Whar Urilirarianism Is include cheir I do nor, indeed, consider The creed which accepts as the foundadon ofmorals, Utility, or the Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure. To give a clear view of the moralstandard set up by the theory, much more requires to be said; in particular, what things it includes in the ideas of pain and pleasure; and to what extent this is felt an open question. But these supplementaryexplanations do not affect the theory of life on which this theory of morality is groundednamely, that and freedom from pain, are the only things desirable as ends; and that all desirable things (which are as numerous in the utilitarian as in any other scheme) are desirable either for the pleasure inherent in themselves, or as means to the promotion of and the prevention of pain. Now, such a theory of life excites in many minds, and among them in some of the most estimable in feeling and purpose, inveterate dislike. To suppose that life has (as they express it) no higher end than pleasure-no better and nobler object of desire and pursuit-they designate as utterly mean and grovelling: as a doctrine worthy only of swine, to whom the followers of Epicuruswere, at a very early period, contemptuouslylikened; and modem holders of the doctrineare occasionally made the subject of equally polite comparisons by its Geman, French, and English assailants. When thus attacked, the Epicureans have always answered, that it is not they, but their accusers, who represent human nature in a degrading light; since the accusation supposeshuman beings to be capable of no pleasures except those of which swine are capable. lf this supposition were true, the charge could not be gainsaid, but would then be no longer an imputation: for if the sources of pleasure were precisely the same to human beings and to swine, the rule of lifewhich is good enough for the one would be good enough for the other. The comparison of the Epicurean life to that of beasts is felt as degrading, precisely because a beasťs pleasures do not satisfy a human being's conceptions of happiness. Human beings have faculties more elevated than the animal appetites, and when once made conscious of them, do not regard anything as happiness which does not Source:JohnStuart Mill, Social Benefit. [he Epicureans to have been by any means faultless in drawing out cheir scheme of consequences from the utilitarian principle. To do this in any sufficient manner, many Stoic, as well as Christian elements require to be included. But there is no known Epicurean theory of life which does not assign to the pleasures of the intellect, of the feelings and imagination, and of the moral sentiments, a much higher value as ~leasuresthan to those of mere sensation. It must be admitted, however, that utilitarian writers in general have placed the superiorityof mental over bodily ~leasureschiefly in the greater permanency, safety, uncostliness, kc., of the former-that is, in their circumstantial advantages rather than in their intrinsic nature. And on all these points utilitarians have fully proved their case; but they might have taken the other, and, as it may be ci~lled,highe~ ground, with entire consistency. It is quitc compiltible with the principle of utility to recognise the fact, that some kinds of pltasure are more desirahlc and more valuable than others. It would be absurd that while, in estimating all other things, quality is considered as well as quantity, the estimation of pleasures should be supposed to depend on quantity alone. If I am asked, what I mean by difference of quality in pleasures, or what makes one pleasure more valuable than another, merely as a pleasure, except its being greater in amount, there is but one possible answer. Of two pleasures, if there be onc to which all or almost all who have experience of both give a decided preference, irrespective of any feeling of moral obligation to prefer it, that is the more desirable pleasure. If one of the two is, by those who are competently acquainted with both, placed so far above the other that they prefer it, even though knowing it to be attended with a greater amount of discontent, and would not resign it for any quantity of the other pleasure which their nature is capable of, we are justified in ascribing to the preferred enjoyment a superiority in quality, so far outweighing quantity as to render it, in comparison, of small ac- count. Now it is an unquestionable fact that those who are equally acquainted with, and equally capable of appreciating and enjoying, both, do give a most marked preference to the manner of existence which employstheir higher faculties. Few human creatures would consent to be changed into any of the lower animals, for a promise of the fullest allowance of a beasťs pleasures; no intelligent human being would consent to be a fool, no instructed person would be Určeno pouze pro studijní účely l ' . \ l ' - I ' I l l , N111111~~I S \ lillll,, an ignor;~m~~s,no pcrsun t r f fcc.ling i~ndconscience \vcl~~lJI~c'si.lfis11 i111dha~il,C\~CII though they should hc pcrsu;~~lcdth;~tihc fool, the dunce, or the rascal is better satisfied with his lot than they are with theirs. They would not resign what they possess more than he, for the most complete satisfaction of all the desires which they have in common with him. If they ever fancy they would, it is only in cases of unhappiness so extreme, that to escape from it they would exchange their lot for almost any other, however undesirable in their own eyes. A being of higher faculties requires more to make him happy, is capable probably of more acute suffering, and is certainly accessible to it at more points, than one of an inferior type; but in spite of these liabilities, he can never really wish to sink into what he feels to be a lower grade of existence. We may give what explanation we please of this unwillingness; we may attribute it to pridc, a llame which is given indiscriminately to some oľthe most and to some of the least estimable feelings of which mankind are capable; we may refer it to the love of liberty and personal independence, an appeal to which was with the Stoics one of the most effective means for the inculcation of it; to the love of power, or to the love of excitemcnt, both of which do really enter into and contribute to it: but its most appropriate appellation is a sense of dignity, which all hulnan beings possess in one for111 or another, and in some, though by no mearis in exact, proportion to their higher faculties, and which is so essential a part of the happiness of those in whom it is strong, that nothing which conflicts with it could he, othcrwise,than momentarily, an object of desire to them. Whoever supposes that this takes at a sacrifice of happiness-that the superior being, in anything like equal circumstances, is not happier than the inferior-confounds the two very different ideas, of happiness, and content. It is indisputable that the being whose capacities of enjoyment are low, has the greatest chance of having them fullysatisfied; and a highly-endowed being will always feel that ~ n yhappiness which he can look for, as the world is constituted, is imperfect. Rut he can learn to bear its imperfections, if they are at all bearable; and they will not make him envy the being who is indeed unconscious of the imperfections, hut only because he feels not at a11 the good wh~chthose imperfections qualify. It is better to be a human being dissntistied than a pig satisficcl; hetter tu bc Socrates dissatisfied than a fool satisticd. And if the fool, or the pig, is of a different opinion, it is becausc thev only know their ou.n side of the question. The other parry ro the con~parisunknows both sides. It may be objected, that many who are capable of the higher pleasures, occasionally, under the influence of temptation, postpone them to the lower. But this is quite compatible with a full appreciation of the intrinsic superiority of the higher. Men often, from infirmity of character, make their election for the nearer good, though they know it to be the less valuable; and this no less when the choice is between two bodily pleasures, than when it is between bodily and mental. They pursue sensual indulgences to the injury of health, though perfectly aware that health is the greater good. It may be further objected, that many who begin with youthful enthusiasm for everything noble, as they advance in years sink into indolence and selfishness. But I do not believe that those who undergo this very common change, voluntarily choose the lower description of pleasures in to the higher. I believe that before they devote themselves exclusively to the one, they have already become incapable of the other. Capacity for the nobler feelings is in most natures a very tender plant, easily killed, not only by hostile influences, but by mere want of sustenance; and in the majority of young persons it speedily dies away if the occupations to which their position in life has devoted them, and the society into which it has thrown them, are not favourable to keeping that higher capacity in exercise. Men lose their high aspirations as they lose their intellectual tastes, because they have not time or opportunity for indulging them; and they addict themselves to inferior pleasu~its,nut because they deliberately prefer them, but because they are either the only ones to which they have access, or the only ones which they are any longer capable of enjoying. It may be questioned whether any one who has remained equally susceptible to both classes of pleasures, ever knowingly and caltnly preferred the lower; though many, in all ages, have broken down in an ineffectual attempt to combine both. From this verdict of the only competent judges, I apprehend there can be no appeal. O n a question which is the best worth having of two pleasures, or which of two modes of existence is the most grateful to the feelings, apart from its moral attributes and from its consequences, the judgment of those who are qualified by knowledge of both, or, if they differ, that of the majority among them, must be admitted as final. And there needs be the less hesitation to accept this judgment respecting the quality of pleasures, since there is no other tribunal to be referred to even on the question of quantity. What means are therc of determining which is the acutest of two piiins, or the intensest of two pleasurable sensations, Určeno pouze pro studijní účely ,..~cpt the general suffrageof those who are familiar both? Neither pains nor pleasures are homogeneous, and pain is always heterogeneous with pleasure. What is there to decide whether a particular is worth purchasingat the cost ofa particularpain, except the feelings and judgment of the experienced?When, therefore, those feelings and jLlJsnlent declare the pleasures derived from the higher faculties to be preferable in kind, apart from the cluestion of intensity, to those of which the animalnature, disjoined from the higher faculties, is susceptible, they are entitled on this subject to the same regard. I have dwelt on this point, as being a necessary part of a perfectly just conception of Utility or Happiness, considered as the directive rule of human But it is by no means an indispensable condition to the acceptance of the utilitarian standard;forthat standard is not the agenťs own greatest happiness, but the greatest amount of happiness altogether; and if it may possibly be doubted whether a noble character is always the happier for its nobleness, there can be no doubt that it makes other peuPle happier, and that the world in general is imlnensely a gainer by it. Utilitarianism, therefore, could only attain its end by the general cultivation of nobleness of character, even if each individual were only benefitted by the nobleness of others, and his own, so far as happiness is concerned, were a sheer deduction from the benefit. But the bare enunciation of such an absurdityas this last, renders refutation superfluous. According to the Greatest Happiness Principle, ils above explained,the ultimate end, with reference to and for the sake of which all other things are desirable (whetherwe are considering our own good or that of other people), is an existence exempt as far as possible from pain, and as rich as possible in enjoyments, both in point of quantity and quality; the test of quality, and the rule for measuring it against quantity, being the reference felt by those who, in their opportunities of experience, to which must be added their habits of self-consciousness and selfobservation, are best furnished with the means of comparison. This, being, according to the utilitarian opinion, the end of human action, is necessarily also the standard of morality; which may accordingly be defined,the rules and precepts for human conduct, by the observance of which an existence such as has been described might be, to the greatest extent possible~secured to all mankind, and not to them only, so faras the nature of things admits, to the whole Sentientcreation. Against the doctrine, hnwcvcr, riscs another class of objectors, who say that happiness, in any form, cannot be the rational purpose of human life and action; because, in the first place, it is unattainable: and they contemptuously ask, What right hast thou to be happy? a question which Mr. Carlyle clenches by the addition, What right, a short time ago, hadst thou even to be? Next, they say, that men can do witl~outhappiness; that all noble human beings have felt this, and could not have become noble but by learning the lesson of Entsagen, or renunciation; which lesson, thoroughly learnt and submitted to, they affirm to be the heginning and necessary condition of all virtue. The first of these objections would go to the root of the matter were it well founded; for if no happiness is to be had at all by human beings, the attainment of it cannot be the end of morality, or of any rational conduct. Though, even in that case, something might still be said for the utilitarian theory; since utility includes not solely the pursuit of happiness, but the prevention or mitigation of unhappiness; and if the former aim be chimerical, there will be all the greater scope and more imperativeneed for the latter, so long at least as mankind think fit to live, and do not take refuge in the simultaneous act of suicide recommended under certain conditions by Novalis. When, however, it is thus positively asserted to be impossible that human life should be happy, the assertion, if not something like verbal quibble, is at least an exaggeration. If by happiness be meant a continuity of highly pleasurable excitement, it is evident enough that this is impossible. A state of exalted last only moments, or in some cases; and with some intermissions, hours or days, and is the occasional brilliant flash of enjoyment, not its permanent and steady flame. Of this the philosophers who have taught that happiness is the end of life were as fully aware as those who taunt them. The happiness which they meant was not a life of rapture; but moments of such, in an existence made up of few and transitory pains, many and various pleasures, with a decided predominance of the active over the passive, and having as the foundation of the whole, not to expect more from life than it is capable of bestowing. A life thus composed, to those who have been fortunate enough to obtain it, has always appeared worthy of the name of happiness. And such an existence is even now the lot of many, during some considerable portion of their lives. The present wretched education, and wretched social arrangements, are the only real hindrance to its being attainable by almost all. Určeno pouze pro studijní účely The objectors perhaps may doubt whether human beings, if taught to consider happiness as the end of life, would be satisfied with such a moderate share of it. But great numbers of mankind have been satisfied with much less. The main constituents of a satisfied life appear to be two, either of which by itself is often found sufficient for the purpose: tranquillity, and excitement. With much tranquillity, many find that they can be content with very little pleasure: with much excitement, many can reconcile themselves to a considerable quantity of pain. There is assuredly no inherent impossibility in enabling even the mass of mankind to unite both; since the two are so far from being incompatible that they are in natural alliance, the prolongation of either being a preparation for, and exciting a wish for, the other. It is only those in whom indolence amounts to a vice, that do not desire excitement after a n interval of repose; it is only those in whom the need of excitement is a disease, that feel the tranquillity which follows excitement dull and insipid, instead of pleasurable in direct proportion to the excitement which preceded it. When people who are tolerably fortunate in their outward lot do not find in life sufficient enjoyment to make it valuable to them, the cause generally is, caring for nobody but themselves. To those who have neither public nor private affections, the excitements of life are much curtailed, and in any case dwindle in value as the time approaches when all selfish interests must be terminated by death: while those who leave after them objects of personal affection, and especially those who have also cultivated a fellow-feeling with the collective interests of mankind, retain as lively an interest in life o n the eve of death as in the vigour of youth and health. Next to selfishness, the principal cause which makes life unsatisfactory, is want of mental cultivation. A cultivated mind-I do not mean that of a philosopher, but any mind to which the foundations of knowledge have been opened, and which has been taught, in any tolerable degree, to exercise its faculties-finds sources of inexhaustible interest in all that surrounds it; in the objects of nature, the achievements of art, the imaginarions of poetry, the incidents of history, the ways of mankind past and present, and their prospects in the future. It is possible, indeed, to become indifferent to all this, and that too without having exhausted a thousandth part of it; hut only when one has had from the beginning no moral or human interest in these things and has sought in them only the gratification of curiosity. Now there is absolutely no reason in the nature of things why an amount of mental culture sufficient to gi\,can intclligcnt intvrcst in tlicsc ul?jccts of contemplation, . s h ~ ) u l ~ inot bc ~ h cinheritance of everyune born in a civilisect country. As littlc is there an inherent necessity that any human being should be .a selfish egotist, devoid of evcry fecling or care but those which centre in this own miscrilble individuality. Something far superior to this is sufficiently common even now, to give ample earnest of what the human species may be made. Genuine private affections, and a sincere interest in the public good, are possible, though in unequal degrees, to every rightly brought up hurlian being. In a world in which there is so much to interest, so much to enjoy, and so much also to correct and improve, everyone who has this moderate amount of moral and intellectual requisires is capable of an exisrence which may be called enviable, and unless such a person, through bad laws, or subjection to the will of others, is denied the liberty to use the sources of happiness within his reach, he will not fail to find this enviable existence, if he escape the positive evils of life, the great sources of physical and mental suffering-such as indigence, disease, and the unkindness, worthlessness, or premature loss of objects of affection. The main stress of the problem lies, therefore, in the contest with these calamities, from which it is a rare good fortune entirely to escape; which, as things now are cannot be obviated, and often cannot be in any material degree mitigated. Yet no one whose opinion descrvcs a ll-romenťs consideration can doubt that ~uostof the great positive evils of the worlcl are in themselves removable, and will, if human affairs continue to improve, be in the end reduced within narrow limits. Poverty, in any sense implying suffering, may be completely extinguished by the wisdom of society, combined with the good sense and providence of individuals. Evcn that most intractable of enemies, disease, may be indefinitely reduced in dinlensions by good physical and morn1 education, and proper control of noxiclus influences; while the progress of science holds out a promise for the future of still more direct conquests over this derestable fc>e.And every ad:':,nce in that dircction relieves us from some, not only of the chances which cut short our own lives, but, what conurns us still more, which deprive us of those in whonl our happiness is wrapt up. As for vicissitc~dcsof fo~tune,and other disappointments connected with worldly circumstances, these are principally the effect either of gross imprudence, of ill-regulated desires, or of bad or imperfect social instirutions. All the grand sources, in shalt, of human suffering are in a great degree, Illany of them almost entirely, conquerable by human Určeno pouze pro studijní účely ,-ilce and effort; and though their removal is grie\-- ,usly slow-though a long succession of generations will perish in the breach before the conquest is completed, and this world becomes all that, if will and knowledge were not wanting, it might easily be rnade-yet every mind sufficiently intelligent and gellerous to bear a part, however small and inconspicuous,in the endeavour, will draw a noble enjoyment from the contest itself, which he would not for any bribe in the form of selfish indulgence consent to be without. And this leads to the true estimation of what is said by the objectors concerning the possibility and the obligation, of learning to do without happiness. unquestionably it is possible to do without happiness. It is done involuntarily by nineteen-twentieths of mankind, even in those parts of our present world which are least deep in barbarism; and it often has to be done voluntarily by the hero or the martyr, for the sake of something which he prizes more than his individual happiness. But this something, what is it, unless the happiness of others, or some of the requisites of happiness? It is noble to be capable of resigning entirely one's own portion of happiness or chances of it, but after all, this self-sacrificemust be forsomeend. It is not its own end; and if we are told that its end is not happiness but virtue, which is better than happiness, I ask, would the sacrifice be made if the hero or martyr did not believe that it would earn for others immunity from similar sacrifices?Would it be made if he thought that his renunciation of happiness for himself would produce no fruit for any of his fellow creatures, but to make their lot like his, and place them also in the condition of persons who have renounced happiness? All honor to those who can abnegate for themselves the personal enjoyment of life, when by such renunciation they contribute worthily to increase the amount of happiness in the world; but he who does it, or professes to do it, for any other purpose is no more deserving of admiration than the ascetic mounted on his pillar. He may be an inspiriting proof of what men can do, but assuredly not an example of what they should. Though it is only in a very imperfect state of the worlďs arrangements that anyone can best serve the happiness of others by the absolute sacrifice of his own, yet so long as the world is in that imperfect state, I fully acknowledge that the readiness to make such a sacrifice is the highest virtue which can be found in man. I will add that in this condition of the world, paradoxical as the assertion may be, the cQnsciousability to do without happiness gives the best prospect of realizing such happiness as is attainable. For nothing except that consciousness can raise a person above the chances of life, by making hinl feel that, let fate and fortune do their worst, they have no power to subdue him, which, once felt, frees him from excess of anxiety concerning the evils of life and enables him, like many a Stoic in the worst times of the Roman Empire, to cultivate in tranquillity the sources of satisfaction accessible to him without concerning himself about the uncertainty of their duration any more than about their inevitable end. Meanwhile, let us utilitarians never cease to claim the morality of self devotion as a possession which belongs by as good a right to them as either to the Stoic or to the Transcendentalist. The utilitarian morality does recognize in human beings the power of sacrificing their own greatest good for the good of others. It only refuses to admit that the sacrifice is itself a good. A sacrifice which does not increase, or tend to increase, the sum total of happiness, it considers as wasted. The only self-renunciation which it applauds is devotion to the happiness, or to some of the means of happiness,of others-either of mankind collectively or of individuals within the limits imposed by the collective interests of man- kind. I must again repeat what the assailants of utilitarianism seldom have the justice to acknowledge, that the happiness which forms the utilitarian standard of what is right in conduct is not the agenťs own happiness but that of all concerned. As between his own happiness and that of others, utilitarianism requires him to be as strictly impartial as a disinterested and benevolent spectator. In the golden rule of Jesus of Nazareth, we read the complete spirit of the ethics of utility. To do as you would be done by and to love your neighbour as yourself constitute the ideal perfection of utilitarian morality. As the means of first making the nearest approach to this ideal, utility would enjoin, first, that laws and social arrangements should place the happiness or (as speaking practically it may be called) the interest of every individual as nearly as possible in harmony with the interest of the whole and, secondly, that education and opinion, which have so vast a power over human character, should so use that power as to establish in the mind of every individual an indissoluble associationbetween his own happiness and the good of the whole-especially between his own happiness and the practice of such modes of conduct, negative and positive, as regard for the universal happiness prescribes-so that not only he may be unable to conceive the possibility of Určeno pouze pro studijní účely happiness to hirnsclf cons is^ c111:Iy\vitl) CLIIIJULI.017posed to the gcnor:11good, h t ~ t;~lsnthat a dircct ilnpulse to promote the gcncral gc~oclm;iy be in ellcry individual one of the habitui~lsnotivcs uf acrion i~nd the sentiments connected herewith may fill a largc and prominent place in every human being's sentient existence. If the impugners of the utilitarian morality represented it to their own minds in this its true character, I know not what recommendation possessed by any other morality they could possihly affirm to be wanting to it, what more beautiful or more exalted developments of human nature any other ethical system can be supposed to foster, or what springs of action, not accessible to the utilitarian, such systems rely on for giving effect to their mandates. The objectors to utilitarianism cannot always be charged with representing it in a discreditable light. O n the contrary, those among them who entertain anythinglike a just idea of its disinterested character sometimes find fault with its standard as being too high for humanity.They say it is exacting too much to require that people shall always act from the inducement of promoting the general interests of society. But this is to mistake the very meaning of a standard of morals and confound the rule of action with the motive of it. It is the business of ethics to tell us what are our duties or by what tests we may know them, but no system of cthics requires that the sole motive of all we do shall he a feeling of duty; on the contrary, ninety-ninc hundredths of all our actions are done from other motives, and rightly so done, if thc rule of duty does not condemn them. It is the more unjust to utilitarianisrn that this particular rnisapprehcnsion should be made a ground of objection to it, inasnluch as utilitarian moralists have gone beyond almost all others in affirming that the motive has nothing to do with the morality of the action, though much with the worth of the agent. He who saves a fellow creature from drowning does what is morally right, whethcr his motive be duty or the hope of being paid for his trouble; he who betrays the friend that trusts him i s guilty of a crimp, even if his object be to serve another friend to whom he is under greater obligations. But to speak only of actions done from the motive of duty and in direct obedience to principle, it is a misapprehension of the utilitarian mode of thought to conceive it as implying that people should 6s their minds upon so wide a generality as the world, or society at large. The great majority of good actions are intended not for the benefit of the world hut tor that of individuals, of which the good of the \vorld is made up; and the thoughts of rhr most virtuo~~sman nced not on thcsc occasions travcl beyond ~ h cparticular persons concerned, cxcept so far as is necessary to assure himself that in benefiting them he is not violating the rights, that is, thc lcgitimate and authorized expectations, of anyone clse. The multiplication of happiness is, according to the utilitarian ethics, the object of virtue. The occasion on which any person (except one in a thousand) has it in his power to do this on an extended scale-in other words, to be a publicbenefactor-are but exceptional, and on these occasions alone is he called on to consider public utility; in every other case, private utility, the interest or happiness of some few persons, is all he has to attend to. Those alone the influence of whose actions extends to society in general need concern themselves habitually about so large an object. In the case of abstinences indeed-of things which people forbear to do from moral considerations, though the consequencesin the particular case might be beneficial-it would be unworthy of an intelligent agent not to be consciously aware that the action is of a classwhich, ifpractised generally,would be generallyinjurious and that this is the ground of the obligation to abstain from it. The amount of regard for the public interest implied in this recognition is no grcaterthan is demanded by every system of morals, for they all enjoin to abstain from whatever is manifestly pernicious to society. The same considerations dispose of another reproach against the doctrine of utility, founded on a still grosser misconception of the purpose of a standard of morality and of the very meaning of the words right and wrong. It is often affirmed that utilitarianism renders men cold and unsympathizing; that it chills their moral feelingstowards individuals; that it makes them regard only the dry and hard consideration of the consequences of actions, not taking into their moral estimate the qualities from which those actions emanate. If the assertion means that they do not allow their judgment respecting the rightness or wrongness of an action to be influenced by their opinion of the qualities of the person who does it, this is a csrnplaint not against utilitarianism but against having any standard of morality at all; for certainly no known ethical standard decides an action to be good or bad because it is done by a good or had man, still less because done by an amiable, a brave, or a benevolent man, or the contrary. These considerations are relevant not to the estimation of actions but of persons; and there is nothing in the utilitarian theory inconsistent with the fact that there are other things which interest us in persons besides the rightness and wrongness of their actions. The Stoics, indeed, with the paradoxical misuse of langcnge {yhichv::~ pait of thcir system and by which Určeno pouze pro studijní účely rhcy srrrwc tu raiw thcnisclvcs above all concern world by utilitarianism, while that doctrine docs ; I \ ~ O L I ~ilnyrllirlg but \,irtuc, \\.ere fond of saying that supply, if not always an easy, at all events a tangible hc who has hat has cvcryrhing, that he, and only and intelligible mode of deciding such differences. hc, is rich, is bcautihl, is u king. But no claim ofthis clcscription is made for the virtuous man by the utilirilrian cloctrins. Utilitarians arc quite aware that tl~creilrc othcr Jcsirahlc possessions and qualities besides virtue and are perfectlywilling to allow to all them their full worth. They are also aware that a right action does not necessarily indicate a virtuous character and that actions which are blamable often pl(lceeJ, frum qualities cn&d to praise. When this is apparent in any particular case, it modifies their estimation, not certainly of the act but of the agent. I grant that they are, notwithstanding, of the opinion that in the long run the hest proof of a good charxccer is good actions and resolutely refuse to consider any mental disposition as good of which the predominant tendency is to produce bad conduct. This makes them unpopular with many people; but it is an unpopularity which they must share with cvcryone who regards the distinction between right and wrong in a serious light, and the reproach is not onc which a conscientious utilitarian need be anxious to repel. If no more be meant by the objection than that many utilitarians look on the morality of actions, as measured by the utilitarian standards, with too exclusive a regard and do not lay sufficient stress upon the other beauties of character which go towards making a human being lovable or admirable, this may be admitted. Utilitarians who have cultivated their moral feelings but not their sympathies nor their artistic perceptions do fall into this mistake; and so do all other moralists under the same conditions. What can be said in excuse for other moralists is equally available for them-namely, that, if there is to be any error, it is better that it should be on that side. As a matter of fact, we may affirm among utilitarians, as among adherents of other systems, there is every imaginable degree of rigidity and of laxity in the application of their standard: some are even puritanically rigorous, while others are as indulgent as can possibly be desired by sinner or by sentimentalist. But on the whole, a doctrine which brings prominently forward the interest that mankind have in the repression and prevention of conduct which violates the moral law, is likely to be inferior to no other in Kurning the sanctions of opinion against such violations. It is true, the question, What does violate the moral law? is one on which those who recognize different standards of morality are likely now and then to differ. But differenceof opinion on moral questions was not first introduced into the Určeno pouze pro studijní účely