the place will run such a market without receiving any remuneration. K The large kind of suq occurs at crossroads or strategic locations, or HE other important points of communication, as at the foot of mountains, HE on the borderline between ecological regions. In some instances such H markets may be surrounded by a wall, especially if market dues are col-■£ lected. They may contain hundreds of shops, like cells in a beehive, ■ made of mud and stone, each the stall of a merchant. Within the en-El closure we find permanent buildings (storehouses, coffee shops, a |l mosque, etc.). Such markets may be frequented by all the tribes of the 11 region and several thousand persons may gather in them every week. I J Suqs as just described are typical of rural North Africa, whether I'M Arab or Berber. With the single exception of the desert areas they form Of a system of weekly markets held alternately within walking distance of fA: the villages. This method is not only advantageous for the farmer who Igets a larger choice of products, but also necessary in nonpoliced countries where no towns are in reach. It is made possible by the villages being close together, not in a line, but rather radially. Indeed, the system is at home throughout the Middle East, for the products of the countryside appear in the city bazaars on appointed days. But nowhere is the system as elaborately perfected as in North Africa.22 The markets are there named for the day of the week in which they are held followed by the name of the tribe to which they belong, and the market days are so allotted between neighboring market places that it is always possible to make weekly rounds of markets, returning home for the night. The whole area could be plotted in this way: as clusters of markets of which it is possible to make weekly rounds, their clustering offering pointers to the student of the geography of economic units. Each village school has its free day on the allotted market day.23 Such a distribution of markets must have been reached in each region by a method of trial and error. Rivalries were bound to arise if two neighboring markets were held on the same day. In Kabylia, when a tribe wanted to establish a new market it had to obtain the consent of the neighboring tribes and select a day which would not infringe their rights.25 Thus, decision by decision, always with the general interest in i 198 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India mind—the nearer and more frequent the markets, the better—the mesh came to be knit. Eventually, on appointed days persons protected by their particular day's safe conducts, flowed from all directions into the paths leading to definite markets. Such a piecemeal method of evolution did not favor a national development. While in pre-Muhammedari nomadic Arabia the time allotted to trading was a specific season of the year (the maswin or monsoon months), when blood feuds and tribal feuds would be dropped, the sedentary population of North Africa seemed to have been prevented by its own devices for continuous trading from achieving a common period of truce which could have acted as an amalgamating factor on a national scale. More often than not the market places are located in the valleys halfway between opposite lefts occupying parallel mountain ranges. They are thus fully exposed to the consequences of that peculiar system of power vacua which is at the heart of the Berber polity. In these nonpoliced and politically split areas, attendance at the markets as well as travel between territories is achieved under agreements providing for neutrality. The Berber anaia or safe conduct is granted either by the tribes themselves or by individual tribesmen who are, of course, supposedly backed by the full force of the tribe to which they belong. Anyone can grant his anaia on his own responsibility and expect his tribesmen to respect it. Thus a person going to the market finds himself the balanced focus of opposite forces and entrusts life and limb to the recognized guarantees that protect the market place. Safe Conduct To secure this peace of the market is one of the supreme aims of the highland polity. This is indeed a dominant theme of Berber life. The markets are the places for "external" contacts, where the narrow in-group solidarity of village life gives way to a "freer" behavior that results from the intercourse with individuals who belong to other groups. Cantonal isolation thus finds its counterpoise and its outlet in the market habit. Psychologically as well as physically market places stand on the "fringes" of the in-groups. Here the world of the villager comes into contact with similar outside groups. The villages, centers of life and habitation of the in-groups, and the markets, centers of commerce of Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands 199 the out-groups, are completely dissociated in the physical sense. The snq stands locationally apart from and in contrast to the village. It is situated well outside of the settled centers, in low-lying and deserted spots, far from the plowed fields. After the market ends, the merchants and shop keepers pack their stands away and the market place remains deserted, unmarked—almost indistinguishable in the landscape. These places resemble in fact no man's lands assigned to the weekly truces of commerce. There are important exceptions. In all regions travelling traders may be stopped and asked to sell the merchandise they carry—compulsory trade—in the villages or in the middle of the road.28 In certain areas, indeed, the markets stand just on the outskirts of the village. Finally, in the specialized towns of the oases (qsar) the market place is in the middle of the town itself which is in fact to be considered as a "market-town" servicing both the visiting nomads and the cultivators of the place. Yet though these last "markets" are "towns" they also carry the imprint of the neutrality that goes with the noninhabited market place. The qsars are generally under the protection of nomadic groups that rent buildings in the town as storehouses. If the qsar is central to different nomadic tribes, its independence may be even more complete. Indeed, the situation of the qsar of the oases seems in many respects to approach that of the "port of trade." Desert and sea are akin. The physical separation of village and market makes possible the co-existence of two well-developed forms of integration in the same society—market exchange and in-group reciprocity. Though at certain times of the year a full tenth of the Kabyle population is engaged in itinerant commerce (mostly of the peddling and barter type described above), in the villages themselves there is a striking absence of professional merchants 27 Nevertheless, apart from some transactions on real estate, sale of trees, or the crops, etc., which may be prepared at the villages and concluded in the market, the extent of the transactions made in the villages is very limited, probably no more than a fraction of the volume of business done in the market. Further, payment in kind, services, barter, etc., prevail in the villages whereas cash payment is the invariable rule at the market. Over and above the anaias and related conventions which made a safe access to markets possible, the groups which "owned" a market delegated authority to certain individuals or certain bodies. The regime of the market which resulted might vary from district to district, but, if 200 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India as we shall see, there were only a few methods available for delegating the administration and the policing of the markets. When the market was truly intertribal, "owned" by different groups, their representatives would obviously sit together and deal with all cases either by common decision or separately, i.e., each representative settling the disputes of his own tribesmen. There is a limit to this method. In the Rif, for instance, the markets are occasions for the concluding of tribal alliances (ribat). In such reunions the chiefs may have to decide litigations that arise in assemblies composed of crowds of armed warriors.28 The market of Tarqist, for instance, situated at a crossroads of the High-Ghis region, was under the control of three amghars appointed by the three interested tribes, the Beni Mesdwi, Tarqist and Zerquet.29 Thus the system of intertribal markets is prevalent in districts belonging to the Makhzen, where the tribes tend to be at peace with one another, and stand moreover under the jurisdiction of the central government. When, on the contrary, a single tribe or village owned the market, the d/'ema'a of one tribe alone could not very well exercise control over the market, for this would have been equivalent to applying local jurisdiction to an interlocal affair. Also, it might not be convenient for a single d/'ema'a to handle the administration of a market place where great distances were involved. Authority over the market would therefore have to be delegated. Now, the simplest solution in the areas where religious personages played an important role in the Berber parts of Kabylia and Northern Morocco consisted in turning control over to a holy man (murabit) or a family of murabits. Such markets under murabitic authority, we are told, while exempt of all specific regulations, offer a picture of general harmony. To the same type belong in the tribal areas of the Makhzen the markets of religious teachers (tolba). Their origin is ancient; in olden times in these places of reunion young men or students would get together to discuss professional questions. Merchants, attracted by the periodic congregations, put up shops and stalls and started a market. Examples are the Kjouma'a Tolba, the Thenin Tolba, where the religious teachers themselves sell all kinds of foodstuffs. The tolba rule and police these markets which have no master, neither qaid nor khalifa. Only to watch over judicial matters does a judge (qadi) turn up from a nearby center.30 These tolba markets seem very independent of Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands 201 Makhzen authority. Towards 1898 the market of Thenin de Smid el-Ma was suppressed at the demand of the lease-holders of the tolls in the neighboring town of El-Ksar. They had complained of unfair competi-; tion exerted by the unofficial tolba market which diverted many goods. But the inhabitants of the countryside continued to visit the market |in spite of prohibition by the Makhzen, and the religious men managed without any representatives of authority.31 I The murabits to whom the market had been entrusted could be long dead. The market place then would continue as a shrine and there remained only the malediction (tagat) of the saint venerated in the sanctuary to punish troublemakers. Since oaths were taken at the shrine, the notables were spared the trouble of intervening in litiga-tions. In particular the great autumn fairs were of this type. "Such fairs," we learn, "attract the populations of whole countrysides of several days distance. The crowds that meet here are rent by lifelong feuds and no chief, no committee of notables can be expected to overawe them. Nothing less than a formidable saint and the awful penalties dispensed by him will suffice."32 In the regions where these religious institutions could not insure neutrality, private individuals were entrusted with the policing of the market. Offhand, it would seem as if this was only a secular variant of murabitic control. But the purpose of this method was rather the opposite, namely, to hand the police of the market not to a superauthority, but to a nonauthority, so as to make it more palatable to visiting aliens by offering the chance of a neutral jurisdiction. Nevertheless the person had to be rich and well connected, able to depend on his soft or leS for allegiance. These persons, a sort of custodes nundinarum, were known as "masters of the market." Actually their semi-official status was only the result of the abstention of the group from applying its territorial jurisdiction over the market. Hanoteau and Letourneux rightly affirmed that the "masters of the market" were, in Kabylia, the only office-holders comparable to our magistrates.33 The practice was an old one. Robert Montagne has traced it, perhaps stretching it too fine, to Roman Africa, where rich gentlemen farmers would establish native markets to their great profit.34 An alternative to the appointment of some local notable was the procedure of farming out the market to individuals by auction. Markets were auctioned for a fixed period of time, generally one year, to the highest bidder, who recouped himself through the collection of market T Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands 203 But this is only the latest stage of a line of evolution. In the regions where the oligarchy did not rise to the status of a social class, representative assemblymen (inflas) continued to administer the markets. In Kabylia, where chieftainship has not made any strides at all though an oligarchy did establish itself as a class, markets are administered by prominent members of the oligarchy appointed as masters of the market. The dangerous combination of expanding market exchanges and .self-aggrandizing personal authority was averted by increasing the number of the markets while keeping their size as small as before. This, in conjunction with the sofT or Ieff mechanisms, themselves the greatest obstacle to the emergence of despotism, kept the traditional social structure intact, and chieftainship did not develop. 202 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India dues. Since the taxes were to be paid over to the Makhzen in full, the tax farmer had to increase their amount, in order to pay the taxes to the government and still retain a profit for himself. It became an open invitation to abuse, sparing only the European and other influential persons who should not be antagonized. Such farmed markets seem in general to run smoothly. The collectors are regarded as individuals who make an investment and therefore can expect a return. Moreover, the policing functions are also auctioned, so that fines are imposed with alacrity by the market constables. In auctioned markets, furthermore, there is a virtual separation of the administrative from the judiciary apparatus, resulting in a better functioning of the whole. The method of farming out the markets, widespread in the Makhzen tribal areas, is almost absent from the Siba. It was a useful method for collecting central government taxes from outlying areas by auctioning them out to local persons. We cannot expect to find such a feature in the Siba regions. Payment of taxes to the Makhzen or the qaids is here not known and, in general, there is a disinclination to tax the goods which enter the market. Nevertheless the men of the Siba accepted this innovation like many other economic or social practices reaching them from the Makhzen. By and large, command of the market is a stepping stone to'power. The mere growth of the market entrusted or farmed to the authority of an individual seems to help in the development of his personal power. In the regions of rampant chieftainship, it is in "commanding over the market" that an amghar shows best his prestige and ability.36 This may open the door to a Makhzen development. A very close dependence upon markets, especially in the High Atlas, follows in the wake of the destruction of the old democratic and co-operative ways, the true home of in-group reciprocity. Sociologically, we have here a set of interacting factors where markets can hardly function without successful oligarchs or prominent chiefs, and the development of chieftainship leads to a further growth in the size of the market. The process may be cumulative and become overwhelming: the amghars or chiefs (later qaids) come to be more and more dependent on Jewish moneylenders, and complicated financial operations begin to take place; the old tribal law is replaced by the religious shari'a, and the local market regulations traditional to the Siba are absorbed by those of the Makhzen. Explosive Markets The different types of control—whether of the supernatural, conventional or administrative order—would normally appear sufficient to ensure the peace of the market place. But not under the extreme conditions obtaining in these traditionally feuding party-ridden areas. Here markets are powder kegs which may go off at the slightest shock. There is a customary name for the sudden, panicky "snapping" which breaks the peace of the suq: the nefra'a. These markets, it must be remembered, are supposedly37 neutral ground, and tribesmen of hostile groups are able to meet each other, even if a merciless intertribal war is raging during the other days of the week. The situation is overloaded with latent conflict and the precarious truce may dissolve in mutual violence. The nefra'a is naturally more common in large intertribal markets, and rather rare in the small markets of the mountain cantons, for these gather too few people to give rise to such a phenomenon of mass psychology as is the nefra'a. The larger intertribal markets are the place where members of opposite tribes, Ieffs, or soffs meet squarely with each other. Where blood feud is the immemorial right of the families even the best controls emanating from neutrality, anaias and covenants cannot replace a common positive authority. The nefra'as thus are not exceptional phenomena; a nefra'a can be intentionally provoked by rogues out for pillage, but generally it is a spillover from a simple dissension between two individuals, ending in a brawl in which 204 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India all take sides. In 1880, in the Sunday suq of El Had Berriada, one Ait Boudvar tribesman and one Ait Wasif tribesman argued about a kid-skin worth no more than thirty cents. Two factions took part in the dispute and came to fight each other for the whole day, using small stones, hatchets and knives. Firearms were prohibited in this suq; everyone was carrying his own dagger. At the end of the day 300 men were lying dead or wounded.38 In the suq of the Ak'bil a man of the Ait el Arba (Ait Yenne) argued with a debtor of his of the Ait Hikhem (Ait Yahyia). The debt was in the amount of forty-five cents. A tribal war ensued.39 Most of these market battles, and the bloodiest ones, are fought in Kabylia. This is a region of large villages, as we saw, divided into soffs which readily organize into Ieff-type alliances. Also, Kabylia is a country of important markets where the tribesmen act as tradesmen and itinerant merchants, mixing freely in the territories of foreign tribes. If the chiefs and constables of the market, as so often happens, are unable to separate the contenders, only exhaustion puts an end to the fray. The very tenseness of the crowd in the market place sometimes acts as a mechanism of control. The people in a market may take terrify-ingly swift measures to stop an imminent nefra'a through a sort of lynch-law. The lightning action of the crowd and the ferocity of the punishment inflicted is the true measure of the instability of these meetings. Often the prohibition of arms was observed in so far as long arms were concerned, but the practice of carrying concealed guns was widespread. In the Sunday suq of the Ait Iraten, Said Naid Ahmed of the village of Ait el Arba (Ait Yenne tribe) was in blood-feud with the clan of Kassi-ou Mrad, an old headman of the Taguemiont Ihedden (soff of the Ait Irsten). Said wanted to kill Kassi, and following the old man to a corner of the market, he cocked the gun he was carrying under his burnous. The noise betrayed him; someone uttered a cry, and only minutes later he lay dead under the pile of stones with which he had been lapidated. Such piles covering a dead body may be left untouched to serve as a reminder. Nothing but brutal preventive behavior can ensure the neutrality of the market place. The Berber social structure permits a chain-reaction of ever larger conflicts. In this politically cleft society it is more important to isolate trouble spots than to punish merely because there was breach of the law. The qanuns chastise threats as heavily as com- Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands 205 pleted acts. To unsheath a yatagan in the suq is as bad as to stab someone. And no meddler in a dispute not his own can get away without a fine. He who fires a gun at the suq of Massat, though nobody is injured, pays as much as the murderer of a man on nonmarket days. To our ears: "Be bold and quick. Give to your act all the marks of the inevitable. Don't fumble." It is not surprising that the nefra'a breeds xenophobia. Strangers and foreigners are sometimes inclined to take the law in their own hands;40 they have no part in the policing of the market and do not suffer from the long-range consequences of a nefra'a. Nefra'as will discredit a suq and people will stop coming to it. Besides, if a murder has been committed in the suq the market is closed for a period of purification, generally one year.41 Lynch law and draconic legislation is thus an outstanding feature of the Berber highland market. Under conditions of anarchy only extreme rigor of the law and its ruthless application can ensure an area of peace and freedom such as these markets broadly represent. Incidentally, women play an important part in maintaining the peace of the market. This sociologically well-grounded fact may also account for the tradition that all through history the Moghreb women were conciliators and messengers of peace in wars and private quarrels. Among the Arabs this mediating function of women derives from the marriage alliance (cihr) which acts to unite two social groups. In many tribes the woman who marries a foreigner becomes a citizen of both tribes. The Ait Mesruh and their neighbors admit also that foreign women married in the tribes become automatically Mesruiah. The Talsint only grant citizenship, however, when the woman gives birth to a male child.42 The anaia of women is the strongest kind of anaia, a cloak of immunity and protection that involves a group's honor. Moreover, as housewives, women are eager for their market supplies and market earnings. Their presence in the market place is a matter of course. To the women belong exclusively two fields of economic activity, namely, poultry and eggs, pottery, as well as within limits, the sale of wool, charcoal and henna. They keep their gains for themselves so that the market is a source of feminine private income. The cash they obtain in these exchanges they keep as ornament money, or convert it into jewels, perfumes, dresses, etc. Many breaches of market peace are avoided by their presence and others are restored by their intervention. 206 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India Rigor of Market Law Islam itself has never developed special codes for commerce, since religious law encompasses all activities. Subject to this limitation, the Berbers have tables of fines for villages and tables of fines for markets. Characteristically, the market, as such, is little mentioned in the qanuns of the villages; out of the 25 complete qanuns and 29 incomplete ones examined, the author has been able to collect only a dozen references to the market (though some qanuns count up to 50 and even up to 150 articles). Almost none exist in regard to the regulation of the markets themselves. In the few cases when the village qanun mentions a specific market it does so to enact penalties that are harsher in the market than elsewhere. The market is the danger spot in the social structure. The full rigor of the law is applied there with intent. Of this we have a confirmation in the qanun of Massat. This tribe of recent constitution in the Moroccan south was studied by Robert Montagne.45 The physical center which held together the newly formed Massat confederation was the market. We can follow step by step its body of laws as it developed, for in the qanuns the regulations appear as added year by year. The climax of this progression is provided by the penalties for thieving in the market. In the final articles—180 and 181—enacted a few years after 1880, we read: The Suq et Tetla being transferred to its old site to the N. of Touba, the Tribe of the Ida u Mont has decided that all adults in full possession of their faculties guilty of stealing in the aforementioned market, will pay 110 mitqals. If one such refuses to pay, or if his means of fortune do not permit him to do so, he will be blinded by gouging out his two eyes, if he cannot manage to obtain the pardon of the inflas. Such is the debt to society of the transgressors of the law. And article 182: The ancient custom by virtue of which fines could be paid for the culprit by the seven nearest kinsmen's houses is hereby abolished, for it was an arbitrary measure which was not according to the Shar'ia [Moslem religious law] nor the orf [Berber customary law]. Only the wife of the thief, or his father, or both together, can help in the payment of the fine, if there has been between them no separation of their property. Otherwise, the transgressor alone is responsible for his act. Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands 207 These two articles reinforced each other. The abrogation of the customary principle of extended family responsibility stands here alongside of the till then harshest law against thievery. What was especially meant by the "neutrality" of the markets was their insulation from all conflicts arising out of other contexts. In the qanun of Massat (article 113) it is forbidden to bring into the market place any litigation of cases except the local commercial ones. Conversely, local commercial transactions have to be executed and completed on one and the same market day, and incompleted ones cannot be left over for the next market day. In Kabylia, for instance, Anyone quitting the market and leaving behind him a debt of more than 1 real is fined Vi real.47 Such provisions would necessarily prevent the emergence of a system of markets, i.e., a linking of markets with one another. No credit system can develop; no price arbitrage can be practiced. The road leading to market trade is blocked. Even finance and business evolve outside of these markets. Not markets, but trade and government are their founts. The Berbers never fully accepted the usury laws of orthodox Islam. It was traditional of the earlier French writers of the conquest to contrast Berbers and Arabs in this respect. In a typical year during the second half of the nineteenth century the French issued 8,000 to 10,000 passports to traders in the circle of Fort National. Considering that the population there numbered only 76,616 inhabitants, at least one-eighth of the total population was, off and on, actively engaged in trade. Three-fourths of these passports were issued to itinerant peddlers, or "perfumers." In payment for their cosmetics, ribbons, charms, kerchiefs and other trifles of female attire, they took some handfuls of flour, or raisins, some wool rags, or oil, whatever the household could dispense with. If these peddlers never asked for money, neither did they spend any. Successful begging was one of the marks of a thriving peddler. When he had gathered enough by barter and begging, he went to town to sell. An Ait Yenne who started with a capital of 25 fr. allegedly made 1,000 by the end of the season. Another Ait Yenne who invested all his capital, amounting to 10 frs. in cheap wares netted 500 frs. These peddlers carry their cheap merchandise in bags, and they are called "traders of the bag" to distinguish them from "traders of the tent," who have pack animals, tents 208 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India and servants. The bags weigh sometimes 35 or 40 legs., and when the poorer Kabyle comes home after one of these ventures, he has deep scars on his back.51-52 Segmental Anarchy and "Free" Prices We have to take up finally the question of price formation in these markets.53 Very broadly we may say that Makhzen and Siba markets were organized along different lines. Markets in the Makhzen were strictly controlled; prices were fixed by authority and publicly announced; such control permitted fluctuations from month to month, week to week, or even day to day, according to proclamations. In the Siba, on the contrary, evidence points to a much greater freedom of transactions with prices at least to some extent the result of the bargaining of the parties.54 Unfortunately, the evidence is one-sided. The Makhzen is fully documented; price lists are available over long periods of time and even the organization of trade is fairly well known. In regard to the Siba we are almost completely in the dark. Our authors offer merely vague statements; not a single detailed description of activities in a typical Siba market is in evidence. In the Makhzen cities the prices of goods—especially foodstuffs, necessities, textiles, etc.—are set by proclamation of an official delegated by the central authority, the muhtasib. His rates are decided upon after consultation with wholesalers and taking into account the prices paid by these to the producers. Once the official rates are proclaimed, nobody is allowed to sell at a higher price although underselling is allowed. The Makhzen prices remain therefore partly a function of the prices paid in the wholesale markets. In these markets, rural and regional, the prices were arrived at by free transactions and by auctioning. Lower prices were obtained whenever wholesale transactions were concluded through long-term operations, the brokers buying up the crops in advance. The Siba markets resented the presence of such rural wholesale markets in the making, since they themselves were often supply markets for the towns. Further, the complicated organization which in the Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands 209 B Makhzen was responsible for the setting of prices, and which involved iT consultations with wholesalers, examinations of the merchandise, pun-|| ishments for the infractors, and a minute policing of the market places, | could hardly be expected from the fickle and transitory political equi-k librium of the Siba markets, which moreover lacked the specific ad-f& ministrative machineries of control.55 Thus, if some of the Siba markets P served, as we have said, as supply markets for the towns, yet wholesaling E of crops by the Berber peasants to the town brokers did not set the i latter's prices, for the wholesale operations and the urban retail sales belonged to two different orders of things. It happened often, then, jj| that although the rural markets supplied the towns, their own subse-k* quent retail prices rose higher than in the Makhzen cities. I Speculation by manipulating the supply was not an unknown phenomenon in the Morocca of pre-Protectorate days. Its effects were, however, not much felt. In the cities and towns of the Makhzen, the organization was based on a policy of protecting the consumers by II fixing the retail price of foodstuffs and other necessities. Wherever such I ■ organization was lacking, as in the Siba, speculation could not be con-I trolled to the same extent; but there the consequences of hoarding and * of manipulating the supplies of necessities were, in the nature of things, much less grave for most consumers were also producers of the same necessities. However, even in the Siba the possibility of speculation appeared in some cases as potentially dangerous. The Kabyles, for one, were ready to cope with this problem, and there is no reason why we should exclude similar restrictive measures in many other of the socially compact tribes or districts of North Africa. Temporary scarcity was met by rationing. As Hanoteau and Letourneux put it, "Trade is almost always free. In wartime when communications are interrupted ^ or inadequate, the d/ema'a fixes the ration of grain that any person may buy at any one time. Similar measures are taken if the roads are blocked by snowfall or there is a failure of crops; in this latter case able-bodied adults must wait their turn until the sick, expectant or recently confined women have been provided for."56 The implications of such ad hoc rationing are far-reaching. It presupposes a high measure of market discipline on the part of the general public; also it establishes a strong presumption in favor of a practice of set prices for the staple and interchangeable necessities of life. Abuses of the freedom of transactions were punished. To dissuade 210 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India competitors from buying, either by gifts or promises, is not an offense in itself among the Kabyles, but "he who runs down the merchandise out of malice, or with intent of purchasing himself at a cheaper rate, is fined 5 duros if it turns out that the merchandise did not suffer from the shortcomings he had asserted."57 From this interesting provision it is further evident that norms of fair bargaining were obtained. In the matter of prices, then, we cannot say that the evidence is very satisfactory. We do not possess any exact details of the bargained prices and of the specific price-mechanisms which functioned in the Siba. Yet there are sufficient indications which point to the fact that these were mostly of the "free" type, and that spontaneous price fluctuations were a widespread feature. Nevertheless the limitation of business ventures to those of the peddler-trade type carried on through barter indicates that profit was taken more on the side of trade, i.e., carrying, than on price differentials in the market itself. The Berber mountain markets, however, remain in economic anthropology one of the rare cases which may approach to bargained market prices for daily necessities. The extent to which they do this may well be related to the fact that attitudes in markets were formed in an implicit system of cultural and social conventions wherein freedom could manifest itself in a pattern of action. Conclusions In-group reciprocity and out-group market exchanges are the two most obvious forms of integration which obtain in this society.58 Their co-existence seems to go hand in hand with the communal, individualistic and segmented traits of a culture of which Hanoteau and Le-tourneux said that "nowhere else could we find such a combination which is nearer equality and farther from communism."59 The reciprocal exchanges, to be sure, bolster the communal feelings of interde-pendency in a community.80 Planting or harvesting are often done communally, especially if a family is short of hands for the occasion. The solicited help received is returned in kind; also he who receives help is host to all who worked for him. The resulting scheme of reciprocally Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands 211 co-operative interaction comprises the whole community. Such work-bees do not exhaust the forms of interpersonal relations of Berber society. The individual is by no means submerged in the group and occasionally he can be the sole beneficiary of reciprocative communal behavior.61 Nevertheless the large field of Berber market exchanges is the ground for the expression of individualistic tendencies. The Berber combination of in-group reciprocity and individualism is made possible because the society is "free" in the sense that the groups which compose it are not related except "freely" to one another. No higher center enforces the unity of the whole—this most basic feature of Berber society, its absence of any political, urban or social center and its lack of any centralization, is so fraught with consequences that we have to stop for a moment in their analysis. The idea of centralization has penetrated our thought to the point that whenever we find a society where it is absent, we are prone to interpret that society incorrectly and to misjudge it for living in a chaos. As E. Masqueray said of the Berbers: ".. . des populations qui n'ont aucune idee, aucun sentiment, qui ne soit 1'inverse des n6tres, ne doivent pas etre etudies avec des id6e preconcues."62 The only comparison which comes to mind for Berber society is one of the Utopian anarchist schemes of a Proudhon, Bakunin or Kro-potkin. Even there, given the relationships of which the social philosopher is aware, the Utopian, like the modern social scientist, is always inclined to confuse organization with central authority. He is likely to assume, forinstance, that a change in population density or numbers necessarily means a complete change in the constitution or structure of society. Bakunin himself—even if it was in the temporary need of launching the revolution—thought it necessary to combine a system of federations of workingmen forming, in the language of the time, free pacts with one another, with a central executive revolutionary body which controlled them. This has been the traditional set-up of the anarchist movements down to the present, deeply affecting the doctrine. Nevertheless, empirically, when centralization is truly absent or only exists in embryo, as is the case here, a change in numbers, for instance, will not readily change the quality of social organization. Society may also develop—as the ethnographic record best shows—along the lines which this very lack of centrality permits. This is the case of ■ 212 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India Berber society which, like the phoenix, is reborn. The absence of a center makes for a system of balances which can regenerate, and in fact has often done so. Sporadically centralization has taken on importance among the Berbers. Nevertheless, every time these new sovereignties were destroyed, decentralized and locally autonomous institutions regained their force as if nothing had happened. They emerged once again, as before, into a wide cultural integration through their inherent system of out-group balances and in-group reciprocities. And alongside them, the economic constitution which fitted that decentralization and balanced integration reappeared. Market exchanges revived and eventually the closed fabric of village and cantonal life was counterbalanced. If markets were wiped out, maybe as a result of warfare, the balance would tip over to the other side, and in-group reciprocities in village, kinship and canton would be strengthened. All this, in the last resort, is possible because, due to the lack of centrality, there is an interplay of two types of behavior which can alternate and find a natural setting in the in-group vs. out-group dichotomy. This society has a double fades, an alternance of reciproca-tive forms and of free individualizing forms. The social anthropologist may be at pains to work out the two faces presented in village and market. To the economist this duality appears in a greatly simplified form: whenever the first fades, that of the village, comes to the fore, economic behavior is reciprocative; when the second fades comes up, in out-group customs of pilgrimages, safe-conducts, travel and trade, exchange and market dominate the economic scene. If the individual ventures out of the district, he is safeguarded only by the customs which govern markets and market places and he himself acts individually—an economic man of market mentality. His personality is limited by the nature of his "free" pacts with the other members of his group in this society and by the contexts, the one reciprocative and bound, the other individualizing and free, which his society and culture provide. Note that no allowance is made at the villages for a disrupting bargaining behavior. It is only at the markets that legislation favors individual action. That both these contexts of Berber life are institutionalized into physically separate places of action, village and markets, is important indeed. If they were not, these contraries would come to a head-on collision. Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands 213 If we look again at the market as we saw it, this situation has curious consequences. First, there was the lack of specific administrative stipulations of internal control of price, motive, or marketing action. It was the context itself, the market peace, which had to be safeguarded and explicitly rigged. Secondly, in the absence of such internal controls, the markets, one would assume, may be on the way to becoming free markets with free and fluctuating prices. This happens, however, only to a point, for essentially they are still merely places where supplies are in fact exchanged by producers against supplies fitted for consumption. They are, in other words, transformation centers which do not acquire an acting power of their own, and where therefore marketing continues to be limited. Thus the markets may threaten the communal fabric of the society, but only within bounds, which again ensures the permanence of the duality of village and market. With this crucial reservation, markets are here external places for exchanges between individuals who are shedding the corporate personality of which they were a part within township and village. One may wonder if this combination of individual behavior and marginal intergroup location is not, where it occurs, a compound which tends to result out of the working of the market institution. Francisco Benet Notes to Chapter X 1. The word is believed to have been first used in North Africa as an official term in the 2nd century A.H, applied to an iron chest in which Ibrahim i. al Aghlab, emir of Ifriqiya, kept the collected taxes. 2. Cf. E. Michaux-Belkire, article "Makhzen," Encyclopedia of Islam. 3. For a discussion of the typicalities of these two worlds cf. C. S. Coon, Caravan, pp. 263 ff. 4. B. Montagne, Beibe'tes et Makhzen, p. 15 3. 5. Ibid, p. 162-163. 6. Cf. Robin, "Fetna Meriem," Revue Africaine, XVIII, no. 105 (mai-juin 1874) 173; cf. E. Doutte, Merrakech, p. 141; also, H. Basset, Literature des Ber-beres, p. 94, where he says: "En Kabylie plus souvent qu'ailleurs il arrive que la coutume reconnaisse, a c6te des individus, l'ensemble en tant qu'etat. . . . Un citoyen n'a pas le droit de ne pas assister au marche, n'eut-il rien a scheter ni a vendre." 7. Hanoteau et Letourneux, Kabylie, III, 65. 214 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India 8. Robin, Ioc. cit. 9. E. Doutte, Merralcech, p. 144. 10. De Segonzac, Au coeur de I'Atlas, p. 162. 11. G. Wysner, The Kabyle People, p. 131-132. 12. E. Michaux-Bellaire, Le Gharb, p. 229. 13. Abridged from a Berber text translated by E. Laoust, Mots et choses Berberes, p. 102-104. 14. Ibid.,p. 308,note25. 15. Ch. de Foucauld, Reconnaissance au Maroc, p. 126. 16. W. Marcais, Tanger, p. 129. 17. This applies both to organized political states and to tribal societies. 18. Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., II, 57; cf. G. Wysner, p. 144. 19. For the muna cf. R. Maunier, Coutumes Algeriennes, pp. 65-66; also E. Daumas, La vie arabe et la soci6t6 musulmane, pp. 449-457. 20. R. Naunier, "Les groups d'interet en Afrique du Nord," p. 45. Probably Naunier mistakes here an uza between friends for a muna. 21. W. Fogg, "A Moroccan Tribal Shrine and its relation to a near-by Tribal Market." Also Folklore, Vol. 51 (June, 1940). In the market of Sidi el Yemani (Djebala) after the wheat harvest there is every year an important mussem at this shrine. The grain is disposed of. 22. This cyclic organization has been studied by E. Michaux-Bellaire, "Le Gharb"; L. Massignon for Fez, finquete sur les corporations musulmanes, pp. 97-98, and the Dukkala, Le Maroc au XVIe si&cle d'aprds Leon 1'Africaine, p. 116; for the Djebala and Anjera regions of Spanish Morocco by Walter Fogg, "Tribal markets in Spanish Morocco," Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society (July, 1939) pp. 322-26 and "The importance of tribal markets in the commercial life of the countryside of Northwestern Morocco," Africa, XI, 4 (1938). 23. G. Wysner, op. cit., p. 130. 24. I. Biarnay, "Un cas de regression vers la coutume Berbere dans une tribu arabisee," fasc. 4, p. 221, note 1. 25. Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., II, 65. 26. Cf. for instance de Segonzac, Au coeur de I'Atlas, pp. 68-69. 27. Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., II, 77. 28. R. Montagne, op. cit., p. 252. 29. Ibid., p. 253. 30. Michaux-Bellaire et G. Salmon, "Les tribus arabas de la vallee du Lekkous," Archives Marocaines, VI (1906), 257-258. 31. Ibid., pp. 261-262. 32. R. Montagne, op. cit., p. 261. 33. Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., Ill, 47. 34. Boissier, Ahique Romaine, p. 149; quoted by Montagne, Berberes et Makh-zen,p. 231. 35. Ubach and Rackow, Sitte und Recht in Nordafrika, pp. 130-132. The money of the grand auction feeds the treasury of the village (Dorfgeldkiste). 36. R. Montagne, op. cit., p. 253. 37. To a lesser extent the cults and pilgrimages of religion function likewise, of course. 38. Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., Ill, 303. 39. Ibid. 40. Ibid., p. 79. 41. I. Biarnay, op. cit., p. 221. Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands 215 42. M. Morand, Etudes de droit Musulman et de droit coutumier Berbere, pp. 314-315. 43. Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., II, 80. 44. A. Hanoteau, Essai de Grammaire Kabyle, Reglement du Village de Thas-lent, pp. 321-328. 45. R. Montagne, "Une tribu berbere su Sud-Marocain, Massat"; also, M. Ben Daoud, "Recueil du droit coutumier de Massat." Montagne et Ben Daoud, "Documents pour servier a l'histoire due droit coutumier du Sud-Marocain." 46. Cf. R. Maunier, Coutumes Algeriennes, p. 44 ff. The Post Office at Fort National, in the middle of Kabyle country, receives the largest number of money remittances from France in North Africa. 47. Qanun of the tribe of the Ait b. Youcef (village of Taourirt Amran), Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., Ill, 429, art. 8. 48. Qanun of the villages of Taourirt Abdallah and Adrar Amellal, Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., Ill, 342, art. 20. 49. E. Daumas, Moeurs et coutumes de l'AIgene, pp. 183-184. 50. Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., I, 564 ff. Not all the tribes were equally bent on commerce. Those of the left bank of the Sebaau (Illiten, Ait Itswar, Ait Yahyia, Ait Frawcen, Igawawen, Ait Iraten, Ait Sedka, Ait Aissai, Maakha) seem to be so much more than those of the right bank (Ait Djennat, Ait Waguennun, Izerfawen, Iflissen, etc.). 51. Ibid., I, 564, ff. 52. Ch. de Segonzac, Voyages au Maroc, p. 221. 53. Market exchanges at set rates (equivalencies) were also known in North Africa, but only in the desert regions. It seems to be proper only with the Arab nomadic tribes. The equivalency of barley against dates, for instance, would alter progressively travelling from North to South. 54. R. Maunier, Loi Francaise etutume indigene en Algdrie, pp. 137-138; Kabylie, op. cit., Ill, 397. 55. It is a pity that most travellers have not given more attention to prices. It is understandable that they were unable to record the index of fluctuation of the market prices from market day to market day, for their weekly nature made it difficult for travelers to attend these markets more than once. 56. Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., Ill, p. 268. 57. Qanun of the Ait Frawsen, art. 94, Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., HI, 393. 58. It can be argued that householding is the most important form of integration in this society, but as it always applies to a group smaller than society, it does not encompass all the systems of relationship found there. 59. Hanoteau et Letourneux, op. cit., II, 468. 60. We have briefly described customs such as the muna and usa. The twiza is bee-work and it is so fundamental that it almost makes unnecessary the existence of a labor market. For the twiza cf. E. Laoust, Mots et choses Berberes, p. 322 ff.; J. Bourrilly, Elements d'ethnographie Marocaine, p. 153 ff.; E. Richardot, Notes sur la touiza: essay d'utilisation de la touiza dans un but mutualiste; R. Richardot, La mutuality agricole des indigenes de l'AIgene; R. Maunier, La construction collective de la maison en Kablie, etc. 61. Cf. the tawsa rituals, a sort of gift-exchange by which the individual obtains cash at certain specific occasions (weddings, births, etc.) at high interest and in mutualistic fashion. 62. E. Masqueray, Comparaison des dialectes, Introduction, p. 5. 216 Bibliography to Chapter X Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India Basset, H, Essai sur la Iitterature des Berberes. Alger, bonel, 1920. Ben Daoud, M, "Recueil du droit coütumier de Massat." Hesperis, 1924. Ben Daoud, M. and Montagne, R, "Documents pour servir a l'etude du droit coütumier du Sud-Marocain." Hesperis, 1927. Biamay, I, "Un cas de regression vers la coütume Berbere chez une tribu arabisee." Archives Berberes, 1,1916. Boulifa, "Le Kanoun d'Adni," Travaux et Memoires publi6s en l'honneur du XlVe Congres des Orientalistes par I'EcoIe Superieure des Lettres d'Alger, 1905. Bourrilly, J., Elements d'Ethnographie Marocaine. Paris, 1932. Coon, C. S, Caravan: the Story of the Middle East. New York, 1953. Daumas, E, Moeurs et coütumes de I'Algerie. Paris, 1853. -, La vie arabe et Ja sodere" musuhnane. Paris, 1869. Doutte, E, Merrakech, Comit6 du Maroc. 1905. Dresch, ]., Commentaries des cartes sur les genres de vie de montagne dans le massif central du Grand-Atlas. Tours, 1941. Fogg, W, "A Tribal Market in Spanish Morocco," Africa, XII, n. 4, 1939. -, "A Moroccan Tribal Shrine and its relation to a near-by Tribal Market," Man, 1940, n. 124. Foucauld, Ch. de, Reconnaissance au Maroc, 1883-1884. Paris, 1888. Hanoteau, A, "Essai de Grammaire Kabyle." Alar, n.d. Hanoteau, A. and Letourneux, La Kabylie et les coütumes Kabyles. 3 vols. Paris, 1872-73. Laoust, E., Mots et choses Berberes. Paris, 1920. Luc, B., Le droit Kabyle. Toulouse, 1911. Marcais, W, Textes Arabes de Tanger. Bibliotheque de l'Ecole des Langues Orientales Vivantes. Paris, 1911. Maunier, R, La Construction collective de la maison en Kabylie. Institut d'ethnog-raphie de l'Universite de Paris, n. 3, 1926. -, "Recherches sur les echanges rituels en Afrique du Nord," Annee Sociolo- gique, nouvelle serie, 1924/25. Paris, 1927. -, Loi Francaise et Coütume indigene en Algerie. Paris, Domat-Montchrestien, 1932. -, Coütumes Algeriennes. Paris, Domat-Montchrestien, 1935. -, "Les groups d'interet en Afrique du Nord," in Annals Sociologiques, coll. de L'Annee Sociologique, fasc. 2. Paris, 1937. Michaux-Bellaire, E. and Salmon, G., "El Qcar el Kabir: Une ville de province au Maroc septentrional," Archives Marocaines, II, 1905. -, "Les tribus arabes de la vallee du Lekkous," Archives Marocaines, VI, 1906. Michaux-Bellaire, "Le Gharb," Archives Marocaines, XX, 1913. -, "Makhzen," in Encyclopedia of Islam. Montagne, R, "Le regime juridique des tribus de Sud-Marocain." Hesperis, 1924. -, "Une tribu berbere du Sud-Marocain: Massat." Hesperis, 1924. -, Les Berberes et le Makhzen dans le Sud du Maroc. Paris, 1930. Morand, M., Etudes de droit Musulman et^de droit coütumier Berbe're. Alger, 1931. Richardot, E, Notes sur la touiza. Alger, 1909. -, La mutuality agricole des indigenes de I'Algerie. Paris, 1935. Explosive Markets: The Berber Highlands Robin, "Fetna Meriem," Revue Africaine, XVIII, n. 105,1874. de Segonzac, Marquis, Voyages au Maroc, 1899-1901. Paris. -, Au Coeur de l'Atlas, Mission au Maroc, 1904-1905. Paris, 1905. Ubach, E. and Rackow, E., Sitte und Recht in Nordafrika. Stuttgart 1925 Wysner, G., The Kabyle People. New York, 1945. ' XI Reciprocity and Redistribution in the Indian Village: Sequel to Some Notable ^Discussions the discipline of economic history has to deal with many areas and many periods in which productive and distributive activities do riot depend on buying and selling or the concept of economic efficiency. The economic activities of such nonmarket societies can present themselves in bewildering complexity unless we possess some broad exploratory approach as an alternative to the market theorem. In the case of the Indian village the need for such nonmarket alternatives has been recognized by a succession of students, but a satisfactory solution requires positive patterns of a nonmarket type. This chapter will show how some of the intractable aspects of the village economy yield to the concepts of reciprocity and redistribution. The Indian village has been described as precapitalistic, as having a barter economy, a subsistence economy, or as being communistic or collectivistic. However, "precapitalistic" tells us only that it is not capitalistic, and implies a sequence with teleological overtones. A "barter economy" refers to the absence of money, and is, as we shall see, misleading. A "subsistence economy" means only that the main occupation is agriculture, and usually implies poverty. As for "communistic," the term is vague. It is not used in the sense of modern variants of K Reciprocity and Redistribution in the Indian Village 219 H Marxism, but refers to a state of affairs in which both none and all are ;i owners. While the term "collectivistic" recognizes this difficulty by | implying that public property requires some definite organization in * order to function, it still does not tell us much about specific economic operations. In any case no explanations or descriptions starting from such concepts can develop a set of formal principles showing how the i production of goods is organized and how the goods are distributed. All a these terms serve merely to stress the absence of certain market insti-l§ tutions in the village system, and while the denial of the existence of the market is correct, no frame of reference for positive description or analysis is offered by them. The problem of describing the Indian village economy was attacked £. chiefly by a succession of British administrators of India who had practical purposes in mind, and then by Sir Henry Maine. From the beginning of the nineteenth century the village community and its economic structure has been a subject of serious consideration. In 1819 Holt Mackenzie, a revenue officer of the East India I Company's Bengal administration, submitted a minute on the various 1 forms of land tenure to be found in the newly acquired districts to the northwest of Bengal. His analysis was inspired by the practical desire for a simple, sure, and yet just way of assessing and collecting revenue. The administrators were faced with the task of raising the revenue and had to work out the technical means to that end. In order to develop an affective revenue system they had to place responsibility for payment on particular persons or groups, and a knowledge of the village structure was necessary in order to decide who these persons or groups should be. There were two considerations. First, the Company had but few officers to administer a very large territory. Responsibility had to be placed where assessment and collection required the least direct supervision and framed in such a way that enforcement would be easy, if not automatic. This consideration reinforced a natural bent to model India after the system existing in the English countryside. Second, equity required that those who enjoyed rights in the land and its produce should be protected in those rights. Further, it required that those who were made responsible for payment of the revenue should have a chance to profit from their responsibilities so long as they did not do so at the expense of the customary privileges of those placed 218 220 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India under them in the revenue hierarchy. This second consideration reinforced the tendency to regard Indian rural areas as counterparts to the hierarchical system in the English countryside, where it could be fairly said that the squirearchy did protect its tenants while profiting from their own position. In order to accomplish these aims the officers of the Company had to be certain that they knew who controlled the produce of the village, and thus would be able to meet the demands of the revenue administration, and they also had to know what rights and obligations attached to other members of the community. The scope of the problem was but slowly realized. In the latter part of the eighteenth and the first decade of the nineteenth century the Company had simply contracted with local personages of power, or revenue farmers, but unrest and dissatisfaction soon showed that stability of the revenue and economy of administration could only be achieved in the long run if the officers of the Company understood the true relationships obtaining among the native villagers. It was for these reasons that Holt Mackenzie set forth the traditional rights and duties of those living on the land in north western Provinces. In addition to the considerations governing the administration of the revenue, the British were faced with a policy decision of how to divide between the Company and other claimants the economic return attributable to land. Until this matter of principle was settled; a permanent system could not be devised. The problem was phrased in terms of ownership. It was accepted as axiomatic that some person or group of persons "owned" the land, and, equally, that whoever owned the land had a right to the economic rent, or, as it was then called, the "net assets" resulting from the productivity of the land. Thus a decision on a matter of policy—how high the land revenue assessment should be—came largely to rest on the answer to a question of law: whether the ruler and his heirs, the Company, or certain private persons or groups of persons owned the land. The decision did not, however, rest on the legal question alone. It was no less important to keep consistently to some practical ideal of rural organization. A persistent aim of the British was to create a native landed gentry. That the Company's servants thought in terms of the English system of landlord, farmer, and agricultural laborer is shown by the Permanent Settlement of Bengal. The Permanent Settlement was a fixing in perpetuity of the amount of land revenue due from those whom the British recognized as owners. The belief was that these Reciprocity and Redistribution in the Indian Village 221 owners would use the profits of their privileged position to develop the countryside and bring prosperity to agriculture. The ideas which the British brought to India were out of tune with the actual relationships of Indian cultivators and artisans. The British found themselves committing one error after another and thereby compounding their difficulties in administering a foreign land. Instead of finding landlords and tenants operating through a system of prices, bargaining, and contracts, the British found a maze of caste and custom regulating inter-family relationships. Where the British expected to find an owner they found a profusion of overlapping claims. These questions came to the attention of scholars with the publication of Sir Henry Maine's work.1 His original interest lay in the history of Roman legal institutions. In examining the laws and customs of ancient Hindu society he wanted at first merely to illustrate the structure of early Roman law. He found support for his interpretation of Roman law as primarily interfamilial by analogy with Hindu law and custom, and argued that the Hindu village was the prototype of the family system of ancient Rome and early Europe. Reaching out from Roman law to Hindu law, Maine found his interests leading him into a comparative jurisprudence encompassing not only Roman and Hindu law, but also early Germanic law and the Brehon Code of ancient Ireland. As Maine's interests spread over a wider geographical area, so also did they spread over a wider area of social thought. From an interest in the development of Western personal and property law the pursuit of origins brought him insights into the structure of the Eastern village community. The invaluable contribution to economic history came with his proof that the Indian village economy did not center on the market; that in fact some new frame of reference was needed in which to discuss its characteristics. Maine himself made the fundamental differentiation between status society and contract society—a distinction which proved extraordinarily fruitful, yet still failed to indicate the variety of institutions of a status nature or to spell out the formal arrangements that status economies may use. Maine recognized that the Hindu village was a closed unit with rights and obligations of its own. It was made up of extended or joint family groups and castes whose legal and economic relationships were interfamilial rather than interpersonal. Our conception of property rights, and consequently of alienability, sale, and market relationships 222 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India was not applicable to a system organized on principles of a religio-legal nature. The Hindu village as pictured by Maine has since been criticized as inaccurate in detail,2 but the general direction of his argument is not open to question. The importance of his discoveries lay in their emphasis upon the corporate unity of the village economy, upon its system of collective responsibility, and above all on status as a rationale of motivation, and as the principle on which the village economy was organized and integrated. The problem of the structure of the village community thus centered on the question of how precisely status was used to organize its economy. While the range of interests encompassed by the work of Sir Henry Maine and the work of British administrators extended from practical questions of establishing responsibility for the payment of revenue to comparative jurisprudence, they never engaged in a formal analysis of the principles of economic integration of the village economy. Maine and his successors were interested in law and rights, while the administrators did not feel called upon to move beyond solutions to their immediate concern with finding a workable system for collecting the revenue and dividing the return from land between the ruler and the ruled. Once the impact of British administration itself had altered original native conditions the problems of administration were" so deeply affected by past British actions that an analysis of the "native state of affairs" must have appeared to the practical administrator as of academic interest only. The intention of this paper is to show that the structure of the village economy and the nature of land revenue can be far better explained by the concepts of reciprocity and redistribution* than they can by the more usual terms of economic theory or by the vaguer terms of pre-capitalistic, barter, or subsistence economy. Reciprocity means that members of one group act towards members of another group as members of that group or a third or fourth group act toward them. There is no implication of equality, justice, or the golden rule. Rather, reciprocity implies only that there is a two-way or round-the-circle flow of goods as exemplified in the Melanesian Kula ring or the Trobriand Islanders' fish and yams transfer between coastal and inland villages. The groups are mutually self-supporting in regard to the articles involved in the reciprocative relationship. * See Ch. XIII. Reciprocity and Redistribution in the Indian Village 223 Redistribution means that the produce of the group is brought together, either physically or by appropriation, and then parcelled out again among the members. Again there is no implication of equality of treatment, fair shares, or payment for value. The social pattern is characterized by centricity—peripheral points all connected with the central point. The symmetrical patterns of reciprocative relationships may merge with the centralized pattern of redistributive relationships, as with the Trobriand Islanders, where the king is the redistributive center of a large number of reciprocative relationships with the brothers of his many wives. In putting these concepts to use in the patterning of empirical economies it must be understood that reciprocity and redistribution do not provide classifications for economies as a whole, for both kinds of relationships may be found in the same economy, either in regard to different goods or in regard to different groups of people. The different relationships of the various groups can be patterned on one or the other, or sometimes both principles. The strength of these concepts lies in their ability to reduce complex relationships to simple patterns. As shall appear, the maze of relationships in the Indian village economy can be set out in terms of reciprocity and redistribution applied to the groups that make up the village as well as to the main goods and services. Two focal points in the workings of the village economy have so far resisted analysis. The one concerns the economic structure of the village; the other refers to the nature of land revenue, its source and its position in the village economy. The Village Economy The three main bodies of Indian social organization were the joint family, made up of related members, numbering up to a hundred or more; the village, essentially a grouping of such families; and the castes. The family generally was a self-sufficient unit under the direction of its head or its senior members. Where special skills or certain specific services were required, it could call on the village artisans, servants, or priests. The basic political and social unit was the village. Within its 224 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India confines almost all economic needs were satisfied. The caste system was much wider than the village and its lines cut across village lines. It was; founded upon religious sanction. Over these basic units ebbed and flowed the surf of political life. Sometimes it was the life of empires such as the Gupta and Mughal Empires. More often it was organized in petty kingdoms varying in size from the area of a New England township to a very few square miles. In eighteenth-century Oudh3 we find a society in which the cultivators are "independent of each other, but connected through village heads, and the villages also independent among themselves, but joined in allegiance to a common Raja; the basis of the whole society being the grain heap, in which each constituent rank had its definite interest."4 The village did not hold its lands in common but it did have common officials and servants: watchman, headman, clerk, blacksmith, carpenter, herdsman, washerman, barber, priest, and potter. These officials and servants received their remuneration in a share of the cultivators' grain heaps. Production of food, the main material item in Indian life, was the business of the joint agricultural family. The officials and servants saw to their jobs, doing the appropriate work as and where it was needed. Throughout the year there was no exchange or payment for services rendered. The herdsman watched the cows and the blacksmith made the implements and repaired any ploughs that broke. Each activity was carried on according to the custom and tradition of the village and within the joint family according to its traditions, station in life, and the judgment of its head. At harvest time the means of subsistence for the rest of the year were distributed. The system of allotting shares in the gross produce of the village was highly complex, yet it did not require any previous knowledge of total gross produce to be divided among the members of the community. While the exact arrangements in the division and distribution of the produce varied from place to place, we may take as a typical example the system recorded by W. C. Bennett.5 Distribution in Gonda took place in three stages: From the standing crop; from the undivided grain heap of each cultivator; and from the heaps after the cultivator had contributed to the Raja's heap. From the standing crop of each cultivator the watchman, the blacksmith, the carpenter, the herdsman, the priest, and often the cultivator himself cut a twentieth of a bigha.6 Next, the crop was harvested and Reciprocity and Redistribution in the Indian Village 225 threshed by the whole community, the grain from the fields of each cultivator being heaped in a separate pile on the community threshing floor. The "slave-ploughman"7 took a share varying from a fifth to a seventh of the heap of the cultivating family to which he was attached. To this share he added a panseri.8 From each pile each person who had cut or threshed the crop (and this meant everyone) took a sixteenth of the rice and the "fattest sheaf in thirty" of the other crops. Then the carpenter, blacksmith, barber, washerman, and watchman each took twelve panseris of threshed grain from each cultivator for each four-bullock plough he owned, and six panseris for each two-bullock plough. When these shares had been passed out the grain heaps were divided in half, the cultivator retaining one half and the other going to the Raja, subject however to further distributions. One sir8 in every maund of the Raja's heap was returned to the cultivator, another sir was given to the scribe, a "double handful" to the priest, and a tenth of the remainder was given to the village headman. From the cultivator's remaining heap the blacksmith and carpenter each received three more panseris, the herdsman one more, and a sir or two went to the scribe. The matter is certainly intricate. Given all the data it would still be possible, of course, to compute the fraction of the total going to any cultivator or servant or to the Raja, but it is not possible to express it in any formula shorter than several pages in length and utterly unmanageable in practice. The proportions vary with the number, size, and distribution of cultivators' holdings, the number, size and distribution of ploughs, the number of bullocks, the number and distribution of slave-ploughmen, as well as the amount of gross produce. Not only do the deductions depend upon variations among these factors but some of the deductions are stated in proportional and some in absolute terms. Besides the inordinate length and cumbersomeness of the formula, there is the fact that the fraction could still not be converted into actual figures since the total was unknown. But again, here lies the true strength of the system employed. Despite the numerous factors involved and the unknown total, the system was not confusing to the participants. It was simple to operate precisely because no aggregate data were required. The operational device took care of the problem, and the device is described by the phrases used, such as: "One sir in every maund," "one seventh of the heap." Each step in the distribution was carried out separately. If the slave-ploughman was to get a seventh of the heap, six measures were 226 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India ladled out to the cultivator, and a seventh to the slave until the heap disappeared. With each proportional division the same process was followed, so that at no point was it necessary to know how much grain there was in the heap. The only accurate measures needed were a container for a panseri of grain and one for a sir of grain.10 Any measure could be used for the other sharing processes, for all they did was to dispose of the heap, so many measures to this pile, so many to that. By such a simple device a great many claimants were served in a great many different ways without need for accounting. Furthermore, honesty was assured because the distribution was public, taking place under the eyes of the villagers and of the Raja or his representative. There were built-in devices which assured each villager a minimum income, and which also tended to equalize the incomes of all the villagers. The fixed quantities going to the village servants gave them a basic minimum even if the harvest was so small that their proportional shares would not support them. When the cultivator "pre-harvested" a twentieth of a bigha of his own land the proportion of the revenue the small-holder was expected to carry was reduced in the same way that the personal exemption reduces the relative burden of the income tax on the man with a small income. The contribution of a sixteenth of. the rice heap and a thirtieth of other crops to the common heap and then dividing the heap equally among all the villagers also tended"to equalize incomes since the wealthier contributed more than the poor, while each shared equally. There was scant regard for economic rationality in the distribution. Some rough approximation to work rendered is indicated in the carpenters' and blacksmiths' shares based upon number and size of ploughs, which were also related to the area protected by the watchmen, but this cannot be said of basing the washerman's and barber's shares on the same criteria. The only approach to payment based on service was that to the herdsman per bullock cared for. Each villager participated in the division of the grain heap. There was no bargaining, and no payment for specific services rendered. There was no accounting, yet each contributor to the life of the village had a claim on its produce, and the whole produce was easily and successfully divided among the villagers. It was a redistributive system.11 Below and above the village level the redistributive pattern continued to prevail. Below, the share remaining to the cultivator's joint family was managed by the head of the family and parcelled out to Reciprocity and Redistribution in the Indian Village 227 the members of the family. The handling of the family's share was a matter of administration on a small scale, the principle being redistributive, for the grain was held in common and its consumption was regulated by handing out from the family store. Above the village level there might be only one or there might be a multiplicity of political authorities, depending on the size of the kingdom and the degree of central control which the king was able to exercise. Whether any economic function was or was not performed by the authorities, the division of the grain heap at the village level was the foundation upon which political authority rested. As the size of the kingdom grew the number of intermediate authorities multiplied, although strong kings attempted to eliminate some of them. The ruler's share was distributed among the competing levels of the military and political bureaucracy according to their relative strengths. In a large kingdom with a moderately powerful center, such as the Mughal Empire was at times, there was a hierarchy of redistributive centers with the village grain heap at the bottom and the king's storehouses at the top. In between, the local powers and provincial governors maintained their own storehouses, retaining a share and passing on the remainder to the level above. In regard to grain, the whole political and social structure was founded on redistribution. Intertwined with the redistributive system of family-village-kingdom was the caste system through which crafts and their services were organized. No contract, no bargaining will account for its structure. It was founded on reciprocity. Every member of each caste contributed his services and skills to the support of every member of the other castes. Its sanction was religious, while its function was largely economic. Rather than a simple dual symmetry, a multiple symmetry underlay the caste system: a large number of groups were sharing out their services among each other although they acted independently. Each caste was economically entirely dependent upon the performance of their duties by the other groups. The members of the society could survive only if each caste did its job for the others, yet each caste remained a "self-governing community" and "set up its own standards of life and conduct."12 Territorially the castes cut across village and political boundaries and functioned whatever course political life was taking. Briefly, it can be said that relationships were reciprocative in regard to services, and redistributive in regard to agricultural produce. 228 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India But the reciprocative caste system as a whole was itself an element within the redistributive system of the village. The functions of priest, watchman, barber and carpenter were caste functions and it was by virtue of each member of each caste within the village fulfilling his or her religiously sanctioned duties that the grain heap was there to be divided at harvest time. Cultivator-artisan relations might therefore be said to be both reciprocative and redistributive. The artisan was supply, ing the cultivator with his skills, and the cultivator in turn, and regardless of the specific services the artisan had performed for him, supplied the artisan with agricultural products. At the same time the artisan and the cultivator jointly contributed to the production of a village grain heap which was in turn redistributed to all the residents of the village. This analysis of the pre-British Indian village shows that formal principles are available to us which are capable of describing a non-market economy. There is no reason why such an economy should be described with negative references or irrelevant ones. An economy is not analyzed by placing it before capitalism in an evolutionary sequence; nor by the mere statement that money is not used. Barter, as a classification, is, if anything, inaccurate, for neither interfamily nor intercaste bargaining was practiced. While there is no disputing the poverty of the Indian villager, the system under which he worked did not depend on the fact that he was at a subsistence level. The same principles were as applicable to the well-to-do village as to the poorer ones, and as applicable to the wealthy rulers as to the peasant cultivators. To call the village economy communistic puts the problem in the wrong light, for our present-day concepts of ownership are here inapplicable. Things were not held in common in the Indian village. Rather, different families as well as other groups had different kinds of rights. To say that the services in the village economy were patterned out by reciprocity and the grain by redistribution still leaves open for detailed description the particular procedures used and shares received by the participants. However, it does acquaint us with the structure of the manifold village activities so that we perceive how it came about that these activities were made to mesh. More than that, we may also, within reasonable limits, compare the organization of the Indian village economy with the organization of other economies—group by group, product by product and service by service. Reciprocity and Redistribution in the Indian Village 229 The Nature of Land Revenue The concepts of reciprocity and redistribution will also help to clarify the old problem of where and how land revenue fitted into the structure of the Indian economy. This was, and is, a problem of great practical importance, for the British Raj drew its resources from the land revenue, and today the Indian states still depend upon the same Tevenue for their development programs. Both ease of, and justice in, administration of the revenue depended upon an accurate appraisal of the nature and function of land revenue. The question whether to regard land revenue as a rent or as a tax exercised the minds of British administrators for a century.13 When the East India Company began to govern India in the last half of the eighteenth century land revenue was the major source of revenue for the native rulers. The Company perforce adopted their fiscal system, and set out to rationalize it. Having succeeded to the political position of the native rulers, the Company had also succeeded to their rights to land revenue. It naturally wished to determine the origin, source, and nature of land revenue so as to adjust the assessment and collection of the revenue correctly. The officers of the East India Company, thinking in European terms, saw only two possibilities, and took the view that their administration of the revenue must depend upon the answer. Land revenue was either a tax on land or it was the rent of the land. If land revenue were in the nature of a tax, then it should be administered according to the canons of taxation, which required that the tax should be as low as possible after allowing for legitimate expenses of government. Any surplus from the land over the costs of management, cultivation, and taxation would then be the property of the owner of the land and should go to him. Assessment of the revenue would then present the problem of an equitable allotment of the gross revenue burden among the owners who were made responsible for payment of the revenue. On the other hand, if land revenue were the rent of the land, then there would be no limit to what the government could claim other than what the traffic would bear. As the owner of the land, the government could claim any surplus over the costs of production, and the rent of land would be a legitimate source of profit to the East India Company. Assessment would in principle be a problem of competitive renting of 230 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India land holdings, and the government would not have to worry about the equity of each assessment. While this was the underlying issue of principle in the discussion, three other considerations weighed heavily with the British. Until 1790 the first two of these had shaped policy. One was the absence of a staff of trustworthy civil servants. The other was the great need for revenue. The absence of a staff made it impossible to attempt a just settlement of the revenue in individual cases, so that the Company had to settle for a rough and ready system requiring neither knowledge nor honesty on the part of those responsible for seeing that the revenue flowed into the Company's coffers. The great need for revenue meant that the Company felt it had to charge as much as the traffic would bear, no matter what principle was applicable to the revenue. This amounted to the view that the legitimate expenses of government would absorb the whole of the economic rent, and more if that were possible. Both considerations were met by the system adopted in the early years: the right to collect the revenue was sold by auction, the native tax-farmer being allowed a ten percent allowance for his labor and, in practice, whatever else he could extract from the cultivator. Thus the Company achieved a maximum extraction rate14 and needed few administrators. However, the system could be justified neither on grounds of equity nor on those of efficiency, and certainly led to widespread dissatisfaction and disaffection. The third consideration to modify a Company policy based on the solution to the rent v. revenue controversy was the belief that a stable landowning class could be created to govern the country-side; that this class would build up the agricultural and natural resources of the area; and that the stability and prosperity so achieved would lead to large trading profits for the Company. This meant taking a long view, anticipating ample future gains at the price of a somewhat reduced tax revenue for the present. It was this consideration, combined with the simplicity of the arrangement and the guarantee of a minimum revenue, that led to the introduction of "permanent settlement" in 1790. Permanent settlement meant that the revenue assessment was fixed in perpetuity, the landowner retaining any future increase of income accruing to the land so long as he paid the assessment. The policy of permanent settlement was dropped after 1795, but Reciprocity and Redistribution in the Indian Village 231 until the late 1860's it was constantly upheld by a sizeable number of Company officials and, later, government officials. Temporary settlements, in which the revenue was fixed for periods up to thirty years were made in the areas west of Bengal as they came under Company government, and the question whether land revenue was a rent or a tax came to the fore. The specific issue of fact on which the debate over the nature of land revenue turned was whether the Emperor at Delhi was or was not the owner of the land at the time the Company succeeded to his powers. Such a question of absolute property, being one which can only be asked in a market economy, was in the nature of things insoluble. In dividing the grain heap between the Raja, the cultivators, and the artisans there was no need to differentiate between rent and tax—one only needed to know the operational devices by which the Raja's share was determined. Nevertheless, the debate continued for years. In practice, victory went to those who supported the view that land revenue was a tax. Certainly the permanent assessment of Bengal implied that answer, as did the progressive reductions in the share of rents taken as revenue in the districts to the northwest of Bengal. Did choosing "tax" instead of "rent" make a difference? It is doubtful whether it did. Whatever it deemed to be the correct position, the Company had good reason to reduce the burden of revenue so as to keep the population moderately happy. What did make a difference was the attitude that prompted the question to be put in terms of rent v. tax. The alternative of rent v. tax stemmed from a deep misunderstanding of the nature of the land revenue. The British administrators were treating land revenue as if it were part and parcel of a market system. Once that assumption is made land revenue must be either rent or tax. If it is rent, land revenue is a return to the inherent productive capacity of the soil and must be measured by the difference between the value of the product and the costs of production, for rent implies that the market evaluates the contribution of land to the productive process. But while in an abstract sense there is always a rent for land because land contributes to the productive process, it is impossible to determine its amount unless there is a market on which people express their judgment of that contribution by offering to pay for its use. They do so by paying a rent. When it became apparent to the British adminis- 232 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India trators that there was no market for the use of land they made efforts to calculate the amount of rent which would he paid if there were such a market. This is called "imputing economic rent." The effort of course proved unavailing. How can the value of a product be computed when so much of it is consumed by the producer and never reaches the market? What meaning can be attached to computations based on prices that vary widely within an area? How can one compute costs when virtually all the costs are implicit and there is no such thing as a standard wage for agricultural labor? Economic rent is a quantity that requires a market system, and could not therefore have meaning in the context of the Indian village economy. A decision to regard land revenue as a tax also implied a market. Since government services must employ economic resources and since it may be impossible or undesirable to sell these services on a market, the government must extract a sum from the current income stream, either directly by a tax on payments made, or indirectly on values created by the market. These taxes are generally levied on income, on property, or on transactions. Taxes on income and property are levied as proportions of the value which is arrived at by the "bid and ask" process of the market. Taxes on transactions are either a proportion of the price at which the goods change hands or a flat rate depending on the quantity of goods which change hands. While it is true that the government can raise money by a charge on transactions that are free of market elements, such as a poll-tax, or upon the mere existence of an item, such as "windows in walls," it is generally true that the British had market values and market transfers in mind when they considered taxes. That the market was implicit in the concept of a tax is shown by the first attempts at assessing the land revenue. Assiduous efforts were made to compute the "net assets" of estate in land. These were to be computed by deducting from the gross value of the produce the costs of production including wages of labor and profits on capital. Now, the remainder, the net assets, is by definition economic rent. For the reasons outlined above the attempts to compute net assets were never successful. Eventually, the British administration fell back on going by rule of thumb, and simply tried to find out how much the owner responsible for the payment of land revenue was collecting from his tenants, and then charging him with part of the rent. That land revenue was not a straightforward tax was further illus- Reciprocity and Redistribution in the Indian Village 233 trated by the problems associated with the various proposed methods of levying it. The main proposals were that land revenue be regarded as a share in the gross produce of the land, either in kind or in money value; a money share in the net produce of the land (i.e., the economic rent); or, finally, a money share in the rents actually collected by the proprietor.15 All three met difficulties in administration and in a just application of the principle invoked. A share in kind is difficult to collect, and for a modern government there is the added problem of converting the produce into money. These were not problems for the earlier rulers. In the first place, the taking of a share in kind fitted neatly into the common village harvest and distribution. Secondly, it was evidence of the prerogatives and power of the ruler. Thirdly, the ruler did not need or wish to convert his share into money until well into the Mughal period. The British, on the other hand, did not desire to fit into the village distribution in the personal way in which the Raja did, and furthermore were simultaneously engaged in market trading activities and did not want a share in kind. Eventually, as the concepts of British law and the produce of British industry entered the village, the redistributive system lost much of its relevance. The share of the grainheap, whether in kind or in money, did not accurately reflect ability to pay, and the British did not wish to be affected by the fluctuations in income which such a sharing system involved. If the share of gross produce were to be taken in money there would be the trouble of estimating the produce and arriving at a price for conversion into money values, in the absence of a market. A tax based on economic rent could only prove impossible to assess. It is noteworthy that after nine years of effort in the north western Provinces, the Company's officers observed that it might take another half century to compute the economic rents for the rest of the province. Land revenue based on the rents actually paid, which was the compromise the British finally adopted, was obviously inequitable. In addition, its computation was so burdensome that the assessments were revised only every thirty years. At best, the rents reflected values as of the time the leases were made, but as a rule the actual amounts charged in rent were affected by caste, local custom, and to no small degree, by favoritism. Unless these extraneous considerations were eliminated, the actual rents would not reflect the ability of the various holdings to pay revenue. A complex set of rules therefore came into 234 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India being to guide the officers in their attempts to adjust the recorded rents. These rules boiled down to a general rule that the officer assessing the revenue should try to adjust recorded rents to the rents at which a genuinely competitive market would arrive. However, a tax on economic rent or actual rents paid is not the same as in income tax, and the British system has been criticized on the grounds that taxes on rent are not taxes based on ability to pay, nor can it be shown that they are equitable according to any other generally accepted standard. The fact of the matter is that land revenue cannot be levied in such a way as to satisfy the canons of taxation as understood in the modern world. It is not a tax on values created by the market nor is it a tax on transactions. The incidence of a tax should be foreseeable if it is to be just. Yet the incidence of land revenue is not foreseeable. Even under the original native system the revenue share of the Raja lacked this characteristic. One could alter the shares in the grain heap so as to give certain participants more, but the ultimate effect of merely changing the Raja's share was anything but obvious. Consequently the efforts to adapt the native system to British conceptions of taxation was fraught with difficulties. These perpetual difficulties which beset the British had their roots in their misconception that land revenue was a tax like any other tax commonly levied where a market system obtains. The picture of the village economy as presented in the preceding section shows the correct answer to be that land revenue formed part of a nonmarket system. Taxes are affected by, and in turn affect, the working of the price mechanism, but land revenue under the Mughals and before left unaffected the cultivator's choice of crops, his methods of cultivation, and his reciprocative and redistributive relationships with the village artisans. The cultivator's decisions were made prior to, and independently of, the assessment of land revenue. The solution was, then, that land revenue was the ruler's share in the produce of the land under a redistributive system. It is not a phenomenon of the market order and cannot be translated into market terms. To ask whether land revenue was a rent or a tax was to misconstrue the economic organization of pre-British India. It falsely assumed that the use of market terminology would prove revealing; actually employment of such terminology clouded the issue. To understand the nature of land revenue one must understand the original native system: here the patterning of the Reciprocity and Redistribution in the Indian Village 235 economy in terms of reciprocity and redistribution can alone provide a clear picture. Sir Henry Maine first presented to Western scholars a picture of the village economy. He characterized it as a "status" as opposed to a "contract" economy. While there can be nothing but admiration for this seminal insight, it left unanswered the question of the principles upon which some seemingly intractable problems of status economies rested. Yet once a pattern of these status relationships is drawn, the concepts of reciprocity and redistribution reveal the comparatively simple devices for distributing services and their products. These concepts also throw light on the underlying difficulties which have dogged the efforts of modern administrations to adopt and adapt the devices of a redistributive economy to the market system. The land revenue which was the raja's share in the village grain heap became the foundation stone of British fiscal resources in India, and is still today a major source of government revenue. Even in our time no generally satisfactory system for assessing and collecting this tax has been found. A scheme for patterning nonmarket economic activities such as is suggested here is needed, if we are to understand institutions and devices which have their origin in nonmarket economies. Walter C. Neale Notes to Chapter XI 1. Sir Henry Sumner Maine, Ancient Law (New York, 1906), especially chapters I, V, and VIII; Village Communities in the East and West (London, 1861); Dissertations on Early Law and Custom (New York, 1886) especially chapters I through IV. 2. See B. H. Baden-Powell, The Origin and Growth of Village Communities in India (London, 1899), especially in regard to geographical variations in the village hierarchy, and the impossibility of establishing an original or "pure" village type. 3. Now part of Uttar Pradesh, in north-central India. 4. W. C. Bennet, Final Settlement Report on District Gonda (Allahabad, 1878), pp. 48-9. 5. Op. cit, pp. 43-8. 6. A bigha is a measure of land which varied from place to place, from a quarter of an acre in Bengal to two-thirds of an acre in U.P, with other variants both 236 Aztec-Maya; Dahomey; Berber; India elsewhere and within these provinces. The right to the standing crop was called biswa. 7. Apparently a typical "debt-slave." 8. One twenty-second of a maund of eighty-two pounds. 9. A fortieth of a maund. 10. In addition, the exact size of a pansefi, or seer varied from village to village, and for that matter still does. 11. It may be of interest to mention that distributions in kind at the time of harvest are still widespread in India. In the Deccan they are known as "balvta" payments; in the Punjam as payments to "kamins." These are still customary rather than bargained shares, but the figures this writer has seen for individual holdings indicate that such payments are now a small proportion of artisans' and servants' income. 12. L. S. S. O'Malley, Modern India and the West (London, New York, 1941), p. 5. 13. By the last quarter of the nineteenth century the problem had become, so far as the British officials were concerned, academic. The methods of assessing and collecting the revenue had been established and no new insight into the original state of affairs would have induced the British to alter their procedures. When Baden-Powell (op. cit.), writing in the 1890's, mentioned the history of the dispute over the nature of land revenue, but insisted most strongly that it was a matter of no importance because it was by then clear that land revenue was de iacto and de jure a prior charge on the land, its produce being "hypothecated" to the land revenue by virtue of British legislation. 14. There is evidence that optimistic tax farmers actually overrated their capacity to collect, and that the revenue may have exceeded the maximum the Company should legitimately have expected. 15. By the nineteenth century something which we might as well call rents were paid. They grew out of the Mughal conversions of revenue shares into money payments in some districts, but mostly out of the legal concepts imposed by the British. The amounts paid and here called rents were a mixture of traditional payments of various sorts and of the market forces introduced by the British. PART III Institutional Analysis XII The Wlace of economies in Societies few social scientists today accept in the whole the Enlightenment's ingenuous view of pristine man contracting for his freedoms and bartering his goods in bush and jungle to form his society and economy. The discoveries of Comte, Quetelet, Marx, Maine, Weber, Malinowski, Durkheim and Freud figure predominantly in the accretion of our current knowledge that the social process is a tissue of relationships between man as biological entity and the unique structure of symbols and techniques that results in maintaining his existence. But while in this sense we have discovered the reality of society, the new knowledge has not produced a vision of society comparable in popularity to the traditional picture of an atomistic individualism. At important junctures we fall back on the earlier rationalizations of man as a utilitarian atom. And nowhere is this lapse more apparent than in our ideas concerning the economy. Approaching the economy in any of its widely varied aspects, the social scientist is still hampered by an intellectual heritage of man as an entity with an innate propensity to truck, barter and ex.-^^!^9R^&iMgJoians^ex. This remains so in spite of all the protestations against "economic man" and the intermittent attempts to provide a social framework for the economy. The economic rationalism to which we are heir posits a type of action as sui generis economic. In this perspective an actor—a single man, a family, a whole society—is seen facing a natural environment that is slow to yield its life-giving elements. Economic action—or, more precisely, economizing action, the essence of rationality—is, then, re- 239 240 Institutional Analysis garded as a manner of disposing of tíme and energy so that a maximum of goals are achieved out of this man-nature relationship. And the economy becomes the locus of such action. It is, of course, admitted that, I! in reality, the operation of this economy may be influenced in any number of ways by other factors of a noneconomic character, be they political, military, artistic, or religious. But the essential core of utilitarian rationality remains as the model of the economy. This view of the economy as the locus of units allocating, saving up, marketing surpluses, forming prices, grew out of the Western milieu of the eighteenth century and it is admittedly relevant under the institutional arrangements of a market system, since actual conditions here roughly satisfy the requirements set by the economistic postulate. But does this postulate allow us to infer the generality of a market system in the realm of empirical fact? The claim of formal economics to an historically universal applicability answers in the affirmative. In effect this argues the virtual presence of a market system in every society, whether such a system is empirically present or not. All human economy might then be regarded as a potential supply-demand-price mechanism, and the actual processes, whatever they are, explained in terms of this hypostatization. If empirical research is ever to enhance our understanding of the basic operation and the position of various forms of the economy in different societies, we must put the test of relevance to this economistic postulate. Approaching the economic process from the vantage point of the new knowledge we have gained of the reality of society, we must say that there is no necessary relationship between economizing action and the empirical economy. The institutional structure of the economy need not compel, as with the market system, economizing actions. The implications of such an insight for all the social sciences which must deal with the economy could hardly be more far-reaching. Nothing less than a fundamentally different starting point for the analysis of the human economy as a social process is required. In search for a new beginning, we turn from the economizing to the substantive meaning of the term "economic," unfashionable though it is. This is not to ignore the popular use of "economic" which compounds economizing with materiality: it is merely to urge the limited applicability of that common-sense compound. Unless a man has food to eat, he must starve, be he rational or not: but his safety, indeed his education, art and religion also require material means, 241 The Place of Economies in Societies 471 weapons, schools, temples of wood, stone or steel. This fact was, of course, never overlooked. Time and again it was urged that "economics" should be based upon the whole range of man's material want satisfaction—his material wants, on the one hand, the means of satisfying his wants, be these material or not, on the other. As experts are unanimous to recognize, all strivings for such a naturalistic economics remained unsuccessful. The reason is simple. No merely naturalistic concept of the economy can even approximately compete with economic analysis in explaining the mechanics of livelihood under a market system. And since the economy in general was equated with the market system those naive attempts to replace economic analysis by a naturalistic scheme stood justly discredited. But was this a conclusive argument against the use of the substantive concept of the economy in the social sciences? By no means. It was overlooked that economic theory, economic analysis, or plain economics is only one of several disciplines that busy themselves with the livelihood of man from the material angle, that is, the economy. Practically, it is no more than a study of market phenomena; apart from mere generalities its relevance to other than market systems, e.g., a planned economy, is negligible. What can it do, for instance, for the anthropologist to disentangle the economy from the general tissues of society under a kinship system? In the absence of markets and market prices, the economist cannot be of help to the student of primitive economies; indeed, he may hinder him. Or take the sociologist faced with the question of the changing place occupied by economies in societies as a whole. Unless we keep to times and regions where price-making markets are extant, economics cannot supply him with orientation of any value. This is even more true of the economic historian outside of that slim strip of a few centuries in which the price-making markets and consequently money as a means of exchange have become general. Prehistory, early history, and indeed, as Karl Bücher was the first to proclaim, the whole of history apart from those last centuries, had economies the organization of which differed from anything assumed by the economist. And the difference, we now begin to infer, can be reduced to one single point—they possessed no system of price-making markets. In the whole range of economic disciplines, the point of common interest is set by the process through which material want satisfaction is provided. Locating this process and examining its operation can only be achieved by shifting the emphasis from a type of 242 Institutional Analysis rational action to the configuration of goods and person movements which actually make up the economy. To shift in natural science from one conceptual framework to another is one thing; to do so in the social sciences is quite another. It is like rebuilding a house, foundation, walls, fittings and all, while con-| tinuing to live in it. We must rid ourselves of the ingrained notion that j the_ economy is a field of experience of which human beings have necessarily always been conscious. To employ a metaphor, the facts of the economy were originally embedded in situations that were not in themselves of an economic nature, neither the ends nor the means being primarily material. The crystallization of the concept of the economy was a matter of time and history. But neither time nor history have provided us with those conceptual tools required to penetrate the maze of social relationships in which the economy was embedded. This is the task of what we will here call institutional analysis. Karl Polanyi, Conrad M. Arensberg, and Harry W. Pearson XIII Tlie Economy as Instituted ^Process our main purpose in this chapter is to determine the meaning that can be attached with consistency to the term "economic" in all the social sciences. The simple recognition from which all such attempts must start is the fact that in referring to human activities the term economic is a compound of two meanings that have independent roots. We will call them the substantive and the formal meaning. The substantive meaning of economic derives from man's dependence for his living upon nature and his fellows. It refers to the interchange with his natural and social environment, in so far as this results in supplying him with the means of material want satisfaction,,. The formal meaning of economic derives from the logical character of the means-ends relationship, as apparent in such words as "economical" or "economizing." It refers to a definite situation of choice, namely, that between the different uses of means induced by an insufficiency of those means. If we call the rules governing choice of means the logic of rational action, then we may denote this variant of logic, with an improvised term, as formal economics. The two root meanings of "economic," the substantive and the formal, have nothing in common. The latter derives from logic, the former from fact. The formal meaning implies a set of rules referring to choice between the alternative uses of insufficient means. The substantive meaning implies neither choice nor insufficiency of means; man's livelihood may cr may not involve the necessity of choice and, if choice there be, it need not be induced by the limiting effect of a "scar- 243 244 Institutional Analysis city" of the means; indeed, some of the most important physical and social conditions of livelihood such as the availability of air and water or a loving mother's devotion to her infant are not, as a rule, so limiting. The cogency that is in play in the one case and in the other differs as the power of syllogism differs from the force of gravitation. The laws of the one are those of the mind; the laws of the other are those of nature. The two meanings couIcTriot be further apart; semantically they lie in opposite directions of the compass. It is our proposition that only the substantive meaning of "eco-! nomic" is capable of yielding the concepts that are required by the social sciences for an investigation of all the empirical economies of the past and present. The general frame of reference that we endeavor -to construct requires, therefore, treatment of the subject matter in \ substantive terms. The immediate obstacle in our path lies, as indicated, ' in that concept of "economic" in which the two meanings, the substantive and the formal, are naively compounded. Such a merger of meanings is, of course, unexceptionable as long as we remain conscious of its restrictive effects. But the current concept of economic fuses the "subsistence" and the "scarcity" meanings of economic without a sufficient awareness of the dangers to clear thinking inherent in that merger. This combination of terms sprang from logically adventitious circumstances. The last two centuries produced in Western Europe and North America an organization of man's livelihood to which the rules of choice happened to be singularly applicable. This form of the economy consisted in a system of price-making markets. Since acts of exchange, as practiced under such a system, involve the participants in choices induced by an insufficiency of means, the system could be reduced to a pattern that lent itself to the application of methods based on the formal meaning of "economic." As long as the economy was controlled by such a system, the formal and the substantive meanings would in practice coincide. Laymen accepted this compound concept as a matter of course; a Marshall, Pareto or Dürkheim equally adhered to it. Menger alone in his posthumous work criticized the term, but neither he nor Max Weber, nor Talcott Parsons after him, apprehended the significance of the disjunction for^sociological ^analysis. Indeed, there seemed to be no valid reason for distinguishing between two root meanings of a term which, as we said, were bound to coincide in practice. The Economy as Instituted Process 245 While it would have been therefore sheer pedantry to differentiate in common parlance)between the two meanings of "economic," their merging in one concept nevertheless proved a bane to a precise methodology in the social sciences. Economics naturally formed an exception, since under the market system its terms were bound to be fairly realistic. But the anthropologist, the sociologist or the historian, each in his study of the place occupied by the economy in human society, was faced with a great variety of institutions other than markets, in which man's livelihood was embedded. Its problems could not be attacked with the help of an analytical method devised for a special form of the economy, which was dependent upon the presence of specific market elements.1 This lays down the rough sequence of the argument. / ^ We will begin with a closer examination of the concepts derived from the two meanings of "economic," starting with the formal and thence proceeding to the substantive meaning. It should then prove possible to describe the empirical economies—whether primitive or archaic—according to the manner in which the economic process_is if instituted. The three institutions of trade, money and market will provide a "test case. They have previously been defined in formal terms only; thus any other than a marketing approach was barred. Their treatment in substantive terms should then bring us nearer to the desired universal frame of reference. The Formal and the Substantive Meanings of "Economic" Let us examine the formal concepts starting from the manner in which the logic of rational action produces formal economics, and the latter, in turn, gives rise to economic analysis. '/ Rational action is here defined as choice of means in relation to ends. Means are anything appropriate to serve the end, whether by virtue of the laws of nature or by virtue of the laws of the game. Thus "rational" does not refer either to ends or to means, but rather to the relating of means to ends. It is not assumed, for instance, that it is more rational to wish to live than to wish to die, or that, in the first case, it is more rational to seek a long life through the means of science than through those of superstition. For whatever the end, it is rational to choose one's means accordingly; and as to the means, it would not be 246 Institutional Analysis rational to act upon any other test than that which one happens to believe in. Thus it is rational for the suicide to select means that will accomplish his death; and if he be an adept of black magic, to pay a witch doctor to contrive that end. The logic of rational action applies, then, to all conceivable means and ends covering an almost infinite variety of human interests. In chess or technology, in religious life or philosophy ends may range from commonplace issues to the most recondite and complex ones. Similarly, in the field of the economy, where ends may range from the momentary assuaging of thirst to the attaining of a sturdy old age, while the corresponding means comprise a glass of water and a combined reliance on filial solicitude and open air life, respectively. Assuming that the choice is induced by an insufficiency of the means, the logic of rational action turns into that variant of the theory of choice which we have called formal econorriies. It is still logically unrelated to the concept of the human economy, but it is closer to it hy one step. Formal economics refers, as we said, to a situation of I choice that arises out of an insufficiency of means. This is the so-called \ scarcity postulate. It requires, first-insufficiency of means; second, that choice be induced by that insufficiency. Insufficiency of means in relation to ends is determined with the help of the simple operation of ■"earmarking," which demonstrates whether .there is or is not enough to go round. For the insufficiency to induce choice there must be given more than one use to the means, as well as graded ends, i.e., at least two ends ordered in sequence of preference. Both conditions are factual. It is irrelevant whether the reason for which means can be used in one way only happens to be conventional or technological; the same is true of the grading of ends. /Having thus defined choice, insufficiency and scarcity in operational J>erms, it is easy to see that as there is choice of means without in-/sufficiency, so there is insufficiency of means without choice. Choice may be induced by a preference for right against wrong (moral choice) or, at a crossroads, where two or more paths happen to lead to our destination, possessing identical advantages and disadvantages (operationally induced choice). In either case an abundance of means, far from diminishing the difficulties of choice, would rather increase them. Of course, scarcity may or may not be present in almost all fields of rational action. Not all philosophy is sheer imaginative creativity, it may also be a matter of economizing with assumptions. Or, to get back The Economy as Instituted Process 247 to the sphere of man's livelihood, in some civilizations scarcity situa- j tions seem to be almost exceptional, in others they appear to be pain-! fully general. In either case the presence or absence of scarcity is a ' question of fact, whether the insufficiency is due to Nature or to Law. j Last but not least, economic analysis. This discipline results from the application of formal economics to an economy of a definite type, L namely, amarket system. T-he,economy is here embodied in institutions that cause individual choices/to give rise to interdependent movements that constitute the economic process. This is achieved by generalizing the use of price-making markets. All goods and services, including the use of labor, land and capital are available for purchase in markets and have, therefore, a price; all forms of income derive from the sale of goods and services—wages, rent and interest, respectively, appearing only as different instances of price according to the items sold. The general introduction of purchasing power as the means of acquisition converts the process of meeting requirements into an allocation of insufficient means with alternative uses, namely, money. It follows that both the conditions of choice and its consequences are quantifiable in the form of prices. It can be asserted that by concentrating on price as the economic fact par excellence, the formal method of approach offers | a total description of the economy as determined by choices induced1 by an insufficiency of means. The conceptual tools by which this is performed make up the discipline of economic analysis. From this follow the limits within which economic analysis can prove effective as a method. The use of the formal meaning denotes the economy as a sequence of acts of economizing, i.e., of choices induced by scarcity situations. While the rules governing such acts are universal, the extent to which the rules are applicable to a definite economy depends upon whether or not that economy is, in actual fact, a sequence of such acts. To produce quantitative results, the locational and appropriational movements, of which the economic process consists, must here present themselves as functions of social actions in regard to insufficient means and oriented on resulting prices. Such a situation obtains only under a market system. ^ The relation between formal economics and the human economy is, in effect, contingent. Outside of a system of price-making markets economic analysis loses most of its relevance as a method of inquiry into the working of the economy. A centrally planned economy, relying on nonmarket prices is a well-known instance. 248 Institutional Analysis The fount of the substantive concept is the empirical economy. It can be briefly (if not engagingly) defined as an instituted process of interaction between man and his environment, which results in a continuous supply of want satisfying material means. Want satisfaction is "material," if it involves the use of material means to satisfy ends; in the case of a definite type of physiological wants, such as food or shelter, this includes the use of so-called services only, y The economy, then, is an instituted process. Two concepts stand > out, that of "process" and its "institutedness." Let us see what they contribute to our frame of reference. - - Process Suggests analysis in terms of motion. The movements refer either to changes in location, or in appropriation, or both. In other words, the material elements may alter their position either by changing place or by changing "hands"; again, these otherwise very different shifts of position may go together or not. Between them, these two kinds of movements may be said to exhaust the possibilities comprised in the economic process as a natural and social phenomenon. f Locational movements include production, alongside of transportation, to which the spatial shifting of objects is equally essential. Goods are of a lower order or of a higher order, according to the manner of their usefulness from the consumer's point of view. This famous "order of goods" sets consumers' goods against producers' goods, according to whether they satisfy wants directly, or only indirectly, through a combination with other goods. This type of movement of the elements represents an essential of the economy in the substantive sense of the term, namely, production. } The appropriative movement governs both what is usually referred to as the circulation of goods and their administration. In the first case, the appropriative movement results from transactions, in the second case, from dispositions. Accordingly, a transaction is an appropriative movement as between hands; a disposition is a one-sided act of the hand, to which by force of custom or of law definite appropriative effects are attached. The term "hand" here serves to denote public bodies and offices as well as private persons or firms, the difference between them being mainly a matter of internal organization. It should be noted, however, that in the nineteenth century private hands were commonly associated with transactions, while public hands were usually credited with dispositions. In this choice of terms a number of further definitions are implied. The Economy as Instituted Process 249 Social activities, insofar as they form part of the process, may be called economic; institutions are so called to the extent to which they contain a concentration of such activities; any components of the process may be regarded as economic elements. These elements can be conveniently grouped as ecological, technological or societal according to whether they belong primarily to the natural environment, the mechanical equipment, or the human setting. Thus a series of concepts, old and new, accrue to our frame of reference by virtue of the process aspect of the economy. Nevertheless, reduced to a mechanical, biological and psychological interaction of elements that economic process would possess no all-round reality. It contains no more than the bare bones of the processes of production and transportation, as well as of the appropriative changes. In the absence of any indication of societal conditions from which the motives of the individuals spring, there would be little, if anything, to sustain the interdependence of the movements and their recurrence on which the unity and the stability of the process depends. The interacting elements of nature and humanity would form no coherent unit, in effect, no structural entity that could be said to have a function in society or to possess a history. The process would lack the very qualities which cause everyday thought as well as scholarship to turn towards matters of human livelihood as a field of eminent practical interest as well as theoretical and moral dignity. Hence the transcending importance of the institutional aspect of the economy. What occurs on the process level between man and soil in hoeing a plot or what on the conveyor belt in the constructing of an automobile is, prima facie a mere jig-sawing of human and nonhuman movements. From the institutional point of view it is a mere referent of terms like labor and capital, craft and union, slacking and speeding, the spreading of risks and the other semantic units of the social context. The choice between capitalism and socialism, for instance, refers to two different ways of instituting modern technology in the process of production. On the policy level, again, the industrialization of underdeveloped countries involves, on the one hand, alternative techniques; on the other, alternative methods of instituting them. Our conceptual distinction is vital for any understanding of the interdependence of technology and institutions as well as their relative independence. The instituting of the economic process vests that process with unity and stability; it produces a structure with a definite function in 250 Institutional Analysis society; it shifts the place of the process in society, thus adding significance to its history; it centers interest on values, motives and policy. Unity and stability, structure and function, history and policy spell out operationally the content of our assertion that the human economy is an instituted process. ; ' The human economy, then, is embedded and enmeshed in institu-! tipns, economic and noneconqmic. The inclusion of the noncconomic is vital. For religion or government may be as important for the structure and functioning of the economy as monetary institutions or the availability of tools and machines themselves that lighten the toil of L labor. The study of the shifting place occupied by the economy in society is therefore no other than the study of the manner in which the economic process is instituted at different times and places. This requires a special tool box. Reciprocity, Redistribution, and Exchange A study of how empirical economies are instituted should start from the way in which the economy acquires unity and stability, that is the interdependence and recurrence of its parts. This is achieved through a combination of a very few patterns which may be called forms«of integration. Since they occur side by side on different levels and in different sectors of the economy it may often be impossible to select one of them as dominant so that they could be employed for a classification of empirical economies as a whole. Yet by differentiating between sectors and levels of the economy those forms offer a means of describing the economic process in comparatively simple terms, thereby introducing a measure of order into its endless variations. Empirically, we find the main patterns to be reciprocity, redistribution and exchange. Reciprocity denotes movements between correlative points of symmetrical groupings; redistribution designates appropri-ational movements toward a center and out of it again; exchange refers here to vice-versa movements taking place as between "hands" under a market system. Reciprocity, then, assumes for a background symmetrically arranged groupings; redistribution is dependent upon the presence of some measure of centricity in the group; exchange in order to produce integration requires a system of price-making markets. It is The Economy as Instituted Process 251 apparent that the different patterns of integration assume definite institutional supports. At this point some clarification may be welcome. The terms reciprocity, redistribution and exchange, by which we refer to our forms of integration, are often employed to denote personal interrelations.. Superficially then it might seem as if the forms of integration merely reflected aggregates of the respective forms of individual behavior: If mutuality between individuals were frequent, a reciprocative integration would emerge; where sharing among individuals were common, redistributive integration would be present; similarly, frequent acts of barter between individuals would result in exchange as a form of integration. If this were so, our patterns of integration would be indeed no more than simple aggregates of corresponding forms of behavior on the personal level. To be sure, we insisted that the integrative effect was ] conditioned by the presence of definite institutional arrangements, j such as symmetrical organizations, central points and market systems, respectively. But such arrangements seem to represent a mere aggregate of the same personal patterns the eventual effects of which they are supposed to condition. The significant fact is that mere aggregates of the personal behaviors irTquestion do not by themselves produce such structures. Reciprocity behavior between individuals integrates the economy only if symmetrically organized structures, such as a symmetrical system of kinship groups, are given. But a kinship system never arises as the result of mere reciprocating behavior on the personal level. Similarly, in regard to redistribution. It presupposes the presence of an allocative center in the community, yet the organization and validation of such a center does not come about merely as a consequence of frequent acts of sharing as between individuals. Finally, the same is true of the market system. Acts of exchange on the personal f level produce prices only if they occur under a system of price-making markets, an institutional setup which is nowhere created by mere random acts of exchange. We do not wish to imply, of course, that those supporting patterns are the outcome of some mysterious forces acting outside the range of personal or individual behavior. We merely insist that if, in any given case, the societal effects of individual behavior depend on the presence of definite institutional conditions, these conditions do not for that reason result from the personal behavior in ques-i tion. Superficially, the supporting pattern may seem to result from a | cumulation of a corresponding kind of personal behavior, but the vital 252 Institutional Analysis -( I elements of organization and yjhdation are necessarily contributed by -an altogether different type of behavior. »' The first writer to our knowledge to have hit upon the factual connection between reciprocative behavior on the interpersonal level, on the one hand, and given symmetrical groupings, on the other, was the anthropologist Richard Thurnwald, in 1915, in an empirical study on the marriage system of the Banaro of New Guinea. Bronislaw Mali-nowski, some ten years later, referring to Thurnwald,' predicted that socially relevant reciprocation would regularly be found to rest on symmetrical forms of basic social organization. His own description of the Trobriand kinship system as well as of the Kula trade bore out the pointy This lead was followed up by this writer, in regarding symmetry as merely one of several supporting patterns. He then added redistribu- § tion and exchange to reciprocity, as further forms of integration; similarly, he added centricity and market to symmetry, as other instances of institutional support. Hence our forms of integration and supporting structure patterns. This should help to explain why in the economic sphere interpersonal behavior so often fails to have the expected societal effects in the absence of definite institutional preconditions. Only in a symmetrically organized environment will reciprocative behavior result in economic institutions of any importance; only where allocative centers have been set up can individual acts of sharing produce a redistributive economy; and only in the presence of a system of price-making markets will exchange acts of individuals result in fluctuating prices that integrate the economy. Otherwise such acts of barter will remain ineffective and therefore tend not to occur. Should they nevertheless happen, in a random fashion, a violent emotional reaction would set in, as against acts of indecency or acts of treason, since trading behavior is never emotionally indifferent behavior and is not, therefore, tolerated by opinion outside of the approved channels. Let us now return to our forms of integration. A group which deliberately undertook to organize its economic relationships on a reciprocative footing would, to effect its purpose, have to split up into sub-groups the corresponding members of which could identify one another as such. Members of Group A would then be able to establish relationships of reciprocity with their counterparts in Group B and vice versa. But symmetry is not restricted to duality. Three, four, or more groups may be symmetrical in regard to two or The Economy as Instituted Process 253 more axes; also members of the groups need not reciprocate with one another but may do so with the corresponding members of third groups toward which they stand in analogous relations. A Trobriand man's responsibility is toward his sister's family. But he himself is not on that account assisted by his sister's husband, but, if he is married, by his own wife's brother—a member of a third, correspondingly placed family. Aristotle taught that to every kind of community (koinonia) there corresponded a kind of good-will (philia) amongst its members which expressed itself in reciprocity (antipeponthos). This was true both of the more permanent communities such as families, tribes or city states as of those less permanent ones that may be comprised in, and subordinate to, the former. In our terms this implies a tendency in the larger communities to develop a multiple symmetry in regard to which reciprocative behavior may develop in the subordinate communities. The closer the members of the encompassing community feel drawn to one another, the more general will be the tendency among them to develop reciprocative attitudes in regard to specific relationships limited in space, time or otherwise. Kinship, neighborhood, or totem belong to the more permanent and comprehensive groupings; within their compass voluntary and semi-voluntary associations of a military, vocational, religious or social character create situations in which, at least transitorily or in regard to a given locality or a typical situation, there would form symmetrical groupings the members of which practice some sort of mutuality. Reciprocity as a form of integration gains greatly in power through its capacity of employing both redistribution and exchange as subordinate methods. Reciprocity may be attained through a sharing of the burden of labor according to definite rules of redistribution as when taking things "in turn." Similarly, reciprocity is sometimes attained through exchange at set equivalencies for the benefit of the partner who happens to be short of some kind of necessities—a fundamental institution in ancient Oriental societies. In nonmarket economies these two forms of integration—reciprocity and redistribution—occur in effect usually together. Redistribution obtains within a group to the extent to which the allocation of goods is collected in one hand and takes place by virtue of custom, law or ad hoc central decision. Sometimes it amounts to a physical collecting accompanied by storage-cum-redistribution, at other 8 | 254 Institutional Analysis times the "collecting" is not physical, but merely appropriational, i.e., rights of disposal in the physical location of the goods. Redistribution occurs for many reasons, on all civilizational levels, from the primitive hunting tribe to the vast storage systems of ancient Egypt, Sumeria, Babylonia or Peru. In large countries differences of soil and climate may make redistribution necessary; in other cases it is caused by discrepancy in point of time, as between harvest and consumption. With a hunt, any other method of distribution would lead to disintegration of the horde or band, since only "division of labor" can here ensure results; a redistribution of purchasing power may be valued for its own sake, i.e., for the purposes demanded by social ideals as in the modern welfare state. The principle remains the same—collecting into, and distributing from, a center. Redistribution may also apply to a group smaller than society, such as the household or manor irrespective of the way in which the economy as a whole is integrated. The best known instances are the Central African kraal, the Hebrew patriarchal household, the Greek estate of Aristotle's time, the Roman familia, the medieval manor, or the typical large peasant household before the general marketing of grain. However, only under a comparatively advanced form of agricultural society is householding practicable, and then, fairly general. Before that, the widely spread "small family" is not economically instituted, except for some cooking of food; the use of pasture, land or cattle is still dominated by redistributive or reciprocative methods on a wider than family scale. Redistribution, too, is apt to integrate groups at all levels and all degrees of permanence from the state itself to units of a transitory character. Here, again, as with reciprocity, the more closely knit the encompassing unit, the more varied will the subdivisions be in which redistribution can effectively operate. Plato taught that the number of citizens in the state should be 5040. This figure was divisible in 59 different ways, including division by the first ten numerals. For the assessment of taxes, the forming of groups for business transactions, the carrying of military and other burdens "in turn," etc., it would allow the widest scope, be explained. Exchange in order to serve as a form of integration requires the support of a system of price-making markets. Three kinds of exchange should therefore be distinguished: The merely locational movement of a "changing of places" between the hands (operational exchange); the appropriational movements of exchange, either at a set rate (decisional The Economy as Instituted Process 255 exchange) or at a bargained rate (integrative exchange). In so far as exchange at a set rate is in question, the economy is integrated by the factors which fix that rate, not by the market mechanism. Even price-making markets are integrative only if they are linked up in a system which tends to spread the effect of prices to markets other than those directly affected. Higgling-haggling has been rightly recognized as being of the essence of bargaining behavior. In order for exchange to be integrative the behavior of the partners must be oriented on producing a price that is as favorable to each partner as he can make it. Such a behavior contrasts sharply with that of exchange at a set price. The ambiguity of the term "gain" tends to cover up the difference. Exchange at set prices involves no more than the gain to either party implied in the decision of exchanging; exchange at fluctuating prices aims at a gain that can be attained only by an attitude involving a distinctive antagonistic relationship between the partners. The element of antagonism, however diluted, that accompanies this variant of exchange is ineradicable. No community intent on protecting the fount of solidarity between its members can allow latent hostility to develop around a matter as vital to animal existence and, therefore, capable of arousing as tense anxieties as food. Hence the universal banning of transactions of a gainful nature in regard to food and foodstuffs in primitive and archaic society. The very widely spread ban on higgling-haggling over victuals automatically removes price-making markets from the realm of early institutions. Traditional groupings of economies which roughly approximate a classification according to the dominant forms of integration are illuminating. What historians are wont to call "economic systems" seem to fall fairly into this pattern. Dominance of a form of integration is here identified with the degree to which it comprises land and labor in society. So-called savage society, is characterized by the integration of land and labor into the economy by way of the ties of kinship. In feudal society the ties of fealty determine the fate of land and the labor that goes with it. In the floodwater empires land was largely distributed and sometimes redistributed by temple or palace, and so was labor, at least in its dependent form. The rise of the market to a ruling force in the economy can be traced by noting the extent to which land and food were mobilized through exchange, and labor was turned into a commodity free to be purchased in the market. This may help to explain 256 Institutional Analysis I the relevance of the historically untenable stages theory of slavery, | serfdom and wage labor that is traditional with Marxism—a grouping which flowed from the conviction that the character of the economy was set by the status of labor. However, the integration of the soil into the economy should be regarded as hardly less vital. In any case, forms of integration do not represent "stages" of development. No sequence in time is implied. Several subordinate forms may be present alongside of the dominant one, which may itself recur after a temporary eclipse. Tribal societies practice reciprocity and redistribution, while archaic societies are predominantly redistributive, though to some extent they may allow room for exchange. Reciprocity, which plays a dominant part in some Melanesian communities, occurs as a not unimportant although subordinate trait in the redistributive archaic empires, where foreign trade (carried on by gift and countergift) is still largely organized on the principle of reciprocity. Indeed, during a war emergency it was reintroduced on a large scale in the twentieth century, under the name of lend-lease, with societies where otherwise marketing and exchange were dominant. Redistribution, the ruling method in tribal and archaic society beside which exchange plays only a minor part, grew to great importance in the later Roman Empire and is actually gaining ground today in some modern industrial states. The Soviet Union is an extreme instance. Conversely, more than once before in the course of human history markets have played a part in the economy, although never on a territorial scale, or with an institutional comprehensiveness comparable to that of the nineteenth century. However, here again a change is noticeable. In our century, with the lapse of the gold standard, a recession of the world role of markets from their nineteenth century peak set in—a turn of the trend which, incidentally, takes us back to our starting point, namely, the increasing inadequacy of our limited marketing definitions for the purposes of the social scientist's study of the economic field. Forms of Trade, Money Uses, and Market Elements The restrictive influence of the marketing approach on the interpretation of trade and money institutions is incisive: inevitably, the market appears as the locus of exchange, trade as the actual exchange, and money as the means of exchange. Since trade is directed by prices The Economy as Instituted Process 257 and prices are a function of the market, all trade is market trade, just as all money is exchange money. The market is the generating institution of which trade and money are the functions. Such notions are not true to the facts of anthropology and history. Trade, as well as some money uses, are as old as mankind; while markets, although meetings of an economic character may have existed as early as the neolithic, did not gain importance until comparatively late in history. Price-making markets, which alone are constitutive of a market system, were to all accounts non-existent before the first millennium of antiquity, and then only to be eclipsed by other forms of integration. Not even these main facts however could be uncovered as long as trade and money were thought to be limited to the exchange form of integration, as its specifically "economic" form. The long periods of history when reciprocity and redistribution integrated the economy and the considerable ranges within which, even in modern times, they continued to do so, were put out of bounds by a restrictive terminology. -; Viewed as an exchange system, or, in brief, catallactically, trade, money and market form an indivisible whole. Their common conceptual framework is the market. Trade appears as a two-way movement of goods through the market, and money as quantifiable goods used for indirect exchange in order to facilitate that movement. Such an approach must induce a more or less tacit acceptance of the heuristic principle according to which, where trade is in evidence, markets should be assumed, and where money is in evidence trade, and therefore markets, should be assumed. Naturally, this leads to seeing markets where there are none and ignoring trade and money where they are present, because markets happen to be absent. The cumulative effect must be to create a stereotype of the economies of less familiar times and places, something in the way of an artificial landscape with only little or no resemblance to the original. A separate analysis of trade, money and markets is therefore in order. 1. forms of trade From the substantive point of view, trade is a relatively peaceful method of acquiring goods which are not available on the spot. It is 258 Institutional Analysis external to the group, similar to activities which we are used to associating with hunts, slaving expeditions, or piratic raids. In either case the point is acquisition and carrying of goods from a distance. What distinguishes trade from the questing for game, booty, plunder, rare woods or exotic animals, is the two-sidedness of the movement, which also ensures its broadly peaceful and fairly regular character. / From the catallactic viewpoint, trade is the movement of goods on their way through the market. All commodities—goods produced for sale—are potential objects of trade; one commodity is moving in one direction, the other in the opposite direction; the movement is controlled by prices: trade and market are co-terminous. All trade is market trade. Again, like hunt, raid or expedition under native conditions, trade is not so much an individual as rather a group activity, in this respect closely akin to the organization of wooing and mating, which is often concerned with the acquisition of wives from a distance by more or less peaceful means. Trade thus centers in the meeting of different communities, one of its purposes being the exchange of goods. Such meetings do not, like price-making markets, produce rates of exchange, but on the contrary they rather presuppose such rates. Neither the persons of individual traders nor motives of individual gain are involved. Whether a chief or king is acting for the community after having collected the "export" goods from its members, or whether the group meets bodily their counterparts on the beach for the purpose of exchange—in either case the proceedings are essentially collective. Exchange between "partners in trade" is frequent, but so is, of course, partnership in wooing and mating. Individual and collective activities are intertwined. Emphasis on "acquisition of goods from a distance" as a constitutive element in trade should bring out the dominant role played by the import interest in the early history of trade. In the nineteenth century export interests loomed large—a typically catallactic phenomenon. Since something must be carried over a distance and that in two opposite directions, trade, in the nature of things, has a number of constituents such as personnel, goods, carrying, and two-sidedness, each of which can be broken down according to sociologically or technologically significant criteria. In following up those four factors we may hope to learn something about the changing place of trade in society. The Economy as Instituted Process 259 First, the persons engaged in trade. "Acquisition of goods from a distance" may be practiced either from motives attaching to the trader's standing in society, and as a rule comprising elements of duty or public service (status motive); or it may be done for the sake of the material gain accruing to him personally from the buying and selling transaction in hand (profit motive). In spite of many possible combinations of those incentives, honor . and duty on the one hand, profit on the other, stand out as sharply distinct primary motivations. If the "status motive," as is quite often the case, is reinforced by material benefits, the latter do not as a rule % take the form of gain made on exchange, but rather of treasure or en-\ dowment with landed revenue bestowed on the trader by king or | temple or lord, by way of recompense. Things being what they are, I gains made on exchange do not usually add up to more than paltry : sums that bear no comparison with the wealth bestowed by his lord i upon the resourceful and successfully venturing trader. Thus he who trades for the sake of duty and honor grows rich, while he who trades for filthy lucre remains poor—an added reason why gainful motives are under a shadow in archaic society. Another way of approaching the question of personnel is from the angle of the standard of life deemed appropriate to their status by the community to which they belong. Archaic society in general knows, as a rule, no other figure of a trader than that which belongs either to the top or to the bottom rung of the social ladder. The first is connected with rulership and government, as required by the political and military conditions of trading, the other depends for his livelihood on the coarse labor of carrying. This fact is of great importance for the understanding of the organization of trade in ancient times. There can be no middle-class trader, at least among the citizenry. Apart from the Far East which we must disregard here, only three significant instances of a broad commercial middle class in premodern times are on record: the Hellenistic merchant of largely metic ancestry in the Eastern Mediterranean city states; the ubiquitous Islamitic merchant who grafted Hellenistic maritime traditions on to the ways of the bazaar; lastly, the descendants of Pirenne's "floating scum" in Western Europe, a sort of continental metic of the second third of the Middle Ages. The classical Greek middle class preconized by Aristotle was a landed class, not a commercial class at all. 1 260 Institutional Analysis A third manner of approach is more closely historical. The trader types of antiquity were the ramkarum, the metic or resident alien, and the "foreigner." The ramkarum dominated the Mesopotamian scene from the Su-merian beginnings to the rise of Islam, i.e., over some 3000 years. Egypt, China, India, Palestine, pre-conquest Mesoamerica, or native West Africa knew no other type of trader. The metic became first historically conspicuous in Athens and some other Greek cities as a lower-class merchant, and rose with Hellenism to become the prototype of a Greek-speaking or Levantine commercial middle class from the Indus Valley to the Pillars of Hercules. The foreigner is of course ubiquitous. He carries on trade with foreign crews and in foreign bottoms; he neither "belongs" to the community, nor enjoys the semi-status of resident alien, but is a member of an altogether different community. (H! A fourth distinction is anthropological. It provides the key to that peculiar figure, the trading foreigner. Although the number of "trading peoples" to which these "foreigners" belonged was comparatively small, they accounted for the widely spread institution of "passive trade." Amongst themselves, trading peoples differed again in an important respect: trading peoples proper, as we may call them, were exclusively dependent for their subsistence on trade in which, directly or indirectly, the whole population was engaged, as with the Phoenicians, the Rhodians, the inhabitants of Gades (the modern Cadix), or at some periods Armenians and Jews; in the case of others—a more numerous group—trade was only one of the occupations in which from time to time a considerable part of the population engaged, travelling abroad, sometimes with their families, over shorter or longer periods. The Haussa and the Mandingo in the Western Sudan are instances. The latter are also known as Duala, but, as recently turned out, only when trading abroad. Formerly they were taken to be a separate people by those whom they visited when trading. Second, the organization of trade in early times must differ ac- ( cording to the goods carried, the distance to be travelled, the obstacles j to be overcome by the carriers, the political and the ecological conditions of the venture. For this, if for no other reason, all trade is origi- ! nally specific. The goods and their carriage make it so. There can be, under these conditions, no such thing as trading "in general." Unless full weight is given to this fact, no understanding of the The Economy as Instituted Process 261 early development of trading institutions is possible. The decision to acquire some kinds of goods from a definite distance and place of origin will be taken under circumstances different from those under which other kinds of goods would have to be acquired from somewhere else. Trading ventures are, for this reason, a discontinuous affair. They are restricted to concrete undertakings, which are liquidated one by one and do not tend to develop into a continuous enterprise. The Roman societas, like the later commenda, was a trade partnership limited to one undertaking. Only the societas publicanorum, for tax farming and contracting, was incorporated—it was the one great exception. Not before modern times were permanent trade associations known. The specificity of trade is enhanced in the natural course of things by the necessity of acquiring the imported goods with exported ones. For under nonmarket conditions imports and exports tend to fall under different regimes. The process through which goods are collected for export is mostly separate from, and relatively independent of, that by which the imported goods are repartitioned. The first may be a matter of tribute or taxation or feudal gifts or under whatever other designation the goods flow to the center, while the repartitioned imports may cascade along different lines. Hammurabi's "Seisachtheia" appears to make an exception of simu goods, which may have sometimes been imports passed on by the king via the ramkarum to such tenants who wished to exchange them for their own produce. Some of the preconquest long-distance trading of the pochteca of the Aztec of Mesoamerica appears to carry similar features. What nature made distinct, the market makes homogeneous. Even the difference between goods and their transportation may be obliterated, since in the market both can be bought and sold—the one in the commodity market, the other in the freight and insurance market. In either case there is supply and demand, and prices are formed in the same fashion. Carrying and goods, these constituents of trade, acquire a common denominator in terms of cost. Preoccupation with the market and its artificial homogeneity thus makes for good economic theory rather than for good economic history. Eventually, we will find that trade routes, too, as well as means of transportation may be of no less incisive importance for the institutional forms of trade than the types of goods carried. For in all these cases the geographical and technological conditions interpenetrate with the social structure. » r 262 Institutional Analysis According to the rationale of two-sidedness we meet with three \ y main types of trade: gift trade, adminjstejoed-trade, and market trade, j (]y Gift trade links the partners in relationships of reciprocity, such as: guest friends; Kula partners; visiting parties. Over millennia trade between empires was carried on as gift trade—no other rationale of two-sidedness would have met quite as well the needs of the situation. The organization of trading is here usually ceremonial, involving mutual presentation; embassies; political dealings between chiefs or kings. The goods are treasure, objects of elite circulation; in the border case of visiting parties they may be of a more "democratic" character. But contacts are tenuous and exchanges few and far between. % Administered trade has its firm foundation in treaty^ relationships that are more or less formal. Since on both sides the import interest is as a rule determinative, trading runs through government-controlled channels. The export trade is usually organized in a similar way. Consequently, the whole of trade is carried on by administrative methods. This extends to the manner in which business is transacted, including arrangements concerning "rates" or proportions of the units exchanged; port facilities; weighing; checking of quality; the physical exchange of the goods; storage; safekeeping; the control of the trading personnel; regulation of "payments"; credits; price differentials. Some of these matters would naturally be linked with the collection of the export goods and the repartition of the imported ones, both belonging to the redistributive sphere of the domestic economy. The goods that are mutually imported are standardized in regard to quality and package, weight, and other easily ascertainable criteria. Only such "trade goods" can be traded. Equivalencies are set out in simple unit relations; in principle, trade is one-to-one. Higgling and haggling is not part of the proceedings; equivalencies are set once and for all. But since to meet changing circumstances adjustments cannot be avoided, higgling-haggling is practiced only on other items- than price, such as measures, quality, or means of payment. Endless arguments are possible about the quality of the foodstuffs, the capacity and weight of the units employed, the proportions of the currencies if different ones are jointly used. Even "profits" are often "bargained." The rationale of the procedure is, of course, to keep prices unchanged; if they must adjust to actual supply situations, as in an emergency, this is phrased as trading two-to-one or two-and-a-half-to- The Economy as Instituted Process 263 one, or, as we would say, at 100 per cent or 150 per cent profit. This method of haggling on profits at stable prices, which may have been, fairly general in archaic society, is well authenticated from the Central Sudan as late as the nineteenth century. Administered trade presupposes relatively permanent trading bodies such as governments or at least companies chartered by them. The understanding with the natives may be tacit, as in the case of traditional or customary relationships. Between sovereign bodies, however, trade assumes formal treaties even in the relatively early times of the second millennium b.c. Once established in a region, under solemn protection of the gods, administrative forms of trade may be practiced without any previous treaty. The main institution, as we now begin to realize, is the port of trade, as we here call this site of all administered foreign trade. The port of trade offers military security to the inland power; civil protection to the foreign trader; facilities of anchorage, debarkation and storage; the benefit of judicial authorities; agreement on the goods to be traded; agreement concerning the "proportions" of the different trade goods in the mixed packages or "sortings." if) / Market trade is the third typical form of trading. Here exchange is the form of integration that relates the partners to each other. This comparatively modern variant of trade released a torrent of material wealth over Western Europe and North America. Though presently in recession, it is still by far the most important of all. The range of tradable goods—the commodities—is practically unlimited and the organization of market trade follows the lines traced out by the supply-demand-price mechanism. The market mechanism shows its immense range of application by being adaptable to the handling not only of goods, but of every element of trade itself—storage, transportation, risk, credit, payments, etc.—through the forming of special markets for freight, insurance, short-term credit, capital, warehouse space, banking facilities, and so on. The main interest of the economic historian today turns towards the questions: When and how did trade become linked with markets? At what time and place do we meet the general result known as market trade? Strictly speaking, such questions are precluded under the sway of catallactic logic, which tends to fuse trade and market inseparably. 264 Institutional Analysis 2. money uses The catallactic definition of money is that of means of indirect exchange. Modern money is used for payment and as a "standard" pre-cisely because it is a means of exchange. Thus our money is "all-pur- ] pose" money. Other uses of money are merely unimportant variants of -its exchange use, and all money uses are dependent upon the existence of markets. The substantive definition of money, like that of trade, is independent of markets. It is derived from definite uses to, which quantifiable objects are put. These uses are payment, standard and exchange. Money, therefore, is defined here as quantifiable objects employed in any one or several of these uses. The question is whether independent definitions of those uses are possible. The definitions of the various money uses contain two criteria: the sociologically defined situation in which the use arises, and the operation performed with the money objects in that situation. f: v Payment is the discharge of obligations in which quantifiable objects change hands. The situation refers here not to one kind of obligation only, but to several of them, since only if an object is used to discharge more than one obligation can we speak of it as "means of payment" in the distinctive sense of the term (otherwise merely an obligation to be discharged in kind is so discharged). The payment use of money belongs to its most common uses in early times. The obligations do not here commonly spring from transactions. In unstratified primitive society payments are regularly made in connection with the institutions of bride price, blood money, and fines. In archaic society such payments continue, but they are overshadowed by customary dues, taxes, rent and tribute that give rise to payments on the largest scale. \/ The standard, or accounting use of money is the equating of amounts of different kinds of goods for definite purposes. The "situation" is either barter or the storage and management of staples; the "operation" consists in the attaching of numerical tags to the various objects to facilitate the manipulation of those objects. Thus in the case of barter, the summation of objects on either side can eventually be equated; in the case of the management of staples a possibility of planning, balancing, budgeting, as well as general accounting is attained. The Economy as Instituted Process 265 The standard use of money is essential to the elasticity of a re-distributive system. The equating of such staples as barley, oil and wool, in which taxes or rent have to be paid or alternatively rations or wages may be claimed is vital, since it ensures the possibility of choice between the different staples for payer and claimant alike. At the same time the precondition of large scale finance "in kind" is created, which presupposes the notion of funds and balances, in other words, the interchangeability of staples. v The exchange use of money arises out of a need for quantifiable objects for indirect exchange. The "operation" consists in acquiring units of such objects through direct exchange, in order to acquire the desired objects through a further act of exchange. Sometimes the money objects are available from the start, and the twofold exchange is merely designed to net an increased amount of the same objects. Such a use of quantifiable objects develops not from random acts of barter—a favored fancy of eighteenth century rationalism—but rather in connection with organized trade, especially in markets. In the absence of markets the exchange use of money is no more than a subordinate culture trait. The surprising reluctance of the great trading peoples of antiquity such as Tyre and Carthage to adopt coins, that new form of money eminently suited for exchange, may have been due to the fact that the trading ports of the commercial empires were not organized as markets, but as "ports of trade." Two extensions of the meaning of money should be noted. The one extends the definition of money other than physical objects, namely, ideal units; the other comprises alongside of the three conventional money uses, also the use of money objects as operational devices. Ideal units are mere verbalizations or written symbols employed as if they were quantifiable units, mainly for payment or as a standard. The "operation" consists in the manipulation of debt accounts according to the rules of the game. Such accounts are common facts of primitive life and not, as was often believed, peculiar to monetarized economies. The earliest temple economies of Mesopotamia as well as the early Assyrian traders practiced the clearing of accounts without the intervention of money objects. At the other end it seemed advisable not to omit the mention of operational devices among money uses, exceptional though they be. Occasionally quantifiable objects are used in archaic society for arithmetical, statistical, taxational, administrative or other non-monetary 266 Institutional Analysis purposes connected with economic life. In eighteenth-century Why-dah cowrie money was used for statistical ends, and damba beans (never employed as money) served as a gold weight and, in that capacity, were cleverly used as a device for accountancy. Early money is, as we saw, speciaj^rr^ejrnone^. Different kinds of objects are employed in the different money uses; moreover, the uses are instituted independently of one another. The implications are -of the most far-reaching nature. There is, for instance, no contradiction involved in "paying" with a means with which one cannot buy, nor in employing objects as a "standard" which are not used as a means of exchange. In Hammurabi's Babylonia barley was the means of payment; silver was the universal standard; in exchange, of which there was very little, both were used alongside of oil, wool, and some other staples. It becomes apparent why money uses—like trade activities-can reach an almost unlimited level of development, not only outside of market-dominated economies, but in the very absence of markets. 3. market elements u Now, the market itself. Catallactically, the market is the locus of exchange; market and exchange are co-extensive. For under the catal-lactic postulate economic life is both reducible to acts of exchange effected through higgling-haggling and it is embodied in markets. Exchange is thus described as the economic relationship, with the market as the economic institution. The definition of the market derives logically from the catallactic premises. / Under the substantive range of terms, market and exchange have independent empirical characteristics. What then is here the meaning of exchange and market? And to what extent are they necessarily connected? Exchange, substantively defined, is the mutual appropriative movement of goods between hands. Such a movement as we saw may occur either at set rates or at bargained rates. The latter only is the result of higgling-haggling between the partners. Whenever, then, there is exchange, there is a rate. This remains true whether the rate be bargained or set. It will be noted that exchange at bargained prices is identical with catallactic exchange or "exchange as a form of integration." This kind of exchange alone is typically The Economy as Instituted Process 267 limited to a definite type of market institution, namely price-making markets. Market institutions shall be defined as institutions comprising a supply crowd or a demand crowd or both. Supply crowds and demand crowds, again, shall be defined as a multiplicity of hands desirous to acquire, or alternatively, to dispose of, goods in exchange. Although market institutions, therefore, are exchange institutions, market and exchange are not coterminous. Exchange at set rates occurs under re-ciprocative or redistributive forms of integration; exchange at bargained rates, as we said, is limited to price-making markets. It may seem paradoxical that exchange at set rates should be compatible with any form of integration except that of exchange: yet this follows logically since only bargained exchange represents exchange in the catallactic sense of the term, in which it is a form of integration. The best way of approaching the world of market institutions ap-! pears to be in terms of "market elements." Eventually, this will not only serve as a guide through the variety of configurations subsumed under the name of markets and market type institutions, but also as a tool with which to dissect some of the conventional concepts that obstruct our understanding of those institutions. Two market elements should be regarded as specific, namely, supply crowds and demand crowds; if either is present, we shall speak of a market institution (if both are present, we call it a market, if one of them only, a market-type institution). Next in importance is the element of equivalency, i.e., the rate of the exchange; according to the character of the equivalency, markets are set-price markets or price-making markets. Competition is another characteristic of some market institutions, such as price-making markets and auctions, but in contrast to equivalencies, economic competition is restricted to markets. Finally, there are elements that can be designated as functional. Regularly they occur apart from market institutions, but if they make their appearance alongside of supply crowds or demand crowds, they pattern out those institutions in a manner that may be of great practical relevance. Amongst these functional elements are physical site, goods present, custom and law. This diversity of market institutions was in recent times obscured in the name of the formal concept of a supply-demand-price mechanism. No wonder that it is in regard to the pivotal terms of supply, de- 268 Institutional Analysis mand and price that the substantive approach leads to a significant widening of our outlook. Supply crowds and demand crowds were referred to above as separate and distinct market elements. In regard to the modern market this would be, of course, inadmissible; here there is a price level at which bears turn bulls, and another price level at which the miracle is re-1 versed. This has induced many to overlook the fact that buyers and j sellers are separate in any other than the modern type of market. This! again gave support to a twofold misconception. Firstly, "supply and demand" appeared as combined elemental forces while actually each consisted of two very different components, namely, an amount of goods, on the one hand, and a number of persons, related as buyers and sellers to those goods, on the other. Secondly, "supply and demand" seemed inseparable like Siamese twins, while actually forming distinct , groups of persons, according to whether they disposed of the goods as of resources, or sought them as requirements. Supply crowds and demand crowds need not therefore be present together. When, for instance, booty is auctioned by the victorious general to the highest bidder only a demand crowd is in evidence; similarly, only a supply crowd is met with when contracts are assigned to the lowest submission. Yet auctions and submissions were widespread in archaic society, and i in ancient Greece auctions ranked amongst the precursors of markets proper. This distinctness of "supply" and "demand" crowds shaped the organization of all premodern market institutions. ' As to the market element commonly called "price," it was here ' subsumed under the category of equivalencies. The use of this general term should help avoid misunderstandings. Price suggests fluctuation, while equivalency lacks this association. The very phrase "set" or "fixed" price suggests that the price, before being fixed or set was apt to change. Thus language itself makes it difficult to convey the true I state of affairs, namely, that "price" is originally a rigidly fixed quantity, ; in the absence of which trading cannot start. Changing or fluctuating ; prices of a competitive character are a comparatively recent develop- ) ment and their emergence forms one of the main interests of the eco- j nomic history of antiquity. Traditionally, the sequence was supposed | to be the reverse: price was conceived of as the result of trade and ex- { change, not as their precondition. j "Price" is the designation of quantitative ratios between goods of i different kinds, effected through barter or higgling-haggling. It is that ! The Economy as Instituted Process 269 form of equivalency which is characteristic of economies that are integrated through exchange. But equivalencies are by no means restricted . to exchange relations. Under a redistributive form of integration equivalencies are also common. They designate the quantitative relationship between goods of different kinds that are acceptable in payment of taxes, rents, dues, fines, or that denote qualifications for a civic status dependent on a property census. Also the equivalency may set the ratio / at which wages or rations in kind can be claimed, at the beneficiary's choosing. The elasticity of a system of staple finance—the planning, balancing and accounting—hinges on this device. The equivalency here denotes not what should be given for another good, but what can be claimed instead of it. Under reciprocative forms of integration, again, equivalencies determine the amount that is "adequate" in relation to the symmetrically placed party. Clearly, this behavioral context is different from either exchange or redistribution. Price systems, as they develop over time, may contain layers of equivalencies that historically originated under different forms of integration. Hellenistic market prices show ample evidence of having derived from redistributive equivalencies of the cuneiform civilizations that preceded them. The thirty pieces of silver received by Judas as the price of a man for betraying Jesus was a close variant of the equivalency of a slave as set out in Hammurabi's Code some 1700 years earlier. Soviet redistributive equivalencies, on the other hand, for a long time echoed nineteenth century world market prices. These, too, in their turn, had their predecessors. Max Weber remarked that for lack of a costing basis Western capitalism would not have been possible but for the medieval network of statuated and regulated prices, customary rents, etc., a legacy of gild and manor. Thus price systems may have an institutional history of their own in terms of the types of equivalencies that entered into their making. It is with the help of noncatallactic concepts of trade, money and markets of this kind that such fundamental problems of economic and social history as the origin of fluctuating prices and the development of market trading can best be tackled and, as we hope, eventually resolved. / • To conclude: A critical survey of the catallactic definitions of trade, money and market should make available a number of concepts which form the raw material of the social sciences in their economic aspect. The bearing of this recognition on questions of theory, policy and out- 270 Institutional Analysis look should be viewed in the light of the gradual institutional transformation that has been in progress since the first World War. Even in regard to the market system itself, the market as the sole frame of reference is somewhat out of date. Yet, as should be more clearly realized than it sometimes has been in the past, the market cannot be superseded as a general frame of reference unless the social sciences succeed in developing a wider frame of reference to which the market itself is referable. This indeed is our main intellectual task today in the field of economic studies. As we have attempted to show, such a conceptual structure will have to be grounded on the substantive meaning of economic. Karl Polanyi XIV Sociology and the Substantive. View of the &conomy Note toChapter XIII 1. The uncritical employment of the compound concept fostered what may well be called the "economistic fallacy." It consisted in an artificial identification of the economy with its market form. From Hume and Spencer to Frank H. Knight and Northrop, social thought suffered from this limitation wherever it touched on the economy. Lionel Robbins' essay (1932), though useful to economists, fatefully distorted the problem. In the field of anthropology Melville Hersko-vits' recent work (1952) represents a relapse after his pioneering effort of 1940. ever since Comte first introduced "sociology" to designate the then new science of society, the term has denoted the discipline whose subject matter is the interrelations among the sundry social processes constituting society. One of the more important of these processes is the economy, for through it the members of society receive a continuous supply of want-satisfying material means. Yet, sociologists have shown rather little originality in developing basic conceptions of this fundamental process. Instead, they have taken economic theory for their point of departure and thereby made the uncritical assumption that rational action and the market are the source and form respectively of the economic process. As a result, economies diverging from the format of the market model are dismissed in advance from serious examination, being viewed instead either as merely curious illustrations of how archaic "traditionalism" curbs the expression of rationality or, among the more skeptical, as substantiating the belief that for a number of "economic" problems orthodox theory needs to be supplemented by sociological propositions. Such easy renderings of the many "deviations" from the market model have for too long marked sociological discussions of the econ- 271 272 Institutional Analysis omy. A more critical perspective is now needed. For if in some instances it is not by economizing actions that empirical economies are identified, then what is it that serves to distinguish them from other societal processes? Or, more fundamentally, what is meant by the very term "economy" when it is applied to a set of activities in which economizing plays a minor role, if indeed it is present at all? As developed in chapter XIII the answer once given appears almost self-evident; the term is then used to denote the processes by which people secure a livelihood. In short, "economy" denotes two quite different concepts, one having the formal or "economizing" meaning, the other the substantive or "livelihood" meaning. Typically, both meanings are combined, so that "economy" designates the compound concept of securing a livelihood by economizing. Whether economic theory provides a suitable explanatory model depends directly, then, on whether this compound concept is an adequate description of actual economies. The two concepts are not only logically disparate. The actual processes to which they refer also occur independently—just as generals may economize in the disposition of their troops, so may people secure a livelihood without economizing. Nevertheless, in what we call a market system the two processes not only appear jointly, but bring about the subject matter of economic analysis, the phenomena of fluctuating prices and of action oriented to them. It is our observations of these phenomena (of an essentially mathematical form) that economics attempts to order. The restriction deriving from this reasoning is of some moment for sociologists, for it implies that the "generality" of economic theory does not lie in the substantive direction, towards other than market-type economies. Rather, as recent applications of "game theory" to such diverse activities as air combat and administrative behavior suggest, the "generality" of economic theory lies in the formal direction, towards other than price-oriented rational actions. Yet, to my knowledge, no sociologist has presented a systematic discussion of the economy in any but formal terms. The more sophisticated the theory, the more prominent is the "economizing" element, the point already having been reached in some theories at which the substantive meaning of the compound concept drops out altogether. And with it has gone such an elementary distinction as that between the processes by which want-satisfying material means are produced and distributed, and the "production" and "distribution" of political power or of social prestige. Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 273 The argument here is for a change in emphasis. Not the formal, but the substantive element of "livelihood," in all its apparent vagueness* should be at the center of sociological theories of the economic process, of those theories in which the economy is seen as one of several generic social processes. No attempt is made in this chapter to review in detail the various versions of the operation and place of the human economy in society proposed by the score or so of sociologists who have dealt seriously with the problems. Instead, three of the more influential conceptions are examined for conceptual clarity, empirical scope, and logical adequacy. Following this abbreviated survey and concluding the chapter is a discussion of one way in which the economy "conceived as a substantive process may be introduced into current sociological thinking. To avoid misunderstandings at the outset, brief remarks on two topics not otherwise explicitly discussed are included in this introduction. One is the significance of economizing actions within a substantive approach. The other concerns the related question of the connections between the disciplines of economics and sociology. One of the major attractions which the substantive view of the economy has for sociologists is its clear compatibility with functional theory. To say of the economic process that its operation in all societies results in the continuous supply of want-satisfying material means is to define that process through a particular set of consequences and to leave unspecified initially the characteristics of the social relations through which this supply is effected. However, this vacancy is one of definition not of knowledge, as other parts of this volume demonstrate. Several types of social arrangements, for example, have been repeatedly found to facilitate the supply of material means, such as the port of trade and gift exchange. But what we know of these devices is indeed little compared with our richer and better organized knowledge of the structures effecting the supply in market-organized economies. So long as the limitations of this knowledge in its present form are recognized, we are in virtue of it far along towards filling the space left open in the definition of the economic process. In so far as structures of economizing actions effect the supply of want-satisfying material means, they thus enter into the substantive conception of the economy on a par with any other type of facilitating structure. With regard to the second topic, then, sociologists have much to gain from economic theory (which according to its postulates is con- 274 Institutional Analysis cerned with economizing action) in the study of market-organized economies. But the correct use by sociologists of the theories and findings of economics presupposes on their part a clearer recognition of the differences between what is sociological and what is economic, in the sense of the theory, than is now sometimes in evidence. For the matter at hand, "sociological" refers not to events but to concepts, problems and propositions, and the same is true of "economic" (again, in the sense of theory).2 Sociological problems cannot, then, be adequately treated merely by generalizing to the total society supply and demand propositions.3 Rather, if such statements are to be used, their contents need recasting into sociological terms. A recent attempt at such a recasting was made by Talcott Parsons in the Marshall Lectures for 1953,4 but in such a way that the conceptual distinctions in fact dividing the problems and propositions of sociology from those of economies come perilously close to being defined away rather than bridged.* In brief, Professor Parsons sees the relations between economy and society as paralleling those between economics and his version of the theory of action: since, he argues, the economy is a sub-system of the wider society, and since the general theory applies to society as a whole, economics (which he seems here to accept as the theory of the economy) must be a special case of the general theory. To include in this manner the corpus of economics within his general theory, not only must Professor Parsons limit the forms that the economic process can take to those found in market and modern planned economies; he must also carry out some strange operations on the concept "society" in order to make it compatible with the given premises of economic theory. Whatever the gain to economics from this incorporation, the net effect for sociology is of doubtful value. For, if the market becomes in this way a sociologically relevant phenomenon, it also becomes thereby the prototypical economic institution within the general theory, a result restricting considerably the theory's generality. In short, "economy" as a social process is confounded or intentionally identified with the subject matter of economics as a discipline. (And, as a result, that the place of the market economy in modern society is the actual problem in these lectures, and the one to which they seem to make a substantial contribution, is almost hidden from the reader.) Conversely, in order that the categories * See below, Ch. XV. Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 275 of his theory may be congruent with those developed by economists, for describing the rather unusual social structures with which they are concerned, the processes making up Professor Parsons' "society" become little more than formal equivalents, metaphorical restatements, of the market economy's price-making process. More generally, however, it would seem to be an open question whether the possibility of characterizing the relations between social structure and economic process depends on being able to describe the connections between sociology and economics. If the two activities are at all related, the order of dependence appears logically to be the reverse of what Professor Parsons assumes. For, to explicate the links between two disciplines one must first be able to show how they differ in their descriptions of similar events. But a sociological conception of how economies operate, developed independently of economic analysis, is precisely what at present is lacking. Professor Parsons has thus not joined two independent disciplines but instead has defined for sociology what it will mean by "economy" and for economics what it will mean by "society." However engaging to the sociologist in his more imperialistic moods the latter prospect may appear, he cannot but pause long and thoughtfully, and eventually reject, a definition of "economy" arrived at in this manner and having such limited content. Despite, then, the partial similarity of the problems dealt with in this chapter and by Professor Parsons, the approach here differs from his considerably, especially in the matter of assumptions about connections between sociology and economics. To omit this topic is not to deny that, such connections are a valid intellectual concern. But spelling out these interdisciplinary linkages is simply a markedly different activity from developing a specifically sociological concept of the economy. Reciprocally, the following critical comments on current sociologies of the economy (and the concluding suggestions for a revision) are not assumed to have any implications for economic theory or to be of more than casual interest to economists. The discipline of economics may have its theoretical problems, and some of these may involve the concept of society, but they are not for that reason the immediate concern of sociologists. Rather, the sociologist, as such, must assume economic theory to be adequate for the solution of its own problems, just as he ought also to view with skepticism both its claims to universality 276 Institutional Analysis and its imputed power to transform into a full grown shade tree the viable but yet slender sociological sapling. Criticism of Current Sociological Views of the Economy Because a sociologist views the economy as an elemental part or process of society, there exist, corresponding to two main conceptions of society, two main conceptions of the economy. In one, the economy is defined through "division-of-labor," in the other, it is the locus of rationality.5 With the development and elaboration of functional analysis in sociology,6 though, some theorists have come to stress less the content of the economy in their initial definitions and more its consequences for society, retaining however the presumption that "economy" denotes primarily "economizing." A third major conception of the economy can be distinguished, then, one which was developed from the rational action view in an attempt to give the latter a functional foundation. This is the "scarcity" conception where the economy is defined as the process through which society's presumed problem of "scarcity" is solved. the division-of-labor conception The division-of-labor definition of the economy is part of a rather familiar theory of society—the one that holds it to be an aggregate of more or less freely moving individual atoms coming together, bouncing off, or avoiding one another in accordance with the laws of nature and rationality. Both the effects of nature and the expression of rationality may be modified, however, by custom, morality, and law, so that society becomes the resultant of three "orders of reality": the physical and chemical order of nature, the psychological and biological order of drives and rationality, and the social and cultural order of "conventions." Such inclusiveness, characteristic of theories purporting to explain uniformities "in their concrete totality" (in contrast to those attempting to explain selected aspects of uniformities through the abstract relations said to exist among inferred properties of behavior), coupled with elevating the classic distinction between society and individual from an heuristic device to a cardinal principle, marks the atomistic theory of society as a product of nineteenth century social thought. Seen as the locus of a "division of labor" and a correlative network Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 277 of "exchange" among these atomistically conceived individuals, the economy is held to evolve through a set sequence of "stages." Actual economies are classified as being in one stage of development or another on the basis of degree of specialization, dominant mode of production, and the scope of the exchange network. (The most familiar of these evolutionary sequences is, perhaps, that which runs from hunting and gathering economies, through pastoral and agricultural, to manufacturing.) Because the stages picture fairly concrete situations that result more from physical and biological factors than from social factors, cultural values and their socio-psycbological counterparts (i.e., motives) occupy at best a secondary place in this conception. The agricultural stage is compatible, for example, with both a system of free peasants and one of serfs. In this sense, the economy is viewed in the "division of labor" approach as basically a "non-cultural" entity. Its structure, composed of the relations among individuals as psycho-biological entities, is grounded in a dependence on others for the satisfaction of organic needs, and its operation is mainly a matter of some kind of overt "exchanges" which occur among the specialized producers and which contribute to the "satisfactions" of each. Finally, the "reality" of the economy is attested by the observable physical "flow" of useful things and by the overt behavior of individuals in relation to this observable movement. Throughout, then, the elements on which interest is centered are more frequently non-social than specifically social. The many attempts to define the economy through "division of labor," however, have generally involved two rather basic difficulties. One of these has to do with marking off the boundaries of the economy as a distinct part of society, the other, with integrating the different parts of the economy. The trouble with using "division of labor" to mark off the boundaries of any social sphere is that the universality which is the concept's main virtue is also its prime defect, a point made by Dürkheim over fifty years ago.7 With respect to the problem of distinguishing the economy from the rest of society, "division of labor" provides no help at all, for what would seem to be distinctly economic matters cannot, by employing that concept as a starting point, be separated from non-economic matters. This becomes evident if one inquires into the empirical content of the "labor" which is divided. When "labor" refers to all social activities, "economy" has no 278 Institutional Analysis specific content but is coterminous with "society": if "labor" designates the same things as "human behavior," then it is no more able than that term to mark off the boundaries of the economy. Praying, playing, and producing are here all equally "economic" activities. Generally, however, "labor" is intended to refer not to all social activities but to some delimited set of them. But then one necessarily, if implicitly, starts from the activities specified and not from the degree of "division of labor." What is of initial conceptual importance is not that "labor" is divided to varying extents—which is true in some sense for activities in every sphere of social life—but that certain activities and not others are "labor," that is, constitute the economy. Such a specification of "labor" is not a minor point, to be made parenthetically, as it were, while one passes on to more important topics. It is, perhaps, the major point. The intelligibility of a discussion of the economy—under any label—is dependent upon the boundaries of the economy being marked out. At this point, though, it is enough simply to note that some references to the nature of the divided "labor" are in fact usually made, for such references, however ill-conceived, substantiate the claim raised here that "the division of labor" is, taken alone, an inadequate point of departure for conceptualizing the economy. The second difficulty attending this view of the economy is connected with the problem of re-uniting "divided" labor. Within the "division-of-labor" theory this problem of integration is typically surmounted by invoking the concept of "exchange," so that "specialized" individuals form a unity through the multiplicity of imputed "exchange" relations among them. Now, it is quite true that if an economy consisting of independent individuals is to have unity whatsoever these individuals must be in some way "related" to one another. And if one wants to use the term "exchange" to denote all the social relations which are found empirically to structure the continuous flow of want-satisfying material means this is certainly permissible, if somewhat misleading. But one cannot then proceed to equate "exchange" in this inclusive operational sense of a mere change of place of material objects, for example, as between places occupied by different individuals, with "exchange" in the market sense. In particular such a concept is neither the prototype of "market exchange" nor even implies anything about "exchange" as a transaction within an instituted system of market relations.8 Movements of things Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 279 may very well occur through other than market arrangements and a market system, on the other hand, may operate without any changes in the physical places of the objects being in evidence. But of course, once these two meanings of "exchange" are equated, the entire value structure of the market-organized economy can be introduced without further difficulty—and the method of history can thereby be reduced to developing the several phases which mark the gradual distention of the market economy. Thus, on the one hand, this conception provides no systematic way to distinguish what parts of a society comprise its economy while, on the other hand, it is all too specific about tbe ways in which these parts are related within an economy, if it could be distinguished.9 the rational action position The introductory summary here of the modern action view of society will be somewhat more extensive than that accorded the more familiar atomistic view, it being both the lesser known of the two and the basis of the discussion in the final section of this chapter. Fundamental differences clearly distinguish the two points of view: (1) in action theory the units of society are not individuals but patterns of interaction; (2) the society formed from these units is not a concrete aggregation but an abstract system. Each of these foci, "interaction patterns" and "society as a system," which are the reference points for the concepts in the action frame of reference, will be taken up in turn.10 First, the idea of a complex of "interaction patterns." The main idea here can be likened to a play: just as Shakespeare's lines in their totality are the fundamental source of unity in any performance of Hamlet, whatever the physical conditions of the staging or the psychological states of the actors may be, so interaction patterns are viewed as the fundamental source for the coherence which characterizes human societies. In the simplest model, that of a fully integrated system, what people "want" to do is no more and no less than what they are "required" or "expected" to do. This identity of personal preferences and social role requirements is asserted by "the postulate of institutionalization," one of the most basic premises of contemporary sociology. In marked contrast to the atomistic conception, cultural values are of prime importance, for they are instituted in the two systems of society 280 Institutional Analysis and personality.11 In the action system formed by society, values state in general what is expected of persons in different situations and what will be the consequences of conformity or deviance. They are thus the main content of social role definitions. In the personality system, through the socialization processes, values become integral parts of personality, in the sense that such "internalized" values are no less essential to individuals as humans than are lungs to individuals as organisms. Any fully instituted "role," then, is a part of two systems-society and personality—so that from the standpoint of the social system as a whole the mature adult's motivation to conform to role requirements is not generally in doubt. No actual groups are, of course, "fully integrated," few if any roles are "fully institutionalized," and the previously asserted "identity of personal preference and social role requirements" is seldom an empirically accurate statement. However, in most groups the "fit" is sufficiently close so that the picture given by the postulate of institutionalization is usually a much closer approximation to the actual state of affairs than is its negation. In addition to empirical discrepancies, there are, however, various theoretical reasons why deviance from social role requirements is usually to be found in all groups. Such behavior is said to call into play the "mechanisms of social control" which, ranging from the informal opinions of others to formal enforcement agencies, operate to maintain or to increase the degree to which the relevant system of cultural values is institutionalized. Compared with the other conception of society, then, here we find cultural elements of primary importance and "individuals" of secondary t importance. The latter, in fact, do not even enter sociological theory v except to play roles and thus to be "points" at which several roles are conjoined. No assumption is made of course that such a conjunction- t of-roles conception of the individual exhausts even his socially relevant s characteristics. To sociologists, however, whose concern is with the i: typical and recurrent social situations rather than with the idiosyncratic p and unique, what is common to divers performances of Hamlet's role n is of greater moment than what distinguishes Gieglud's playing from n that of Olivier or Evans. t< Second, the idea of "society as a system." For our purposes here ci this can be taken to mean that a certain set of processes, those "in" the system, operate in relative independence from other processes, those d "external" to the system. But society is generally conceived to be a Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 281 "self-maintaining" type of system, and this means that the internal processes constituting the system do not vary greatly in their operation even though the external processes to which they are causally linked show considerable variation.12 Thus two primary aspects of society exist to which its constituent social processes may be functionally related. They can be evaluated for their contributions to the internal interrelations among the parts of the system, to "integration," or to the external relations between the system as a whole and its environment, to "adaptation." Primary social processes, such as the economy, make major contributions to the maintenance of the system in both the adaptive and the integrative respects. As was mentioned previously, two formulations of the economy can be distinguished within this general view of society as a system of interaction patterns, since the way in which the economy is defined has changed from an emphasis on interaction patterns to an emphasis on the economy's functional relevance for the total system. Initially, the economy was held to consist of rational actions—or of contractual relations in which such actions occurred—the economist's model of the market being introduced explicitly as the functional and structural prototype of all economies. Subsequently, the emphasis in the definition of the economy was shifted from the economy's content to its consequences for society. As a result, the economy is at present defined functionally but in terms of the functions for society of a sub-system of rational actions, namely, the solution of the alleged problem of "scarcity." The initial conception and its development may perhaps best be presented by singling out from a host of representative views the perspective advanced by Max Weber.13 An antithesis to the rather non-social evolutionary view of the economy represented by the division-of-labor school would be an "idealistic" view (e.g., Sombart's) in which the uniqueness of empirical cultures and of their derivative social and economic structures is emphasized.14 While such an extreme cultural determinism has found little favor among American sociologists, the action view of the economy does, as has been said, include cultural values as a fundamental concept, and Weber was one of two or three important figures in the introduction of cultural values into the definitions of the economy. Weber's approach to social institutions was generally to ignore the traditional facades, and to enter instead by a side door from where he drew up "ideal" versions of the several types of social action occurring in the 282 Institutional Analysis religious, political, and economic spheres. These types he distinguished according to (1) various psychological dispositions—which, generalized, are cultural values—and (2) the social relational contexts of the actions in which these dispositions are appropriate motivational forces. Society is thus seen, basically if implicitly, as several structures of social relationships in which various types of action occur. The economy is that part of society which consists of rational actions in the context of impersonal relationships. Weber developed his views on the economy not as a formulation in a general theory—he considered such a theory impossible or at least fruitless—but as an aid in working through a particular historical problem, the social conditions necessary for the development and persistence of modern capitalism. While his analyses and conceptions became gradually a part of American sociology, his opinion on the usefulness of a general theory was by and large rejected, and with it, the limited role he had intended his conception of the economy to play. The result was a confounding of two fundamentally different questions. A concern with the conditions for rational action was not clearly distinguished from a concern with the divers types of structures occurring in various economies. This confusion of the history and functioning of one type of economy with the problem of comparing economies led to the presumption, held here to be unwarranted, that the market economy is the structural and functional prototype of the economy in general. This failure to distinguish clearly between these sets of problems would probably not have persisted were it not for the singularly important orientation to economic matters which fell to Americans in their package inheritance of European sociology and which continues today to permeate sociological thinking about the economy. In essence, this orientation is that insofar as economies consist of rational action, economic theory is adequate as a kind of sociology. However, some economies do not manifest primarily rational action, and the institutional contexts of the rest are characterized predominantly by values other than rationality. Therefore, this view holds, certain economic problems—those which are peripheral in the study of rational action, though perhaps of some importance in the study of society—cannot be fully analyzed within the discipline of economics. Instead they are fit subject matter for sociological analysis, and the study of such problems is to constitute the sociology of the economy. The result of this orientation, and of the eventual generalization of Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 283 Weber's conception, is the widespread use of the economist's model of the economy as a roughly accurate formulation of the economy, so that non-market economies become mere appendages composed of deviant forms of essentially market economy parts. Such an approach, however, seems very like using as the guide to how all types of houses are built the principles by which, say, wooden houses are constructed. While brick, mud, and wooden houses are put together in quite different ways, one could never find it out by employing this procedure. Nevertheless, in this manner have the two action versions of the economy been formulated. The criticisms of these two will be presented separately, but those lodged against the direct rational action approach apply also to the "scarcity" approach, since the latter is actually little more than a functionally formulated justification for equating the economic process in general with its market form. For this very reason, though, the "scarcity" view has more serious theoretical implications. 1. The market model view The values used to characterize "economic action" may be summed up by the terms "rationality" and "utilitarianism." In its formal sense the first denotes allocating means in order to maximize returns, while the second refers to viewing all objects, persons as well as things, as means and never as ends in themselves.15 Of course, as far as introducing the market model is concerned, whether the economy is defined as consisting of actions guided by these values or of social relations in which the role definitions permit if they do not enjoin such actions makes no difference. In the latter type of definition, impersonal "contractual" relations are usually contrasted with the gemeinschaft character of "familistic" relations and with the unilateral, if also gesellschaft character, of "compulsory" relations.16 That no empirical economy is wholly constituted either by "economic actions" or by "contractual relations" is of course recognized. These are "pure" or "ideal" types. But the operation of just such an "ideal" version of the economy is what the market model explains. By working with such a view sociologists can therefore include almost without modification the economist's model as a detailed description of how economies are supposed to work. Moreover, because any actual economy only more or less conforms to the economist's description, adjustments in his basic model are called for in specific instances. All in all, a generalized economic theory together with its largely ad hoc 284 Institutional Analysis empirical qualifications are taken to constitute the beginnings of a sociology of the economy. It must be emphasized that those who proceed in this fashion towards a sociological theory of the economy do not deny the extremely limited role played by a self-interested rationality in what are called "traditional economies." But they presume that, whether or not rationality is in fact present, they can draw conclusions about the extent to which actions are "economic"—which they can do, of course, only in the formal sense of the term—and that such conclusions are steps towards a general sociological theory of the economy. From the fundamental assumptions that economizing is, or should be, central in all substantively economic activities and that the market pattern offers an explanatory paradigm, there follow for theory several types of consequences, only two of which are discussed in any detail here, a third being but briefly mentioned. First is the consequence that the concepts used in analysis are initially concepts of economics, not of sociology. In conjunction with the view that economic theory describes the activities within the "pure" form of contractual relations,17 this results in the derivative sociological "theory" being little more than a series of metaphorical constructions faulty at both ends. The data which support the assertions are taken from their meaningful context in society and the terms used to interpret them are lifted from their context in economic theory.18 The different meanings of the term "choice" may illustrate this point. In economic theory, roles and social relationships are just two more objects of choice: whether to enter or to leave social relations, in terms of the net satisfactions expected, is merely one of the several alternatives among which "individuals" are seen to choose. The "satisfactions" from being a member of a particular work crew, for example, are treated as theoretically commensurable with the "satisfactions" of an additional dollar a day income. Sociologically, however, "choice" denotes a behavioral relating of means to ends that is carried out by the acting person in accordance with a generally held norm which, by virtue of his roles and the corresponding internalized values, he also presumably holds. Thus, in sociology one's "choice" has no meaning except where explicit reference is made to the values defining current role obligations or to those internalized in his personality. In economics it is not only meaningful independently of such references, but values and obligations are among the very objects to be chosen. To treat these Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 285 as equal concepts is to relativize "choice" beyond the point where it carries any significant meaning. The very different way individuals enter into economic compared with sociological analyses may serve as an example of the contextual differences which distinguish the two disciplines. Economists can strip individuals of their beliefs and divorce them from their social relations because such specters are all that are needed to enact the processes in which, as economists, they are interested. This is not a "mistake" on the part of economists; on the contrary, by simplifying the situation they are able to center their attention on economizing action and its results and to ignore by and large the many "complicating factors" which from most other perspectives cannot be overlooked. Nevertheless almost every major contribution to sociological thinking in the past half century constitutes in some measure a challenge to the adequacy of this view. The current conception of society as a system of interaction patterns is one result. True, in studying contemporary societies, the degree of rationality in the patterned interactions is a strategic concern. But it has no intrinsic preeminence over other instituted values. Individuals, although entering mainly as centers at which diverse roles are conjoined, are enmeshed in social relations and must hold dear at least those beliefs corresponding to the values defining their major role obligations. The presuppositions of modern sociology are thus markedly different from the "individualistic" grounding of economics. A second set of consequences of the market view of the economy concerns the reading of the interrelations between the economy and the several other institutional spheres of society. In short, in the construction of general sociological theories as well as in the largely ad hoc interpretations of empirical cases, these relations are frequently grossly misread. Questions concerning social structures alternative to market arrangements are seldom raised, while the functional implications of the market system are generalized into propositions about the economy. For example, that "natives" do not respond with more work when they are offered more pay is not usually because they have "fixed" wants-whatever this may mean in a situation as unstable as one where a wage system impinges on a village economy—but is because in most "native" economies wants are met through distributive arrangements other than market exchange. Such arrangements are not, it is true, structural 286 Institutional Analysis equivalents of market patterns, but they are functional equivalents.19 Through them as well as through market arrangements the economic process is in part carried on. Thus the ubiquitous activity of gift-giving need not be viewed as an anomaly. Although its content is marked usually neither by rational calculation nor by underlying elements of a competitive antagonism, its consequences for the economic process are similar to those of market exchange. In the same way, what contributions other social structures make to the economy are overlooked unless equivalent to those they make to the market economy. Rules of kinship obligation or of political obedience become "primitive" forms of contractual law, while socialization processes can always be alleged to foster in personalities the "economic" attitude par excellence, self-interest, since in all societies some scope is in fact allowed for individually oriented decisions. That many economic activities are organized through non-market structures obscures not only the contributions of such activities to the actual economy, if it is viewed as if it were a market system. Their significance for other institutional spheres is also overlooked. Reciprocity activities that are organized through kinship relations constitute in most instances reaffirmations of these ties. In this way they contribute directly to the stability of the kinship system, a result entirely foreign to the market system. On the contrary, the historical consequences of the market economy for the family structure have not infrequently led to the mistaken assumption of an intrinsic incompatibility between economic and kinship activities. It is just such an unwarranted generalization, in another institutional sphere, that characterizes Professor Maclver's resurrection of the Spencerian antithesis between state and economy: The political system is ... an organization of means for the control of means, an authoritative ordainment for the socal regulation of the basic technology. The economic system is also an organization of means for the control of means, directing under conditions laid down by the state, the production, exchange, and distribution of commodities and services. This function the economic system fulfills not by authoritative regulation but by the interadjustment of divers and conflicting interests that bargain and compete in terms of their respective command of money and credit. The political and the economic systems together form a co-ordinate institutional complex, the character of which is always changing according as more or fewer regulative functions are performed by one or the other system.20 Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 287 What is implied here is that the state and the economy are functionally alternative structures for securing order in society. It is of somewhat more than passing interest that though his basic orientation is so alien to the action viewpoint, Herbert Spencer was perhaps the first to give this contrast a fundamental place in sociology. If for Comte the state was needed to counteract the disintegrating effects of occupational specialization, for Spencer—much more than for Engels—it could indeed wither away since free enterprise would in the fullness of time organize the whole of the "sustaining system." In any case, the nice phrasing of the contrast drawn in the excerpt should not obscure that it is a generalization from the relations observed to hold between the liberal state and the market economy. Let us be clear on the basic point at issue here and in the immediately preceding paragraphs. All societies, viewed as self-maintain-ing social systems, have certain fundamental requirements which must be met if they are to continue in operation.21 One of these requirements is that the members of a society be provided with a continuous supply of want-satisfying material means. Furthermore, all societies in fact have structures of social relations through which this supply is maintained, and in any given case that structure (or structures) is its economy. But, on the one hand, many different combinations on the structural theme can maintain some supply; on the other, the structure in any given case will perform for its society some functions which its counterpart in a different society does not perform. If, as in the instance recorded above, "the state" is identified as a certain type of structure, and if in some actual societies it plays a minor role in effecting the supply of material means, this fact says nothing about its role in this respect in other societies. Similarly, that in some societies a certain type of structure is observed to effect this supply cannot be taken to mean that this supply is invariably secured through such a structure. A third consequence of the market model view of the economy need be only briefly mentioned. This is the ideological bias built into sociological theory through taking uncritically the economist's path as a shortcut to a sociology of the economy. For, as the Maclver excerpt indicates, integrating consequences are thereby ascribed by definition to the market form of the economy. Admittedly, many have agreed both before and after Adam Smith that frequent commerce increases trust. But the occasional integrating contributions of a type of economy are not sufficient to assert integration as a function universally per- 288 Institutional Analysis formed by that type. To make such an assertion is to invite the criticism raised by Merton against picturing "religion as integrative, without limiting the range of social structures in which this is indeed the case.'" If, when this is done to religion, "the entire history of religious wars, of the Inquisition (which drove a wedge into society after society), of internecine conflicts among religious groups" is blotted out,22 then, when it is done to commerce, the wars of conquest, class conflict, and agrarian uprisings are also struck from the historical record—and the sociology of the economy takes on the character of an inadvertent apologia for exploitation. 2. The "scarcity" defined economy With the development of functional formulations attention has ostensibly turned from the structural content of the economy to its contributions to society as a system of interaction patterns. I say "ostensibly" because it is the functions of the market system that have been generalized and made to account for all economies. Given the prominence of the formal element in the compound concept of "economy," such a generalization amounts to little more than the provision of a functional explanation of economizing actions. It is, then, on the basis of a revised version of economic theory's "scarcity postulate" that • this explanation is developed. As has recently been emphasized, however, the so-called "scarcity postulate" is not one postulate at all but a carefully constructed set of premises defining a situation from which the act of choosing logically follows (and dubious motivational assumptions are thereby avoided).23* Briefly, a "scarcity-situation" should be defined as one where means have alternative uses and are insufficient to achieve all of a set of goals; since the goals must be ranked in the order preferred, and some action is presumed, a choice between the uses of the means is logically implied. When this "postulate" is carried into sociology, however, the specifying premises are left behind, so that "scarcity" comes to denote no more than insufficiency: By virtue of the primordial fact that objects—social and non-social—which are instrumentally useful or intrinsically valuable are scarce in relation to the amount required for the full gratification of the need-dispositions of every actor, there arises the problem of allocation: the problem of who is * See above, pp. 245-7. Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 289 to get what, who is to do what, and the manner and conditions under which it is to be done.24 But shorn of its specifying premises—that the means have alternative uses and that the goals are arranged in a priority scale—"the postulate of scarcity" merely denotes a condition of "not enough." This is an important change in meaning, for from the sheer "fact of scarcity," which after all is only the minor premise of a syllogism, nothing at all logically follows, much less the act of choosing. Thus certain assumptions must be made in order for the existential condition of "scarcity" to give any result. These assumptions vary, depending on whether "scarcity" is held to characterize the situation of the individual or that of society as a whole. In either case, however, a statement about how the individual or society will behave when faced with "scarcity" must be asserted or assumed. As to the first, the individual, the two quotations below state, and with equal clarity despite three centuries of intervening thought, the naturalistic premise usually associated with "the scarcity postulate" when it is used to characterize the individual's situation: If any two men desire the same thing, which neverthelesse they cannot both enjoy, they become enemies; and in the way to their End, (which is principally their owne conservation, and sometimes their delectation only) endeavour to destroy, or subdue one an other. (Hobbes) Both the facilities necessary to perform functions and the rewards which are important to the motivation of individual actors are inherently scarce. Hence their allocation cannot be left to an unregulated competitive process without great frustration and conflict ensuing. (Parsons, et al.)25 Stated in the form of a syllogism this naturalistic argument reads: if there is not enough, there will be war; there is not enough (i.e., the "scarcity postulate"); and therefore, there is war—or, in Hobbes' version, would be except that government restrains men's impulsive behavior. Underlying this argument is the assumption that what men strive for is given in nature, independently of their existence in society. Therefore, since men must live "in society," societies must provide solutions to this conflict of natural interests. But, in company with Rousseau, modern sociological theory flatly denies Hobbes' "solution" —the fundamental social controls are "not graven on tablets of marble 290 Institutional Analysis or brass, but on the hearts of the citizens"26—and thereby it denies also the major premise. Instead, the sociological premise reads, "If there is not enough, men will act in accordance with the instituted values"— which is of course how they will act whether or not there is enough. This sweeping assertion must be understood in the spirit in which it is written. There is no intention of denying that scarcity, under certain social conditions and used in the technical sense, may not be of relevance for sociological theory. But the concept of "society" has meaning for action-theory sociologists only insofar as it refers to a system of interaction patterns. Both the patterning of interaction and the integration of the patterns into a system result from a coherent set of cultural values being present. Furthermore, they are present in a definite way, as basic parts both of the role definitions and of the personalities of the persons playing the roles. Independently of values instituted in this double sense, there can be no conception of a system of interaction patterns and hence none of society either. It cannot be "scarcity as a fact of nature" which is relevant, then, but only "scarcity" either as a critical shortage or as a generally acted upon cultural definition of situations. In neither case is "scarcity" universal, since neither famines and floods nor money as a generalized means of exchange are recurrent characteristics of all societies. As to the second—when "scarcity" is held to characterize the situation of society as a whole—we confront a type of formulation which is unfortunately all too frequent in the social sciences. For, to propose the question of how "society will act" under conditions of chronic shortage—or under any others—and to give a literal answer is to commit the sin of reification. The concept of "society" refers to a system of varied modes of behavior, but the concept of "action" requires a substantial agent, and one to which subjective states such as "end" or "attitude" can be attributed. "Society" cannot, then, in the literal sense, perform an "action." But if a literal reading of the question of how society responds to "scarcity" is logically fallacious, a metaphorical reading results in the elimination of "scarcity." The alleged response of society to the condition of "scarcity" is "allocation," a term referring either to the process of distributing things or to the state of affairs consequent upon such a distributing. In either case, "allocation" denotes what we already know, that members of society are continually being supplied with material Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 291 means or that at any given time they have a supply. The process of supplying them consists, in the part denoted by the summary concept of "allocation," of a multiplicity of "allocating" actions that are performed by individuals in their respective social roles and in accordance with the instituted values. "Scarcity" can be said to cause this process only if it is said to cause the actions by individuals through which it is carried on. And this argument, except for rather special cases, we have already seen to be sociologically untenable. To deny the universal relevance of "scarcity" for the operation of the economy is of course not to deny the relevance of scarcity-situations under specific social conditions.* Correspondingly, while the compound concept of "economy" is certainly unsatisfactory as a conception of the generic economic process, it just as certainly is of great importance in certain types of cases. The actual conditions under which scarcity-situations occur and the compound concept applies remain in large part still a problem for research. But two conditions seem of obvious importance: one is the presence of money as a generalized means of exchange, the other, the extent to which cultural definitions and social control permit "free choices" to occur. In the absence of the first, the uses to which material means may be put are considerably restricted—at least to the objects' culturally recognized technical characteristics. Because "generalized" refers to a means' usefulness in very many ways, a generalized means can be said to be invariably "scarce." But because wheat, for example, has a distinctly limited range of uses, there can be too much of it as well as too little. Moreover, whatever the listed range of uses to which an object is at some time or another put, individuals may not be free at any one time to choose among these technical alternatives. If, in particular, automatic rules govern an object's use for all times and places, and if most objects are covered by such rules, then no one exercises "choice" about how the objects are to be used, no matter what the amount available. (A variation on this point is where choice in the use of material objects is a prerogative of authority positions, so that again the bulk of the population make no choices.) Thus the presence of scarcity-situations would seem to be a matter of degree. And the actual extent to which such situations affect the supply of material means would seem to be a result in part of the * See above, pp. 246-7. 292 Institutional Analysis "generality" of money, assuming of course it is present as a means of exchange at all, and of the scope permitted to individuals to choose among the uses to which the means may be put. But both the exchange use of money and the frequence and scope of choosing stand within the sphere of culturally defined and socially sanctioned activities. Neither is present in all societies, and so scarcity-situations cannot be used to define what is present in all societies, the economic process. At the same time, both are present in some societies, and in these the social activities contributing to the economic process are typically organized by market-type arrangements, for which "economy" in the compound sense is the appropriate initial conception. The basic point remains, however, that "economy" defined functionally in terms of certain requirements of the system is a different process, sub-system or institution from "economy" defined in terms of constituent actions. To presume that one can use "scarcity" as a system-problem and thereby introduce the economizing process is either to strip the concept of its meaning and substitute instead naturalistic assumptions or to retain the formal- economic assumptions and make all economies variations on the market theme, thereby negating the very purpose of a functional formulation. The functional and the rational action formulations of "economy" may coincide in fact—under those specific conditions when scarcity-situations are instituted. But this is only one type of economy. conclusion of part i The description of the economy as a generalized version of the theory of the market is simply one more instance of an indiscriminate eclecticism which has occasionally marked the development to modern sociological theory. In this instance, the lens of the borrowed looking glass was too powerful and sociologists, failing to make the necessary adjustments, have ignored economic phenomena where they exist, postulated market phenomena where they do not in fact exist, and confused questions about the historical and functional conditions of structures of rational action with questions about the types of social structure which make up different kinds of economies. More concerned in theory with the relations between economics and sociology than Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 293 -with the relations between economy and society, and their researches limited to areas bordering on economic analysis, they have neglected the basic problem of comparing economies, namely the conceptualization of a generic economic process. In effect, sociological problems within the sphere of the economy have been defined by economists, and one result is that today we are largely ignorant of economies other than our own. And, lacking a sociology of the market, we understand even that only partially. The Substantive View of the Economy Despite the popularity of the gemeinschaft-gesellschaft theme, the assumption has persisted in sociological circles that the only "real" economic process is the one observed to operate in market-type economies. Some years ago, the usefulness was demonstrated of taking the distinction literally and of not presuming that the economies of communally or centrally ordered societies are organized through legally limited and contractually specified relations entered into by what Max Weber called "formally free" individuals. In the years since The Great Transformation27 was written much effort has gone into developing what is in this book called the substantive conception of the economy. The problem in this second part of this chapter will be to develop in sociological terms the high points of this conception. The discussion will proceed in two steps, focusing first on the manner in which the economic process is instituted in all societies and then on the various ways in which it may be organized in different societies. Addressing the discussion to this pair of questions would seem to be doubly useful. Answers to them not only may constitute a step in the direction of a sociological theory of the economy, but will also give the sociological import of the recurrent assertions that the economic process is an instituted process and that it may be instituted in significantly different ways. Whether the ideas presented are useful depends, however, less on the stated points of convergence between them and contemporary sociological theory than on the extent to which they jibe with present knowledge of current and historical economies. This test, however, cannot in the limited scope of this chapter be carried out, so that the conceptions advanced here are done so very tentatively. 294 Institutional Analysis the economic process and society The economic process—that which results in the continuous supply of want-satisfying material means—is not only, nor even mainly, an object of sociological concern. Physical, chemical, biological, and psychological factors, as well as social factors, contribute to the actual livelihood of men, so that the total process is a complex network of causality effecting this supply. However, the causal web is not all of a piece. Rather, it is chain-like, each link having distinctive properties. It is, so to speak, broken up into several segments, each of which forms a part of the subject matter of a special discipline. But each segment can be such subject matter only because its activities operate in relative independence of the activities in the other segments; or, the properties of no one segment determine the properties of either any other segment or the total process. For our purposes here, it is sufficient to distinguish three segments or levels, the strictly social, the psychological, and the naturalistic. From an outright naturalistic position, the social and psychological aspects of the total economic process appear as mere epiphenomena in the fundamental relation between the human organism as a biological system and the biological, physical, and chemical processes in the environment which satisfy the organism's requirements. The other two enter, if they enter at all, as no more than complicating links in a chain which otherwise consists of phenomena like breathing, processes which directly involve an interchange between organic requirements and the satisfying objects in the environment. Fortunately for our concern, however, the biological relation is basically the same within an enormously variable range of human activities. This relative independence of the biological and the specifically human aspects of the economic process means that those primarily interested in the latter can abstract them from the total economic process. For the causally related biological aspects cannot account for any of the differences which are in fact observed in the patterning of the social activities. From a social standpoint, then, the non-social aspects of the economic process appear largely as constant processes which in no wise determine the variations in human activities although they just as certainly are present in all concrete actions. These relatively independent social aspects of the economic process Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 295 are usually introduced by saying that the organic needs and what in the environment satisfies them are "socially defined," but in the sense, that the needs become "wants" (or "felt needs") and the objects must be "perceived." This casting of a psychological light on the whole subject has been a constant source of trouble for the sociologist, since he has had to deal with what is from the standpoint of substantive economies the pseudo-problem of a specific type of "economic motivation." That there is a psychological level to the economic process which is intermediate to the sociological and sub-social and links them, is of course true. But the specifically psychological processes (e.g., memory, perception, etc.) are also, like the naturalistic processes, fairly constant over a wide range of human activities. For this reason, we can go one step further here. "Socially defined" can be interpreted to refer to the conception that role definitions—what from the perspective of the person playing the role are role-expectations—state the socially acceptable or required goals that are to be pursued and the similarly acceptable or required meanings which are to be imputed to material objects. Thus while the economic process includes much more than the socially defined activities of men that contribute to the supply of material means, this set of activities is what in the total process primarily interests the sociologist. This social aspect, denoted here by the usual term "economy," is relatively independent of the non-social and psychological aspects of the total economic process, in the sense that the latter remain fairly constant over a wide range of variations in the character of the specifically social aspect. To explain these variations in men's economic activities, then, one must turn to the wider system of social actions, the society, of which the economy as a social process is a part. For these economic activities, while attuned to the environing conditions, are the product not primarily of these conditions but of the ordered ways of group living, of the patterns of interaction; and the coherence that the activities clearly manifest results primarily from being a part of this system of interaction patterns. The economic process is an "instituted process," then, in the obvious sense that an essential part of it is also a part of a social system— that part composed of the activities of men contributing to the supply of material means. The patterning manifested by these "economic activities" derives from the same source that the patterning of any set of social actions derives, namely, the process of institutionalization. Thus what goals are pursued, either in regard to the economic process or 296 Institutional Analysis otherwise, and how material objects are defined (i.e., the meanings imputed to them) can be viewed as patterned by social role definitions. It is not, then, the economic process in its totality that is instituted, but only that part consisting of men's actions. The other parts of the economic process, specifically, the "natural" or non-social parts, while they can in varying extents be "controlled" by men, can never be instituted in the strict sense of the concept. Thus so long as men cannot live by moral convictions alone there will be a constant source of instability in their action systems, no matter how well integrated these convictions are. For, some of the properties of the situation on which the stability of the action systems causally depends are in turn causally dependent on natural processes external to social systems, and in this way are a source of instability. This formulation of the social aspects of the economic process suggests the basis for developing a functional conception of the economy, for the economy is evidently one of the mechanisms through which this potential instability is kept to a minimum. If it is true that the meanings of material objects are given by role definitions, then it is also true that the stability of the system of role definitions, and hence of the actions carried out in accordance with them, depends upon the objects being present in the situation of action in order to be defined. A shoemaker must "have" leather in order to make shoes, but his "having" the leather is only partly a resultant of processes internal to the system of roles. The calf's maturation and the action of the acid on the hide are just as important as the feeding of the calf and the application of the acid. But these causally relevant processes external to the social system continually vary in ways which would upset the equilibrium of expectations if the economy, a part of both the economic process and the social system, did not operate as a reduction gear, transforming the large fluctuations in the non-social part of the economic process into smaller rhythmic variations to which role expectations can be attuned. This function is, logically, a necessary one if the social system is to be viewed as a relatively independent focus of investigation. If every fluctuation in nature produced a corresponding fluctuation in society, the hypothesis that social processes constitute a system sufficiently independent to be the subject of a scientific discipline would be invalid. Thus a tentative way of viewing the economy functionally is as a process operating within the "boundary sphere" between the "purely" Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 297 social and the "purely" natural. In this capacity as a boundary-process, it functions to maintain the line separating the social processes which are internal to society and compose it, from the natural processes which, while external to society, are causally related to the social processes. It performs this function by keeping the fluctuations in the natural environment from impinging on social processes in forms, or to degrees, not taken into account by the instituted set of role expectations. THE tNSTTTUTING OF THE ECONOMIC PROCESS In the preceding analysis it was suggested that the economy consists of all those social actions which contribute to the supply of material means, and that the defining function for society of this aggregate of actions is to maintain the boundary between processes internal to society and the external processes of the natural environment. The next question to take up is how this functionally identified aggregate of actions comes to manifest the stability and recurrence which characterizes in varying degrees all economies. By using the market model, sociologists have had to assume in fact, if not explicitly, that the immediate and most important source has been the price system. As the following paragraphs will suggest in more detail, the problem is substantially more complicated. The stability and recurrence of economic activities derive from sources so various that even a simple formulation of the question leads directly to fundamental sociological problems. The assumption which underlies any explanation of the stability and recurrence of the set of functionally defined economic actions is that they are not only an aggregate of actions, a logical class, but are also an "economy," a natural grouping. It is assumed that the actions occur in ordered sequences and that these bear definite relations to one another and to sequences of non-economic actions. The problem is thus to locate in various societies the patterned social arrangements of which economic actions are a part and from which their orderly occurrence derives. This is, however, a complicated problem. These social arrangements, that give to sets of economic actions their stability and recurrence, are social units of more or less inclusiveness, existing at different "levels" within society. They may be, for example, the roles of which economic action patterns are a part; or the organizations of which eco- 1 298 Institutional Analysis nomic roles are a part; or the broader structures of which economic organizations themselves are a part.28 One result of this complication is that we must expect to see considerable variation from society to society in the "level" at which economic action patterns are integrated with non-economic action patterns. In what follows, mention will be made only of the four most evident levels. At the first level, economic actions are carried out in roles that are constituted predominantly by actions having negligible effects on the economic process. The basic values defining activity in such roles and thus ordering the action sequences are not likely to be oriented primarily to the economic process, so that economic actions are closely integrated and guided by non-economic considerations. An example of integration at this level is the distribution of foodstuffs (economic action) to the poor by a priest (non-economic role context). Second, economic actions may be the major elements in roles, but these economic roles themselves may be units of structures consisting mainly of non-economic roles. The tamkarum, a specifically economic role found throughout the societies of the ancient Near East, is almost always a unit of a structure political in overall organization and basic policy.* The purchasing agent of a modern university is, similarly, an economic role in an organizational context that is primarily non-economic. Predominantly economic roles may however be grouped or organized to form continuous economic organizations, such as plantations, factories, guilds, etc. The third level at which economic and non-economic action patterns are integrated is where such organizations operate in non-economic structural contexts, as in an Israeli commune. Finally, the structure of relations among economic organizations may itself be economic, as in a market system or in the planned economy of a modern complex society. In so far as the set of economic actions are all elements within this inclusive structure, the economy is a relatively independent sub-system of society and is integrated with non-economic sub-systems primarily through that set of instituted values common to all roles (secondary means being the structural modes of interdependence, e.g., multiple roles). To use the market model as the theory explaining how all economies operate, then, is to assume that the coherence undoubtedly manifested by the economic activities in all societies results mainly from * See above, Ch. II, and p. 260. Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 299 the integration of economic actions at the fourth system-level and thus in relative independence from the organization of action patterns, in other institutional spheres. Generally, this means assuming coher-' ence to occur because actions are oriented to the conditions of a price-making market system; but, with certain adjustments in the model, it can also mean assuming coherence to result from actions being oriented to the conditions of a modern "nationalized" economy. In any case, the implied assumption is the basic reason why, where such markets or planning are absent, no understanding of the structuring of economic activities is possible by using this model. Here lies also the significance of the distinction between "embedded" and "unembedded" economies.29 As the above description of system-levels suggests, "embeddedness" is a matter of more or less, at one end being economies whose constituent actions are patterned through their occurrence in non-economic roles, at the other end, those economies organized through such economic institutions as fluctuating prices and centralized planning. While the market model may explain the coherence of actions in economies near the zero end of the "embeddedness" dimension, it can never explain this property of the economic actions carried out either as secondary aspects of non-economic roles (such as the priests) or within economic roles which are secondary elements in non-economic organizations (such as the university or state). Strictly speaking, then, there are no "different ways" of instituting the economic process, since all actions are instituted in basically only one way. What is meant by the phrase is that the economic process is instituted at different social levels, in the sense that the explanation for its degrees of unity and stability in one society may be a matter of the integration of actions in roles, while in another, of the integration of roles in organizations, and in yet another, of the integration of organizations into systems. Yet another way of phrasing the limitations of the market model, then, is to say that a necessary condition of its application is the organization of almost all economic activities into a coherent and relatively independent sub-system of society. In so far as the economy, defined as the aggregate of actions contributing to the supply of material means, is not organized as a structurally distinctive sub-system of society, then the market model is not merely useless, it is positively misleading. 300 Institutional Analysis locational and appropriational types of economic action However, the substantive analysis of economies is complex not only because the economic process may be instituted at different levels in different societies. It is complex also because this may be true within any one society. Since any empirical economy consists in its social aspects of an aggregate of actions, some of these may be organized in non-economic roles while others are parts of roles occurring within economic organizations. (This is the main difference between the economic actions of the housewife in our society and those of her husband.) This very general assertion suggests that economic actions may not be merely an undifferentiated aggregate but may be classifiable into types which are frequently found to be instituted at different levels within any one society. While a list of the dimensions useful for distinguishing types of economic actions which vary in this respect is yet to be drawn up, it is possible to indicate a seemingly basic distinction. The two types of economic action so derived appear likely to vary in the level, or at least in the concrete social arrangements, in which they are instituted. To develop this dichotomy, we must turn to a distinction between two kinds of changes which occur in the economic process. While so far we have treated the economic process as divisible mainly in terms of social and non-social aspects, this has been a simplification which must now be given up, for from another perspective the material objects in the continuous flow are characterized by two basic types of movements. One type consists of changes in an object's relations to other objects, and is called "locational movements." The other consists of changes in an object's relations to social roles, is called "ap-propriational movements," and usually but not always involves "rights" (but in the broad sociological, not the legal sense).* Corresponding to these two types of movements of objects are two types of economic actions, that is, of social actions contributing to the supply of material means. One consists of appropriational actions, which comprise almost all appropriational movements, whether these consist of one-sided dispositions, or two-sided transactions, whether of things, rights, or what Max Weber called "opportunities." The other consists of those actions which directly cause locational changes. In * See above, pp. 248-9. Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 301 moving particles or masses of matter, in Locke's phrase, "men mix their labour with their produce." In company with natural processes, these locational actions account for all locational movements. In contrast to the redefinition of the social situation involved in appropriational actions, these imply "effort." Before discussing these types of economic action in relation to levels of instituting, we should note that they correspond to the usual distinction between "production" and "distribution" (or "circulation" or "allocation"). However, they are more precise. "Distribution" in particular tends to be used in two quite different ways, one referring to locational movements, as in transporting, the other, to appropriational movements, as in retailing. From the substantive economic standpoint, "distribution" consists only of appropriational movements. Locational movements, on the other hand, include both transporting and what is usually understood by "production," the difference between the two being mainly a difference in the scale of the spatial frame of reference in which the locational operations are carried out. That these two types of action may be instituted at different levels is exemplified in Walter Neale's analysis of the traditional Indian village.* There "labour" or, more strictly, locational actions (excepting tillage), is instituted through the caste system. What contributions (apart from grain) a person makes to the supply of material means are organized through his more inclusive caste role. On the other hand, the appropriational movements—who appropriates how much from what piles of produce—do not appear to follow caste lines. Within the total community they are organized through the different community roles, such as cultivator, priest, herdsman, etc., while within the joint family they are organized through the patriarchal structure of that social unit, the head of the family parcelling out shares to the family's members. The distinction between the two types of economic action, empirically useful in describing the structure of an economy, is however not only based on the substantive conception of the economic process as consisting of two types of movements. It also relates to the previously formulated sociological conception of the economy as a boundary sphere, one which keeps the operation of natural processes from impinging on the total system of social processes. For the locational economic actions constitute the specific interchanges linking the social and non-social aspects of the total economic process. The appropria- * See above, pp. 226-7. If 302 Institutional Analysis tional actions, on the other hand, are the specific interchanges linking the economy as a social process to the other social processes—and to other economies, though this problem of inter-society "trade" will not be discussed here. Those two dimensions, the degree of "embeddedness" and the types of movements, are basic to a substantive conception of the economy in its sociological aspects. Yet a third, the patterns which integrated sets of economic movements manifest, might also be mentioned. To date, these have been described by the "forms of integration" as "reciprocity," "redistribution," and "exchange." Whether there are other patterns as fundamental, or whether these three exhaust the principal "pure" types, must remain problems for research. That a similar threefold distinction characterizes both the mechanisms regulating the "al-locative flow," in the monograph by Parsons, Shils, and Olds, and Pitirim Sorokin's types of social relations argues that the forms of integration are more than merely ad hoc principles.30 The "allocative mechanisms" are in fact very close parallels, consisting of allocation through selective decisions by people in authority, automatic application of cultural rules, and impersonal competition among "free" individuals. Nevertheless, the theoretical underpinnings of the "forms of integration" have not been clearly stated—so that at times the "forms" are used to refer to locational changes of objects, at other times, to appropriational changes and occasionally to both—and need to be developed if the concepts are to be basic tools as well as pragmatically useful designations. So far then it has been suggested that the economic process is instituted through the integration of men's patterned economic actions, which make up its social aspect, with their non-economic actions; that even within the same society the process may be instituted at different system levels, in the sense that the stability and recurrence of the economic actions may derive from their integration at any one of a number of these levels; and that "productive" and "distributive" actions, as these were defined above, are particularly subject to being instituted at different levels or at least through different sets of social arrangement. I have, perhaps too rigidly, attempted in this conceptual presentation to avoid identifying any particular subjective or psychological dispositions as appropriate by definition to economic actions. This by no means should be taken to mean that such dispositions are irrelevant (i.e., random) or even constant: not only can we presume Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 303 variations, but we can expect patterned variations. However, since most contemporary writers have stressed a particular type of subjective element (i.e., rationality), I have wanted to indicate that many types are potentially compatible. While further conceptual elaborations easily suggest themselves, for example, the various motivational components of the types of actions when they are included in different kinds of social structure, such conjecturing would take us well beyond present knowledge. Indeed, the supply lines to this knowledge may already have become too long. conclusion In this essay an attempt has been made to show that present sociological views of the economy are inadequate formulations of a generic economic process, and are thus unsuitable as basic conceptions within a general theory of social systems, and that what is needed is a conception based on the substantive meaning of "economy." In both the "division-of-labor" view and that of the economy as a sphere of rational actions (or of contractual relations), the economist's model of the market was seen to be the guiding image. In the first, "exchange" was assumed to be the only way in which the allegedly divided labor was united; in the second, it is the only mode of distribution. Where a functional definition of the economy has been introduced, the presumption has been that the economy consists of economizing, so that the relevant system problem, in terms of which the economy is functionally defined, is "scarcity." It was argued that this concept is ambiguous in meaning, has irrelevant naturalistic implications, and at best serves only to define the market system. Present functional formulations, being little more than devices to introduce a market economy, are also subject to the same criticisms made against viewing the economy as composed of rational actions, namely, conceptual confusions, parochialism, and a tacit ideological bias. Starting from the fact that "economy" is usually used in its compound sense, of a process supplying material means through economizing actions, I suggested that a functional formulation of the economy, based on the substantive element of the supply of material means, would be more fruitful. From this fundamental idea, which included stating in what sense the total economic process is instituted, two basic 304 Institutional Analysis dimensions of the economy were developed. One is the system level at which economic actions are integrated, the other is the distinction of these actions into two types, locational and appropriational. As with most conceptions in the contemporary social sciences, the validity of those presented here depends perhaps more upon their usefulness in helping to pose theoretically important but researchable questions than upon their logical coherence—though it is hoped that that quality is not entirely lacking. The basic set of ideas in the substantive approach to the economy has already demonstrated its usefulness in economic history and anthropology, a fact to which other parts of this book bear witness. Perhaps it can similarly assist in the development of a sociological theory of the economy, one with relevance for a broader set of problems than those bounded by the Western economy of the nineteenth century. Terence K. Hopkins Notes to Chapter XIV 1. Seeesp. pp. 243 ff. 2. See, e.g., Wilbert Moore's Economy and Society (Garden City, N.Y., 1955), esp. 5. 3. For an instance of such a generalization, see Kingsley Davis and Wilbert Moore, "Some principles of stratification," American Sociological Review, 10 (1945): 242-9; reprinted in Logan Wilson and William L. Kolb, eds., Sociological Analysis (New York, 1949) 434-443. 4. The Integration of Economic and Social Theory (1953, mimeographed) on file at the Social Relations Library, Harvard University. 5. The concept of rationality may be introduced initially in several ways, for example, as a type of action, as a preferred norm in certain kinds of social relations, or as a general cultural value. 6. The most systematic presentation of functional concepts in sociology is in "Manifest and latent functions," ch. I of Robert K. Merton's collected essays, Social Theory and Social Structure (Glencoe, 111.: 1949), esp. 49-81. 7. The Division of Labor, Introduction and ch. 1. 8. "Exchange" in this latter case denotes a concept that not only is operationally independent of observable vice-versa movements of useful things between people, but is instead theoretically dependent on a conception excluded from the basic schema of atomistic sociologies, namely, shared reciprocal expectations. For it is in the context of such expectations that rational calculations take place, as Adam Smith intuitively perceived when he writes of a "certainty of being able to exchange" (The Wealth of Nations, Bk. I, ch. 2). It is of course no solution to the complex problem of what socio-cultural phenomena are indicated by the various overt forms which men's activities take to assume simply that discrete movements of Sociology and the Substantive View of the Economy 305 material, whether organic or inorganic, stand in a one-to-one correlation with a particular type of normatively defined social relation. 9. At the root of both difficulties—marking off the economy and integrating its parts—is the conversion of a methodological problem, which resides in the fact that cultural values are not "observable" in the same way as overt forms of activity are, into the theoretic orientation that the forms of activity are to be understood without reference to values. While this radical disjunction between outer and inner forms of behavior is in fact maintained neither in specific concepts nor in drawing the social implications of the asocial premises, it nevertheless constitutes a fundamental tenet of atomistic sociology. That the dichotomy results in significant oversights was explicitly noted by Karl Marx (Capital, I, Pt. IV, ch. 14, Sec. 4) when he took Adam Smith to task for equating the division of labor in factories with its division in society: the social and psychological consequences of divided labor differ substantially when the way in which such labor is integrated differs. The distinction between the two forms cannot be one of basic sociological theory but at the most only of procedure: one can leave open the question of specific values and motivations associated with otherwise identifiable kinds of economic activity, but one cannot dismiss as irrelevant the categories of value and motivation. 10. As the discussion is necessarily brief, and to that extent imperfect and perhaps involuntarily misleading, the interested reader is advised to examine the following works which present in some detail the general action frame of reference: Talcott Parsons and Edward A. Shils, eds., Toward a General Theory of Action (Cambridge, Mass., 1952); Talcott Parsons, The Social System (Glencoe, 111., 1951) ; Pitirim A. Sorokin, Social and Cultural Dynamics (New York, 1937-41, 4 vols); Pitirim A. Sorokin, Society, Culture and Personality: Their Structure and Dynamics (New York, 1947); Florian Znaniecki, Cultural Sciences (Urbana, 111., 1952) ; and Robert M. Maclver, Social Causation (Boston, 1942). 11. These three spheres of culture, personality, and society are viewed as relatively independent systems of action patterns, representing not distinct entities, for men's activities are the common concrete points of reference, but distinctly different ways of perceiving such activities and of organizing the uniformities the activities manifest. 12. See Ernest Nagel, A Formalization of Functionalism (mimeographed, 1953) on file in Burgess Library, Columbia University. The logic of functional analysis in sociology is not yet well developed. In addition to Nagel, who should be read in conjunction with Merton, "Manifest and latent functions," and to several scattered comments in the works of Parsons, see the brief "axiomatic" statement by Morris Zelditch, Jr., "A Note on the Analysis of Equilibrium Systems," Appendix B, in Talcott Parsons and Robert F. Bales, Family, Socialization and Interaction Process (Glencoe, 111., 1955). See also, Talcott Parsons, Robert F. Bales, and Edward A. Shils, Working Papers in the Theory of Action (Glencoe, 111., 1953), chs. III-V. 13. Of the several works by Weber that are translated, the most relevant to cite here is The Theory of Social and Economic Organization, trans, by A. M. Henderson and Talcott Parsons (New York, 1947). 14. See the discussion in Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action (Glencoe, 111., 1949), ch. X, "The Idealistic Tradition." 15. See "The Motivation of Economic Activities" in Parsons' collected essays, Essays in Sociological Theory (Glencoe, 111., 1949), esp. 202. 16. See, for example, Sorokin, Social and Cultural Dynamics, III, ch. 1; Hans Speier's review in American Sociological Review, 2 (1937), 924-929; and Soro-kin's revision of these three types in Society, Culture and Personality . .., 99-110. t 306 Institutional Analysis 17. For example, Znaniecki, Cultural Sciences, 322-323. 18. Evidence for this claim is to be found in several of the peripheral studies which Wilbert Moore has included in "The Sociology of Economic Organization," in Gurvitch and Moore, eds. Twentieth Century Sociology. However, Moore himself mentions explicitly that such terms as "demand," "labor," and "price" lose almost all of their precision in being transferred from economics to sociology. 19. See Merton, Social Theory, ch. 1, esp. 35-38. 20. Social Causation, 284-285. 21. For discussions of the concept "functional requirements" see the previously cited references on the logic of functional analysis. See also, Parsons, The Social System, chs. II and V; Kingsley Davis, Human Society (New York, 1949) 29-50; and David Aberle, et al, "The functional prerequisites of a society," Ethics, 60 (1950) 100-111. It is outside the scope of this paper to assay whether the statement, that those "requirements must be met," rests on the logical ground that the requirements are part of what is meant by "society as a system," on the theoretic ground that meeting them follows from, some more basic postulates, or on the empirical ground that all known societies do in fact meet certain requirements. 22. Social Theory ..., 81. 23. See Ch. XIII, pp. 245-247. 24. Talcott Parsons, Edward A. Shils, and James Olds, "Values, motives, and systems of action," in Parsons and Shils, eds. Toward . . . , 197. 25. Pt. 1, ch. 13 of Leviathan; Talcott Parsons, et al., "Some fundamental categories of the theory of action," in Parsons and Shils, eds. Toward . . . , 25. 26. The Social Contract, Bk. II, ch. 12. 27. Karl Polanyi, The Great Transformation (New York, 1944) esp. ch. 4. 28. Readers versed in "Columbia sociology" will recognize here the formulations of Professor Merton, from whose lectures on "The Functional Analysis of Social Structure," given at Columbia University, I have taken the idea. 29. See Polanyi, The Great Transformation, ch. IV. The distinction is com- ' parable to, though not quite the equivalent of, the sociologist's distinction between "differentiated" and "undifferentiated." 30. "Values, motives and systems of action," 207; Social and Cultural Dynamics, III, ch. 1; see also, Margaret Mead, "Public Opinion Mechanisms Among Primitive Peoples," Public Opinion Quarterly, 1 (1937), 5-16, for a surprisingly similar trichotomy in this somewhat different field of "public opinion." XV ^Parsons and Smdscr on the &conomy the publication of a greatly enlarged and revised version of Professor Talcott Parsons' "Marshall Lectures"1 lends impressive support to our conviction that a discipline which may be called "economic sociology" is being newly established in the United States. The impetus for the widely current efforts in the direction of an economic sociology comes from the increasing array of empirical problems met by all social scientists who must face up to economies as social systems. The problems arise in two different areas of interest; those involving premarket economies, both literate and nonliterate, and those where contemporary departures from the pattern of a self-regulating system of markets pose the problem. Attempts to deal systematically with these distinctly separate empirical problems converge on a common interest: the establishment of a generally relevant theory of economic organization and development. It is this interest that we have in mind in attempting to appraise the accomplishments of Talcott Parsons and Neil Smelser in their new book, Economy and Society, for, although the empirical problems with which this book deals are derived from a market-ordered economy, it represents a theoretical tour de force aimed in the direction of a general theory. Starting at the opposite pole, the book in which this chapter appears is concerned with the problems of primitive, early historical and nonwestern economies, but it too is regarded as a modest offering in the same direction. The opportunity to discuss the position now taken by Professor Parsons is therefore welcomed on general grounds. 307 308 Institutional Analysis Our purpose is to clarify points held in common, differences in approach and fundamental disagreements in so far as both efforts come to grips with the problem of determining the shifting place of the economy in human society. It is encouraging to find that there are important areas of agreement between these two books. A "functional" approach is common to both. Professor Parsons' sociology views society in terms of certain functional requirements all of which must be satisfied if that society is to continue and prosper. All of the specific units of the society—the "collectivities," institutions and roles—are seen as necessarily contributing to the fullfillment of these functional prerequisites; although they may, of course, be differentiated in terms of primary functions. The central analytical problem is that all the units of the whole society "participate in the economy," but, because every concrete unit is multifunctional, none is "purely economic" (p. 14). Thus, although we feel that the authors' analysis is based on a mistaken quasi-identification of economic theory and sociology, in principle the Parsons-Smelser book conceives the problem of economy and society in the same way as it is here conceived. The fruitfulness of employing the basic conceptual tools of modern sociology in approaching the economy—especially the conception of cultural values embedded in institutions, roles and personalities (i.e., the "reality" of society)—is clearly demonstrated in the ease with which this new book is able to dispose of some hoary problems of economic theory which arise from that theory's "psychological and sociological atomism" (p. 23). A functionally defined economy is seen as performing within the structural context of society. Thus, "the goal of the economy is not simply the production of income for the utility of an aggregate of individuals. It is the maximization of production relative to the whole complex of institutionalized value-systems and functions of the society and its subsystems" (p. 22). We believe that the maximization principle introduces a bias into the definition of the economy's function, but again in principle there is agreement with many of the basic ideas in the present book. While we thus find important areas of fundamental agreement and the underlying concepts for the articulation of an economic sociology are clearly presented, the two efforts part company in their separate attempts to deal systematically with the problems. In fact they seem to move in almost opposite directions. This divergence may be due in large measure to the different location of the empirical problems which Parsons and Smelser on the Economy 309 the two books set out to examine. But in so far as both make some claim to generality this reason cannot be accepted as decisive. More significant, is the fact that in the manner of attacking the problem, once it is stated, we are at opposite poles. In the history of the attempt to locate the place of the economy in society—or, as we should prefer, of economies in societies—two distinct lines of approach can be discerned. Both take their cue from the entrance of the market system onto the scene of history. One approach proceeds through what might be called "institutional" analysis. The economy in its concrete manifestations is here the subject of interest. Aristotle, Marx, the German "Historical School," Menger in his posthumous work, the American "Institutional-ists," to name but a few, resorted to this approach with varying degrees of success. It is also the method of the book in which this chapter appears. It was the appearance of the market system with its inherent tendency to separate the economic process from its societal integument which urgently raised the question of the different ways in which the organization of livelihood affects the community. And this is the parent interest of all those who followed this line of attack. The first essential of this method (here most attempts have foundered) is a definition of the economy that allows an analytical distinction between what is economic and what is not. This requires a statement of the economy's function and of the operations necessary to that function. The analysis of any particular economy, its development over time, or the comparison of different economies hinges here upon observation of the manner in which the economic operations are institutionalized. And this is an empirical problem. The ability to generalize and predict depends, with this method, upon the emergence of common patterns in the institutionalized operations. The forms of integration—reciprocity, redistribution and exchange as they are employed in the present book, for example—are typical of such empirically derived patterns.* There is another tradition of social thought which was brought to the consideration of our problem through an interest in, to use Weber's term, the Zweckrational orientation of modern western society, i.e., its heightened concern with the rational way of doing.things whatever the ultimate ends. Represented most prominently by Weber, Marshall, Pareto, and Parsons, this strain of thought has therefore been concerned primarily with a certain "aspect" of social behavior, its develop- * See above, Ch. XIII. 310 Institutional Analysis ment and organizational consequences. The link between this interest and the location of empirical economies in societies was provided by the advent of the market system which institutionalized economizing action so that the goods and person movements of the empirical economy tended to be ordered by individuals rationally choosing among alternative uses of scarce means. The interest of the scholars in this tradition thus turned very largely around the economy in its market form. If this approach is consistently followed, it will become obvious, as Parsons has clearly shown, that economizing does not exhaust rational human experience, but is inevitably overlaid with other attitudes and orientations toward the just, the kind, the temperate, the politic, or otherwise "right" way of doing things.2 In logic, the ultimate step in the development of this approach would be the proper identification of all the "aspects" of social action. If this were possible—an attempt Weber himself declined to make—it might then seem feasible to employ the universal "aspects" in the analysis of operating social systems, economic as well as noneconomic. Crucial to the fruitfulness of this approach in the analysis of empirical problems would be the ability to relate in a meaningful way the universals to the actual social structure under consideration. If, for example, the economizing "aspect" of behavior is under scrutiny, then it must first be located in some structure or other—the family, the government, the economy. Economy and Society represents the logically ultimate step in the tradition of this latter attempt to locate economizing action in its social setting. Professor Parsons long ago rejected the "institutional" approach. His decision grew out of the "dilemma," as he saw it, presented by the American "institutionalist" school of economics, especially in the work of Veblen (pp. 5-6). Parsons viewed the "institution-alists" as rejecting economic theory (i.e., the theory of economizing behavior) on the grounds of its failure to explain the concrete facts of economic life, and as attempting, in its stead, to propound "a complete theory of social development." He felt strongly that in such a theory the "economic aspect" of social action "loses its theoretical specificity altogether," hence his own rejection of "institutionalism" (p. 6). Unfortunately, his new statement of the problem does not resolve so much as raise to another level precisely the "dilemma" which is presented not only by the American "institutionalist" movement, but by the whole tradition of western social thought in its attempts to deal with the economy. Parsons and Smehei on the Economy 311 The aim of the Parsons-Smelser work is stated as the formulation of "economic theory's relation to the non-economic aspects of social life" (p. 5), and this is equated with "the relation of the economy to the total society" (p. 16). It thus continues in the direction established by Parsons in The Structure of Social Action. Yet, in another sense, as we are told, the position here is "distinctly different" (p. 6). The alternative to the institutional approach which Professor Parsons took in his earlier work was to follow Pareto,3 maintaining the general validity of economic theory, but admitting that it dealt only with "some of the variables which determine concrete social behavior in the 'economic' as in other spheres" (p. 6). The formal advance beyond Pareto in the new statement lies in the identification of all the "aspects" of social action ["on a cognate level" of abstraction] (pp. 5-6), and their inclusion in a general theory of action, applicable to all systems and subsystems of social interaction. Thus there are no special variables unique to economies as social systems, only "the general variables" of social theory, which are the universal "aspects." The economic case of the general theory is distinctive only in the sense that here "the concrete structures of different societies" are "most favorable empirically to 'purely economic' analysis." That is, economizing action tends to be located in the economy. The authors are aware that there are empirical economies where the social structure does not enforce economizing rationality to any important degree, and further that, "most so-called 'economic' processes must be regarded as resultants of economic and non-economic factors." The former condition, however, is that of the "completely routinized," "undifferentiated" economy with which they are not primarily concerned; the latter, i.e., the interplay of "economic" and "noneconomic" factors, is really the subject of the book (p. 6, n. 4; p. 42). In developing their subject the authors identify four properties of social action as representing the universal functional requirements of social systems and subsystems. The "economic" aspect is said to arise out of the requirement of "adaptation" to an external environment in order that the goals of the system may be achieved. The function of this aspect is said to be, "the generalization of facilities for a variety of system and subsystem goals." The "facilities" are specified as "wealth" or "income" (pp. 18 ff). Their important feature is "their adaptability to . . . various uses" (p. 48). Thus the "economy" becomes a kind of value-neutral sphere of action devoted exclusively to making means 312 Institutional Analysis available. Of the "noneconomic factors" with which "economic" processes are compounded, one is said to be "goal attainment," a requirement also growing out of the relationship between system and environment. It is distinguished from "adaptation," however, by its special function: "the mobilization of the necessary prerequisites for the attainment of given system goals of the society" (p. 48). Thus the attempt is made to distinguish between means and ends by making each a distinctive category of social action. In addition, the fact that these categories necessarily operate in a larger social environment is made the subject of two other system requirements. The process of attaining specific goals and making means generally available must be consistent with the values of the total social system, and it must be coordinated with other processes so as to avoid undue internal conflict among the parts. These two additional requirements are given the names "pattern maintenance" and "integration," respectively. The means-ends distinction has, of course, long been basic to Professor Parsons' analysis of social action. And he has always identified "economic" action with "an intermediate position in the great chain of means and ends."4 That is, economic action was held to be directed toward maximizing the supply of generally available means.5 But Professor Parsons has, in the past, been careful to point out that economizing is a norm of action; its empirical relevance resting on the "circumstance that men do in fact try (not merely 'tend') to 'economize.' "6 And economizing has been distinguished from other types of action in terms of the different norms involved in each case. Thus political action, for example, has been identified as "a rational process of the attainment of ends through the acquisition and exercise of coercive power over other individuals and groups."7 It is important, therefore, to emphasize (a point we shall return to) that in this new elaboration of his position, Professor Parsons has, with Mr. Smelser, taken an important step beyond his previous stand. For while economic ("adaptive") and political ("goal attainment") action are defined in essentially the same way as before, they now assume an entirely new significance by being classed not merely as types of action, but as functional prerequisites of any and all social systems. The "most general proposition" of the authors regarding these categories is that "total societies tend to differentiate into subsystems (social structures) which are specialized in each of the four primary Parsons and Smelser on the Economy 313 functions" (p. 47). Thus they argue that the empirical economy tends to be specialized according to the "adaptive" requirement of the society as a whole, maximizing the flow of "fluidly disposable means," or "utility," to the total social system (pp. 20-1). In other words, although, like every other "concrete" social system, the empirical economy is a composite of all the "aspects" of social action, it tends to be structurally differentiated according to its primary function the definition of which corresponds to economizing with scarce means. This leaves us in the following position: Economizing rationality has been identified as one of the universal aspects of human social behavior. The actual appearance of such behavior, however, is said to depend upon the prior existence of social structures which favor action so oriented. If we are primarily interested in locating the types of social structure in which economizing is found, all of this seems unexceptionable. But if the method is to enhance our understanding of that system whereby men secure the means of their livelihood, then a bridge must be provided between economizing and the economy. Parsons and Smelser do indeed fashion such a bridge, but it is constructed out of conjecture, not the empiry of comparative analysis. Apparently by virtue of a familiar developmental law involving the tendency toward greater division of labor and its assumed correlative, exchange* (p. 104, p. 141), the human economy is said to exhibit a tendency to differentiate according to the society's "adaptive" requirement, which is defined in terms of economizing with scarce means. It is a process consisting of instrumental activity designed to maximize the "economic value" of inherently scarce means.8 By thus joining a formal category of action, economizing, with an empirical entity, the economy, the authors have committed a fateful error. Inevitably, the economy tends to be identified with its market form. The source of the error appears to lie in their having confused the functional requirement of adaptation to environment in the process of achieving system goals with one of the modes of adaptation, namely, economizing. This leads us to suggest that the economic sociology of this new book is founded upon a confusion of two quite different methods of approach. The "Columbian map" by means of which the authors attempt to locate the universal aspects of social systems is capable of being read in two distinctly different ways, and these different interpretations are not adequately distinguished. * For criticism of this view, see above, pp. 276 ff. 314 Institutional Analysis One reading implies a separation, for purposes of analysis, between goal states and the means of attaining them. It is a generalization of the means-ends distinction. The primary "function" of any particular system is, in this interpretation, defined in terms of specific "goals" of the subsystem. For example, at one point we are told, "the goal of the economy is to provide goods and services for consumption" (p. 42). Here we find no assumption regarding how the goal is to be achieved. Since every social structure must somehow reflect the requirement that it "adapt" to its environment, natural and social, there can be no objection to this reading of the "map." And the "exigencies" of that environment will necessarily shape the social structure. Thus societal ■values will leave their imprint and the necessity of integration with other structural units will be reflected. These are requirements of the social situation. The important feature of this interpretation is that it requires no unwarranted assumptions. Specific system goals and the mode of their attainment are here open to investigation. A social system is identified in terms of its goals, while its actual societal form is determined through study of the situation in which it functions. Another interpretation, however, views the same "Columbian" classification in terms of certain types of social action. Here "adaptation" and "goal attainment" are defined as the locus of economizing and power, respectively, acquiring the names "economy" and "polity" (pp. 47-8). The analytical isolation of such spheres may be useful for some purposes, but they are, for that reason, not mere phantoms; their actual appearance presupposes definite social structures. That is, the social structure for economizing action can be clearly defined; it has definite requirements. A perfect market system is the embodiment, although certainly not the only one, of these requirements. The same may be said regarding the exercise of power, although here, of course, the typical social structure would be different. In any case, the correspondence between these types and actual social structures, the economy or government, for example, is problematical. It is precisely the problem for investigation, given this method of approach. To say that the empirical economy inevitably becomes more and more specialized in economizing is to posit a relationship between the livelihood process and a type of rationality which we must insist is not inherent. The above criticism is relevant only in so far as the authors tend to generalize economic rationality as the typical economic process. A fatal blow to a general economic sociology, this false equation might Parsons and Smelser on the Economy 315 be less serious given the principal subject of the book itself. For the authors are chiefly concerned with the "noneconomic" aspects of the market economy, and here, it is true, their analytical subsystem, "economy," and the empirical economy do in fact tend to coincide. It seems to us, however, that a fallacy of misplaced concreteness; ramifies throughout the whole presentation. The "Columbian map" according to which all of the aspects of the total social system are identified is employed to "locate" specifically the noneconomic social environment with which the "economy" (read, "economizing" action) must somehow come to terms in its functioning. As a social system the economy itself is said to have pattern maintenance, integrative, adaptive and goal-attainment exigencies of its own to meet (pp. 40-3). It too is thus composed of analytical subsystems, which, it must be remembered, may not be identified with the firms, unions, banks, etc., of the empirical economy. The economy thus differentiated is bounded by the remaining three subsystems of the total society. In order for the economy to perform its total function all of its system members must somehow come to terms with the apposite member of the societal subsystem at that boundary. This "coming to terms" with the counterpart in a bordering subsystem is viewed as a series of "inputs" and "outputs"' and their "exchange" between system members. In these terms each subsystem is regarded as "producing" an output and exchanging it for the output of its bordering system to their mutual advantage, and contributing, incidentally, to the equilibrium of the total system (Cf. Ch. III). The subsystems of society thus behave toward one another like persons in a price-making market. The details of this scheme of analysis are much too elaborate to describe here, but it clearly represents a highly formalized attempt to illustrate the subordination of the economy to the functional requirements of the whole society. While every social scientist must applaud the basic objective, and even agree that important insights may be gained from such schematic outlines, the same basic criticism must be levelled against the details of this sociology of the market economy as against the general scheme itself. The temptation to reify the purely analytical categories is apparently too great to be resisted. Thus the authors insist that there must be "some correspondence between these economic differentiations and those of social structure . . . though the concrete social structures vary from one society to another" (p. 52). But this is precisely what cannot be concluded from their scheme. It is 316 Institutional Analysis said, for example, that the "polity" is that sphere where power is employed to achieve collective system goals (p. 48). The importance of the "polity" vis-á-vis the "economy" lies in its making available credit facilities for purposes of capital investment. In other words, money is a "political" instrument. Formally, this is stated in terms of the exchange between the "economy" and the "polity" across their "adaptive" boundaries, "rights to intervene" being exchanged for the polity's "decision" to provide credit facilities for capital investment (Cf. Ch. III). Putting aside the difficulty of distinguishing between analytical categories and concrete structures here, what is primarily objectionable is the identification of the general interest of the "polity" in the economic process with only one of the markets in the total system, i.e., the money market. At this point of the analysis, where it is argued that "each of the four [societal subsystems] has one boundary which interchanges primarily with one of the other three cognate subsystems" (p. 297), the "Columbian map" is in danger of becoming a Procrustean bed. Does not the "polity," for example, necessarily have a similar "interest" in regulating the employment of labor and land in the productive process, i.e., in the economy's "goal attainment" sphere? Perhaps the most important achievement of this new statement by Professor Parsons and Mr. Smelser lies in their emphasizing the priority of a state of equilibrium for the society as a whole over that of the economy considered in isolation. In this way the problem of an economic sociology finds its proper statement. We feel however that, in their analysis of the problem, they have maintained the "theoretical specificity" of economics at what may well be the inevitable cost of confusing economizing with the economy. But what is more, their interpretation of the mode of interrelationship between the "economic" and "noneconomic" aspects of social life, i.e., the economic sociology itself, is imbued with a bias which appears to have been derived from formal economic theory. Basic to their analysis is the contention that in all social interaction, "The amount of performance contribution is a function of the expectation (and in the long run, receipt) of sanction. . . . Conversely, amount of sanction or reward is a function of amount of performance contribution" (p. 10). It is then suggested, however, that the "conceptual structure in economics which defines the elements involved in an exchange transaction can be generalized to all cases of performance-sanction balancing" (p. 13). It is a daring theoretical move to apply the concept of inputs and outputs in equilibrium Parsons and Smelser on the Economy 317 to the whole of society, but whatever the ultimate verdict of scholarship regarding this move, it is surely premature to apply the terminology of the supply-demand scheme of economic theory to the general balancing of performances and sanctions in social interaction. The "economistic" character of the sociology here is perhaps most apparent in Chapter III, where an attempt is made to develop a sociology of markets. The economics of imperfect competition is shown to be limited by the narrow range of the imperfections considered. It is suggested that the degrees of "imperfection" of markets can be more fully understood if their qualitative differences are analyzed. And such differences are sociological in character. The sellers in the money market, for example, are located at a different point on the sociological compass than the sellers in the labor market. These suggestions, while not new, are presented with a clarity that excites anticipation of what. is to come. But in the analysis built upon these insights a penchant for the formalisms of economic theory mars the whole scheme. The concepts of property, contract, and market are expanded to include "properties" in the "possession" of noneconomic subsystems, the "noncontractual" elements of contract, and the noneconomic modifications of market behavior, respectively. Persistent imperfections in the "economic" market are then explained by the allusion to a broader hypothetical market which must always be in equilibrium if the economic market is not. This is certainly an ingenious scheme, and no one will read the book without receiving important insights into the sociology of a market economy. But what have we learned about the actual mechanisms through which different markets are modified by the social situations in which they operate? Here, instead of maintaining the specificity of economic theory, the authors have so diffused it in application to phantom subsystems without shape or form that even the economist must object. A market is not a self-sufficing social system, but at least it presents us with a concrete mechanism which validates the abstractions of economic theory. It would seem that Professor Parsons and Mr. Smelser have indeed provided some relief from the one-sided rationalism of the economic theorist, but have they not conjured empty sociological boxes to replace their misnamed economic counterparts? Weaknesses such as these which we find in the book, Economy and Society, lead us to suggest that Parsons and Smelser have not resolved the so-called "institutionalist dilemma," but only raised it to another 318 Institutional Analysis level. Like the most sophisticated of the economic theorists, the authors do not set out to detail the operation of concrete economic systems. Several times they are at pains to point out the lack of correspondence between their categories and the real flesh and blood units of the economic system. Nevertheless, again like many economic theorists, they exhibit a persistent tendency to assume that there must be such a correspondence, and this assumption, when it is made, confuses the analysis, and bars the door to the understanding of how in fact social interaction in the economy is patterned. Having in mind again the two traditions according to which western social scientists have attempted to place the economy in society, we suggest that the "dilemma" consists primarily of the question, What is it that we wish to know? If it is the problem, which occupied Weber and Pareto, of the degree to which the rationality of economizing with scarce means can be present in society, that is one thing. If we wish to generalize our understanding of the way in which substantive economic processes are institutionalized, that is another. Each will have its appropriate method. The two interests have been greatly confused because of their convergence on the presumed super-rational market economy of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. The market system in its ideal form is the very embodiment of that rationality of which economizing with scarce means is the essence. Economic analysis, as that discipline developed in the late nineteenth century, is the perfect theoretical statement of such action, wherever it may actually be located in society. But the unique convergence of substantive economic process, economizing rationality and economic theory is an event of history which cannot justify their being equated everywhere and always. And the attempt to locate the place of economies in societies which begins with the question of the relationship between economic theory and theory of other "aspects" of social action is doomed to failure unless the significance of this special case is clearly recognized. Harry W. Pearson Parsons and Smelser on the Economy 319 | might appear in the present book. Page proof was also kindly provided so that ref- erences to Economy and Society might be identified by the page on which they ap-f pear.) 2. Cf. Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action (Glencoe, 111, 1949). See also, Paul Diesing, "The Nature and Limitations of Economic Rationality," Ethics, Vol. 61 (October, 1950); A. L. Macfie, "What Kind of Experience is f Economizing?" Ethics, Vol. 60 (October, 1949); Paul Streeten, "Programs and Prognosis," Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 68 (August, 1954). 3. Cf. Structure of Social Action, p. 757 ff. 4. Parsons, "Sociological Elements in Economic Thought," Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 49 (May, 1935), p. 421. See also, Parsons, "Some Reflections on 'The Nature and Significance of Economics,' " Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 47 (May, 1934), 522-529. 5. Parsons, "Some Reflections," p. 526. 6. Ibid., p. 520. 7. Ibid, p. 528. : 8. On the inherent scarcity of the means involved in the adaptive process, see % also, T. Parsons, Robert F. Bales and Edward Shils, Working Papers in the Theory f of Action (Glencoe, 111, 1953), p. 210; and T. Parsons and Edward Shils, eds. Toward a General Theory of Action (Cambridge, Mass, 1954), pp. 25, 197. See also Hopkins, this book, pp. 289 ff. There are exceptions to this interpretation - of adaptation. When the authors discuss the "adaptive exigencies" of "concrete economic structures," for example, they say that the economy must "adapt" to its ecological-technological and socio-cultural environment. And the nature of that natural-social environment then will explain the differentiation of the economy into its structural elements (industries, etc.) (Ch. II). Here, in other words, the mode of adaptation is left open to research. Notes to Chapter XV 1. Talcott Parsons and Neil Smelser, Economy and Society (Glencoe, 111, 1956). (The author wishes to express his sincere thanks to Professor Parsons and Mr. Smelser for providing the manuscript of Economy and Society so that this review XVI The Economy has no Surplus: Qritique of a Theory of (Development in the preceding chapters it has been shown that the concept of scarcity applied to the economy is a derivative of the market system, and of the Enlightenment's atomistic conception of society. Here, indeed, the conditions, institutional and ideal, are satisfied for the scarcity postulate to have operational significance. But the common assumption that the fact of scarce natural means sets off, everywhere and always, a series of economizing actions, skips over the vital step of introducing the social condition of man into consideration of his acting upon nature to produce his livelihood. The concept of scarcity will be fruitful only if the natural fact of limited means leads to a sequence of choices regarding the use of these means, and this situation is possible only if there is alternativity to the uses of means and there are preferentially graded ends. But these latter conditions are socially determined; they do not depend in any simple way upon the facts of nature. To postulate scarcity as an absolute condition from which all economic institutions derive is therefore to employ an abstraction which serves only to obscure the question of how economic activity is organized. There is no formal theory of the development of economic institutions which has reached anything like the generality of formal economic theory. Nevertheless there is a concept of widely current use in anthropology, prehistory, and economic history which bears a relationship to 320 The Economy has no Surplus 321 the analysis of economic development similar to that between the scarcity postulate and economic analysis. This is the concept of surplus employed in a way which makes the appearance of a "surplus" over bare subsistence needs the critical determinant in the evolution of complex social and economic institutions from simple beginnings. Thus an oversufficiency of means is said to bring on the development of economic institutions just as an insufficiency of means is said to enforce the utilitarian management of resources, which is the economy in the formal sense. The argument of this chapter is that when the surplus concept is employed in this way it too represents an inadmissable abstraction from the social conditions which surround the daily business of securing the material means of want satisfaction. Like the concept of scarcity, the surplus theorem is useful only where the conditions of a specific surplus are institutionally defined. Again, like the scarcity postulate, the concept of a general surplus arises out of that ideal and institutional complex which views man as economizing atom with "propensity to truck, barter and exchange,"1 and then provides the system of markets to make it so. It has been said that under a market system the economic process is organized through scarcity situations. It might be added that of necessity market behavior is directed towards the creation of surpluses. A mistake is made, however, when it is assumed that these institutional characteristics of a market economy are a natural feature of economic life. Invested as it is with a common sense plausibility, the popular surplus theorem has hitherto aroused little suspicion of its rationalistic bias. Let us examine its content. When employed as the key to evolutionary change, the surplus theorem has two essential parts. There is first the very concept of such a surplus. It is taken to represent that quantity of material resources which exists over and above the subsistence requirements of the society in question. Such surpluses are supposed to appear with advancing technology and productivity, and serve to distinguish one level of social and economic organization from another. The second part of the surplus theorem is the expectation that the surplus has an enabling effect which allows typical social and economic developments of prime importance to take place. Trade and markets, money, cities, differentiation into social classes, indeed civilization itself, are thus said to follow upon the emergence of a surplus.2 322 Institutional Analysis "Surplus," as defined by Melville Herskovits, for example, is "an excess of goods over the minimum demands of necessity."3 Following the lead of Thorstein Veblen,4 he feels that surplus opens an important avenue for the investigation of economic change in primitive societies; although, "Just why the surplus is produced remains obscure."5 Comparing the Bushmen of South Africa with the Hottentot, Herskovits notes that the Hottentot have developed a greater specialization of ruling function. He finds, "The reason [for this difference] is simple: the Bushmen produce no surplus."6 Gordon Childe defines "social surplus" as, "food above domestic requirements."7 And, for him, the development of neolithic trade and the emergence of civilization hinge upon the appearance of such a surplus.8 The meaning of the concept is thus clear enough. There is a level of subsistence which once reached provides a measure—so to speak the dam over which the surplus flows. This surplus which is beyond needs however these happen to be defined, is then in some sense available: it may be traded abroad, or used to support the existence of craftsmen, a leisure class, or other nonproductive members of the society. In other words, it becomes the key variable in the emergence of more complex social and economic institutions. In the argument which follows we shall discuss (1) The implications of the surplus concept when it is introduced as the enabling factor in the process of social and economic change; (2) The doctrinal origins and developments of the concept in order to shed light on its inherent rationalistic bias; (3) Briefly, the way in which an institutional concept of specific surpluses—their creation and employment—may be fruitfully applied to the analysis of economic development. A Rationalistic Construct Let us first reexamine the meaning of the term surplus itself. It is applied to that which is over and above subsistence needs. Therefore the first requirement of its usefulness as a concept is that subsistence needs be defined. There are, logically, only two ways of defining these needs. They may be determined by reference to a biologically fixed requirement of food essentials for human existence. Or, on the other hand, it may be The Economy has no Surplus 323 held that subsistence needs are socially derived, in which case biological necessity cannot be used as a measuring rod. If subsistence needs are allowed to be biologically determined, theh the surplus which is said to arise after these needs are met would be an absolute surplus. That is, it would be a quantity appearing with no socially defined purpose over and above that which is biologically necessary, thus available and in a distinctive sense having a causal effect of its own. The sequence moves from the availability of a quantity of goods or services to the decision that these may now be used to support the emergence of new economic or social institutions such as trade, markets, or a leisure class. Sometimes it is implied that the surplus is the causal factor; more often it seems to be regarded as a necessary, if not sufficient cause of development. Both uses, we shall argue, are inadmissible. If it is held that subsistence needs are not biologically but socially defined, there is no room for the concept of absolute surplus, for then the distribution of economic resources between subsistence and other requirements is determined only within the total context of needs thus defined. There is no disentangling bare subsistence needs from the total functional demands which the society makes on the economy. If the concept of surplus is to be employed here at all, it must be in a relative or constructive sense. In brief: A given quantity of goods or services would be surplus only if the society in some manner set these quantities aside and declared them to be available for a specific purpose. Into this category might then fall such things as food set aside for ceremonial feasts or in anticipation of future dearth, war chests, budgetary surpluses, or savings for whatever purpose. The essential point is that relative surpluses are initiated by the society in question. It is true that such surpluses may be made to appear along with a windfall increase of material means, or a more permanent rise in productive capacity; but they may also be created with no change whatever in the quantity of subsistence means by re-allocating goods or services from one use to another. The Biblical story of the grain storage by Joseph in Egypt is one illustration of the latter. More important than the natural conditions associated with the creation of relative surpluses is thus an attitude towards resources, and the institutional means of counting out, setting aside, and making available. In the actual use of the surplus concept as a key to economic and social development there is much confusion which results from the { 324 Institutional Analysis failure to distinguish between these two possible meanings. The confusion results in attributing to relative surpluses the causal effects which only the absolute surplus would have if its existence and relevance could be established. Since the relative surplus is a mere construction, it must be apparent that only the absolute meaning can be employed to explain economic and social change. It is this meaning, therefore, the implications of which must be further examined. If the subsistence level is the measure of what is to be deemed surplus, one must be able to determine, in any specific instance, just where that level is. Logically, it may seem as if there must be a biologically fixed minimum requirement of food for a man's existence. An individual man will surely perish in a short time if he has no food at all. But how long can a man exist on a deficient diet? And if it is difficult to establish the subsistence minimum for one individual, it is impossible to determine it for a society. There is no historical evidence of a whole human society ever having lived at this level. In fact, what would we accept as evidence? We know that large or small sections of the population of every society live at a level of subsistence which science has established as inadequate. As a consequence infant mortality will be high, and life expectancy low as disease takes its devastating toll, but does this mean that every member of these groups is therefore engaged in producing food during all his waking hours? There is no support for this assumption from contemporary primitive societies, even the poorest, for they too dance and sing, and fight wars, thus using their small resources in non-utilitarian ways. Nor does the mute evidence of archaeology help us. What appears to be an objective fact of nature disintegrates upon closer examination. The fact is that "Man does not live by bread alone," no matter how meager the bread. The supposition that there is a biological minimum level of subsistence for a society fails to allow for the flexibility of a culturally determined subsistence level and thus the power of a society to employ physical resources in ways which may be regarded as even more important than a given level of subsistence. Modern India, for example, is one of the countries of relatively rapid population growth, at least since 1921. Poor as the diet of the Indian people has been, and extremely low as their customary level of living has been, the country has fed, after a fashion, a population that has risen from 306 million in 1921 to about 438 million in 1951 (India and Pakistan). . . . Even the experts do not fully understand how this has been possible, and the evidence is conflicting as to how The Economy has no Surplus 325 far the level of living of the people has changed for better or worse. In other words, no one can estimate with assurance how many more people India can feed at some level of diet, or how much the prevailing diet might deteriorate below current low levels without forcing deaths into balance with births.9 It may be argued, however, that the idea of a subsistence level is, after all, only an heuristic device. Whether or not it can be determined objectively, it is there in principle and can be used to establish the emergence of a surplus. Because of the obvious impossibility of determining the biological subsistence minimum for a whole society, it is in this heuristic sense that the surplus concept has most often been employed. But this heuristic employ raises even more serious difficulties. It is based upon the a priori assumption that absolute economic surpluses are the generating force in social change. The very fact that the particular society under examination does not spend all of its time and resources in the pursuit of bare subsistence is then called in as proof that a surplus must have been produced. The very fact that means of effectuating the circulation of goods within and between tribes do exist signifies that something more than just enough to feed, clothe, and shelter a people is available, while such phenomena as the delayed exchange of goods on a ceremonial basis, or the extension of credit by one tribesman to another prove that not only entire groups, but individuals within these groups possess a surplus over immediate need.10 The heuristic postulate then proves the existence of surplus. And it then follows that the more complex the society, the greater must have been the surplus. Clearly it is important to inquire into the legitimacy of such a postulate. At the base of the surplus theorem thus employed is the assumed primacy both in time and urgency, of eating over thinking, socializing, governing, crafting, trading, playing. As expressed by Engels, it is "the simple fact. . . that human beings must have food and drink, clothing and shelter, first of all, before they can interest themselves in politics, science, art, religion, and the like."11 Here is a crude kind of economic determinism which bases social and economic development upon "the narrow capacity of the human stomach."12 Into the sphere of the hu-logical and social requirements, the latter following only after the former are satisfied. It is sufficient, perhaps, to point out that such is 1 I I i 326 Institutional Analysis the view of subsistence and society which, at bottom, supports this idea of surplus, for very few, even of those who employ it, would subscribe to this position.13 In any case, the preponderant weight of modern evidence bearing on the social psychology and sociology of economic activity stands in opposition to this view of economy and society. We need point out only that the economy at all levels of material existence is a social process of interaction between man and his environment in the course of which goods and service change form, are moved about and change hands. They are produced and distributed. The shape of this process, i.e., its institutional form and the motives which make it run are determined not by any single factor either in nature or man, but are the resultants of several interdependent levels of human existence, ecological, technological, social and cultural. And questions such as what things and how much a given society produces, who is responsible for production, how much is consumed and in what proportion by the various groups in the society, how much is saved or diverted from immediate consumption and for what purposes, are resolved only through the complex interaction of these variables. Man, living in society, does not produce a surplus unless he names it such, and then its effect is given by the manner in which it is institutionalized. To emphasize the complexity of the causal nexus in any given situation is not to deny that there may be important social consequences of increases in subsistence means. Changing technology and productivity play their role in the course of institutional development. The argument here is simply that they do not create generally available surpluses, for this implies a separation of technological development from the institutional complex of which it is but a part. To apply the concept of surplus to new economic means which result from improvement in productivity is to imply that they are outside the social forces which integrate and control the economic process. These means thus become a kind of "free-wheeling" entity which may then be called upon to explain any development from trade to shamanism14 according to the predilections of the investigator. It is this invitation to rationalize complex economic problems of development and change which is the most disturbing aspect of this widely used idea of an enabling surplus. A catalogue of the economic institutions which have been attributed to the appearance of a surplus at critical steps in the development of human society would include private property, barter, trade, division of labor, markets, money, com- The Economy has no Surplus 327 mercial classes and exploitation.15 But there is not a shred of evidence to support these constructions. The only conceivable justification for these claims is the postulate that the logical course of economic development, once there are sufficient means available, is toward the market system of nineteenth century western Europe. This assumed train of events is based upon a crude confusion of the economy with the state of technology. The economy, to repeat, is a social process which means that the production, movement and transfer of economic goods may be variously organized. Precisely how these elements of early economies were organized and integrated is the problem for investigation. Unless we can prove man to possess an "inherent propensity to truck, barter and exchange" there is no justification for assuming that his economy must follow the market pattern. In fact, as many contributions to this book have indicated, the evidence for the economies of primitive and archaic societies proves exactly the opposite. Neale has shown, for example, that the distribution of the grain heap in the Indian village follows the pattern of mutual sharing which is institutionalized in the system of reciprocative social relationships typical of the village community.* What a distortion of the actual situation it would be to regard this grain heap as an absolute surplus, and to expect it to leave commercial exchange, money, and the rest in its wake! Reifying the Profit Concept In the course of the argument so far we have tried to indicate the basic weaknesses of the surplus concept and to point out some of the rationalizations of institutional development following upon its use. We will now touch upon the doctrinal origins and development of the surplus construct, for only in this way can we learn how the figment of an absolute surplus arises. There is little doubt that the surplus theorem in current usage is the result of the convergence of two distinct lines of inquiry. One is Lewis H. Morgan's general theory of social and economic evolution.16 The other is Karl Marx's investigations of capitalism, the analytical heart of which was a theory of "surplus value." But Marx's theory was derived from the earlier economic theories of the Physiocratic and Classical schools, and it is thus to the substantive value theory of these * See above, Ch.XI. 328 Institutional Analysis earlier economists that we must look for the origins of the concept of surplus value. The point of convergence was Friedrich Engels' adaptation of Morgan's work in The Evolution of Private Property, the Family and the State, first published in 1884. The theory of family and state development originally put forward by Morgan and by Engels' interpretation of Morgan have received wide critical review, and the relatively facile and dogmatic scheme of lineal evolution of those institutions implied therein is held by almost no one today. Implied in the Morgan-Engels theory, however, there is a scheme of economic evolution, especially of exchange institutions, which has not received the same critical attention as those more explicit theories regarding the family, state and private property. Morgan had made "enlargement of the sources of subsistence" the independent variable in an evolutionary sequence.17 Thus arose, according to him, the monogamous family, private property and territorial government out of the aboriginal gens and tribal property. As real wealth increased with the appearance of pastoralism, the "passion for its possession" also increased, and private property became a significant reality.18 This emergence of private property in the stage of "barbarism" encouraged individual motives of accumulation and gain, economic inequality and, in general, the "principles which now govern society."19 Thus, although Morgan was concerned more with establishing the emergence of private property than with the full range of economic institutions, the implication is clear that growth in means of subsistence led to the accumulation of "exchangeable" wealth, and that once this appeared the exchange institutions of civilized society were assumed to be not qualitatively different from those of modern Western society. Engels superimposed upon this theory of Morgan's the concept of surplus which was, of course, derived from Marx's surplus value. Engels said that as the "productivity of labor increasingly develops" in kin-organized "savage" society, there comes a time when "human labor power" is able to produce a "surplus over and above its maintenance costs."20 The crucial role of this surplus is explained by Engels as follows: In the middle stages of barbarism we already find among the pastoral peoples a possession in the form of cattle which, once the herd has attained a certain size, regularly produces a surplus over and above the tribe's own The Economy has no Surplus 329 requirements, leading to a division of labor between pastoral peoples and backward tribes without herds, and hence to the existence of two different levels of production side by side with one another and the conditions necessary for regular exchange. The upper stages of barbarism bring us the further division of labor between agriculture and handicrafts, hence the production of a continually increasing portion of the products of labor directly for exchange, so that exchange between individual producers assumes the importance of a vital social function.21 As the size of the surplus increases there is further division of labor, towns develop which brings a merchant class, money and even land becomes a commodity22 And since the surplus "growfs] above the heads of the producers ... [it will] raise up incorporeal alien powers against them, as in civilization is always and inevitably the case."23 Thus the surplus also provides the basis for class division and exploitation. This application of the surplus theorem to the evolution of economic institutions reflects a confusion between two entirely different concepts of surplus: a naturalistic absolute surplus which is an illusion, and a socially derived relative surplus. This same confusion lay at the heart of the value theory of the English Classical school and their immediate precursors, the French Physiocrats. It is, therefore, to the work of these early economists that we must turn to find the origin of the notion that economic activity besides being useful is somehow surplus-producing. One prerequisite of an absolute surplus, as pointed out in Part I, is that there be an objectively ascertainable level of subsistence needs over and above which the surplus appears. We suggested there that while logically a minimum level of biological need may seem to satisfy this requirement, it can only be employed in an heuristic sense. In Engels' definition of surplus, however, the objective standard is provided by the key phrase, "maintenance costs." When "costs" of production are measurable it is indeed possible to think of that which is produced over and above these costs as constituting a general surplus. But there is one other prerequisite. There can be no other socially sanctioned claim on any product above maintenance costs. Again, in Part I, it was argued that such an assumption is contrary to fact, for the economic process provides the material means necessary for all societal roles to be played, whether of consumer or totemic destroyer of worldly goods. The surplus theorem gained currency because both m 330 Institutional Analysis of these prerequisites were satisfied by the institutional and philosophical framework of early economics. Measurable costs of production appear on the scene with the advent of the market system which affixed money prices to land and labor. These are the "costs." And since the first rule of the market game is the maintenance of a differential between these costs and selling price, the market system may seem to create a surplus as a matter of course. This, at any rate, was necessarily the case given the philosophical position which allowed of no legitimate non-cost claims on the product. The increasing importance in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries of the market as a relatively independent arbiter of production and distribution called forth the new discipline of economics. For under the market new mysteries had to be explained. Resources now moved into the productive process, and finished goods moved from producer to consumer under the aegis of price. The mystery was what does eventually determine the price, or value, of a day's work, a hogshead of wine, a woolen coat? It was this interest that absorbed the early economists, and since they believed that value must have a natural origin, traceable either to land or labor, they were convinced that whatever product appeared over and above these costs of production must be a surplus. This idea of production as a surplus producing activity appears first in the works of the French Physiocrats of the eighteenth century, the so-called economistes.2* Their orientation was far from being purely academic. The Physiocratic school represented the aspirations of the newly market-oriented class of French landowners. The first prerequisite of the surplus concept was fulfilled by the growing commercialization of French agriculture and the consequent interest in costs of production. The fortunes of commercial agriculture rested upon a bon prix for grain and a low price for manufactured articles. The Physiocrats therefore were opposed to the mercantile system of Colbert which, on the contrary, favored cheap grain to maintain low wages and to demand, in export, a good price for protected manufactures. In consonance with the Enlightenment's belief in the natural order of things, they reasoned that the original source of all economic value was Nature, and that the division of labor between agriculture and manufacturing, and the circulation of commodities through the economy in support of the non-productive or "sterile" classes, was made possible by the unique The Economy has no Surplus 331 faculty of the land to produce a surplus over the costs of agricultural production. This gift of nature they called the produit net. Turgot, perhaps the most influential member of this school, explained the * produit net most clearly. The produce of the land divides into two parts. The one comprehends the subsistence and the profits of the husbandman, which are the rewards for his labor, and the conditions on which he agrees to cultivate the field of the proprietor; the other which remains is that independent and disposable part, which the earth produces as a free gift to the proprietor over and above what he had disbursed.25 Upon their analysis of surplus in circulation rested the Physiocrats' specific policy suggestions: Iaissez faire, Iaissez aller to allow the free export of grain and thereby achieve the bon prix, and the single tax to be levied on the produit net. What concerns us here, however, is the fact that the produit net was an illusion. The mysterious power of producing a surplus which the Physiocrats attributed to Nature was nothing more than the market measurement of the difference between production cost and selling price. If, through the normal operation of market forces the price of grain should fall to the level of the labor cost of production, the produit net would disappear. Because of their interest in finding the natural law of the circulation of commodities, they did not see that the production of economic value is a social phenomenon, and that in this case the surplus grew out of the institutional features of the market.26 Crossing the Channel, the surplus concept figured importantly in the work of Adam Smith, the first of the Classical economists. Smith disputed the Physiocratic claim that land was the progenitor of surplus, substituting labor instead as the original source of economic value. The chain of reasoning is almost too familiar to bear repeating. The Jcernel is found in Locke's dissertation on property in the Second Treatise on Civil Government, and similarly in the first two books of Smith's The Wealth of Nations. The earth is given to all mankind in common, but man is an individual. Among other things he must eat. He therefore must work, and the mixing of the individual's energy with nature's common gift extracts from the common and stamps the subtracted part as private property. Hence the natural right of private property. But the individual soon finds that he can pick more acorns or kill more deer than his own subsistence requires, and since he is a 332 Institutional Analysis rational utilitarian, he exchanges his surplus for that of another individual to the mutual advantage of both. Here is the naturalistic, or •what we have called absolute surplus, an inevitable construction here, given the starting point of man as utilitarian atom. If man is viewed as atom, then once his biological needs are satisfied any remaining material goods must be regarded as surplus. The atomistic conception allows the existence of no socially derived claims on the product. And the utilitarian assumption directs the surplus into the uses of exchange. But this is not the end of the surplus story, for classical economics went on to confuse this mistaken idea of an absolute surplus with the cost-price differential of the market. The economic problem was to determine the terms of exchange between individuals exchanging their surplus. The obvious answer, since these were regarded as free and equal individuals outside the integument of social valuation, was the quantity of labor that went into the production of the goods exchanged. But while the labor theory of value may have been the obvious construction for Locke's individualistic savages, it created problems logical as well as moral for Classical economics when applied to the complex economy of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.27 Smith reasoned logically that once the process is started, the exchange of surplus will lead to specialization and thus wider exchange relationships which finally call for the use of money to facilitate complex division of labor and ever expanding exchange. As society advances ". . . beyond that early and rude state which precedes both the accumulation of stock and the appropriation of land" some individuals "naturally" will use their accumulated surplus. ... in setting to work industrious people, whom they will supply with materials and subsistence, in order to make a profit by the sale of their work, or by what their labor adds to the value of the materials.28 The logical dilemma was how to explain the market price and still retain this substantive theory of value, for now price was clearly a composite of more than one factor of production, thus not reflecting the quantity of labor alone. The moral problem was to square the facts of a very real return to land (rent) and to capital (interest or "profits") with the conviction that capitalism represented the system of natural justice where each individual was free to receive only the rewards to which his own labor entitled him. Even the brilliant mind of David Ricardo could not resolve these contradictions. The Economy has no Surplus 333 At the heart of the difficulty was a massive confusion between a naturalistic concept of surplus and a socially determined difference between labor cost and price dictated by the requirements of the mar-" ket. The "subsistence" which the capitalist pays the laborer is the wage, but the wage rate is determined by the forces of supply and demand operating in the market. There is no objective measure of subsistence which determines the wage and no absolute surplus appears. Other factors of production playing their respective roles (of which one may morally approve or disapprove) also receive market sanctioned returns. To the functioning of the market system, one is as important as the other. The idea that the economy produces an absolute surplus as a matter of course was due to the application of an atomistic philosophical position to the functional problems of the market system. As soon as economic theory recognized, in the second half of the 19th century, jj that a commodity is worth what it will fetch on the market, the logical, I if not the moral, problem of surplus ceased to plague economic J theory.29 i For those who were morally opposed to the distribution of wealth under capitalism, however, the classical surplus dilemma was too obvious a tool to miss. It was left for Karl Marx to turn the contradictions of "this very Eden of the rights of man"30 into a theory of exploitation. But Marx pulled the classical labor theory of value out of its original naturalistic setting and placed it into a definite social setting: that of capitalistic production. No more than Ricardo was Marx able successfully to resolve the logical contradictions involved in the labor theory of value. But the important point to be made here is that Marx made it perfectly clear that a surplus is not something that arises as a natural consequence of the labor process itself. Favorable natural conditions alone, gave us only the possibility, never the reality, of surplus-labour, nor, consequently, of surplus-value and a surplus-product. ... In the midst of our West European society, where the labourer purchases the right to work for his own livelihood only by paying for it in surplus-labour, the idea easily takes root that it is an inherent quality of human labour to furnish a surplus-product. . . . The productiveness of labour that serves as its foundation and starting point, is a gift, not of nature, but of a history embracing thousands of centuries.31 The so-called "primitive accumulation" of capital that provides the starting point for capitalism and surplus value is not the gradual ap- 334 Institutional Analysis pearance of surpluses born of technological progress; it is "nothing else than the historical process of divorcing the producer from the means of production."32 Marx scoffed at the idea of a naturalistic surplus and spoke only of "surplus value" which he attributed to the institutional features of capitalism alone. It is all the more ironic then that the facile rationalization of the development of economic institutions set in motion by the surplus concept should have been derived from Marx's surplus value. i Surplus—the Economic Aspect of Institutional Change . 1 The argument thus far has necessarily taken a negative tack. A j critical appraisal of the surplus concept has been undertaken in an effort to dispel the long-standing confusion between absolute and relative surpluses. Hardly anyone anymore accepts in the whole the atomistic philosophical position upon which the surplus theorem rested. But enforced as this position was by a misunderstanding of the market system with its numerous relative surpluses, and a misrendering of Marx's theorem of surplus value, the two meanings of surplus have been confused, with the result that important matters of institutional change are rationalized in alarming fashion. We have argued against the idea of any absolute standard which automatically determines the availability of material resources for institutional development. The question rather is one of the relative uses to which resources are put under definite social arrangements, and whether or not it is useful to distinguish one use from another with the term surplus. We think it is, for, although such a distinction may be entirely arbitrary on the part of the investigator, it focuses attention \ upon a phenomenon of basic importance. It might be called the eco- j nomic aspect of institutional growth. In these terms relative surpluses f are simply material means and human services that are in some sense set aside or mobilized apart from the existing functional demands which a given social unit—a family—a firm—a society—makes upon its economy. Since we are not searching for absolute consumption levels after which surpluses automatically appear, research interest is directed toward the positive factor of the institutional means by which the course of the ongoing economic process is altered to support the ma- The Economy has no Surplus 335 terial requirements of new or expanded societal roles, whether of consumer, producer, general or priest. Viewing the problem from this angle it is clear that there are. definite institutional requirements for the creation of relative surpluses. Briefly, the operational facilities, as well as the motivation for separating out, counting up, storing, mobilizing material means and human services must be provided by the institutional framework of the economy if surpluses are to be made available for specific purposes. The institutional medium of money and market provide, of course, a set of conditions highly conducive to the manufacture of surpluses. Where money is used as a generalized means of exchange the infinite variety of substantive economic qualities are quantifiable in terms of a single measure; thus they are freely interchangeable and substitutable. Here the facilities for separating, counting, budgeting are fully provided. In addition, the institutional separation of the economic from other aspects of social existence in a market system provides a "self-conscious" economic process, as it were, directing the attention of all participants to the economic significance of all decisions. Outputs are measured against inputs. And the individuation-cum-contract feature of a market ordered economy attaches inevitable uncertainties to the roles of producer and consumer, uncertainties which can be hedged only by the creation of surpluses.34 Families as well as business firms save, and entrepreneurs drive for profits. It is these features of the system which necessarily direct market behavior toward the creation of surpluses. The apparently favorable milieu of market and money for the creation of specific surpluses should not, however, lead us to infer the absence of institutional means for making surpluses available in non-market economies. Nor, on the other hand, should the market way be taken as the paradigm for the production of surpluses. Raymond Firth has pointed out that primitive man does not live simply "by a day-today satisfaction of his needs but shows foresight and engages in forms of abstinence."35 The difficulty, he goes on to emphasize, lies in finding out just how such decisions regarding the use of economic means are in fact carried out. Finding the economic process embedded in essentially noneconomic institutions as we do in the vast number of nonmarket economies, it would seem obvious to suggest that both the motives and the institutional means for accumulating surpluses would also be of a noneconomic character. The question, then, is what institutional pro- 336 Institutional Analysis visions for the exceptional employment of material means do we find in economies where the basic continuity of the process is insured through the patterns of reciprocity and redistribution. In the case where the goods and person movements of the economic process are channelled through redistributive institutions, the means for the creation of surpluses seem to be fairly direct and obvious. Since, under this form of integration, it is power located in a central institution which sanctions the locational and appropriational movements, the same power may demand tribute, levy assessments, mobilize labor, decree consumption standards, etc. And, in a similar vein, one of the most common of all means of surplus accumulation has been the power of arms to plunder and secure booty. Corvee, boon days, tithes, censuses, tax farming, auctions, markets by decree—these are some of the paraphernalia of surplus mobilization in redistributive economies. Interest here centers also on these operational devices by means of which the facility to count out, compare, and balance accounts is enhanced in the absence of a general medium of exchange. One example is the use of "money" as a standard of account, greatly facilitating thereby the planning and budgeting operations of staple finance in the redistributive economies of the ancient Near East.86 But if the means of establishing surpluses under redistributive forms of organization are straightforward, what of those economies, or those economic operations, held firmly in the reciprocities of kinship, neighborhood, community? The practice of mutually obligatory sharing typical of reciprocity is certainly not conducive to the individual building of surpluses since it insures against the very personal uncertainties which induce saving. Among the Bantu Bemba people of Africa, for example, one finds little attempt made to overcome the recurrent food shortage by saving up and marketing surpluses. The economic process is located in kinship units here; thus "they are unaccustomed to commerce of this kind."37 This lack of saving and individual foresight is disastrous only where, in the neighborhood of the white man's towns, the kinship unit has broken down. The same Bemba tribe, however, keeps chickens, but they "do not use these for food, except for ceremonial occasions, or as presents of respect; nor do they ever eat the eggs. Pigeons are kept but very rarely eaten even in times of hunger. 'We like to see them flying about the village,' says the native, 'it is a sign of a man of rank.' "38 Here we may have the clue to one of the most important of the means for the creation of surpluses in the absence of The Economy has no Surplus 337 market methods or those centers of power able to enforce the production of surpluses. We refer, of course, to that omni-present catalytic agent in human society usually called the prestige factor. The persistence and the power of the prestige factor in primitive and archaic societies is universally attested, but the complexity of its function and, especially, its economic significance is, to say the least, still an enigma. Viewing this phenomenon from the vantage point of a market ordered universe we may be hampered in our understanding of the economic relevance of prestige institutions in early societies. Prestige in a market system is very largely a by-product of successful market activity. Wealth is the exclusive symbol of prestige, and wealth is the product of successful selling. That such a state of affairs leads to "conspicuous consumption" and even distorts the substantive economy in the direction of "conspicuous waste" is now, thanks to the trenchant criticism of Veblen, a part of our common understanding. Nevertheless prestige is no more than an epiphenomenon to the functioning of the ideal market economy. In primitive and archaic societies the function of prestige seems rather the reverse of that found in our economy. For there it appears as a culture pattern sui generis with a rationale and institutional fittings of its own, and capable, vis-a-vis the economy, of stimulating feverish goods and person movements, the goal of which may be the fierce destruction of wealth in Kwakiutl potlatch ceremonies, or the comely reciprocities of the Trobrianders' "trade game."39 Prestige wealth, whether the red sulawa necklaces and white umwala armbands of the Trobrianders, the copper plates of the Kwakiutl, or the iron, bronze, gold goblets, tripods and caldrons of Homeric Greece, circulates only among the gods, kings, and chiefs.40 It may move against other prestige objects or against items of honor, power or safety, but always it adds up to an elite circulation of prestige wealth. Pointing to the frequency of money payments, calculation, interest, profit, business partnership, accountancy, and shrewd bargaining in this sphere of activity, Cora DuBois has employed the apt term, "prestige economy" to describe it.41 But while the elite circulation of prestige wealth involves a certain amount of material means, sometimes absorbing a disproportionate amount of time and resources, it is not this feature which is of primary interest in the mobilization of surpluses. Strange though it may seem to the modern mind prestige wealth represented a regular claim upon 338 Institutional Analysis the services and material resources of communities even on a very low level of subsistence. ' Prestige is the prize of all this activity which may itself involve the accumulation of symbolic wealth, but it also functions indirectly as a mobilizer of relatively large quantities of material means as well as human services to be employed in a variety of ways, utilitarian and not, but which, in any case, make them available to the community at large, as they otherwise would not be. It is here that we see the surplus creating function of the prestige factor in early society. For with the prestige gained in the prestige economy go honorific duties and public trustee functions which result in making available to the community services and material means which would not otherwise be put to use. Food must be mobilized for the largesse which accompanies the potlatch ceremonies, or the feast of the Pomo prestige trade. The Tolowa-Tututni "rich man" must act as a state surrogate, negotiating in disputes, settling torts by the payments of fines for any of his village kinsmen. And probably the clearest example comes from classical Athens where it was the onerous privilege of the wealthy to provide the state with services at their own cost, the so-called Ieiturgies. Among these were the maintenance, command, and manning of the naval craft provided by the state (rrierarchy); the training of personnel for the annual religious performances (choregy); the providing of physical training for the young (gymnasiarchy and Jampadarchy); and the contributing of funds for the import of grain to be distributed freely or at low cost to the citizenry (sitesis). So intricate is the interlacing of prestige and economy that our discussion offers little more than to suggest the lines along which investigation might move. So much is clear, however, prestige institutions are not simply a kind of societal afterthought appearing only upon the emergence of an imagined surplus above subsistence means. They are woven into the warp and weft of the social fabric, and, where the economic process is threaded into the same fabric, may shade into and even color over the economic threads. Prestige institutions are not the result of surpluses appearing at certain stages of social development, but neither are cities, nor pyramids, nor markets, nor money, nor exploitation, nor civilization. The interrelationship between the material and the societal aspects of existence are such that they cannot be separated into "first," "then" sequences. And the market system with its institutional separation of The Economy has no Surplus 339 economic and social is only an apparent exception. Here, too, those surpluses which seem to appear "above the heads of the producers" are explained only by the institutional features of the market economy: It is no good either to go half the distance in the surplus argument by admitting that surplus is a necessary but not sufficient cause of change, for this is to beg the question. There are always and everywhere potential surpluses available. What counts is the institutional means for bringing them to life. And these means for calling forth the special effort, setting aside the extra amount, devising the surplus, are as wide and varied as the organization of the economic process itself. Harry W.Pearson Notes to Chapter XVI 1. Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations, Bk. I, ch. II. 2. Some examples: Melville J. Herskovits, Economic Anthropology (New York, 1952), esp. ch. XVIII; Gordon Childe, What Happened in History (New York, 1946); Social Evolution (1951); "The Birth of Civilization" in Past and Present, II (November, 1952), "Trade and Industry in Barbarian Europe till Roman Times," in Cambridge Economic History of Europe, II (Cambridge, 1952); Leslie White, The Science of Culture (New York, 1949); Melville Jacobs and Bernhard J. Stern, Outline of Anthropology (New York, 1947), esp. ch. VI; R. H. Hilton, 'The Transformation from Feudalism to Capitalism," Science and Society (Fall, 1953); Shephard B. Clough, The Rise and Fall of Civilization (New York, 1951), pp. 6-7 ff. 3. Herskovits, op. cit., p. 395. 4. ibid., pp. 396-7. For Veblen's employment of the surplus concept see The Instinct of Workmanship and the State of the Industrial Arts (New York, 1914), ch. IV. 5. Ibid., p. 413. 6. Ibid., p. 399. 7. Childe, Past and Present, p. 3. 8. Ibid., p. 4, and Cambridge Economic History of Europe, II, 2 ff. 9. Joseph S. Davis, "Adam Smith and the Human Stomach," Quarterly Journal of Economics, Vol. 68, No. 3 (May, 1954), 283. 10. Herskovits, op. cit., p. 395. Cf. G. Childe, Cambridge Economic History of Europe, II, 2. 11. Engels' funeral oration at the grave of Marx, March 17, 1883; quoted in Otto Rühle, Karl Marx, His Life and Work (English translation, 1929), p. 366. 12. Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations, Bk. I, ch. XI, Pt. II. 13. Cf. G. Childe, Introduction to What Happened in History, and Herskovits, op. cit, ch. XXII and p. 294. 14. Cf. Paul Radin, Primitive Religion (New York, 1937), esp. pp. 40-58. 15. F. Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the State CNew 340 Institutional Analysis York, 1942), pp. 6, 48, 146, 149, 160; Lewis H. Morgan, Ancient Society (New York, 1877), Part IV; Thorstein Veblen, op. cit., pp. 150-1. Childe, Cambridge Economic History of Europe, II, 4-5; Herskovits, op. cit, p. 395; Jacobs and Stem, op. cit, p. 141; Hilton, op. cit, p. 347. 16. Ancient Society. 17. Ibid, p. 19. 18. Ibid, p. 547. 19. Ibid, p. 550. 20. Op. cit, p. 6 (preface to first edition). 21. Ibid, pp. 150-1. 22. Ibid, p. 152. 23. Ibid, p. 159. 24. Strictly, it is not true that the idea appears "first" with the Physiocrats. The idea was "in the air," so to speak; all of those who tackled the problem of exchange value came up with a surplus. The idea may be found in embryonic form in the work of Sir William Petty (1623-87) and,, more fully developed in Richard Can-tillon (1680-1734) Essai sur la nature due commerce en general. Cf. Joseph Schum-peter, History of Economic Analysis (New York, 1954), pp. 209-223; and J. J. Spengler, "Richard Cantillon: First of the Moderns," in Journal of Political Economics, Vol. 62, Nos. 4, 5 (August, October, 1954). For the Physiocrats, see Schumpeter, op. cit, pp. 223-249; Norman J. Ware, "The Physiocrats," American Economic Review, XXI, No. 4 (December, 1931); and Marx's discussion in Theories of Surplus Value (Selections, translated from German by G. A. Bonner and Emile Burns (New York, 1952). 25. M. Turgor, Reflections on the Formation and Distribution of Wealth (Translated from French, London, 1793), p. 252. 26. Cf. K. Maix, Theories of Surplus Value, op. cit, p. 56: "Their error flows from the fact that they confused the increase of material substance . . . with the increase of exchange value." 27. For the discussion of these difficulties see Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action (Glencoe, 111, 1947), Ch. Ill; Elie Halevy, The Growth of Philosophic Radicalism (Translated from French, New York, 1949); A. D. Lindsay, Karl Marx's Capital (London, 1925), esp. Ch. HI. 28. The Wealth of Nations (1776), Book I, Part VI. 29. This is true of the objective surplus of classical economics but marginal utility economics invented subjective or "utility surpluses" to take their place. See, e.g., A. Marshall, Principles of Economics (8th ed. New York, 1920), pp. 124— 133 and Appendix K. For criticism see F. H. Knight, Risk, Uncertainty and Profit (New York, 1921), pp. 69-73. 30. K. Marx, Capital, I (1867) Modern Library edition, p. 195. 31. Ibid, pp. 562, 564-5. 32. Ibid, p. 786. 33. Marx was perhaps the first to emphasize the institutional origin of relative surpluses in a market economy by focusing on the contractual relationship between worker and capitalist. Marginal utility economics imputed the surplus away by pointing to the functional significance of all contributors of "scarce" means to the productive process. J. Schumpeter (The Theory of Economic Development, English translation, Cambridge, Mass, 1934) and F. H. Knight (Risk, Uncertainty and Profit), showed that after values were imputed to all functional "cost" factors, there still remained "profit" and this "surplus" they explained in terms of specific institutional features of the market system. For an extension of these views see, Jean The Economy has no Surplus 341 Marchal, "The Construction of a New Theory of Profit," American Economic Review, Vol. 61, No. 4 (September, 1951); also Peter Drucker, The New Society (New York, 1950), ch. IV. 34. Cf. Joan Robinson, "Mr. Wiles' Rationality: a Comment," Soviet Studies, VII (January, 1956), 269: "The primary function of price, in both sorts of economy [capitalist and socialist], is to make accumulation possible," 35. Primitive Polynesian Economy (London, 1939), p. 9. 36. Cf. The use of cattle for "money" in Homeric Greece; M. I. Finley, The World of Odysseus (New York, 1954), p. 65. 37. A. I. Richards and E. M. Widdowson, "A dietary study in Northeastern Rhodesia," Africa, No. 9 (1936), p. 196. 38. Ibid, p. 174. 39. R. T. Thurnwald, Werden, Wandel und Gestaltung der Wirtschaft (Berlin and Leipzig, 1932), p. 121. 40. See B. Malinowski, Argonauts of the Western Pacific (New York, 1922); Cora Du Bois, "The wealth concept as an integrative factor in Tolowa-Tututni culture," Essays in Anthropology (Berkeley, Calif, 1936); Herskovits, op. eft., ch. XXI; Finley, op. cit, pp. 58-9 ff.; A. P. Vayda, "Notes on trade among the Pomo Indians of California" (mimeographed) Columbia Univeisity Interdisciplinary Project (1954). ••" " 41. Op. cit. XVII Economic Theory displaced: Livelihood in Primitive Society this chapter is an examination of some methodological problems that have developed in the study of primitive economics, with special reference to the application of economic theory to anthropological studies. The first section points out that the types of problems facing the anthropologist and the economic theorist have differed substantially and required different approaches; the second examines the contribution of leading writers on primitive economics who did not use formal economic theory as an analytical tool; the third is a critique of writers who have used formal economic theory in cross-cultural studies and points out the methodological problems that have been created; and the fourth summarizes the chief methodological problems and suggests that a broader approach to economic life than that offered by modern economic theory is necessary for the study of primitive economics if the results are to be meaningful. Economic Anthropology Although the study of the economic life of primitive peoples has not been a major concern of modern anthropologists, it is realized by most that no analysis of a culture is complete unless some attention is given to the production and distribution of goods and services. Not Economic Theory Misplaced: Livelihood in Primitive Society 343 only must man feed, clothe and house himself, but the institutions he has developed to meet his material needs are an integral part of his social life. In understanding the nature of society it is essential to" recognize that social institutions make up an integrated web of which the economic form a major part. And in understanding the nature of man it is essential to recognize that his motivations are all but determined by the web of social institutions within which he operates. The anthropologist has helped to make these ideas a part of the intellectual currency of our time, and in doing so has fostered the study of economic motivations within the broader context of society as a whole. Modern economic theory, on the other hand, seeks to separate out the economic from other aspects of society. In doing so, two simplifying concepts have commonly been employed: the maximization principle and the allocation principle. The individual is conceived of as maximizing his satisfactions in the use of means to satisfy his wants, and is thereby given a set of motivations that can be thought of as purely economic, separated from other types of motivations that may be present at the same time. The whole individual operating in a web of social institutions is abstracted from in order to define a specialized aspect of behavior. While this simplifying technique may have resulted in important developments in economic theory, it has grave drawbacks if the investigator conceives of motivations as a pattern in which each part is influenced by the configuration as a whole. For the anthropologist, who works with the latter type of concept, the economic theorist's view of motivations seems narrow and tends to obscure rather than illuminate the questions he wants to ask. Just as the maximization principle separates out economic motives, so that allocation principle abstracts from the institutional complex. Economics is conceived of as the rational allocation of scarce means to achieve given goals, and it is held that this type of activity must be carried on within any set of socio-economic institutions, at any time, and in any environment. It is argued that the logic of choice must therefore be applicable to any society. But the anthropologist has discovered that economic activity must be explained primarily in terms of a given society's social institutions. Even scarcity is present or absent in varying degrees as a result of the structure of society and social attitudes, and choice is often severely restricted by the social structure within which the individual functions. The very foundations of the 342 344 Institutional Analysis theory of choice are socially conditioned, and to abstract those foundations from their social matrix obscures the essential problems. Not only does economic theory seek to separate the economic from other facets of society, but it has developed a conceptual framework characteristic of the modern market economy that is difficult to apply to nonmarket economies. The concepts analyzed in economic theory— money, prices, supply and demand, capital, rent, interest, profit and the like—are characteristic of the institutional framework of the self-adjusting market system. Their theoretical analysis has a real basis in the actual structure of institutions. But in nonmarket economies those concepts have no institutional counterpart. Applying market concepts cross-culturally to an institutional framework in which they do not exist will result in a falsified picture of the actual structure and functioning of the social order.1 For practical purposes the economic theorist does not worry about the limitations of his discipline, because he applies it only to the market economy: for his purposes and problems it is a highly useful tool. But the social scientist who deals with cross-cultural problems is inevitably concerned with institutions and cannot use effectively a set of tools which deliberately abstracts from the institutional framework. The problem is that the anthropologist asks a different type of question than that asked by the economic theorist: he wants to know about the interrelationships that exist within the societal complex and seeks to explain the functioning of society as a whole. The economic theorist has a different kind of problem: he is interested in the logical principles by which scarce resources can be allocated to maximize the attainment of desired goals—and in attacking this problem he has lifted his inquiry out of the institutional complex that is the center of interest of the anthropologist. The Societal Approach For many years anthropologists made little use of economic theory. When they first began investigating the economic life of primitive peoples they concentrated almost exclusively on ecology and technology. Economics was thought of narrowly in terms of the techniques employed in the production of useful things. There was some justification for this approach, for differences in technology are often associated Economic Theory Misplaced: Livelihood in Primitive Society 345 with major differences in social structure based on hunting, herding, gardening, agriculture, handicrafts, and other means of gaining subsistence. And it has the advantage, at least, of centering attention on * substantive problems of economics—production of material things— rather than the formal theoretical problems of maximization and allocation. The narrowness of this early approach to economic life developed into a much broader one. In the period between 1910 and 1935 came pathbreaking work by Boas, Thurnwald and Malinowski. Economics was conceived by these writers as the process of satisfaction of material needs, and economic motivations and institutions were treated as integral parts of the total social process. Most significantly, it was shown that the acquisitive motivations characterstic of economic life in modern society were generally not to be found among primitive peoples, and that the market institutions of modern society were definitely not the rule in primitive society. The self-adjusting market economy of the western world was found to be unique in the history of mankind. Perhaps the most important single work was Malinowski's multi-volume study of the Trobriand Islanders.2 He showed how thoroughly the production of goods and services was embedded in political, religious, social and kinship institutions. The economic activities of individuals were motivated by social and political obligations, by kinship, by friendship, and by magical rituals and beliefs. Exchange was carried on by gift-giving and ceremonial distribution of goods; barter existed only with persons outside the tribe; buying and selling were nonexistent. The Trobrianders were a typical nonmarket people, with an economic system and motivations that can hardly be understood by modern market-conditioned man. Supplementing Malinowski's pathbreaking work were the studies made by the followers of Boas, particularly those of Benedict and Mead.3 Proceeding from a different methodological base than Malinowski's, some of the conclusions are nevertheless startlingly similar. Especially important is confirmation of Malinowski's view that primitive economic institutions are so thoroughly entwined with otheT social institutions that one can hardly speak of economic motives in the modern sense of that term. Mead's description of the gift-giving Ara-pesh is a classic example of kinship and friendship obligations as motivations for economic activity. Indeed, the numerous descriptions 346 Institutional Analysis of the porlarch of the Northwest Coast Indians illustrate a general principle; acquisitive motives are usually channeled into activities other 'than the provision of goods and services to meet material needs. Also of importance along these lines has been the work of DuBois, emphasizing the importance of prestige elements—a "noneconomic" factor— in channeling economic activity in primitive society.4 Of special relevance to the development of economic institutions is the work of Thurnwald.5 From his ethnological studies in East Africa he developed a theory of the development of simple societies into stratified social systems, feudalisms and despotisms. He pointed out that a stratified society with clearly distinguishable social classes usually results from cultural contacts between gardening, artisan, or hunting-fishing peoples on the one hand and herding peoples on the other, with the herdsmen tending to form an aristocracy. Such a society may develop along feudal lines if the clan heads of the herdsmen remain relatively equal rivals, into a despotism if power can be centralized under a single dynasty, or into a tyrannis if someone outside the traditional aristocracy can seize power. The ancient despotic state, such as Egypt, is a development typical of this scheme.6 Not only is the economy intimately connected with the social structure in Thurnwald's schema, but development of the two is pictured as a dynamic relationship. The importance of Thurnwald's theory of economic development is twofold. In the first place, it directly connects modern anthropological studies of simple societies with the origins of ancient states, and whether his schema will be found by further studies to be right or wrong he has created a bridge between the anthropologist and the historian that must be explored further. In the second place, Thurnwald's theory suggests that the present emphasis in historical research on gradual, evolutionary development of more advanced forms of society from simpler forms may be incorrect. It suggests that homogeneous societies do not develop into stratified societies without such exogenous forces as cultural contact, and his scheme of evolutionary development ends with feudalisms and despotisms. The market society of the modern world is not seen as a natural outgrowth of feudal forms of society. For the economic historian of the western world this means a re-evaluation of the neo-Darwinism that pervades much historical research. For example, did the modern market economy gradually evolve out of the commercial activities of the Economic Theory Misplaced: Livelihood in Primitive Society 347 medieval bourgeoisie, as many historians believe, or did the whole fabric of feudal society have to be broken by new methods of warfare, the. rise of national states, the discoveries and the Reformation before modern capitalism could emerge?7 Thurnwald also placed great stress on gift-giving, or reciprocity, as a pervasive element in primitive economic life, a pattern far removed from the acquisitive motives of the market economy and requiring a symmetrical pattern of social relationships for its operation. Indeed, Mauss has suggested that gift exchange is the fundamental principle underlying all primitive trade.8 Anthropologists such as Malinowski, Benedict, Mead and Thurnwald found little use for economic theory. In part this was because some of their chief targets were the postulates of man's acquisitive nature, his alleged dislike for work, and his economic rationality as they were described by economic theory. These scholars were engaged in building a concept of man's nature at odds with the "economic man" of economic theory. In part, also, they were concerned with the whole social structure and not just that part of it called the economic, realizing that the economic life of primitive man did not function through economic institutions separate from other social institutions. These writers recognized the methodological problem: their goals were different from those of the economic theorist and a different set of analytical tools had to be used. The Use of Economic Theory9 In the last fifteen years the study of primitive economics has taken a different turn, making use of the concepts of modern economics to a much greater extent than did the earlier anthropologists. The results of this marriage of the two disciplines have not been happy. The earlier studies had an important drawback. Since their major emphasis lay in the relationship of economic institutions to the total social structure there was a tendency to forego detailed study of economic processes themselves. In studying the distribution of goods from a chief to his tribesmen, for example, the earlier anthropologists emphasized the social setting of the distribution, the socio-political motives involved, and the submergence of economic life in the total life of the tribe. Economics was treated as only one facet of society, and although 348 Institutional Analysis this position is methodologically unassailable it led to a slighting of the detailed facts of economic life. It is also important to know exactly what goods the chief distributed to his tribesmen, in what quantities, and under what circumstances, and in general terms that would permit comparison with other peoples. This would mean less attention being paid to the social matrix of economic life and more attention to the detailed facts themselves. This weakness of the early studies of primitive economics has led to the appearance of a new "school" of anthropologists who have devoted themselves to studies of primitive economic life in great detail, using the terminology of economic theory in order to make comparisons between different societies. Less emphasis is placed upon the uniqueness of each society, and more is placed upon such things as incentives, exchange, trade and barter, money, use of capital, land tenure, and so on. The goal of this newer group of anthropologists is to derive some general principles of economic behavior among primitive peoples out of detailed studies of everyday economic affairs. Chief among them are Melville Herskovits, Sol Tax, Raymond Firth, and D. M. Goodfellow.10 Typical of this group of writers is Herskovits. His Economic Anthropology (1952) attempts to bring together all of the empirical knowledge of primitive economics and analyze it within the framework of orthodox economic theory. The major subjects treated are production, distribution, exchange, property and economic surplus—the outline might well have been taken from John Stuart Mill—and the goal is to understand the economics of primitive peoples in terms of the categories of modern economic theory so that general principles may be derived from the studies of individual peoples. In pursuing the goal of understanding economic life in economic rather than social terms, Herskovits begins by accepting the definition of economics that most orthodox economists hold: economics is the study of the allocation of scarce means to achieve given ends. Every society, argues Herskovits, has this problem of choice, and has developed an economic system within which it is solved. Indeed, "it can also be taken as cross-culturally acceptable that, on the whole, the individual tends to maximize his satisfactions in terms of the choices he makes" (p. 18). Even though the choices may appear to us to be irrational or wasteful, in terms of a different social matrix and attitudes they will be seen to be rational. This definition, of course, encompasess a universal principle that Economic Theory Misplaced: Livelihood in Primitive Society 349 applies to many other areas of life in addition to the economic. But it can lead to valid analytical results in economics only when applied to a set of market institutions that permits a direct achievement of eco- • nomic goals through the market. In the modern market economy allocation of resources is responsive to profits, and maximization of that calculable sum is the goal of business enterprise.11 It is the complex of markets and prices, profits and acquisitiveness that provides an institutionalized means for the making of choices in our economy. In such an institutional setting the theory of choice has led to the development of modern economic theory. But where economic life is embedded in an institutional matrix other than that of a system of markets the theory of the market tells us little. For example, when the economy of a tribe is based upon gift-giving the institutional framework of production and distribution is the prevailing system of kinship and friendship, and economic activities become entwined with motives of maintaining and promoting kinship and friendship ties. "Social motives" become more important than the "economic motives" of acquiring goods; resources are used to achieve "social goals." Under such circumstances the theory of choice leads only to the vague generalization that satisfactions have been maximized. The most striking characteristic of Herskovits* work from the viewpoint of methodology is that his conceptual framework causes him to emphasize market phenomena and largely to ignore the remainder of primitive economic life. For example, he asserts that gift and ceremonial exchange are "noneconomic" because they are used to obtain "prestige," and devotes only a short chapter to them (Ch. VIII). This is in spite of his recognition that those forms of exchange are used to distribute goods "in many, perhaps a majority of instances" (p. 181). On the other hand, trade and barter are treated at great length (Ch. IX-XI), although Herskovits admits that trade "is usually intertribal and involves the acquisition of goods not available in one's own group" (p. 181; Herskovits' italics). This is strange economics indeed—practically to ignore institutions that channelize distribution within the economic system and center attention on intertribal economic relationships. A similar methodological weakness is found in Herskovits' treatment of money. The modern economist defines money as anything generally acceptable in making payments, and adds that money also 350 Institutional Analysis functions as a means of storing wealth, as a standard of value, and as a standard of deferred payments. In the modern market economy all of • these functions have been institutionalized in a single object which we call money. But in primitive societies the various functions of money are institutionalized separately; that is, different things are used in making payments of different kinds, other objects are "valuables," other objects are used to validate the individual's social status, while still others are used to facilitate exchange where markets exist. It is to ; this last function of "money" that Herskovits limits his discussion; he j defines money as "any kind of least common denominator of value-so long as it is regarded as part of a system of graded equivalents, and is used in payment for goods and services" (p. 245). Money, so defined, j is currency, and that is how Herskovits treats it. But he ignores or ' treats only in passing all those monetary functions that are not performed by currency—storing of wealth in the form of cattle or "valuables," payments in kind or in services, and so on. In short, Herskovits has failed to realize that currency performs only a relatively insignificant role in primitive society, that the great bulk of payments are not I made by currency, and that most wealth is not stored in the form of currency.12 Herskovits' faulty methodology stems from his use of the economist's conceptual framework. Such things as money, credit, value, business enterprise, capital formation, and the like are among the major subjects studied in modern economics, and he therefore concentrates on them. They are also separately institutionalized within a market economy. Needless to say, such a conceptual framework is inadequate in discussing economies in which market phenomena are relatively unimportant in channelizing production and distribution. Put bluntly, Herskovits seeks to cram the multifarious forms of non-market economic life into the pigeonholes of the market economy, ignoring what will not fit. The result is a distorted and inaccurate picture of primitive economic life.13 When Herskovits gets away from problems of exchange and distribution he gets away from his market-oriented terminology, and it is here that his work is most valuable. Modern economics takes for granted the institution of private property, and did not develop a specialized terminology for that aspect of economic life. Not being artificially restricted by a market terminology, Herskovits gives a very realistic description of land tenure and ownership of property among Economic Theory Misplaced: Livelihood in Piimitive Society 351 primitive peoples: private property in land, as we know it, does not exist, but land is held by the social unit and the individual has rights in it; the complex nature of rights in land make a market for land impossible; nevertheless, every primitive society recognizes some types of property as privately owned and capable of alienation—the wide prevalence of gift-giving and ceremonial exchange would be impossible without such property. Suffering from similar methodological difficulties is Tax's work on the Guatemalan village of Panajachel.14 Tax describes "a money economy organized in single households as both consumption and production units, with a strongly developed market (for commodities) which tends to be perfectly competitive" as "very strongly a market economy" (pp. 11-13). But as he describes it, the economy of Panajachel has only the most rudimentary of markets for factors of production: although land is freely transferable its sale is highly restricted by the attitude that land holdings must be preserved for the family; the absence of any large body of both free and landless workers precludes the development of a true labor market; and there hardly exists a capital market although loans are sometimes made for consumption purposes. The fundamental institutional bases of the market economy and the tremendous differences between market and non-market institutional patterns are not understood. The underlying difficulty is Tax's use of the conceptual framework of the economics of the market and analysis of the economy of Panajachel in terms of the maximization and allocation principles. Again a distorted picture and improper conclusions emerge. Far more sophisticated than Herskovits or Tax in use of economic theory is D. M. Goodfellow. He has applied the basic concept of choice among alternatives in an analysis of the economic life of the Bantu peoples of south and east Africa, in an effort to show that individual choice is the universal phenomenon of economic activity and that it results in a scale of economic values by which material goods can be compared.15 He argues that the concepts of economic theory have "universal validity" (p. 3) and that "there is no gulf between the civilized and the primitive; one cultural level shades imperceptibly into another" (p. 5). While arguing that "economic choice is constantly exercised by the individual" (p. 11) he recognizes that "resources are indeed disposed of according to the dictates of social values and rules of behavior, describable in terms of custom" (p. 15). On the basis of ^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^^ 352 Institutional Analysis these principles the Bantu economy is examined; it is a society of patriarchal families in which kinship relations create reciprocal obligations, but in which each family manages its own household. Chief attention in Goodfellow's work is paid to the management of the household and practically no space is devoted to the economics of anything else in Bantu society. Among the aspects of Bantu economic life not adequately treated are reciprocal economic relationships based on kinship, redistribution through the chieftain, and economic relationships that transcend the household-kinship-chieftain complex. Here again is the methodological difficulty that emerged in Herskovits' work: tbe conceptual framework has limited the inquiry to only part of the subject. The saving feature of Goodfellow's work is that he chose for study an economy in which the principle of householding is the dominant feature of economic life, and it is obvious that economic management must take place in the household. Even within this type of economy, however, Goodfellow selected those aspects that involved choice, slighting those that did not involve choice, and came out with the conclusion that economics—the theory of choice—is applicable cross-culturally. The reader comes out with the conclusion that while choices may well be made within the Bantu economy, a full understanding of that economy requires a broader approach. Much more useful than the work of Herskovits, Tax, or Goodfellow is that of Raymond Firth.16 His study of the economy of the Polynesian island of Tikopia makes use of the concepts of modern economics, but Firth never allows those concepts to obscure the relationship between economic life and kinship, magic, ritual and chieftainship, nor to obscure reciprocal or redistributive forms of economic activity. While he shows that individual advantage is pursued, he emphasizes that such activity is closely limited and defined by traditional patterns of behavior and that the individual is not permitted by social sanctions to pursue his own interests to more than a very limited extent. Indeed, the concepts of economic theory are used primarily to show that the Polynesian is both realistic and rational in his economic life, rather than as a framework within which to analyze the economy. Yet when economic theory and its concepts can be applied without distorting the picture, Firth does not hesitate to do so. In his book on the Malay fishing industry he describes a peasant fishing economy in which there are local, regional and export markets for dried fish, wholesalers and retailers, and a complex system of credit. The fish trade is Economic Theory Misplaced: Livelihood in Primitive Society 353 market-oriented, and a meaningful analysis in terms of ownership and management of capital, credit, marketing organization, distribution, output and levels of income is possible. But Firth is frank in his recog* nition that the analysis does not txplore the relationships between fishing activities and other aspects of social and economic life in tie society. It is essentially a study of a single market-oriented industry in a peasant economy, and shows that modern economic theory can be successfully applied to market aspects of primitive economic life if its limitations are recognized. While the weaknesses of Herskovits' and Goodfellow's work arise from a largely uncritical acceptance of economic theory, Firth's success is due in large part to his selective use of its concepts and principles. His awareness of the methodological pitfalls involved in economic theory is typified by the statement that "the anthropologist accepts as valid the body of economic doctrine" but "he can absorb only a very small part of it into his conceptual apparatus for the study of primitive society."17 A A Cross-cultural Economics 1 To summarize, the use of modem economic theory as a tool of (analysis in studying primitive economics has two principal drawbacks. • First, the categories and definitions of modern economies are not ap- plicable to cross-cultural studies. The basic reason for this lack of ! applicability is that the phenomena isolated for study—money, capital, profit, wages, rent, business enterprise, markets and the like—not only perform economic functions, but have an institutionalized reality in the modern economy that can be identified and usually measured. And they are the result of a unique historical development that has not been repeated in other cultures. Capital, for example, is not only the goods ! used for the production of other goods, but in the modern economy it can be identified and measured as part of business institutions, and i enters into the calculations of businessmen through widely accepted accounting procedures. In the primitive economy the economic functions performed by capital can be analyzed and described, but there is no way of treating them as a separate and discrete part of the institutional structure of society. Rather, the economic functions of capital 354 Institutional Analysis are generally found institutionalized as part of other social institutions —kinship, the family unit, religion and magic, tribal political structure, and the like—rather than separately, and an analysis of capital in the economy becomes analysis of the whole society. If the analysis were limited only to those cultural elements clearly identifiable as capital as a separately institutionalized element much of the relevant data would be missed. Secondly, the formal economics of the maximization and allocation principles—the theory of choice—represents only a portion of the subject matter of economics.18 Economics deals with the production and distribution of material goods and services. At one boundary of the subject it gets very close to the study of technology and processes of production. At the other limit it treats of attitudes and motivations, social classes and relationships, and the institutional framework within which production and distribution" are carried on. Only a relatively small part of the subject matter of economics is the theory of choice among alternatives—and even choices are conditioned by technological possibilities and the social structure. If attention is centered narrowly on the logic of choice a large portion of economics will be ignored. For the anthropologist a methodological difficulty of the utmost gravity is created. Use of the tools of economic theory offers only limited advantages in centering attention on individual choices, while it interferes with the institutional analysis that is at the heart of anthropological study. The anthropologist who studies primitive economics cannot go to another already developed discipline for his conceptual framework or his problems and questions. Instead, a broader theoretical schema must be developed—broad enough to encompass both the modern market economy and the economies of primitive peoples—in which the formal economics of the market is a special case. The task is no easy one. It requires not only empirical studies of production and distribution that center on economic institutions and their relationship to the larger social structure, but also a willingness to theorize about the place of the economic system in society and not merely about individual choices.19 The leading ideas that have to be developed further are those of Malinowski, Thurnwald, Benedict, Du-Bois and Mead, and not those of the economic theorists. The real task is nothing less than the building of a cross-cultural economics based on Economic Theory Misplaced: Livelihood in Primitive Society 355 the substantive problems of production and distribution rather than on formal problems of choice. Daniel B.Fusfeld • . Notes to Chapter XVII 1. See J. H. Boeke, The Structure of Netherlands Indian Economy (New York, 1942), pp. 3-6, for a discussion of the difficulty of applying modern economic theory to the Oriental peasant economy. For the opposite view see Raymond Firth, Malay Fishermen: Their Peasant Economy (London, 1946)—but note that Firth's discussion is limited to the Malay fishing industry, which operates within a market framework. Simon Rottenberg has recently argued that failure of workers in primitive economies to respond to wage incentives does not mean that there is no effective labor market, but rather that the supply of labor is inelastic. See his "Discussion," American Economic Review, Vol. 65, No. 2 (May, 1955), 194. Such a conclusion !is the inevitable result of the theoretician's method of abstracting from the institutional framework. What does it tell us about the functioning of the primitive economy? See also Simon Rottenberg, "Income and Leisure in an Underdeveloped Economy," Journal of Political Economy, Vol. 60, No. 2 (April, 1952). 2. Bronislaw Malinowski, "The Primitive Economics of the Trobriand Islanders," Economic Journal, XXXI, 1-16; Argonauts of the Western Pacific (New York, 1950); Crime and Custom in Savage Society (London, 1926); Coral Gardens and Their Magic (London, 1935). 3. The best introductions to this "configurational" school of anthropologists . are Ruth Benedict, Patterns of Culture (New York, 1934) and Margaret Mead (ed.), f Cooperation and Competition Among Primitive Peoples (New York, 1937). 4. Cora DuBois, "The Wealth Factor as an Integrative Factor in Tolowa-1 Tututui Culture" in Essays in Anthropology Presented to A. L. Kroeber (Berkeley, I 1936), pp. 49-66. J 5. Summarized in Richard Thurnwald, Economics in Primitive Communities I (London, 1932). | 6. Tnurnwald's theory of the state has a close affinity with that of Franz Op- j penheimer (The State, New York, 1914), but goes far beyond Oppenheimer's ver- I sion. I 7. The evolutionary approach to economic history is particularly prevalent | among English and American scholars. German writers, on the other hand, have | emphasized discontinuities and irregularities in economic development; this is j especially true of Karl Marx, Gustav Schmoller, Werner Sombart, and Max Weber. | Anthropologists since Thurnwald's day have eschewed consideration of prob- 1 lems of social change in a reaction against the earlier theories of "stages" of de- velopment. The whole range of problems explored by Thurnwald has unfortunately been dropped until very recently. 8. Marcel Mauss, The Gitt: Forms and Functions of Exchange in Archaic Societies (Glencoe, 111., 1954). 356 Institutional Analysis 9. Parts of this section are reprinted from reviews in the Journal of Economic History, XIII, No. 2 (Spring 1953), 219-221 and Explorations in Entrepreneurial History, VI, No. 3 (February 1954), 190-191. 10. Melville Herskovits, Economic Anthropology (New York, 1952), originally published as The Economic Life of Primitive Peoples (New York, 1940); Sol Tax, Penny Capitalism: A Guatemalan Indian Economy (Washington, 1953); Raymond Firth, Primitive Polynesian Economy (London, 1939) and Malay Fishermen: Their Peasant Economy (London, 1946); D. M. Goodfellow, Principles of Economic Sociology (London, 1939; New York, 1950). 11. This is true, at least, of theoretical models of the market economy; it is less true of the actual world. 12. Firth recognizes this difficulty and points out that true money is not widely found among primitive peoples, but he also fails to consider adequately the wide diffusion of the functions of money and the problem of its institutionalization. He adopts the definition of money developed by the modern economist, and in so doing eliminates from consideration much of the reality of primitive economic life, and ignores the most important problem, namely, how the various functions of money come to be institutionalized in a single element of culture. See Raymond Firth, "Currency, Primitive," Encyclopedia Brittanica, 14th ed. 13. For the opposite view, praising Herskovits' use of the conceptual framework of modern economics, see K. F. Walker, "The Study of Primitive Economics," Oceania, XIII (1942-3), 131-42. 14. Sol Tax, Penny Capitalism (Washington, 1953). 15. D. M. Goodfellow, Principles of Economic Sociology (London, 1939; New York, 1950). 16. His two recent works in primitive economics are Primitive Polynesian Economy (London, 1939) and Malay Fishermen: Their Peasant Economy (London, 1946). 17. Raymond Firth, Elements of Social Organization (London, 1951) pp. 129-130. 18. See John R. Hicks, "Economic Theory and the Social Sciences," in The Social Sciences: Their Relations in Theory and Teaching (London, 1936), pp. 129-140. 19. A good recent example of this approach is Eleanor Leacock, "The Mon-tagnais 'Hunting Territory' and the Fur Trade," American Anthropologist, Vol. 56, No. 5, Part 2 (Memoirs of the American Anthropological Association, No. 78). Other anthropologists who have been dealing with the problem of economic development have given similar emphasis to their work. XVIII The ^Ma-ri^et in Theory and History the existence of a market is often taken to establish the existence of a market system in the modern sense of price-making markets, and to imply the relevance of the body of economic theory to the analysis of the situation in which the market is found. As a result a modern, market economy is read into the social organizations of many historical and primitive societies where there is no other evidence to support the existence of a system similar to ours except the occurrence of some form of market. There would be no objection to such reasoning if the term market had only one, precise meaning, but this is not the case. To the economist the market is a specific institution with rules of its own upon which he has built a very powerful analytic structure. To the historian and anthropologist the market is often the "market place," a meeting place for the transfer of goods from one set of hands to another, and such a market place is not necessarily the basis of the economic theory which economists have created. There is a great danger that in adopting the common terms of economics the less perfectly understood implications which economists attach to these terms may slip into the description of societies other than our own, and, in consequence, the inappropriate usage of the terms of economics will hide from the investigator the true institutional mechanisms of the society which he is analyzing. In view, therefore, of the real differences between a market as it is conceived by economists and the market place as it is found by anthropologists and economic historians, it seems useful to make explicit 357 358 Institutional Analysis the differences in meaning which may be attached to the term market, and so avoid serious mistakes in interpreting evidence of trade, money and market elements in societies without a market system. Price-making Markets To the economist the market is a mechanism which produces prices. The function of market prices is to regulate the supply of goods1 in relation to the demand, and to channel the demand for goods in relation to the available supply. Hence the market may be called a supply-demand-price mechanism. As we shall see, all and everything that is comprised in a market economy can be subsumed under these terms. (a) The supply is the amount of goods on the market at a given time, or flowing into the market over a given period of time. It is a characteristic of the market that the supply of a good offered for sale increases as the price rises, and this for two reasons: (A) A higher price will bring higher cost producers into the market. (B) At a higher price, holders of the good who had no intention of selling may change their minds because their command over other goods has thus increased. Thus there is a definite relationship between the prevailing price and the goods made available by the suppliers. Prices regulate the movement of goods into the market. (b) Demand means the quantity of goods which buyers will take at a particular price; e.g., so many pounds of butter per month if the price is, say, fifty cents. Given people's preferences, a market is expected to register a rise in the level of demand for a good if the prices of other goods rise relative to the price of that good, and a fall if the prices of other goods go down. Thus prices regulate the movement of goods out of the market. Demand figures importantly at two junctures in the economist's market. There is demand for consumers' goods like butter, and demand for the various inputs needed to produce the butter. Relative prices play the decisive role in both cases. Consumers face an array of goods with limited purchasing power. Since they must, in order to get desired goods, cover prices with their limited purchasing power, their purchases will obviously depend on prices. Producers demand factors of produc- The Market in Theory and History 359 tion because they can make a profit by employing them as inputs. Within the limits set by technology producers demand more of the cheaper and less of the dearer inputs. If the price of labor rises producers will try to use more capital goods as substitutes for labor. Here again prices rule, for the producer will succeed only to the extent that he maximizes the spread between cost and price. (c) The mechanism of the market refers to the systematic reactions of all prices and quantities to changes in any one of them. Prices move goods into the market (supply) and move them out of the market (demand). At the same time prices themselves are affected by supply and demand. As the conditions of supply—relative scarcity—or of demand —relative preferences—change, such changes will be reflected in prices. An increased preference for one good means that buyers will buy more of it than formerly at any given price. Suppliers will not sell more at the old price, so the price must rise until it has called forth an increased supply. At the same time the rise in price will eliminate a certain amount of the willingness to buy which existed at the lower price. This double action of fluctuating prices constantly moves supply and demand to a position of equilibrium. That is, relative prices are constantly moving toward the combination at which the quantity of each good which suppliers will sell at the market price is exactly matched by the quantity which buyers will purchase at that price, thus "clearing the market." It is this self-equilibrating mechanism which the economist has in mind when he employs the term "market." Since all economic decisions will be based upon prices and all events of economic importance will become effective through prices, this concept of the market provides a simple, yet comprehensive, tool for explaining all the movements of goods and services involved in the complex process of production and distribution. The choice of what goods to produce and of what means to use to produce them, and thus the allocation of productive resources between uses, the distribution of income, the choice between present and future consumption (or how much to save and invest) and even the effects of social and political factors upon the economy—all these choices can be explained within the framework of the market concept. To illustrate the scope of the economist's concept, and to give con-creteness to the characteristics of the major subdivisions of the self- 360 Institutional Analysis regulating market system, it may be helpful to present a bird's-eye view of the different types of markets. Types of Markets: the Economist's View Product markets are markets for goods which have been processed to some extent. The product markets which we, as consumers, are constantly influencing and being influenced by are the innumerable markets for the goods and services which we buy for ourselves and our families. These we may call Consumer Goods Markets. Another sub-classification can be made for the finished and semifinished goods which businesses buy to use in further production and distribution, for these product markets overlap with those of the consumer. These are the markets in which businesses buy buildings, machinery, processed raw materials, semifinished and finished goods. Factor markets are the markets for land, labor, and capital. All basic inputs are classified under one of these three headings, being either a natural resource; human work of the manual or mental kinds; or buildings and equipment needed for production and distribution. Each of these markets has its special characteristics: (a) The Market for Land is the market in which claims or title to land and all its natural characteristics can be bought and sold. The concept of "land" is broad, including not merely the surface area involved, but also the advantages of its climate, location, and mineral wealth. However, the concept of land is limited to the conditions and content which nature or chance put into the plot; the economist would say that all man-made changes are properly capital investments added to the land. While there is a purchase price for the paramount title-ownership—one generally takes Rent for the use of land over a period as the Price of land on the Land Market. The unique characteristic of this market is that the supply was fixed in Genesis and changes in rent cannot alter the amount on offer. If demand for land increases there is a rise in price, but the rise is incapable of calling forth a larger supply. Conversely the price can fall to zero and there will be no diminution of supply.2 (b) The Market for Labor is the market for the hiring of all humans used in the productive process. Unlike product and land mar- The Market in Theory and History 361 kets, the buyer cannot buy the man, but only the use of his brain and brawn over a period. The price here is generally called the wage (per unit of time), and this term is taken to include salaries and the bonuses of top directors. The unique characteristic of this market is that it involves the buying and selling of the time and activities of the people who make up the society. On the demand side there is only one consideration involved in hiring the man: whether or not his labor will contribute to the productive process as much or more in value than the wage he is paid—exactly the same consideration that governs demand in any other factor market. But on the supply side, there are peculiarly human elements involved. A man must eat to live, and to eat he must work: i.e., hire out his labor. The more efficient or skilled a man is, the higher the wage he can command, but except for the small number of persons who can live on the proceeds of their titles to land and capital, everyone must succeed in getting 3 job at some wage. This means that the supply of labor has something in common with the supply of land. As wages vary old people, young people, wives, and such on-again-ofE-again laborers may add to or deduct from the labor supply, but the overwhelming part of the labor supply is determined by the size and age distribution of the population. (c) The Capita] Market refers not to the buildings and equipment which are in reality the capital used in the productive process, but to the market for the money (purchasing power) which can buy the capital equipment or the use of land and labor. Thus we have divided the capital market in two parts: the one a product market similar to the Consumers Product Market except that it is governed not by taste but by calculable profitability; and the other a market for the money which can buy these products. The Capital Market is subdivided into a number of Financial Markets: e.g., the Stock Exchange for the permanent borrowing of money in exchange for a share in the profits of the business using the money, the Money Market for the temporary borrowing of funds in exchange for a fixed return on the money until it is repaid. The price paid for the use of money on the Money Market is called interest, and since the Money Market and the Stock Exchange are alternative sources of money, economists generally treat only the interest rate when discussing the price of money. The Money Market is of course divided again into closely related parts, such as the Mortgage Market where funds are tied up for long periods, as they are in the Long-Term Bond Market; the Short-Term Money Market where ibl Institutional Analysis money can be borrowed for as short a time as overnight, and various intermediate markets. • The distinguishing characteristics of the Money Markets, which constitute the central institution of the more general Capital Market, is again on the supply side. Demand for money and therefore the goods and factors which money controls depends, like the demand for land, labor and capital products, only on how much the business can pay for money and still increase, or at least maintain, its profits. The supply of money, like the supply of land and labor, is not primarily responsive to the price—the interest rate-offered for its use, although there is a tendency for owners of money to lend more when the interest rate rises because the alternative uses of money, such as the safety arising from hoarding, become relatively less attractive. However, we may distinguish two basic supply conditions for the money market: (I) The supply of money is governed by the supply of precious metals, which meant gold in the late nineteenth century. Perhaps the purest example of this Gold Standard was the United States in the thirty-five years which preceded the Federal Reserve Bank Act (1879-1914). There was responsiveness to price changes, for the higher the price of money the more profitable it became to mine gold in high cost mines, but even this responsiveness (economists call it elasticity) was of small importance in comparison with the importance of fortuitous gold discoveries such as occurred in California (1849), in Australia (1850's) and in South Africa (1880's). Primarily the supply of money which is based upon precious metals is a matter of chance discoveries. (II) The supply of money may be governed by the authority of the State, more or less directly through the issue of paper money by the treasury and the control of the Central Bank and the banking system. It is not necessary to describe the techniques of control. It is sufficient to recognize that the supply of money in this case depends on the decisions of the monetary authority as to whether the supply of money shall be increased or decreased. This is inevitably a control of the market, not a part of the formal market mechanism, for there cannot be a market determined money supply if the money supply is determined by an authority. The supply of money can therefore be said to be relatively independent of the price offered. These then are the markets with which the economist deals. Their characteristics may be briefly summarized: | The Market in Theory and History 363 ! (a) Prices on the Consumers Product Markets are set by equilibrat- ing a demand based on tastes and relative prices with a supply based on prices and costs—i.e., profitability. (b) Prices on Producers (Capital) Product Markets are set by equilibrating a demand based on prospective profitability (ultimate prod-*" uct price minus price of the input) and a supply based on the same con- sideration as under (a) just above. ! (c) Prices on Factor Markets are set by equilibrating a demand 1 again based upon prospective profitability with a supply resulting from considerations outside of the supply-demand mechanism of the market. This ultimate dependence of Factor Supply on nature, sex or government is the distinguishing characteristic of the Factor Markets. The Self-Regulating Market is essentially the kind of market we [ have been discussing up to this point. It is a closed system. There is t no need to go outside of the considerations already mentioned to un- derstand the mechanism, nor to work out the theoretical implications I of any added set of assumptions about demand or cost conditions. If one wants to determine the effects of government policy on this mechanism, it is not necessary to examine the political institutions, but only to make an assumption that a certain policy is put into effect, and then to examine its effects on the supply and demand sides and thus on the whole mechanism. To illustrate, questions about political constitution, religious ethics, or the structure of the family are irrele-■ vant. All the economist need do is take the effects of these upon de- mand and costs and follow through the type of analysis indicated above. | A Market System is a group of such related markets. One can j conceive of having a market for only one thing, perhaps a particular consumer good. Sitting isolated and alone there would not be much play for supply-demand-price interaction, but in fact the modern west-I ern economy is made up of a vast number of markets, each for one good ! or service. These markets are closely related, for every good has some substitute which will be chosen in greater or lesser quantity depending ! on their relative prices, and the particular allocation of expenditure between goods made at any time depends upon the relative prices \ existing in all product (goods and services) markets. All these product ! markets in turn may be related to the Factor Markets through the | supply-demand-price mechanism, so that the market for milk affects | other product markets (e.g., beer), producer goods markets (e.g., 364 Institutional Analysis bottles), and factor markets (e.g., for farm land, for labor, and for the money to build barns and buy feed). A Self-Regulating Market System is such a system as that outlined in the two preceding paragraphs. Each change in demand or supply conditions reacts through the whole system until each and every market has achieved a new equilibrium, where suppliers bring forward exactly the amount which buyers will take at the existing price, with no further pressures on either side to change the price.3 It is to be noted that it is the very strength of economic analysis in the market context which sets its limits in the analysis of non-market economies. It is the precision of the market concept which allows the economist to analyze our market system in such detail as he does, and it is this precision which sets the limit to his analysis when the economy involved is not based upon a price-making market. All this amounts to saying that economic analysis is based upon the institutions of the markets: independent decision makers buying and selling and producing for sale with inputs bought on the market, protected by law in their contractual rights, and making their decisions with the objective of a monetary profit or gain. When these conditions and the specific institutions which embody them (such as business firms, corporations, banks, free wage labor, alienable land) are absent, economic analysis cannot be effective. For the moment we will leave aside the possibilities of combining markets for some goods and factors into a System, while leaving other goods and factors out of the System. We will assume that everything that is scarce relative to potential uses is bought and sold in a market. We will also for the moment leave aside the possibility that the System is only partially self-regulating, or that it somehow combines a self-regulating sector with a non-self-regulating sector.4 (a) The first significant implication is in regard to people. In a Self-Regulating Market System the whole complex of personal life is irrelevant. Religious faith, social status, political belief, family life, loving, hating, gossiping, do not decide what shall be done, except as they are part of the complex of motives and emotions creating demand for products. On the contrary, the Self-Regulating Market, relieved of higher restraint, tends to govern the personal life. The demand for labor has a direct effect upon the locality in which one lives (where the job is), the kind of economic activity in which one engages (that for which the demand gives the highest return to one's talents), and the security of The Market in Theory and History 365 one's bodily survival. This last, being able to eat, sleep under cover, and keep warm, depends, in a Self-Regulating Market System, on there being a demand for labor great enough to provide a living wage. A failure of demand here means at best temporary disruption of the flow { of life, and at worst starvation, whether because the sum of consumer and producer demand for goods falls, setting off a spiral of declining incomes and declining demand, as occurs in the wealthier western nations, or because there is so much labor that the gain in productivity of hiring another man is close to zero, as is the case in southeast Asia. Even without this kind of disaster, changes in relative demands may require the removal of labor from one place to another and result in changes in the relative income and social status of various segments of the labor force. h (b) Another significant implication is that in regard to non-eco- * nomic political and social institutions. The management of the area and resources of the nation (the land market) and management of the productive resources of the nation (the capital market) are the result of the working of the Self-Regulating Market. When the Self-Regulating Market is international this severely limits the freedom of national action. On the social side family unity and community life are put in '■ a constant state of flux since the personnel are so easily forced into j movement. \ (c) Therefore, a System of Self-Regulating Markets takes a large i portion of human activity and sets it aside from all other activity, gives it a set of rules to live by—rules subject to no higher control—and permits the whole of this activity to be governed by the supply-demand-price mechanism. Because economic activities and other aspects of life are closely interrelated, a self-regulating market therefore tends to shape all other activity to a much greater degree than the economy would under other types of economic organization. Markets in Economic History No social institution is a perfect copy of its ideal, but the Self-Regu-j lating Market System can be said to have existed in a workable approxi- j mation to the ideal type during the latter part of the nineteenth and the early part of the twentieth centuries. In many places, and in greater | or less degree, it is still an appropriate model for the solution of many 366 Institutional Analysis economic problems. By making allowances and recognizing limitations the economist still finds it the most useful tool for discussing problems of choice, economic efficiency, prices, the distribution of goods, and the particular uses to which resources are put. It is now our purpose to discuss other types of markets which are significantly different, some so different that they should never be thought of as markets in the senses we have been using. As a first step, we shall distinguish between markets in the economist's sense and markets in the sense of market-place. In the former sense, a market need have no physical location, although of course it may. "While the Chicago Board of Trade provides a room for transactions in grain, the international money market is a world-wide network of knowledge and communications between many centers and individuals. Unlike the Chicago Board of Trade it has no concrete geographical existence; it exists because there are many persons demanding and supplying foreign exchange. It is this sort of vague supply-demand-price mechanism of "no fixed address" which produces the phenomena known as world markets and world prices. A Market Place is a very different matter. Here we have a specific location where people meet for the purpose of transferring goods from one to another. The term "exchange" really has three levels of meaning:* 1. Operationally defined, exchange includes any two way passing of goods—at a fixed price, or at an indeterminate or unknown ratio, such as Christmas presents. In this broad sense it includes reciprocity and redistribution. 2. In a more limited sense exchange means buying and selling at a definite or fixed price. The choice presented is whether or not to accept the option offered. This meaning includes: 3. Exchange used to describe buying and selling at a bargained price. Here there is an added element of freedom in the option; negotiating the price which provides the final option. This is the meaning of exchange in a self-regulating market system. It now becomes clear that we can have "exchange" or a "marketplace" in the first or second meanings of the term exchange, and not have markets in the economists' sense. In a Market Place there is no necessity for a supply-demand-price mechanism. Whereas in the economist's markets individuals can be * See above, pp. 254-5. The Market in Theory and History 367 indiscriminately buyers and sellers, shifting from one side to the other,5 this need not be the case in a Market Place. For instance, farmers could come to the town market only to sell food while the townsmen1 came only to buy. Furthermore, the farmers might bring a fixed quantity of food and sell it all no matter what the price, and townsmen buy no matter what the price. The price itself might be fixed by some official or simply be the traditional price. In these cases price would not determine either the amount supplied or the amount demanded. The medieval food market approximated this situation. The Market Place need not even involve a price. For instance, there could be a meeting place simply for the transfer of one kind of goods from one group to another, which in turn would turn over another ft kind of goods to the first group. No element of barter need enter, for If equivalence may be determined on entirely different principles. The * fish-yams exchange of the Trobriaftd Islanders is of this nature. So are the meeting places of the Kula Ring. Clearly a Market Place of this kind has little in common with the supply-demand-price mechanism. A Market Place can be of fixed location and open all the time, or it can be open only on certain days—market days in an English market town is an excellent example. Another example is the medieval fair, which met once a year. These example also provide a contrast between the Market Place which has physical equipment such as permanent stalls or a paved open space and the Market Place which reverts to countryside when the market is over. The sort of market which occurs in a Market Place could occur in different locations at different times. Any particular market day would have to be in some specified place, but the place might vary from day to day, rotating among towns. Again, a fair or different fairs involving the same personnel might travel from one fixed Market Place to another. This situation is typified by the autumnal agricultural fairs. In all these cases of Market Place markets we have a meeting of persons for the transfer or exchange of goods, but we do not necessarily have a supply-demand-price mechanism. The Chicago Board of Trade, already mentioned, and the markets of English market towns of the last century and a half have operated with such a mechanism. But it is a question of historical fact whether or not a particular Market Place is also the physical seat of a supply-demand-price mechanism. The important thing is that the use of the term market in an historical docu- 368 Institutional Analysis ment or current description cannot be taken to imply that there is a supply-demand-price mechanism in operation. ' The difference between Self-Regulating Markets and other markets can be illustrated in several ways: (a) The auction is a market with a supply, a group of people demanding and prices, but it is not a Self-Regulating Market. The supply is determined outside the economic system. For instance, the supply of war captives sold as slaves at auction is economically a fortuitous consequence of political action. The auction today of the household effects of the deceased is not a supply in response to a price resulting from demand and cost of production, but a chance supply caused by death. The point is that high prices at the auction will not call forth a larger supply (i.e., they will not cause more wars, and certainly not more victories, nor will they cause more deaths). On the demand side also the auction price has no repertussions (i.e., there is no long-run equilibrating mechanism). There is a "one-shot" chance at a particular batch of goods. In a Self-Regulating Market the existence of high prices induces demanders to shift to lower priced substitutes, or low prices induce an increased consumption of that good. There is a continuous process of adaptation among streams of goods. But this is not the case at the auction. There are no streams of goods coming along. One buys what one wants if one bids the highest, and that is the end of it, the consumer reverting after the auction to his normal sources of supply. (b) Milk is sold for money in Indian villages. Women of cow-owning families bring to the Market Place the milk their families do not consume. As a rule the price for milk is a traditional price, and does not vary although the prices of other agricultural goods dealt with in the World Market fluctuate widely. It is also clear that the cow-owning families do not increase the number of their cows in response to changes in the difference between the traditional price and the cost of keeping cows. (c) There are markets which more nearly approach the Self-Regulating Market, but are intermediate classifications (not stages). Thus one might have a market in which the price is fixed by official action and the supply and demand crowds adapt to the fixed price more or less as the economist would expect. Price control in war time illustrates this case, as did some mercantilist efforts to fix prices. Then one might have the demand occur independently of the economist's considerations, while prices and supply react as the economist would expect. An The Market in Theory and History 369 illustration is the "sky's the limit" demand of a government for armaments during a war with no price control, or United States strategic stockpile purchases on the international market. To some extent all government purchases on all markets have partaken of this character. (d) There have beeen and are many examples of markets in which one or more of the economist's economic elements are governed by considerations outside the scope of the Self-Regulating Market. Illustrations are the politically determined unlimited demand at a specified price of the United States government for certain farm products and the Soviet demand for a minimum quantity of agricultural produce at a specified, low price. (e) The Self-Regulating Market works only with demand, cost of supply, and prices, all reached by mutual interaction. This character may be destroyed by the introduction of outside elements affecting the equilibrating mechanism. Mercantilist governments of the sixteenth to eighteenth centuries altered the equilibrium at which the market acting alone would have arrived by subsidizing some industries, prohibiting the export of some goods and the import of others. Freedom to minimize costs was limited by government regulations of the techniques of production. (f) These examples bring out a significant difference between Self-Regulating Markets and others. In a Self-Regulating Market the participants act on the basis of the relative prices arrived at by the supply-demand-price mechanism. If they are to survive in the market game they must follow the rule of maximizing return and minimizing cost. In non-Self-Regulating Markets the participants may act partly on "rational economic grounds" or relative prices, but they also reach decisions on the basis of other, different, or additional considerations. Generally economists think of Self-Regulating Markets as being part of an all-embracing System of Self-Regulating Markets. Where some markets are Self-Regulating and others are not, it is correct to say that none of the markets can be truly Self-Regulating, for the limiting elements in the controlled markets will affect the working of all markets. Whether or not the limiting elements destroy the validity of analysis based on the assumption of Self-Regulating Markets is a question of how close an approximation to the ideal one requires and how frequent or widespread the limitations are. It is a matter of interest to the economic historian whether the markets at any particular time and place approximate Self-Regulating Markets or whether the limitations 370 Institutional Analysis and interferences are so great as to make economic analysis inapplicable or applicable only with the greatest care. If the limitations upon Self-Regulation are great economic history must differentiate these markets from Self-Regulating markets, and establish their characteristics independently of the economist's deductions from the Self-Regulating Market. The history of western Europe from the fifteenth to the nineteenth centuries has often been misread because of a failure to grasp the distinction between a Self-Regulating Market System and a number of markets more or less free to regulate themselves, but in sum not constituting a Self-Regulating System. An instance is the early English woollen market, where the international prices fluctuated, and merchants behaved much as modern merchants do. However, the production of wool from sheep farming was still in the hands of persons living under a feudal system of land tenure, while labor was organized in guilds and under the guilds in a strictly regulated hierarchy of apprentices and journeymen. Taking this period, usually called the Commercial Revolution and the Mercantile Period, we find that typically product markets tended insofar as they could to approximate the Self-Regulating Market, but were subject to controls of varying efficiency and importance, while Factor Markets in the economist's sense had not come into existence, except for the Capital Market.6 The situation was logically (and in this case historically) a stage between non-supply-demand-price Market Places and a supply-demand-price Self-Regulating Market. For our purposes we may use it as an example of a System of Markets of a specific nature covering only a portion of the economy as distinct from a System of Self-Regulating Markets. We have looked at an array of market types found in economic history. They may be ranged from: (a) Self-Regulating Markets, where demand, price and cost mutually and exclusively determine what shall be produced, how it shall be produced, and to whom it shall be distributed, to: (b) Market Places, which have nothing in common with Self-Regulating Markets except that goods move from person to person. The varying systems of rules under which these Market Places operate is a subject for investigation to which the economist can contribute no more than anyone else, unless we emphasize his advantage in being The Market in Theory and History yi\ able to utter warning when other unconsciously attribute Self-Regulating characteristics to these Market Places. Between these two types are other markets having some of the characteristics of Self-Regulating Markets. They may be price-making markets in which considerations other than demand, price, and cost *F affect what is produced, how it is produced, and to whom it goes. They may be essentially Market Places which happen to make use of money but fix the prices. The closer these markets approach the price-making and self-regulatory types the more useful is economic theory, but eco-j nomic theory has explanatory value only after the facts are established. It will not explain activity in a Market Place a priori. For the economic historian a subject of special interest is the oc-! currence in Market Places of institutions or mechanisms resembling I those in a Self-Regulating Market. Partly this interest arises from a de- * sire to see how powerful these institutions and mechanisms are in forc- I ing upon the economy other characteristics of Self-Regulating Markets; i partly from a desire to see how these similar institutions can be made to operate in different ways and for different purposes from those we have come to expect of them as economists. Another special interest of the economic historian is to see what other, nonmarket, ways have developed in the course of history to accomplish the same basic end as the Self-Regulating Market has accomplished for those of us who live in a market economy—namely, the provision of material means to satisfy our needs and wants; hence our interest in systems of Reciprocity and Redistribution. As a final point it is probably fair to say that the social scientists writing this volume are at least tentatively committed to the view that Self-Regulating Markets are the exception rather than the rule—even to the view that they are unique to the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Further, they regard price-making markets as the exceptional occurrence in history, and incline to the view that for most of its span man has lived with fixed price markets, non-price making Market Places, and perhaps mostly with economic systems best treated in terms of reciprocal or redistributive institutions whose essential character must be established independently of orthodox economic theory and with the help of other disciplines more familiar with nonmarket institutions. Walter C. Neale #2 Institutional Analysis Notes to Chapter XVIII 1. Here and hereafter "goods" shall be used with the same meaning as the more cumbersome "goods and services." Also, when talking about nonmarket economies the technical term for a saleable commodity (i.e., "good") has been retained instead of using the more correct "material means of want satisfaction." 2. One may raise the question of an increase in supply when the price rises by citing the great and successful efforts to find more oil-bearing land after the usefulness of oil was discovered. However, here we have no increase in the supply of nature's resources, but only an increase in our knowledge about them and consequent increases in the price of land. In fact, this question illustrates the point: the oil-bearing land has always been an offer at some price, and that price has varied in response to a demand either ignorant of the uses of oil or cognizant of the uses and aware that the plot in question contained oil. The efforts at discovery, the analytic economist would say, were illustrations of the productivity of using capital resources to increase our knowledge. 3. The economist may think that short shrift is given to the range of economic theory. Our purpose, however, is to provicle a picture of the formal characteristics of the genus "market" as understood in economic theory. There is no intention to imply that economics does not have much to contribute to analyses of markets which are not self-regulating or even not price-making. The important point is that economists begin with a model of the self-regulating system of markets and work from it, and our purpose here is to point out the limits of the concept, not its strengths. 4. Concrete meaning will be given to this possibility below under Types of Markets: Historical Examples. 5. In true speculative markets like the Stock Exchange and the Cotton Exchanges, each person has a price at or below which he will buy and another, higher price, at or above which he will sell. 6. Here again, there was not complete freedom of Self-Regulation since governments followed a bullionist policy of restricting the export of gold and silver in coin or bullion form, and during the earlier part of the period interest rates were by no means free of religious doctrine on usury and avarice, enforced by the governments. •r Qoncluding ]S[ote in the preface we spoke of this book as work-in-progress. Let us take a swift glance at the road we have traversed and at the position thus reached. The fruits of the empirical research on trade and market institutions offered in Parts I and II admittedly provide but a slim foundation for the structure of theory and method erected in Part III. The historical and anthropological data of those parts fall short of exhausting the conceptual area marked out in the final section. We may thus appear to have been left with an array of untested tools. Actually, however, those theoretical considerations and the facts that precede them are more closely linked than the subject matter of the loose sequence of chapters might indicate. The authors see in the market bias the intellectual obstacle to that broadening of our vision in matters economic which they advocate. Adam Smith's discovery of the market as the pivot of the economy was more than a practical insight of superlative relevance; more than a pinpointing of the cell whence the emergent economic life could be theoretically mastered. His concept of the market as a spur to competition gave the decisive impetus for that view of society that was to arise from such an economy: a concept that was eventually regarded as an universal tool in the atomistically conceived history and theory of man. The market, then, shaped both the organization of our actual 373 t 374 Institutional Analysis material existence and the perspectives from which we were allegedly enabled to grasp all forms of social organization. And herein lies the key to unity in the argument of this book. The market envelopment of our own economy and society was seen as the major obstacle to understanding the economy in early societies. Only by a radical separation of the economic process from the market complex was it possible to proceed. The conceptual separation of trade from market institutions which might otherwise have appeared as merely pedantic, if not artificial, was justified by the uncovering of the "port of trade," that almost universal precursor of modern organs of foreign trade. Equivalencies, again, those antecedents of "prices," only became visible against this background. Similarly, regarding the purely theoretical question of what is and what is not "economic," what is and what is not a "surplus," and what is and what is not "scarce," the role which the market played in the"evolution of our thinking emerged as the heart of the problem. Thus both in theory and in fact, detachment from the market context was the way to clarity. The exploring of new paths, the inevitable testing of new tools along the way, does not, of course, amount to a general theory of the interaction of economy and society. No more can be claimed here than an approach that may help to produce identifiable elements in economic institutions without regard to "economic" motives or "economic" rationality. Yet, by providing this precondition of comparative and developmental studies in this field, the threshold of much more comprehensive research in the social sciences may well have been reached. For in some such way, we believe, will be built up in due course the valid contents of the reality of society that is replacing in our day the fading image of an individualistic atomism. 3 r 7 Index of Authors Acosta Saignes, M., 147 Baden-Powel,B.H.,235 Bales, Robert F., 305 Benedict, Ruth, 345 Boas, Franz, 345 Boeke, Julius H., 353 Bücher, Karl, 3 ff, 15,241 Cary, Max, 63 Chappie, Eliot D., 100, 113 Childe, V. Gordon, 112, 322 Coon, Carleton S., 100,113 Davis, Kingsley, 304 Drucker, Peter, F., 341 DuBois, Cora, 337, 341, 346 Dürkheim, Emile, 100, 239 Dussaud, Ren£, 62 Engels, Friedrich, 328, 339 Finley, Moses I., 93, 341 Firth, Raymond, 335, 348, 352 ff Friedrich, Johannes, 62 Goodfellow, David M., 351 Götze, Albrecht, 62 Hasebroek, Johannes, 11 Hegel, Georg W. F., 70 Herskovits, Melville, 100, 270, 325-6, 341, 348 ff Hobbes, Thomas, 289 Homans, George C, 112 Hume, David, 270 Kirchhoff, Paul, 146 Knight, Frank H., 270, 340 , Koschaker, Paul, 15 Kroeber, Alfred L., 98 Landsberger, Benno, 17 Lehmann-Hartleben, Karl, 62 Lewy, Julius, 17 Locke, John, 331-2 Maclver, Robert M., 286 Mackenzie, Holt, 219-20 Maine, Sir Henry S., 69 ff, 219, 221, 239 Malinowski, Bronislaw, 70, 239, 245, 252, 341, 345 ff Marchai, Jean, 341 Marshall, Alfred, 244, 338, 340 Marx, Karl, 69, 227, 239, 305, 309, 333-4, 340, 355 Mauss, Marcel, 100, 355 Mead, Margaret, 72-3, 306,345 Menger, Karl, 244, 309 Merten, Robert K., 302 ff Meyer, Eduard, 3 ff Mill, John Stuart, 348 Moore, Wilbert, 304 Morgan, Lewis H., 227, 327-8 Nagel, Ernest, 305 Oertel, Friedrich, 3 ff 322, Olds, James, 302 Pareto, Vilfredo, 244, 309, 339 Parsons, Talcott, 244, 274 ff, 307-17 Pirenne, Henri, 259 375 376 Index of Authors Radin, Paul, 339 Ricardo, David, 64, 332 Robbins, Lionel, 270 "Robinson, Joan, 341 Rodbertus, Karl, 3 ff Rostovtzeff, Michael I., 3 ff Rousseau, Jean Jacques, 289 Roys, Ralph L., 147 Schaeffer, Claude, 62 Scholes, France V., 147 Schumpeter, Joseph, 93, 338, 340 Shils, Edward A., 205, 302 Smelser, Neil, 307 Smith, Adam, 64, 304, 331-2, 373 Sorokin, Pitrim A., 302 Spudek, C. Josef, 94 Spencer, Herbert, 287 Spengler, Joseph ]., 93, 340 Stem, BemardJ., 338 Tax,Sol, 348, 351-2 Thurnwald, Richard, 252, 341, 346 Tönnies, Ferdinand, 69 ff Turgot, Robert J., 331 Vehlen, Thorstein, 210, 322, 340 Weber, Max, 12, 15, 239, 244, 269, 281,293, 300,355 Wiles, Peter J. D., 341 Will, Eduard, 11 Woolley, Sir Charles Leonard, 62 Zelditchjr., Monis, 305 Znaniecki, Florian, 305 Index of Topics Action, as rational a., 85, 239, 243 ff, 246, 270 Allocation principle, as abstracting from the institutional complex in the economy, 291, 301, 343 Appropriational movements, as forming part of the economic process, 248 and gift-giving, 351 Atomistic view of society, 239, 276, 304 f (8), 320, 332, 374; see also surplus Auction, 14,268, 368 Awareness, of the existence of an economic sphere in society, 70,242; see also embeddedness Banking, pre-market b. as appearing in an inverted perspective, 14 (a) money changing, 14 (b) clearing in kind, 14, 263 Barter, facilitated through standard use of money, 14, 264 utilitarian b., 74 Brokerage, 14 Buffer areas, early b. created by tacit agreement or treaty, 52 Instances: Kizzuwatna, 2nd millennium, 48 ff, Mesoamerica, before the 1520ies, 116-7, 144 ff, 257 Whydah, before 1727,155 Cash and credit cash sales only permitted, 21,207 • Catallactic, as a view of the economy, i.e., as a system of exchange, 251, 269 catallactically, trade, money and market form an indivisible whole, 256-8 catallactic triad: trade-money-market, 245,257 Chieftain, 262; see also king's trade ch.'s confederacy: 'weak hands,' 104, 155 Choice, 246; see also scarcity operational ch.: a situationally given requirement of and attainment (crossroads); moral ch.: under a valuations! postulate; economic ch.: between alternative uses of insufficient means range of ch. in sociology and economics, 284 foundations of the theory of ch. are socially conditioned, 344, 347 Chrematistike, as the art of supply, 92 Coast and continent, 38 ff; see also port of trade Colonization, Instances: Greek (Asia Minor), 52 Phoenician (Syria), 39 Roman (W. Mediterranean), 61 'Columbian map,' its ambiguity, 313-6 Competition, pre-market c, 87 market c, 267 377 378 Contract, p. XI; see also status; transaction . c. society involves exchange institutions, 70 Cultural evolution, 109 ff Disposition, as one-sided action of an agent to which a definite appropri-ative effect attaches by force of law, 22 ff Division-of-labor definition of society, 276-9,313 Economic, see also sociology two meanings: substantive and formal, 243, 272 the substantive meaning given preference, 82, 100, 244, 273, 303, 318 compound concept in which the two meanings are merged, 243, 269 f (1), 303 great significance of the compound concept for sociological analysis, 244,274 ff, 309 ff substantive meaning, as referring to material want satisfaction, 243 ff, 248 ■ formal meaning, see economizing substantive and formal meanings coincident in regard to a market economy, 245, 315, 344 subsistence, 244 rationality, 239, 276, 309, 313, 347 institutions, as a concentration of e. activities, 249 motives, 343, 345 elements, as components of the e. process, 249 a type of action, 239 e. systems, in history, 254-5 Economic analysis, as the application of formal economics to situations of economic choice, 247 as a theory of prices, 247 Economic anthropology, p. X, 99, 342 ff Economic choice, see choice Economic organization, p. xviii theory of, 307 Economic process, a process of interaction between man and his natural and social environment, which re- Index of Topics suits in material want satisfaction, 248 locational and appropriative movements, 248, 294-6, 304 instituting of, 250, 295, 297 ff distinction between material and sociological aspects of, 294-6 combinational movement, as defining production, 248 embeddedness, as relating the economic to the non-economic sphere, 293, 302, 309 Economic sociology, 307, 313, 316 Economics, formal e., a branch of the logic of rational action, 245 restricted relevance to a centrally planned economy relying on non-market prices, 247 Economistes, 71; see also Physiocrats Economistic fallacy, 270, f.(l), 313 Economizing, as choice induced by scarcity situations, 238, 243, 274, 310 Economy, two meanings of e., the formal and the substantive, 243 formal meaning of e.: a sequence of acts of economizing, 247, 320 substantive economy as an instituted process of interaction between man and his environment which results in material want satisfaction, 248 as goods-handling and goods-receiving, p. XI market model view of e., 283 ff marketless e., p. XVII division-of-labor conception, 276-8 as a sphere of impersonal 'contractual' relations, 283 as value neutral sphere, 311 and state, as alternative orders, 286-7 defined through scarcity, 288 ff contrast between functionally defined and type of action defined e., 292, 308, 313 embedded in essentially non-economic institutions, 335; see also instituting compound concept, 272 rational action view of the e., 279 ff sociological theories of, 273 ff Index of Topics Economy (cont.) place of the e. in society, p. IX, 27, 250,270, 318, 354, 374 Embeddedness, see also institutionalization e. of economic elements in economic and noneconomic institutions, 71 e. as related to 'undifferentiated,' 306 f(29) anonymity of the economy in early society, 67 ff degree of e. dependent upon the level on which integration occurs, 298 Equivalencies, 262; see also price under different forms of integration, 269 various origins, 168, 208 complex units: sortings, proportions, 263 Instances: Dahomey, 208-9 Aztec, 27 Mesopotamia, 20, 269 Berber, 209 Greece: Solonic and Draconic census, 90-1 E. Mediterranean, 51-61 Ethnographic data, use made in interaction theory, p. XI Exchange, levels of, 254; see also transactions; equivalencies operationally defined (at uncertain rate), 304f(8), 366 decisional (at set rate), 254 integrative (at bargained rate), 255 Exchange or catallactic definitions, 266 of trade, 258 of money, 264 of markets, 266 Export, absence of e. interest, 258 collective e., 262 goods exported, 258 collecting of e. goods, 261 Farming out, see also taxation of taxes, 261 of market dues, 202 Fine, 264: see also payment Formal economics, as a branch of the logic of rational action, 245-6 379 Functional equivalents, 102, 109, 302 f(6) Gain, 255, 259; see also profit traders' g. embodied in imports, 86 decisional g. (made at set prices), 254-5 at uncertain rate, 366 Import, 262 necessaries of life, 262 changed into tribute, 261 distribution of import goods, 261 Instituting, 73, 105, 242, 248ff, 294 ff, 309, 339 Institutional analysis, 242, 248-50, 309 Institutionalist school, 310 Institutionalist "dilemma," 310, 317 Institutionalization, or instituting, 105, 248 • four levels of, 297-8, 303-4 economic process, 24, 295 embeddedness, 71,103, 299 Interaction theory, p. XI Interdisciplinary Project, at Columbia University, p. X, 29 Manor, see redistribution; oikos Market, 266; see also auction; market-trade; supply-demand meanings for the theorist and the historian, 365 ff catallactically, the m. is the locus of exchange, 257 substantive definition: meeting of a number of persons desirous of acquiring, and getting rid of, goods through acts of exchange, 267 price-making m., 244, 267, 358 ff, 371 as randomized action, p. XIII one-price m.: set-price m. and competitive m.s., 3 mechanism, 186, 359 visible m. (m. place), 267, 357 ff local food m. (cooked-food m.) 83-4, 177 ff m. economy as a self-regulating system of price-making m.s, 345, 358, 363-5 m. bias, 373 ownership of m., 199 farming out of m. dues, 261 380 Market (cont.) setting up of a m, 85 . types of markets: labor, 360; land, 361; capital, 361 organization: site or place, 369; goods present, 267; peace of the m., 198, 200,204,206 for specific goods: slaves, 87, 125; grain, 87 for complex services: transportation, 261; riskbearing, 261 Market institutions, 267 ff Market-trade, 83, 263 absence of market places in Mesopo- tamian cities, 31 Hellenic origins of m.-t. in Europe, 11,26,64-5 Material and nonmaterial means and ends, 245-6 Material want satisfaction: m. refers primarily to the means needed for the satisfying of the wants whatever these be, only secondarily to the wants satisfied, 248,250 Maximization principle, as separating out economic motives, 343 Means and ends distinction, 312-4 Metadosis; giving one's share, 93 Method, preference for operational definitions and quantitative descriptions, p. XI unhappy results of marriage of economic theory with anthropology, (M. Herskovits), 347-51 discontinuous evolution, 347 holistic aims, 347 economics of the market applied to a nonmarket institutional pattern (S. Tax), 351 rationalizing methods, 99 history and anthropology, 97 ff, 346 cross-cultural economics desirable, 344 Modernizing: 'a complete disregard for the essentials of the economics of the ancient great civilizations,' 29 ancient Greece, 3 ff inverted perspective, 13 ff Money, catallactic definition, 264 substantive definition: quantifiable objects employed in any of the following three uses: payment, Index of Topics standard, exchange, 263 specific m. objects employed in different m. uses, 266, 350 widely spread use of m. as a means of exchange and scarcity situations, 291-2 m. as generalized means of exchange, 291 m. of account (ideal units), 265 in relation to surplus, 335 modern multi-purpose m, 350 m. objects employed as an operational device, 265 Instances: gold dust (Ionia, 84; Nupe, 84; Aztec, 127), 266 cacao—Mesoamerica, 116 cowrie—Dahomey, 266 silver coins—Athens, 84 Oikos, 254 controversy, 3 ff, 13,64 Arist.Pol. Bk.: I, 67,81 Operational definitions of money uses, 263-5 insufficiency of means, 289 scarcity, 245, 288 economic choice, 246 redistribution, 223, 250-3 reciprocity, 222, 250—3 exchange, as a form of integration, 254 Patterns, alternative p. of organizing man's livelihood, 368 only a few general organizational p, p. XVII supporting structure p., 252 complex of 'interaction p.,' 100, 279 Payment, p. use of money, 264 staple finance and clearing of accounts, 264 Port of trade, an organ of administered trade, 115,154, 263, 374 political configuration of hinterland, 50, 54, 155 developmental features: silent trade, 52; neutral sanctuary, 154ff; treaty trade, 263; remote control, 59 ff, 162 ff; symbiosis, 55 ff food markets in ports of trade (Piraeus, Whydah), 177 ff Index of Topics Port of trade (cont.) warehouses, 262-3 Instances: Mesopotamia and Persian Gulf: numerous riverain kars, 30-1 Syria: Ugarit, Al Mina (3rd millennium), 53 ff Sidon, Tyre (2nd millennium), 5 5,58 ff Fy- Egypt: Naukratis, Alexandria 1st millennium), 61 Greece: Piraeus (5th century), 162 Mesoamerica: Acalan, Xicalango, Xoconusco, Gulf of Honduras, 114ff Guinea coast: Whydah, 154 ff Physiocrats, 330-1; see also surplus Prestige, 337, 346, 349 Price, 358 ff; see also equivalencies p. suggests fluctuation, while equivalency lacks this association, 268 p. system as layers of equivalencies that have historically developed, 269 Primitivism, 10,11,26,64-5 Production, 249 as defined through locational and combinational movements, respectively, 248 markets for factors of p, 360 Profit, see also surplus p. made on retailing, 84,92,259 p. made on price differentials, 83 p. made on turnover, 20-3 haggling on rate of profit, 262-3 Quantitativity necessaries possessing a quantitative connotation as with 'rations,' 74 no q, 74 Reciprocity, p. XI, 222, 250 ff, 371 symmetry, 250-1 gift-giving, 73-4,286,347 antipeponthos, phiha, 90, 253 reciprocative sequence, p. XI Instances: Berber: muna, 195; tawza, 216 f (61);twiza,216f(60) Greek: gift-giving, 90 Ancient Israel: exchange of equiva- 381 lents (Deut.), Trobriander patri-local chassez-croisez, 252,262 Mesopotamia, 29 Indian village castes, 225 Redistribution, p. XII, 250 ff, 371 centrality: 'centripetal movement of many upon one,' p. XII, 254 linked to reciprocity, 29,253-4 storage economies, 253-4 Instances: Egypt, 30 Mesopotamia, 29, 31, 254 Aztec (foreign imports), 126 Dahomey (foreign imports), 157 Berber: Makhzen, 190 Greece: oikus and polis, 78 Remote control, see port of trade Risk, no price r., 21 no r. of debtor's insolvency, 22 •Scarcity, s. as dependent upon social attitudes, 343 s. definition of the economy, 288 ff s. postulate, 246, 288-9, 319 f(8), 323 s. situations as inducing choices of a definite kind, 246, 291; see also choice Self-regulating market and market system; see market Separateness of trade and market-institutions, 86,115 Society, see also sociology s. as a system, 280-1, 309-10 s. and economic process, 294 ff s. as a system in equilibrium, 316-7 reality of s., 239, 308, 374 functional prerequisites (adaptation, integration, etc.), 281, 311-2 markets, 255 'orders of reality,' 276 Social arrangements, 99,102 Sociology, 271 ff, 307 ff Staple finance: the role of money objects as standards and equivalents, 265, 269 Status, see also transactions; traders s. traders, see traders s. transactions concerning persons may involve appropriational movements in regard to goods, 75 382 Index of Topics Status (cont.) economic transactions (e.g., in regard to land, slaves or cattle) may 'peel off* from s. transactions, 75-6 Storage economy, 31, 262; see also port of trade Instances: Mesopotamia, 31 Egypt, 30 Aztec: exports, 125 Subsistence, 80; see surplus Substantive economy, 240, 273, 302; see also economy Supportive structure patterns, symmetry, centrality, market, 257 ff Supply-demand-price mechanism, 86-7, 268, 358 ff widening of concept of supply from foods to persons, 268 t c market elements: supply crowds and demand crowds, 267 Surplus, naturalistic and social concept, 241, 333 definition of absolute and relative s. (physiological vs. cultural minimum), 32, 323 s. and the division of labor, 328-9 s. and the atomistic view of man, 332 institutional requirements of s.s, 335 ff, 339 s. as an economic aspect of institutional change, 334 ff s. as an alleged developmental law, 321 history of concept of s: Physiocrats, 329-30 parallelism of scarcity and surplus, 320-1 the institutionalization of surpluses, 339 Symbiosis, 55; see port of trade Taxation, in kind, 32 money as a standard, 265 equivalencies, 32 Technological progress, p. XVIII Technology, 81, 249, 261, 321, 326, 344, 354 trade, 257 ff forms of t: eift t, 262; administered TULIB t, 138 ff, 168, 262; market t, 263, 266 distinctions between t. and market institutions, p. X, 120,176-7 treaty t, 86-7,263 expeditionary raids, 41,45 discontinuity of ventures, 261 long distance t. often preceded t. over middle distances, 321 king's t., 120, 123, 143,258,262 'specificity' of archaic t. in regard to goods, 260 ff Instances: Greek: origins of market-t, 263 Aztec-Maya: long distance trade, 114ff Dahoman: t. through Whydah, 154 ff Berber: Kabyles, 207 Assyria: karum of Kanish, 17 ff Tyre: Ezek. XXVII, 265 E. Mediterranean, 55 ff Egypt, 43 ;. Trader, metic t, 2 59-60 » t. by status, 259 kapelos and emporos, 92—3 Instances: tamkarurn (Codex Hamurabi), 24, 298 pochteca (Aztec), 120 passim ppolom (Maya), 132 Trading peoples Instances: Acalan, 142 ff Phoenicians, 55 ff Rhodians, Gadensians, Jews and Levantines, Sudanese (Haussa, Mandingo, Duala), 260 Transactions, status t. vs. economic t., 65,69,75 gainful t. vs. exchange of equivalencies, 255 t. in regard to property, as against use, 6 individual vs. collective t, 75 Treaty trade, 262; see also trade Tribute replacing trade, 122 Utilitarian value scale, u. goods, 74, 77 u. necessaries, 78,80 u. philosophy, 81,28? A31379001927905B