1 Tazenbach: In years to come, you say, life on earth be mar- Defmitions vellous, beautiful. That's true. But to take Part in that now, even from afar, one must prepare, one must work - . yes,one must work. Perhaps you think - this German is getting Nationalism is primarily a political principle, which holds that the over-excited.~~t on my word of honour, I'm Russian. I cannot even political and the national unit should be congruent. speak German. My father is Orthodox - - Nationalismas a sentiment, or as a movement, can best be defined / in terms of this principle. Nationalist sentimentis the feelingof anger Anton Chekhov, Three Sisters aroused by the violationof the principle, or thefeeling of satisfaction aroused by its fulfient. A nationalist m o v m t is one acmated by a politikn rids byla vzak ,spire me'nt? smBlejzifomo~kultury- sentiment of this kind. (ourpolitics however was a rather less daring form of culture.) There is a variety of ways in which the nationalist principlecan be J. SlgdeEek, OsmajedesLit$ ('68), Index, K o ~ ~ Y1 9 8 0 ~ violated. The political boundaryof a given state can fail to includeall (wri=en under this pen name by Petr Pithart, sub- themembersof the appropriate nation; or it can include them all but sequentlyprime minister of the Czech lands, and alsoincludesome foreigners; or it canfail in both these ways at once, previously circulated in samizdat in Prague). not incorporating all the nationals and yet also including some nonnationals. Or again, a nation may live, unmixed with foreigners, in a ournationaliry is like our relations to women: too implicated in Our multiplicity of states, SO that no single state can claim to be the national one. moral nature to be changed honourably, and too accidental be But there is one particular form of the violation of the nationalist worth changing. principle to which nationalist sentiment is quite particularly sensiGeorge Santayana tive: if the rulers of the political unit belong to a nation other than that of the majority of the ruled, this, for nationalists, constitutes a quite outstandingly intolerable breech of political propriety. This can occur either through the incorporation of the national territory in a larger empire, or by the local domination of an alien group. In brief, nationalism is a theory of political legitimacy, which requires that ethnic boundaries should not cut across political ones, and, in parricular, that ethnic boundaries within a given state - a contingency already formallyexcludedby the principlein its general formulation- should not separate the power-holdersfrom the rest. The nationalist principle can be asserted in an ethical, 'universdistic' spirit. There could be, and on occasion there have been, nationalists-in-the-abstract,unbiassedinfavourofanyspecialnationality of their own, and generously preaching the docvine for all nationsalike: let all nations have their own politicalroofs, and let all 2 DEFINITIONS of them also refrain from including non-nationals under it. There is no formal contradiction in asserting such non-egoistic nationalism. As a doctrineit can be supported by some good arguments, such as the desirability of preserving cultural diversity, of a pluralistic international political system, and of the diminution of internal strains within states. In fact, however, nationalism has often not been so sweetly reasonable, nor so rationally symmetrical. It may be that, as Immanuel Kant believed, partiality, the tendency to make exceptions on one's own behalf or one's own case, is the central human weakness from which all others flow; and that it infects national sentiment as it does all else, engendering what the Italians under Mussolinicalled the sacro egoismo of nationalism. It may also be that the political effectiveness of national sentiment would be much impaired if nationalists had as fine a sensibility to the wrongs committed by their nation as they have to those committed against it. But over and above these considerations there are others, tied to the specificnature of the world we happen to live in, which militate against any impartial, general, sweetly reasonable nationalism. To put it in the simplest possible terms: there is a very large number of potential nations on earth. Our planet also contains room for a certain number of independent or autonomous political units. On any reasonablecalculation, the former number (of potential nations) is probably much, much larger than that of possible viable states. If this argument or calculation is correct, not all nationalisms can be satisfied, at any rate at the same time. The satisfactionof somespells thefrustration of others. This argument is further and immeasurably strengthened by the fact that very many of the potential nations of this world live, or u n d recently havelived, not in compactterritorial units but internnixedwith each other in complex patterns. It follows that a territorial political unit can only become ethnically homogeneous, in such cases, if it either kills, or expels, or assimilates all non-nationals. Their unwillingnessto suffersuchfatesmay make the peaceful implementation of the nationalist principle difficult. These definitions must, of course, like most definitions, be applied with common sense. The nationalist principle, as defined, is not violated by the presence of small numbers of residentforeigners, or even by the presence of the occasional foreigner in, say, a national rulingfamily. Just how many residentforeignersor foreignmembers of the ruling class there must be before the principle is effectively DEFINITIONS 3 violated cannot be stated with precision. There is no sacred percentagefigure, below which the foreigner can be benignly tolerated, and above which he becomes offensiveand his safety and life are at peril. No doubt the figurewill vary with circumstances. The impossibility of providing a generally applicable and precise figure, however, does not undermine the usefulness of the defmition. State and nation Our defmition of nationalism was parasiticl on two as yet undefined terms: state and nation. Discussion of the state may begin with Max Weber's celebrated definition of it, as that agency within society which possesses the monopoly of legitimate violence. The idea behind this is simple and seductive: in- well-ordefed~societies, such as most of us live in or aspire to live in, private or sectional violence is illegitimate. Conflict as such is not illegitimate, but it cannot rightfully be resolved by private or sectional violence. Violence may be applied only by the central politicalauthority, and those to whom it delegates this right. Among the various sanctions of the maintenance of order, the ultimateone-force-may be applied only by one special, clearly identified, and well centralized, disciplined agency within society. That agency or group of agencies is the state. The idea enshrined in this defintion correspondsfairly well with the moral intuitions of many, probably most, members of modern societies. Nevertheless, it is not entirely satisfactory. There are 'states' - or, at any rate, institutions which we would normally be inclined to call by that name - which do not monopolizelegitimate violence within the territory which they more or less effectively control. A feudal state does not necessarily object to private wars between its fief-holders, provided they also M1 their obligations to their overlord; or again, a state countingtribal populationsamongits subjects does not necessarily object to the institution of the feud, as long as those who indulge in it refrainfrom endangering neutrals on the public highway or in the market. The Iraqi state, under British tutelage after the First World War, tolerated tribal raids, provided the raiders dudfully reported at the nearest police station beforeand after the expedition, leaving an orderly bureaucratic record of slain and booty. In brief, there are states which lack either the will or the 4 DEFINITIONS means to enforce their monopoly of legitimate violence, and which nonetheless remain, in many respects, recognizable 'states'. Weber's underlying principle does, however, seem valid now, however strangely ethnocentric it may be as a general defition, with its tacit assumption of the well-centralizedWestern state. The state constitutes one highly distinctiveand important elaboration of the social division of labour. Where there is no division of labour, one cannot even begin to speak of the state. But not any or every specialism makes a state: the state is the specialization and concentration of order maintenance. The 'state' is that institution or set of institutions specifically concerned with the enforcement of order I (whatever else they may also be concerned with). The state exists where specialized order-enforcing agencies, such as policeforces and courts, have separated out from the rest of social life. They are the state. Not all societies arestate-endowed. It immediatelyfollowsthat the problem of nationalism does not arise for stateless societies. If there is no state, one obviously cannot ask whether or not its boundaries are congruent with the limits of nations. If there are no rulers, there being no state, one cannot ask whether they are of the same nation as the ruled. When neither state nor rulers exist, one cannot resent their failure to conform to the requirements of the principle of nationalism. One may perhaps deplore statelessness, but that is another matter. Nationalists have generally fulminated against the distribution of political power and the nature of politicalboundaries, but they have seldom if ever had occasion to deplore the absence of power and of boundaries altogether. The circumstances in which nationalism has generally arisen have not normally been those in which the state itself, as such, was lacking, or when its realitywasin any serious doubt. The state was only too conspicuously present. It was its boundaries a d o r the distribution of power, and possiblyof other advantages, within it which were resented. This in itself is highly significant. Not only is our defmition of nationalism parasitic on a prior and assumed definition of the state: it also seems to be the case that nationalism emerges only in milieux in which the existence of the state is already very much taken for granted. The existence of politically centralized units, and of a moral-politicalclimate in which such centralized units are taken for granted and are treated as normative, is a necessary though by no means a sufficient condition of nationalism. By way of anticipation, some general historical observations should be made about the state. Mankind has passed through three fundamentalstages in its history: the pre-agrarian, the agrarian, and the industrial. Hunting and gathering bands were and are too small to allow the kind of political division of labour which constitutes the state; and so, for them, the question of the state, of a stable specialized order-enforcing institution, does not really arise. By contrast, most, but by no means all, agrarian societies have been stateendowed. Some of these states have been strong and some weak, some have been despoticand others law-abiding. They differ a very great deal in their form. The agrarian phase of human history is the periodduring which, so to speak, the very existenceof the state is an option. Moreover, the form of the stdte is highly variable. During the hunting-gathering stage, the option was not available. By contrast, in the post-agrarian, industrial age there is, once again, no option; but now the presence, not the absenceof the state is inescapable. ParaphrasingHegel, once none had the state, then some had it, and finally all have it. The form it takes, of course, still remains variable. There are some traditions of social thought anarchism, Marxism - which hold that even, or especially, in an industrial order the state is dispensable, at least under favourable conditions or under conditions due to be realized in the fullness of time. There are obvious and powerful reasons for doubting this: industrial societies are enormously large, and depend for the standard of living to which they have become accustomed (or to which they ardently wish to become accustomed) on an unbelievablyintricate general division of labour and co-operation. Some of this cooperation might under favourable conditions be spontaneous and need no central sanctions. The idea that all of it could perpetually work in this way, that it could exist without any enforcement and control, puts an intolerable strain on one's credulity. So the problem of nationalism does not arise when there is no state. It does not follow that the problem of nationalism arises for eachand everystate. On the contrary, it arisesonly for some states. It remains to be seen which ones do face this problem. 1 $ The defmition of the nation presents difficulties graver than those \ attendanton the defmitionof the state. Although modern man tends j: Y fi ; 6 DEFINITIONS to take the centralized state (and, more specifically, the centralized national state)for granted, nevertheless he is capable, with relatively little effort, of seeingits contingency, and of imagining a social situation in which the state is absent. He is quite adept at visualizing the 'state of nature7 . Ananthropologistcanexplaintohimthat the tribe is not necessarily a state writ small, and that forms of tribal organization exist which can be describedas stateless. By contrast, the idea of a man without a nation seems to imposea far greater strain on the modem imagination. Chamisso, an emigre'Frenchman in Germany during the Napoleonic period, wrote a powerful proto-Kafkaesque novel about a man who lost his shadow: though no doubt part of the effectiveness of this novel hinges on the intended ambiguity of the parable, it is difficult not to suspect that, for the author, the Man without a Shadow was the Man without a Nation. When his followers and acquaintances detect his aberrant shadowlessness they shun the otherwisewell-endowedPeter Schlemiehl.A man without a nation defies the recognized categories and provokes revulsion. Chamisso's perception - if indeed this is what he intended to convey - was valid enough, but valid only for one kind of human condition, and not for the human condition as such anywhere at any time. A man must have a nationality as he must have a nose and two ears; a deficiency iuany of these particularsis not inconceivableand does from time to time occur, but only as a result of some disaster, and it is itself a disaster of a kind. All this seems obvious, though, alas, it is not true. But that it should have come to seem so very obviously true is indeed an aspect, or perhaps the very core, of the problem of nationalism. Having a nation is not an inherent attribute of humanity, but it has now come to appear as such. In fact, nations, like states, are a contingency, and not a universal necessity. Neither nations nor states exist at all times and in all circumstances. Moreover, nations and states are not the same contingency. Nationalism holds that they were destined for each other; that either without the other is incomplete, and constitutes a tragedy. But before they could become intended for each other, each of them had to emerge, and their emergence was independent and contingent. The state has certainly emerged without the help of the nation. Some nations have certainly emerged without the blessings , of their own state. It is more debatablewhether the normativeidea of the nation, in its modern sense, did not presuppose the prior exis- ' tence of the state. I What then is this contingent, but in our age seemingly universal and normative, idea of the nation? Discussionof two very makeshift, temporary definitions will help to pinpoint this elusive concept. 1 Two men are of the same nation if and only if they share the same culture, where culture in turn means a system of ideas and sfgns-andassociations and ways of behaving and communicating. + 2 Two men are of the same nation if and only if they recognize _, each other as belonging to the same nation. In other words, nations maketh man; nations are the artefactsof men's convictionsand loyal- ' ties and solidarities. A mere category of persons (say, occupants of a given territory, or speakers of a given language, for example) becomes a nation if and when the members of the category f d y recognize certain mutual rights andlduties to each other in virtue of their shared membershipof it. It is their recognitionof each other as fellowsof this kind which turns them into a nation, and not the other shared attributes, whatever they might be, which separate that category from non-members. Each of these provisional definitions, the cultural and the volun- ., taristic, has some merit. Each of them singles out an element which is of real importance in the understanding of nationalism. But neither is adequate. Definitions of culture, presupposed by the first defmition, in the anthropological rather than the normative sense, are notoriously difficult and unsatisfactory. It is probably best to approach this problem by using this term without attempting too much in the way of formal definition, and looking at what culture does. Culture in Agrarian Society CULTURE IN AGRARIAN S o c m 9 the Black, the specialists of violence and of faith, are indeed independently operating rivals, and their territories are often not co- extensive. Power and culture in the agro-literate polity These two crucial and idiosyncratic forms of the divisionof labourthe centralizations of power and of culturdcognition - have proOne development which takes place during the agrarian epoch of found and special implications for the typical social structure of the human history is comparable in importance with the emergence of ago-literate polity. Their implications are best considered jointly, the state itself: the emergenceof literacyand of a specialized clerical and they can be schematized as shown in figure 1. class or estate, a clerisy. Not all agrarian societies attain literacy: paraphrasingHegel once again, we may say that at first none could read; then somecould read; and eventuallyall can read. That, at any rate, seems to be the way in which literacy fits in with the three great ages of man. In the middle or agrarian age literacy appertains to some only. Some societies have it; and within the societies that do have it, it is always some, and never all, who can actually read. The written word seems to enter history with the accountant and the tax collector: the earliest uses of the written sign seem often to be occasioned by the keepingof records. Once developed, however, the written word acquires other uses, legal, contractual, administrative. God himself eventuallyputs hiscovenantwith humanityand his rules for the comportmentof his creationin writing. Theology, legislation, litigation, administration, therapy: all engender a class of literate specialists, in alliance or more often in competition with freelance illiterate thaumaturges. In agrarian societies literacy brings forth a major chasm between the great and the little traditions (or cults). The doctrines and forms of organization of the clerisy of the great and literate cultures are highly variable, and the depth of the chasm between the great and little traditions may vary a great deal. So does the relationship of the clerisy to the state, and its own internal organization: it may be centralized or it may be loose, it may be hereditaryor on the contrary constitute an open guild, and so forth. Literacy, the establishment of a reasonably permanent and standardizedscript, means in effect the possibility of cultural and cognitive storage and centralization. The cognitive centralization and codification effected by a clerisy, and the political centralization which is the state, need not go hand in hand. Often they are rivals; sometimes one may capture the other; but more often, the Red and stratified, horizontally segregated layers of military, administrative, clerical and sometimes commercial ruling class communities of I agricultural producers 1 Figure 1 General form of the social structure of agrarian societies. In the characteristic agro-literate polity, the ruling class forms a small minority of the population, rigidly separate from the great majority of direct agricultural producers, or peasants. Generally speaking, its ideology exaggerates rather than underplays the inequality of classesand the degreeof separation of the rulingstratum. This can in turn be sub-divided into a number of more specialized layers: warriors, priests, clerics, administrators, burghers. Some of these layers (for example, Christian clergy) may be non-hereditary and be re-selected in each generation, though recruitment may be closely predetermined by the other hereditary strata. The most important point, however, is this: both for the ruling stratum as a whole, and for the various sub-strata within it, there is great stress on cultural differentiation rather than on homogeneity. The more differentiated in style of all kinds the various strata are, the less friction and ambiguity there will be between them. The whole system favours horizontal lines of cultural cleavage, and it may invent and reinforce them when they are absent. Genetic and cultural differences are attributed to what were in fact merely strata differentiated by function, so as to fortify the differentiation, and endow it with authorityand permanence. For instance, in early nineteenth-century Tunisia, the ruling stratum considered itself to be Turkish, though quite unable to speak that language, and in fact of very mixed ancestry and reinforced by recruits from below. Below the horizontally stratified minority at the top, there is another world, that of the laterally separated petty communities of the lay members of the society. Here, once again, cultural differentiationis very marked, though the reasons are quite different. Small peasant communities generally live inward-turned lives, tied to the locality by economicneed if not by political prescription.Even if the population of a given area starts from the same linguistic base-linewhich very often is not the case - a kind of culture drift soon engenders dialectal and other differences. No-one, or almost no-one, hasan interestin promotingcultural homogeneityat this social level. The state is interested in extracting taxes, maintaining the peace, and not much else, and has no interest in promoting lateral com- ~munication between its subject communities. The clerisy may,it is true, have a measure of interest in imposing I certain shared cultural norms. Some clerisies are contemptuous of I and indifferenttowardsfolk practices, while others, in theinterest of , monopolizingaccess to the sacred, to salvation, therapyand so forth, I combat and actively denigrate folk culture and the freelance folk !': shamanswho proliferatewithinit. But, within thegeneralconditions I prevailing in agro-literate polities, they can never really be i i CULTURE IN AGRARIANSOCIETY 11 successful. Such societies simply do not possess the means for making literacy near-universal and incorporating the broad masses of the population in a high culture, thus implementing the ideals of theclerisy. The most the clerisy can achieveis to ensurethat its ideal is internalized as a valid but impracticable norm, to be respected or even revered, perhaps even aspired to in periodic outbursts of enthusiasm, but to be honoured more in the breach than in the observance in normal times. But perhaps the central, most important fact about agro-literate society is this: almost everythingin it militates against the definition of political units in terms of cultural boundaries. In other words! had nationalismbeen invented in such a period its prospects of general acceptance would have been slender indeed. One might put it this way: of the two potential partners, cultureand power, destined for each other according to nationalist theory, neitherhas much inclinationfor the other in the conditionsprevailing in the agrarian age. Let us take each of them in turn. Culture Among the higher strata of ago-literate society it is clearly advantageous to stress, sharpenand accentuate the diacritical, differential, and monopolizable traits of the privileged groups. The tendency of liturgical languages to become distinct from the vernacular is very strong: it is as if literacy alone did not create enough of a barrier between cleric and layman, as if the chasm between them had to be deepened, by making the language not merely recorded in an inaccessible script, but also incomprehensible when articulated. The establishment of horizontal cultural cleavages is not only attractive, in that it furthers the interests of the privileged and the power-holders; it is also feasible, and indeed easy. Thanks to the relative stability of ago-literate societies, sharp separations of the population into estates or castes or millets can be established and maintained without creating intolerable frictions. On the contrary, by externalizing, making absolute and underwritinginequalities, it fortifiesthem and makes them palatable, by endowingthem with the aura of inevitability, permanence and naturalness. That which is inscribed into the nature of things and is perennial, is consequently not personally, individually offensive, nor psychicallyintolerable. 12 CULTURE IN AGRARIANSOCIETY By contrast, in an inherently mobile and unstable society the maintenance of these social dams, separating unequal levels, is intolerably difhcult. The powerful currents of mobility are ever undermining them. Contrary to what Marxism has led people to expect, it is pre-industrial society which is addicted to horizontal differentiation within societies, whereas industrial society strengthens the boundaries between nations rather than those between classes. The same tends to be true, in a different form, lower down on the social scale. Even there, preoccupationwith horizontal, often subtle but locallyimportant differentiationscan be intense. But even if the local group is internally more or less homogeneous, it is most unlikely to link its own idiosyncratic culture to any kind of political principle, to thinkin terms of a politicallegitimacy defined in a way which refers to the local culture. For a variety of obvious reasons, such a style of thinking is, in these conditions, most unnatural, and would indeed seem absurd to those concerned, were it explained to them. Localcultureis almostinvisible.The self-enclosedcommunity tends to communicatein terms whose meaning can only be identified in context, in contrast to the relatively context-free scholasticism of the scribes. But the village patois (or shorthand or 'restricted code') has no normative or political pretensions; quite the reverse. The most it can do is identify the village of origin or anyone who opens his mouth at the local market. In brief, cultures proliferate in this world, but its conditions do not generally encourage what night be called cultural imperialisms, the effons of one culture or another to dominate and expand to fill out a political unit. Culture tends to be branded either horizontally (by social caste), or vertically, to define very small local cornmunities. The factors determining political boundaries are totally distinct from those determining cultural limits. Clerisies sometimes endeavour to extend the zone of a culture, or rather, of the faith they codified for it; and states sometimes indulge in crusades, faithendorsed aggression. But these are not the normal, pervasive conditions of agrarian society. It is important to add that culturesin such a world proliferate in a very complex way: in many cases, it is far from clear how a given individual is to be assigned to his 'cultural background'. A Hirnalayan peasant, for instance, may be involved with priests and monks and shamans of several religions in different contexts at different CULTURE IN AGRARIAN SOCIETY 13 times of the year; his caste, clan and language may link him to diverse units. The speakers of a given tribal language may, for instance, not be treated as members of it, if they happen to be of the wrong occupational caste. Life-style, occupation, language, ritual practice, may fail to be congruent. A family's economicand political survival may hinge, precisely, on the adroit manipulation and maintenance of these ambiguities, on keeping options and connections open. Its membersmay not have the slightest interest in, or tastefor, an unambiguous, categorical self-characterization such as is nowadays associated with a putative nation, aspiring to internal homogeneity and external autonomy. In a traditional milieu an ideal of a single overriding and cultural identity makes little sense. Nepalese hill peasants often have links with a variety of religious rituals, and think in terms of caste, clan, or village (but not of nation) according to circumstance. It hardly matters whether homogeneityis preached or not. It can find little resonance. The state in agrarian society In these circumstances there is little incentive or opportunity for cultures to aspire to the kind of monochrome homogeneityand political pervasiveness and dominationfor which later, with the coming of the age of nationalism, they eventually strive. But how does the matter look from the viewpoint of the state, or, more generally, of the political unit? Political units of the agrarian age vary enormously in size and kind. Roughly speaking, however, one can divide them into two species, or perhaps poles: local self-governing communities, and large empires. On the one hand, there are the city states, mbal seg-, - ments, peasant communes and so forth, running their own affairs, with a fairly high political participation ratio (to adapt S. Andreski's useful phrase), and with only moderateinequality; and on the other, largeterritories controlled by a concentrationof forceat one point. A very characteristicpoliticalform is, of course, one which fuses these I two principles: a central dominant authority co-exists with semiautonomous local units. I The question which concerns us is whether, in our world, con- I taining these types of unit, there are forces making for that fusion of t culture and polity which is the essence of nationalism. The answer 14 CULTURE IN AGRARIAN SOCIETY must be No. The local communities depend for their functioningon a good measure of face-to-face contact, and they cannot expand in size radically without transformingthemselvesout of all recognition. Hence these participatory communities seldom exhaust the culture of which they are part; they may have their localaccent and customs, but these tend to be but variants of a wider inter-communicating culture containing many other similar communities. City states, for instance, seldom have a languageof their own. No doubt the ancient Greeks were reasonably typical in this respect. While they possessed a vigorous awareness of their own shared culture and the contrast' between it and that of all barbarians(with, incidentally, a rather low degree of horizontalcultural differentiation bemeen Hellenes), this sense of unity had little political expression, even in aspiration, let alone in achievement. But when a pan-Hellenic polity was established under Macedonian leadership, it very rapidly grew into an empire transcending by far the bounds of Hellenism. In ancient Greece, chauvinistic though the Greeks were in their own way, there appears to have been no slogan equivalent to Ein Reich, Ein Volk, Ein Fuehrer. The varieties of agrarian d e r s The agro-literatepolity is a kind of society which has been in existence some five millennia or so and which, despite the variety of its fonns, sharescertain basicfeatures. The great majority of its citizens are agricultural producers, living in inward-turned communities, and they are dominated by a minority whose chief distinguishing attributes are the managementof violence, the maintenanceof order, and the control of the official wisdom of the society, which is eventually enshrined in scrip< his warrior-and-scribe ruling class can be fitted into a rough typology, in terms of the following set of oppositions: 1 Centralized Uncentralized 2 Gelded Stallions 3 Closed Open 4 Fused Specialized 1 Both a clerisy and a military class can be either centalized or decentralized. The medieval Catholic Church is a splendid example of an effectively centralized clerisy which can dominate the moral CULTURE IN AGRARIAN SOCIETY 15 climate of a civilization. The ularna of Islam achieved as much, but with an almost total absence of any centralized organization or internal hierarchy, and they were theoretically an open class. The Brahmins were both a clerisy and a closed kin group; the Chinese bureaucracy doubled up as scribes and administrators. 2 From the viewpoint of the central state, the major danger, as Plato recognized so long ago, is the acquisition, or retention, by its militaryor clerical office-holders of links with particular kin groups, whose interests are then liable to sway the officers from the stern path of dub, and whosesupport is, at the same time, liable to endow them on occasion with too much power. The strategies adopted for countering this pervasive danger vary in detail, but can be generically characterized as gelding. The idea is to break the kin link by depriving the budding &&ior/bureaucrat/ cleric either of ancestry, or of posterity, or of both. The techniques used included the use of eunuchs, physically incapable of possessing posterity; of priests whose privileged position was conditional on celibacy, thereby preventing them from avowing posterity; of foreigners, whose kin links could be assumed to be safely distant; or of members of otherwise disfranchised or excluded groups, who would be helpless if separated from the employing state. Another technique was the employment of 'slaves', men who, though in fact privileged and powerful, nevertheless, being 'owned' by the state, technically had no other legitimate links, and whose propem and position could revert to thestate at any time, without even thefiction of a right to due process, and thus without creatingany rights on the parts of some local or kin group of the destituted official. Literal eunuchs werefrequently employed.' Celibate priestswere, of course, prominent in Christendom. Slave military bureaucracies were conspicuous in Islamic polities after the decline of the Kaliphate. Foreignerswere often prominent in palaceeliteguards and in the fmancial secretariats of the empires. However, gelding was not universal. The Chinese bureaucracy was recruited from the 'genuy'; and the European feudal class rapidly succeeded in superimposing the principle of heredity on to that of the allocation of land for service. In contrast with gelding, elites whose members are formally allowed to reproduce themselves 'Keith Hopkins, Conquerors and Slaves, Cambridge, 1978, ch. 4. socially, and retain their positions for their offspring, may be called stallions. 3 There are advantages in clerisies, bureaucracies and military classes being open, and in their being closed. European clergy and Chinese bureaucratswere technicallyopen (as were Muslim ulama), though they were recruitedpredominantlyfrom a restrictedstratum. In Hinduism, priestsand warrior-rulersare both closed and distinct, and their mutual(theoretical)impenetrabilitymay be essentialto the working of thesystem. Theyare both closed and non-fused, distinct. In Islam (excluding Mamluk and Janissary periods) neither clerisy nor the military are gelded. 4 Finally, the ruling class may either fuse the military and clerical (and possibly other) functions, or carefully segregate them into specialized groups. Hinduism formally separated them. European feudalism fused them on occasion, in the military orders. It would be intriguing to follow in concrete historical detail the various possible combinations resulting from choosing from among these alternatives. For our present purpose, however, what matters is something that all the variants tend to have in common. The power-holdersare caught in a kind of field of.tension between local communitieswhich are sub-national in scale, and a horizontal estate or caste which is more than national. They are loyal to a stratum which is much more interested in differentiating itself from those below than in &sing its own culture to them, and which quite often extends its own limits beyond the bounds of the local polity, and is trans-political and in competition with the state. Only seldom ' (as in the case of the Chinese bureaucracy) is it co-extensive with a 1 state (and in that case, it did display a certain kind of nationalism). 1 I The only stratum which can in anysense be said to have a cultural j policy is the clerisy. Sometimes, as in the case of the Brahmins, its 1policy is in effect to create a complementarity and mutual inter- j dependence between itself and the other orders. It seeks to strengthen its own position by making itself indispensable, and the com- 1plementary roles it ascribes to itself and to the laity, far from requiring its own universalization, formally preclude it. Notwithstanding the fact that it claims monopolistic authority over ritual propriety, it does not wish to see itself emulated. It haslittlewish for the sincerest form of flattery, imitation, though it does provoke it. Elsewhere, as in Islam, the clerisy from time to time takes its own missionary duties, to be practised among the habitually relapsing weaker brethrenwithinthefaith, with becomingseriousness. Thereis here no rule enjoining that some must pray, some fight, and some work, and that these estatesshould not presume to meddlewith each other's realm. Asfar as the actual prescriptionsof thefaith go, everyone is allowed to do all three of these things, if his aptitudes and energy allow. (This latent egalitarianismis very important for the successful adaptation of Islam to the modem world.) Thus there is no formal or theological obstacle to a clerical missionary cultural policy a outrance. In practice there is still a problem: if everyone really systernatidly indulged in legal-theological studies, who would look after the sheep, goatsand camels?In certain parts of the Saharathere are entiretribes designated, by inter-tribal compact, as Peopleof the Book. In practice, however, this only means that religious perso~el are habitually drawn from among their number. It does not mean that all of them actually become religious specialists. Most of them continue to work and fight. The only communitiesin which a really very ~ i g ~ c a n tproportion of adult males indulged in the smdy of the Law were some Jewish ones in Eastern Europe. But that was a special and extreme case, and in any case these communities were themselves sub-communities in a wider and more complex society. So for very deep, powerful and insuperable reasons, clerisies in agro-literate societies cannot properly dominate and absorb the entire society. Sometimestheir own rules prohibit it, and sometimes external obstacles make it impossible; but the latter would in any case constitute a ~ ~ c i e n tand effective impediment, even if the rules were always favourable to this aspiration. In the agrarian order, to try to impose on all levels of society a universalized clerisy and a homogenized culture with centrally imposed norms, for tifi ed by writing, would be an idle dream. Even if such a programme is contained in some theological doctrines, it cannot be, and is not, implemented. It simply cannot be done. The resources are lacking. But what happens if the clerisy one day is universalized, becomes co-extensive with the entire society, not by its own efforts, not by some heroic or miraculous internal Jihad, but by a much more effective, deeply-rootedsocialforce, by a total transformation of the whole nature of the division of labour and of productive and cognitive processes? The answer to this question, and the specification of the nature of that transformation, wiU turn out to be crucial for the understanding of nationalism. 18 CULTURE IN AGRARIANSOCIETY Note also that in the agrarian order only some elite strata in some societiesweresystematically gelded, by one or anotherof the specific techniques described above. Even when it is done, it is difficult, as Plato foresaw, to enforce the gelding indefbitely The guardians, be they Mamluks or Janissaries, bureaucrats or prebend-holders, become corrupted, acquire interests and links and continuity, or are seduced by the pursuit of honour and wealth and the lure of selfperpetuation. Agrarianmanseemsto be madeof a corruptible'metal. His successor, industrial man, seems to be madeof purer, though not totally pure, metal. What happens when a social order is accidentally brought about in which the clerisy does become, at long last, universal, when literacy is not a specialism but a pre-condition of all other specialisms, and when virtually all occupations cease to be hereditary? What happens when gelding at the same time also becomes near-universal and very effective, when every man Jack amongst us is a Mamluk de Robe, putting the obligations to his callingabove the claims of kinship?In an age of universalizedclerisy and Mamluk-dom, the relationship of culture and polity changes radically. Ahighculturepervadesthewholeof society,definesit, and needsto besustainedby the polity. Thatis the sepretof nationalism. 3 Industrial Society \ The originsof industrial society continueto be an object of scholarly dispute. It seems to me very probablethat this will continueto be so for ever. An enormously complex transformation occurred in a very large, diversifiedand intricate society, and the event was unique: no imitativeindustrialization can be treated as an event of thesame kind as the original industrialization, simply in virtue of the fact that all the others were indeed imitative, were performed in the light of the now established knowledge that the thing could be done, and had certain blatant and conspicuous advantages (though the emulated ideal was, of course, interpreted in all kinds of quite diverse ways). So we can never repeat the original event, which was perpetrated by men who knew not what they did, an unawareness which was of the very essence of the event. We cannot do it, for quite a number of cogent reasons: the sheer fact of repetition makes it different from the original occasion; we cannot in any case reproduce all the circumstancesof early modern Western Europe;and experimentson such a scale, for the sake of establishing a theoretical point, are morally hardly conceivable. In any case, to sort out the causal threads of so complex a process, we should need not one, but very many re-runs, and these will never be available to us. But while we cannot reallyestablish theaetiologyof industrialism, we can hope to makesomeprogressin puttingforward modelsof the generic working of industrial society. In fact, the real merit and importance of klax Weber's celebrated essay (The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism)seems to me to lie far less in his fascinating but speculativeand inconclusive hypothesis about the genesis of the capitalist spirit, than in his reflections about what constitute the general distinguishing features of the new social order. In fact, although the (entirelysalutary) shift of concern from the origins of capitalism to that of the origins of industrialismonly occurred after Weber, and as a consequence of the emergence of non-capitalist industrial societies, nevertheless this reformulation of the crucial 20 INDUSTRIAL S o c i ~ n question is already implicit in Weber's preoccupation with bureaucracy, alongside his concern with the entrepreneurialspirit. If a centralized bureaucracy exemplifies the new Geist just as much as does the rational businessman, then clearly we are concerned with industrialism, rather than with capitalism as such. In the Weberian, and I think in any plausible accountof the new spirit, the notion of rationaliey must be centraland important. Weber himself was not particularly deft in giving coherent and adequate definitions, particularlyso in this case, though it is perfectlypossible to distilfrom the contexts of his,use of this notion of rationality what he meant by it, and that this underlyingnotion is indeed crucial for this topic. As it happens, this notion is explored, with unparalleled philosophic depth, by the two greatest philosophers of the eighteenth century, David Hume and Immanuel Kant, both of whom, under the fond delusion that they wereanalysing the human mind as such, an sich, anywhere, any time, werein fact giving very profound accounts of the general logic of the new spirit whose emergence characterized their age. What these two thinkers shared was at least as important as what separated them. Two elements are conspicuously present in Weber's notion of rationality. One is coherence or consistency, the like treatment of likecases, regularity,what might be called theverysoul or honourof a good bureaucrat. The other is efficiency, the cool rationalselection of the best available means to given, clearly formulatedand iso!ated ends; in other words, the spirit of the ideal entrepreneur. Orderlinessand efficiency may indeed by seen as the bureaucratic and the entrepreneurial elements in an overall spirit of rationality. I do not myself believethat these two elementsare reallyindependent of each other. The notion of means-ends efficiencyimplies that the agent will always choose the self-same solution to a given problem, irrespectiveof 'irrelevant' considerations;and consequently it carries the bureaucratic requirement of symmetry of trearmentas an immediate corollary. The imperative of symmetry does not quite so immediately imply the corollary of efficiency (and indeed, as an empirical fact, bureaucrats, even or especially perfectly honest and conscientious ones, are not always particularly efficient, as Weber himself noted); nevertheless, any sustained and non-superficial implementation of the requirement of orderliness will imply the use of a general and neutral idiom for the specification both of ends and of fact, of the environment in which the ends are to be pursued. INDUSTRIAL SDCIETY else. What underlies the two elements of the rational spirit of which Weber was clearly aware (orderliness and efficiency) is something deeper, well explored by Hume and Kant under the blithe impression that they were investigating the human mind in general: namely, a common measureof fact, a universalconceptualcurrency, so to speak, for the generalcharacterization of 'things;and the esprit d'analyse, forcefuliy preached and characterized already by Descartes. Each of these elements is presupposed by rationality, in the sense in which it concerns us, as the secret of the modem spirit. By the common or single conceptual currency I mean that all facts are located within a single continuous logical space, that statements reportingthem can be conjoined and generally related to each other, and so that in principle one single language describes the world and isinternally unitary; or on the negativeside, that thereare nospecial, privileged, insulated facts or realms, protected from contamination orcontradictionby others, andlivingininsulated independentlogical spaces of their own. Just this was, of course, the most striking trait of premodern, pre-rationalvisions: the co-existencewithin them of multiple, not properly united, but hierarchicallyrelated sub-worlds, and the existence of special privileged facts, sacralized and exempt from ordinary treatment. In a traditional social order, the languages of the hunt, of harvesting, of various rituals, of the council room, of the kitchen or harem, all form autonomous systems: to conjoin statements drawn assumed that all referential uses of language ultimately refer to one coherent world, and can be reduced to a unitary idiom; and that it is legitimate to relate them to each other. 'Only connect' is an intelligible and acceptable ideal. Modern philosophies of knowledge are frequently our expfession and codification of this idea and aspiration, which in turn is not a philosophical whim, but has profound sodalroots. 22 INDUSTRIAL SOCIETY Equalization and homogenization of facts is incomplete unless accompanied by what may be called the separation of all separables, the esprit d'analyse, the breaking up of all complexes into their constituent parts (even if it can only be donein thought), and the refusal to countenance conceptual package deals. It is precisely by binding things together that traditional visions perpeNate themselves and the prejudgements contained within them; and it is by insisting on prising things apart that we have liberated ourselves from them. These package-deals, and the discontinuous conceptual spaces, are the equivalents, in the sphere of ideas, of the stable social groupings and smctwes at the level of men. Likewise, the milied and standardized, as it were metric world of facts, as conceivedin the philosophies of Hume or Kant, is the analogue of the anonymous and equal collectivities of men in a mass society. In the present argument, we are concerned with men and their groupings, rather than with ideas; but the unif~cationof their ideas in continuous and unitary systems is connected with their re-groupingin i n t e d y fluid, culturally continuous communities. Industrial society is the only society ever to live by and rely on sustained and perpetual growth, on an expected and continuous improvement. Not surprisingly, it was the fnst society to invent the concept and ideal of progress, of continuous impfovement. Its favoured mode of social control is universal Danegeld, buyihg off socialaggressionwith materialenhancement; its greatestweaknessis its inability to survive any temporary reduction of the social bribery fund, and to weather the loss of legitimacy which befalls it if the cornucopiabecomes temporarily jammedand the flow falters. Many societies in the past have on occasion discovered innovations and improved their lot, and sometimes it may even have been m e that improvements came not as single spies but in battalions. But the improvementwas never perpetual, nor expected to be so. Something special must have happened to have engendered so unusual and remarkable an expectation. And indeed, something unusual, something unique, had happened. The conception of the world as homogeneous, subject to systematic, indiscriminate laws, and as open to interminable exploration, offered endless possibilities of new combinations of means with no f m prior expectations and limits: no possibilities would be barred, and in the end nothing but evidence would decide how things were, and how they could be combinedto secure desired I m u s m SOCIETY 23 effects. This was a totally new vision. The old worlds were, on the one hand, each of them, a cosmos: purposive, hierarchial, 'meaningful'; and on the other hand, not quite unified, consisting of subworlds each with its own idiom and logic, not subsumable under a single overall orderliness. The new world was on the one hand morally inert, and onthe other, unitary. Hume's philosophy is one of the most important codifications of this vision. Its best-known part is his treatment of causation, which : indeed follows from the overall vision and its central insights. What 1 it amounts to in the end is this: in the very nature of things, nothing is inherently connected with anything else. The actual connections of this world can only be established by first separating in thought everything that can be thought separately-so that wecanisolatethe pure elements, so to speak - and then seeing what, as a matter of experience, happens to be actually conjoined to what. Is the world like that? Ours is. This is the pre-condition, the price of a world of endless discovery. Inquiry must not be bound by the natural affmitiesand liaisons of things, built into this or that vision and style of life. And, of course, Hume's account of causation is not 1 merely an admirable summary of the background picture facing the ! i untramrnelled, eternal inquirer; it is also an account of the com- 1 pomnent of his economic counterpart, the modem entrepreneur. Not for the merchant or manufacturer of the age of reason thefusion i of labour, technique, material and mould, prescribed by custom, i tied to a social order and rhythm; his progressand the advancement / of the economy of which he is a part hinges, once again, on his unI trammelledselection of whatever means, in the light of the evidence j and of nothing else, serves some clear aim such as the maximization i of profit. (His predecessor or indeed his surviving feudal contemporary would have been hard put to it to single out a solitary, isolablecriterion of success. Profitfor them would have been merged in a number of inseparable other considerations, such as the maintenaqceof their positions in the community. Adam Smith saw only tw dearly the difference between a Glasgow burgher and, say, Cameron of Lochiel. Hume's theory of causation ratifies the perceptions~ofthe former.) This vision of a society which has become dependent on both cognitive and economic growth (the two being, of course, linked to each other) con- us here, becausewe are piimady interested in the consequences of an ever-growing, ever-progressing society. But 24 INDUSTRIALSOCIETY the consequences of such perpetual growth have striking parallels with the vision which was its condition. The society of pmpetual growth If cognitive growth presupposes that no element is indissolubly linked a priori to any other, and that everything is open to re- , thinking, then economicand productive growth requires exactty the same of human activities and hence of human roles. Roles become optionaland instrumental. The old stability of the social role srmcm e is simply incompatiblewith growth and innovation. Innovation means doing new things, the boundarks of which cannot be the same as those of the activities they replace. No doubt most societies ; can cope wiih an occasional re-drawing of job-specifications and 1 guild boundaries, just as a football team can experimentally switch 1 from one formation to another, and yet maintain continuity. One 1 change does not make progress. But what happens when such changes themselves are constant and continuous, when the per- t1' sistence of occupational change itself becomes the one permanent feature of a social order? When this question is answered, the mab part of the problem of nationalismis thereby solved. Nationalism is rooted in a cerrainkind of division of labour, one which is complex and persistently, cumulatively changing. High productivity, as Adam Smith insisted so much, requires a complex and refmed division of labour. Perpetually growing productivity requires that this division be not merely complex, but also perpetually, and often rapidly, changing. This rapid and continuous change both of the economic role system itself and of the occupancy of places within it, has certain immediate and profoundlyimportant consequences. Men located within it cannot generally rest in the same niches all their lives; and they can only seldom rest in them, so to speak, over generations. Positions are seldom (for this and other reasons) transmitted from father to son. Adam Smith noted the precariousness of bourgeois fortunes, though he erroneously amibuted stabiity of social station to pastoralists, mistaking theii genealogical myths for reality. The immediate consequence of this new kind of mobility is a certain kind of egalitarianism. Modern society is not mobile because INDUSTRIAL SOCIETY 25 it is egalitarian; it is egalitarianbecauseit is mobile. Moreover, it has to be mobile whether it wishes to be so or not, because this is required by the satisfaction of its terrible and overwhelming thirst for economic growth. A society which is destined to a permanentgameof musicalchairs cannot erect deep barriers of rank, of caste or estate, between the various sets of chairs which it possesses. That would hamper the mobility, and, given the mobility, would indeed lead to intolerable tensions. Men can tolerate terribleinequalities, if they are stable and hallowed by custom. But in a hectically mobile society, custom has no time to hallow anything. A rolling stone gathers no aura, and a mobile population does not allow any aura to attach to its stratifmtion. Stratification and inequality do exist, and sometimes in extreme form; neverthelessthey have a muted and discreet quality, attenuated by a kind of gradualnessof the distinctions of wealth and standing, a lack of social distanceand a convergenceof life-styles, a kind of statistical or probabilistic quality of the differences (as opposed to the rigid, absolutized, chasm-like differences typical of agrarian society), and by the illusion or reality of social mobiity. That illusion is essential, and it cannot persist without at least a measure of reality. Just how much reality there is in this appearance of upward and downward mobility varies and is subject to learned dispute, but there can he no reasonable doubt that it does have a good deal of reality: when the system of roles itself is changing so much, the occupants of positions within it cannot be, as some leftwing sociologists claim, tied to a rigid stramcational system. Compared with agrarian society, this society is mobile and egalitarian. But there is more than all this to the egalitarianism and mobility engendered by thedistinctivelyindustrial,growth-orientedeconomy. There are some additional subtler traits of the new division of labour, which can perhaps best be approached by considering the differencebetween the division of labour in an industrialsociety and that of a particularly complex, well-developed agrarian one. The obvious differencebetween the two is that one is more stableand the other is more mobile. In fact, one of them g e n d y willsitself to he stable, and the other wills itself to he mobile; and one of them pretends to be more stable than social reality permits, while the other often claimsmore mobility, in the interestof pretendingto satisfyits galitmianideal,thanits real constraintsactually permit. Nevertheless, though both systems tend to exaggerate their own cenud 26 INDUSTRIALSOCIETY features, they do indeed markedly possess the trait they claim as their own when contrasted with each other: one is rigid, the other mobile. But if that is the obvious contrast, what are the subtler features which accompany it? Compare in detail the division of labour in a highly advanced agrarian society with that of an averageindustrialone. Every kind of function,forinstancenow hasat leastone kindof specialistassociated withit. Car mechanicsare becomingspecializedin termsof the make of car they service. The industrial society will have a larger population, and probably, by most natural ways of counting, a larger number of different jobs. In that sense, the division of labour has been pushed much further within it. But by somecriteria, it may well be that a fully developed agrarian society aaually has the more complex division of labour. The specialismswithin it are more distant from each other than are the possibly more numerous specialisms of an industrial society, which tend to have what can only be described as a mutual affiity of style. ; Some of the specialisms of a matureagrarian society will be extreme: i they will be the fruits of lifelong, very prolonged and totally dedic- 1 ated training, which may have commenced in early youth and re- ; quired an almost complete renunciation of other concerns. The 1 achievements of craft and art production in these societies are I extremely labour- and skill-intensive, and often reach levels of iintricacy and perfection never remotely equalled by anything later 1 attained by industrialsocieties, whosedomesticarts and decorations, ' gastronomy, tools and adornments are notoriously shoddy. Notwithstanding their aridity and sterility, the scholastic and ritual complexity mastered by the schoolmen of a developed agrarian society is often such as to strain the very limits of the human mind. In brief, although the peasants, who form the great majority of an agrarian society, are more or less mutually interchangeable when it comes to the performance of the social tasks which are normally assigned to them, the important minority of specialists within such societies are outstandingly complementaryto each other; each one of them, or each group of them, is dependent on the othersand, when sticking to its last, its specialism, quite incapable of self-sufficiency. It is curious that, by contrast, in industrial society, notwithstanding its larger number of specialisms, the distance between specialists is far less great. Their mysteries are far closer to mutual intelligibility, their manuals have idioms which overlap to a much greater extent, and re-training, though sometimes difficult, is not generally an awesome task. So quite apart from the presence of mobility in the one case and stabilityin the other, there is a subtle but profound and important qualitative differencein the division of labour itself. Durkheim was in error when he in effect classed advanced pre-industrial civilizations and industrial society together under the single heading of 'organic solidarity', and when he failed to introduce properly this further distinction within the wider category of organic solidarity or of complementary division of labour. The difference is this: the major part of training in industrial society is g m - c training, not specif~callyconnected with the highly specialized professional activity of the person in question, and preceding it. Industrial society may by most criteria be the most highly specializedsociety ever; but irs educational system is unquestionably the least specialized, the most universallystandardized, that has ever existed. The same kind of training or education is given to all or most children and adolescents up to an astonishinglylate age. Specializedschools have prestige only at the end of the educational process, if they constitute a kind of completion of a prolonged previous unspecialized education; specialized schools intended for a younger, earlier intake have negative prestige. Is this a paradox, or perhaps one of those illogical survivals from an earlier age? Those who notice the 'gentlemady' or leisure-class elements in higher education have sometimes supposed so. But, although some of the frills and affectations amched to higher education may indeed by irrelevancies and sunivals, the central fact the pervasiveness and importance of generic, unspecialized training -is conjoined to highly specialized industrial society not as a paradox, but as somethingaltogether fitting and necessary. The kind of specializationfoundin indusuial societyrests preciselyon a common foundation of unspecialized and standardized training. A mo+m army subjects its recruits first to a shared generic training, in the course of which they are meant to acquire and internalize the basic idiom, ritual and skills common to the army as a whole; and only subsequentlyare the recruitsgiven morespecialized rraining. It is assumed or hoped that every properly trainedrecruit can be re-trained from one specialism to another without too much loss of time, with the exception of a relatively small number of very highly trained specialists. A modern society is, in this respect, like a 28 INDUSTRIAL SOCIETY modem army, only more so. It provides a very prolonged and fairly thorough training for all its recruits, insisting on certain shared qualifications: literacy, numeracy, basicwork habitsandsocialskills, familiarity with basic technical and social skills. For the large majority of the population the distinctive skills involved in working life are superimposed on the basic training, either on the job or as part of a much less prolonged supplementary training; and the : assumption is that anyone who has completed the generic training common to the entire population can be re-trained for most other 1 jobs without too much difficulty. Generay speaking, the additional ! skills required consist of a few techniques that can be learned fairly : quickly, plus 'experience', a kind of familiarity with a milieu, its 1 personneland its manner of operation. This may take a little time to acquire, and it sometimes reinforced by a little protective mystique, I but seldom really amounts to very much. There is also a minority of i genuine specialists, people whose effective occupancy of their posts really depends on very prolonged additional training, and who are i not easily or at all replaceable by anyone not sharing their own par- 1 ticular educational background and talent. I The ideal of universalliteracy and the right to educationis a wellknown part of the pantheon of modem values. It is spoken of with respect by statesmen and politicians, and enshrined in declarations of rights, constitutions, party programmes and so forth. So far, nothing unusual. The same is m e of represenrativeand accountable government, free elections, an independent judickay, freedom of speech and assembly, and so on. Many or most of these admirable values are often and systematically ignored in many parts of the world, without anyone battingan eyelid. Very often, it is safe to consider these phrases as simple verbiage. Most constitutions guaranteeingfree speech and electionsareas informativeabout the societies they allegedly define as a man saying 'Good morning' is about the weather. All this is well known. What is so very curious, and highly signifant, about the principle of universaland centrally guaranteed education, is that it is an idealmore honoured in the observance than in the breach. In this it is virtuallyuniqueamong modem ideals; and this calls for an explanation. Professor Ronald Dore has powerfully criticizedthis tendency,' particularlyamong developingsocieties, of 'Ronald Dore, TheDiploma Disease, London, 1976. For an approachto the s d implications of literacy at an earlier stage, see Jack Gmdy (ed.), Literacy in TradirioMlSocieries, Cambridge, 1968. INDUSTRIALSOCIETY 29 ovenadngformal 'paper' qualifications, and no doubt it has harmful side effects. But I wonder whether he fully appreciates the deep roots of what he castigates as the Diploma Disease. We live in a world in which we can no longer respect the informal, intimate transmission of skills, for the social structures within which such transmission could occur are dissolving. Hence the only kind of knowledge we can respect is that authenticated by reasonably imp a n d centres of learning, which issue ceracates on the basis of honest, impartially administered examinations. Hence we are doomed to suffer the Diploma Disease. All tbis suggests that the kind of education described- universal, standardized, and generic - really plays some essential part in the effective working of a modem society, and is not merely part of its verbiage or self-advertisement. This is in fact so. To understand what that role is, we must, to borrow a phrase from Marx (though not perhapsin the sense in which he used it), considernot merely the mode of production of modern society, but above alJ its mode of reprodufrion. Social generics The reproduction of socialindividualsand groupscan be carried out either on the one-to-one or on-the-job principle, or by what may be called the centralizedmethod. There are, of course, manymixed and intermediate ways of doing this job, but their considerationcan best be postponed until after the discussion of these two extreme, as it were polar, pssibities. Theone-to-one, on-the-jobmethodis practisedwhen a family, kin unit, village, tribal segment or similar fairly small unit takes the individualinfants born into it, and by allowingand obliging them to Sharein the communallife, plusafew morespecific methodssuch as training, exercises, precepts, rites &passage and so forth, eventually "Uns these infants into adults reasonably similar to those of the precedinggeneration; and in this manner the society and its culture prpetuate themselves. The centralizedmethod of reproductionis one in Ghich the local method is significantlycomplemented (or in extreme cases, wholly replaced) by an educationalor mining agency which is distinctfrom the local community, and which takes over the preparation of the young human beingsin question, and eventuallyhands them back to the wider society to fulfil their roles in it, when the process of trainingis completed. An extreme version of this system developeda high degree of perfection and effectiveness in the Ottoman empire, when under the devshinne and janissary systems, young boys, either secured as a tax obligation from conquered populations, or purchased as slaves, were systematically trained for war and administration and, ideally, wholly weanedand separatedfrom their families and communities of origin. A less total version of this system was and in part still is practised by the British upper class, with its reliance on boarding schools from an early age. Variants of this system can on occasion be found even in relatively simple, preliterate agrarian societies. Societiesconsistingof sub-communitiescan be divided into those ; in which the sub-communities can, if necessary, reproduce themselves without help from the rest of society, and those in which mutual complementarity and interdependence are such that they i cannot do rhis. Generally speaking, the segments and rural com- I rnunities of agrarian society can reproduce rhemselves indepq- ; dently. The anthropological concept of a segmentary society con- I tains precisely this idea: the 'segment' is simply a smaller variant of the larger society of which it is a part, and can do on a smaller scale I everything done by the larger unit. I! Furthermore, one must disringuishbetween economic and educationalself-sufficiency, in the sense of capacity for self-reproduction. The ruling strata of an agrarian society are, of course, dependenton a surplus drawn from the rest of society, but they may nevertheless be educationally quite self-sufficient. Various other kinds of nonself-sficiency can also be engendered by social rules, such as those which makecommunitiesdependenton external ritual specialists, or on the supply of brides from outside. Here we are concerned with educational, not economic capacity for group self-reproduch There are numerous complex, mixed and intermediate forms of group reproduction. When feudal lords send their sons as halftrajnees, half-hostages to the local court, when masters accept apprentices who are not their sons, and so forth, we are obviously in the presence of such mixed systems. Generally speaking, the situation in agrarian society seems to be this: the great majorityof the population belongs to self-reproducing INDUSTRIAL SOCIETY 31 units, suchas in effect educate their young on the job, in theirstride, as part and parcel of the general business of living, without relying much or at all on any kind of educational specialist. A minority of the population receives specialized training. Thesociety will contain one or more strata of full-time educators, who both reproduce themselves by taking on aoprentices, and perform part-time s e ~ c e sfor the rest of the community: ritual, therapeutic, admonitory, secretarial, and so on. It may be useful to distinguish betweenone-to-one, intra-community training, and call it acculturation, and specialized exenaining (on the analogy of exogamy), which calls for skills outside the community, and call that education proper. A very important stratum in literate agrarian society are the clerks, thosewho can read and transmit literacy, and who thus form one of the classes of specialists in that society. They may or may not form a a d d or be incorporated in an organization. As, generally speaking, writing soon transcends its purely technical use in recordkeeping, and acquires moral and theological sinificance, the clerks or clerics are almost invariably far more than mere graphotechnicians. It is not just writing, but what is written that counts, and, in agrariansociety, the ratio of the sacred to the profane, within the realm of the written, tends to be heavily weighted in favour of the first. So the writersand readers are specialists and yet more than specialists; they are both part of a society, and claim to be the voice of the whole of it. Their specialism says somethihg, something special, more so perhaps than that of the woodcarvers and other designers, and much more than that of the tinkers. Specialists are often feared and despised in this kind of society. The clerics may be viewed ambivalently, but in the main their Sanding is rather high. They are both specialists and a part of societyamong others, and yet also, as stated, claim to be the voice of the totality. They are in an inherently paradoxical situation. Logicians possess, in their armoury of allegedly deep and significant puzzles, ,the Problem of the Barber: in a village, all men can be divided into those who shave themselves, and those who are shaved by the barber. But what of the barber himself? Is he a self-shaver, or one of the barber-shaved? In this form, let us leave it to the logicians. But the clerics are somewhat in the barber's situation. They reproduce their own guild by training entrants, but they also givea bit of training or provide services for the rest of society. Do they or do they not shave themselves?The tension and its problems (and they are not just logical)are with them, and they are not easily resolved. In the end, modem society resolves this conundrum by turniog everyone into a cleric, by turning this potentially universal class into an effectively universal one, by ensuring that everyone without ( exception is taught by it, that exo-education becomes the universal j norm, and that no-one culturally speaking, shaves himself. Modern I I society is one in which no sub-community, below the size of one ; capable of sustaining an independent educational system, can any 1 longer reproduce itself. The reproduction of fully socialized indivi- 1 duals itself becomes part of the division of labour, and is no longer performed by sub-communities for themselves. i1That is what developed modern societies are like. But why must this be so? What fate impels them in this direction?Why, to repeat the earlier question, is this one ideal, that of universal literacy and education, taken with this most unusual, untypical seriousness? Part of the answer has already been given, in connectionwith the stress on occupational mobility, on an unstable, rapidly changing division of labour. A society whose entire political system, and indeed whose cosmology and moral order, is based in the last analysis on economic growth, on the universal incremental Danegeld and the hope of a perpetual augmentation of satisfactions, whose legitimacy hingeson its capacity to sustain and satisfy this expectation, is thereby committed to the need for innovation and hence to a changing occupationalstructure. From this it follows that certainly between generations, and very often within single life-spans, men must be ready for reallocation to new tasks. Hence, in part, the importance of the generic training, and the fact that the little bit extra of training, such as is attached to most jobs, doesn't amountto too much, and is moreover contained in manuals intelligible to all possessorsof the society's generic training. (While the little bit extra seldom amounts to much, the shared and truly essentialgenericcore is supplied at a rather high level, not perhaps when compared with the intellectual peaks of agrarian society, but certainly when placed alongside its erstwhile customary average.) But is is not only mobility and re-training which engender this imperative. It is also the content of most professional activities. Work, in i n d u s d society, does not mean moving matter. The paradigmof work is no longer ploughing, reaping, thrashing. Work, in the main, is no longer the manipulation of things, but of INDUSTRIAL SOCIETY 33 meanings. It generally involves exchanging communications with other people, or manipulating the controls of a machine. The proportion of peopleat the coal face of nature, directlyapplying human physical force to natural objects, is constantly diminishing. Most jobs, if not actually involvingwork 'with people', involvethe control of buttons or switches or leaverswhich need to be understood,and are explicable, once again, in some standard idiom intelligible to all comers. For the first time in human history, explicit and reasonably precisecommunication becomes generally, pervasivelyused and important. In the closed local communitiesof the agrarianor nibal worlds, when it came to communication, context, tone, gesture, personality and situation were everything. Communication, such as it was, took place without the benefit of precise formulation, for which the locals had neither taste nor aptitude. Explicitnessand the niceties of precise, rule-bound formulation were left to lawyers, theologians or ritualspecialists, and were parts of their mysteries. Among intimates of a close community, explicirness would have been pedantic and offensive, and is scarcely imaginable or intelligible. Human language must have been used for countless generations in such intimate, closed; context-bound communities, whereas it has only been used to the full by schoohenand jurists, and all kinds of contextevadingconceptualpuritans, for a very small number of generations. Itis avery puzzlingfact that an institution, namely human language, should have this potential for being used as an 'elaborate code', in Basil Bernstein's phrase, as a formal and fairly context-free instrument, given that it had evolved in a milieu which in no way called for this development, and did not selectively favour it if it manifested irself. This puzzle is on a par with problems such as that posed by the existence of skills (for example, mathematical ability) which throughout most of the period of the existence of humanity had no survival value, and thus could not have been in any direct way produced by natural selection. The existence of language suitable for such formal, context-liberated use is such a puzzle; but it is also, clearly, a fact. This potentiality, whatever its origin and explanation, happened to be there. Eventually a kind of society emerged -and it isnow becomingglobal -in which this potentiality reallycomes into its own, and within which it becomes indispensable and dominant. To sum up this argument: a society has emerged based on a highpowered technology and the expectancy of sustained growth, which 34 ~ U S T R WSOCIETY requires both a mobile division of labour, and sustained, frequent and precise communicationbetween strangersinvolvinga sharing of explicit meaning, transmitted in a standard idiom and in writing when required. For a number of converging reasons, this society must be thoroughly exo-educational: each individual is trained by specialists,not just by his own local group, if indeed he has one. Its segments and units-and this society is in any case large, fluid, and in comparison with traditional, agrarian societies very short of internal structures - simply do not possess the capacity or the resources to reproduce their own personnel. The level of literacy and technicalcompetence, in a standardized medium, a common conceptual currency, which is required of members of this society if they are to be properly employable and enjoy full and effective moral citizenship, is so high that it simply cannot be provided by the kin or local units, such as they are. It can only be provided by something resembling a modem 'national' educational system, a pyramid at whose base there are primary scbools, staffed by teachers trained at secondary schools, staffed by university-trained teachers, led by the productsof advancedgraduate schools. Such a pyramid providesthe criterionfor the minimumsizefor a viable political unit. No unit too small to accommodate the pyramid can function properly. Units cannot be smalh than this. Constraintsalso operate which prevent them being too large, in various circumstances; but that is another issue. The fact that sub-units of society are no longer capable of selfreproduction, that centralized exo-education is the obligatory norm, that such education complements(thoughit does not wholly replace) localized acculaation, is of the very &st importancefor the political sociology of the modem world, and its implications have, strangely enough, been seldom understood or appreciated or even examined. At the base of the modem social order stands not the executioner but the professor. Not the guillotine, but the (aptly named) doctorat d'btar is the main tool and symbol of state power. The monopoly of legitimateeducation is now more important, more central than is the monopoly of legitimate violence. When this is understood, then the imperative of nationalism, its roots, not in human nature as such, but in a certain kind of now pervasive social order, can also be understood. Contrary to popular and even scholarly belief, nationalism does not have any very deep roots in the human psyche. The human INDUSTRIAL SOCIETY 35 psyche can be assumed to have persisted unchanged through the many many millennia of the existence of the human race, and not to have become either better or worse during the relatively brief and very recent age of nationalism. One may not invoke a general substrate to explain a specific phenomenon. The substrate generates many surface possibilities. Nati~nalism,the organization of human groupsinto large, centrallyeducated, culturally homogeneousunits, is but one of these, and a very rare one at that. What is crucial for its genuineexplanationis roidentifyits speciiic roots. It is thesespecific roots which alone can properly explain it. In this way, specific factors are superimposed on to a shared universal human substrate. The roots of nationalism in the distinctivestructural requirements of industrialsocietyare very deepindeed. This movementis the fruit neither of ideological aberration, nor of emotional excess. Although those who participatein it generally, indeed almost without exception, fail to understand what it is that thev do. the movement is~ ..----.nonetheless the external manifestation of a deep'adjustment in the relationship between polity and culture which is quite unavoidable. The age of universal high &re Let us recapitulate the general and central fearures of indusuial society. Universal literacy and a high level of numerical, technical and general sophisticationare among its functional prerequisites. Its members are and must be mobile, and ready to shift from one activity to another, and must possess that generic training which enables them to follow the manuals and instructions of a new activity or occupation. In the course of their work they must constantly communicate with a large number of other men, with whom they frequently have no previous association, and with whom communication must consequentlybeexplicit, rarherthanrelying on context. They >mustalso be able to communicate by means of written, impersonal, contm-free, to-whom-it-may-concern type messages. Hence these communications must be in the same shared and standardized linguisticmedium and script. The educational system which guarantees this social achievement becomes large and is indispensable, but at the same time it no longer possesses monopoly of access to the written word: its clientele is co-extensive with the society at large, and the replaceability of individuals within the system by others 36 INDUSTRIAL SOCIEN applies to the educational machine at least as much as to any other segment of society,and perhaps more so. Some very great teachers and researchers may perhaps be unique and irreplaceable, but the average professor and schoolmastercan be replaced from outside the teaching profession with the greatest of ease and often with little, if any, loss. What are the implications of all this for the society and for its members? The employability, dignity, security and self-respect of individuals, typically, and for the majority of men now hinges on their education; and the limits of the culture within which they were educated are also the limits of the world within which they can, morally and professionally, breathe. A man's education is by far his most precious investment, and in effect confers his identity on him. Modem man is not loyal to a monarch or a land or a faith, whatever he may say, but to a culture. And he is, generally speaking, gelded. The Mamluk condition has become universal. No important links bind him to a kin group; nor do they stand between him and a wide, anonymous community of culture. The obverse of the fact that a school-transmitted culnue, not a folk-transmitted one, alone confers his usabilityand dignityand selfrespect on industrial man, is the fact that nothing else can do it for him to any comparable extent. It would be idle to pretend that ancesuy, wealth or connectionsare unimportant in modem society, and that they are not on occasion even sourcesof pride to their beneficiaries; all the same, advantages secured in these ways are often explained away and are viewed at best ambivalently. It is interesting to ask whether the pemasive work ethic has helped to produce this state of affairs, or whether, on the contrary, it is a reflection of it. Drones and rentiers persist, of course, but they are not very conspicuous, and this in itself is highly signiticant. It is an important fact that such privilege and idleness as survive are now discreet, tending to prefer obscurity to display, and needing to be uncovered by eager researchers bent on unmasking the inequality which lurks underneath the surface. It was not so in the past, when idle privilege was proud and brazen, as it persists in beingin some survivingagrarian societies, or in societies which continueto uphold the ethos of pre-industrial life. Curiously enough, the notion of conspicuous waste was coined by a work-oriented member of a work-addicted society, Thorsten Veblen, scandalized by what he saw as the sunrivals from a INDUSTRIAL SOCIEN 37 pre-industrial, predatory age. The egalitarian, work- and careeroriented surface of industrial society is as sig cant as its inegalitarian hidden depths. Life, after all, is lived largely on the surface, even if imporrant decisions are on occasion made deep down. The teacher class is now in a sense more important - it is indispensable- and in dother sense much less so, having lost its monopoly of access to the cultural wisdom enshrined in scripture. In a society in which everyone is gelded by indentification with his professional post and his mining, and hardly anyone derives much or any security and support from whatever kin links he may have, the teaching clerics no longer possess any privileged access to administrative posts. When everyone has become a Mamluk, no special mamluk class predominates in the bureaucracy. At long last the bureaucracy can recruit from the population at large, without needing to fear the amval of dozens of cousins as unwanted attachments of each single new entrant. Exo-socialization,education proper, is now the virtually universal norm, Men acquire the skills and sensibilities which make them acceptable to their fellows, which fit them to assume places in society, and which make them 'what they are', by being handed over by their kin groups (normally nowadays, of course, their nuclear family) to an educational machine which alone is capable of providing the wide range of training required for the generic cultural base. This educational infrastructure is large, indispensable and expensive. Its maintenance seems to be quite beyond the fmancial powers of even the biggest and richest organizations within society, such as the big industrial corporations. These often provide their personnel with housing, sports and leisure clubs, and so forth; they do not, except marginally and in special circumstances, provide schooling. (They may subsidize school bas, but that is another matter.) The organization man works and plays with his organization, but his children srill go to state or independent schools. So, on the one hand, this educational infrastructure is too large and costly for any organization other than the biggest one of all, the state. But at the same time, though only the state can sustainso large a burden, only the stateis also strongenough to control so important and crucial a function. Culture is no longer merely the adornment, confirmation and legitimation of a social order which was also sustained by harsher and coercive constraints; culture is now the necessary shared medium, the life-blood or perhaps rather the minimal shared atmosphere, within which alone the members of the society can brearhe and survive and produce. For a given society, it must be one in which they can all breathe and speak and produce; so ! it must be the same culture. Moreover, it must now be a great or high ; (literate, training-wsrained)culture, and it can no longer be a diverIsified, locality-tied, illiterate little culture or tradition. But some organism must ensure that this literate and unif~edculture is indeed being effectively produced, that the educational product is not shoddy and sub-standard. Only the state can do this, and, even in countries in which important parts of the educational i machine are in private hands or those of religious organizations, the state does take over quality control in this most important of industries, the manufacture of viable and usable human beings. That shadow-state dating back to the time when Europeanstateswere not merely fragmented but socially weak- the centralized Church- did put up a fight for the control of education, but it was in the end ineffectual, unless the Church fought on behalf of an inclusive high culture and thereby indirectly on behalf of a new nationalist state. Time was when education was a cottageindustry, when men could be made by a village or clan. That time has now gone, and gone forever. (In education, small can now be beautiful o@yif it is coverdy parasitic on the big.) Exo-socialization, the production and reproduction of men outside the local intimate unit, is now the norm, and must be so. The imperative of exo-socialization is the main clue to why state and culture must now be linked, whereas in the past their connection was thin, formitous, varied, loose, and often minimal. Now it is unavoidable. That is what nationalism is about, and why we live in an age of nationalism. The Transition to an Age of Nationalism The most important steps in the argument have now been made. Mankind is irreversibly committed to indusuial society, and therefore to a society whose productive system is based on cumulative science and technology. This alone can sustain anything like the present and anticipated number of inhabitants of the planet, and give them a prospect of the kind of standard of living which man now takes for granted, or aspires to take for granted. Agrarian society is no longer an option, for its restoration would simply condemn the great majority of mankind to death by starvation, not to mention dire and unacceptablepovertyfor the minorityof survivors. Hence there is no point in discussing, for any practical purpose, the channsand the horrors of the culturaland political accompaniments of the agrarian age: they are simply not available. We do not properly understand the range of options available to industrial society, and perhaps we never shall; but we understand some of its essentialconcomitants. The kind of cdtural homogeneitydemanded by nationalism is one of them, and we had better make our peace withit. It is not the case, as Elie Kedourie claims,' that nationalism imposes homogeneity; it is rather that a homogeneity imposed by objective, inescapable imperative eventually appears on the surface in the form of nationalism. Most of mankindenters the industrialage from the agrarianstage. (The tiny minority which enters it directly from the pre-agrarian condition does not affect the argument, and the same points apply to it.) The social organization of agrarian society, however, is not at all favourableto the nationalist principle, to the convergenceof political and cultural units, and to the homogeneity and school-transmitted nature of culture within each political unit. On the contrary, as in medievalEurope, it generatespoliticalunits whichare either smaller or much larger than culnual boundaries would indicate; only very 'Elie Kedourie, Naziamlinn, London, 1960. 40 THE TRANSITION TO NATIONALISM occasionally, by accident, it produced a dynastic state which corresponded, more or less, with a language and a culture, as eventually happened on Europe's Atlantic seabord. (The fit was never very close. Culture in agrarian society is much more pluralistic than its empires, and generally much broader than its small participatory social units.) All this being so, the age of transition to industrialism was bound, according to our model, also to be an age of nationalism, a period of turbulent readiustment, in which either political boundaries, or cultural ones, or both, were being modified, so as to satisfy the new nationalistimperativewhich now, for the fusttime, was makingitself felt. Because rulers do not surrender territory gladly (and every change of a political boundary must make someone a loser), because changing one's culture is very frequently a most painful experience, and moreover, because there were rival cultures struggling to capm e the souls of men, just as there were rival centres of political authoritystriving to subom men and capture territory: given all this, it immediately follows from our model that this period of transition was bound to be violent and contlict-ridden. Actual historical facts fully confirm these expectations. Nevertheless, it would not be correct to proceed by simply workingout the implicationsof the implementationof the nationalist imperative for agrarian society. Industrial society did not arrive on the scene by divinefiat. It was itself the fruit of developmentswithin one particular agrarian society, and these developments were not devoid of their own turbulence. When it then conquered the rest of the world, neither this global colonization, nor the abandonment of empire by those who had been carried forward on the wave of industrial supremacy but eventually lost rheir monopoly of it, were peaceful developments. All this means that in actual history the effects of nationalism tend to be conflated with the other consequences of industrialism. Though nationalismis indeed an effect of industrial social organization, it is not the only effect of the imposition of this new social form, and hence it is necessary to disentangle it from those other developments. The problem is illustrated by the fascinating relationship between the Reformation and nationalism. The stress of the Reformation on literacy and scripturalism, its onslaught on a monopolistic priesthood (or, as Weber clearly saw, its universalization rather than abolition of priesthood), its individualism and links with mobile urban populations, all make it a kind of harbinger of social features and attitudes which, accordingto our model, produce the nationalist age. The role of Protestantism in helping to bring about the indusmal world is an enormous, complexand contentious topic; and there is not much point in doing more than cursorily alluding to it here. But in parts of the globein which both industrialism and nationalism came later and under external impact, the full relationship of Protestant-type attitudes and nationalism is yet to be properly explored. This relationship is perhaps the most conspicuous in Islam. The cultural history of the Arab world and of many other Muslim lands during the past hundred years is largely the story of the advance and victory of Reformism, a kind of IslamicProtestantism with a heavy stresson scrip&alism and above all a sustained hostility to spiritual brokerage, to the local middlemen between man and God (and, in practice, between diverse groups of men), who had become so very prominent in pre-modem Islam. The history of this movement and thatof modemArab (andother)nationalismscan hardly beseparated from each other. Islam always had an in-built proclivity or potential for this kind of 'reformed' versionof the faith, and had been seduced away from it, presumably, by the social need of autonomous rural groups for the incarnated, personalized location of sanctity which is invaluable for local mediation purposes. Under modem conditions its capacity to be a more abstractfaith, presidingover an anonymous community of equal believers, could reassert itself. But even religions which might be thought to have had little inherent potential for such 'protestant' interpretation, could nonetheless be turned in that direction during the age when the drives to indusmalism and to nationalism were making their impact. Formally speaking, one would not expectShintoismto have any marked resemblance to, say, English nonconformity. Nevertheless, during the Japanese modernization drive, it was the sober, orderly, as it were Quaker e1,ements in it (which evidently can be found or imposed anywhere if one tries hard enough) which were stressed to the detriment of any ecstatic elements and any undue privatefamiliarity with the sacred.' Had ancient Greece survived into the modem age, Dionysiaccultsmight have assumed a more sobergarb as Hellas lurched forward along the path of development. 'Personal communicationfrom Ronald Dore. 42 THE TRANSITION TO NATIONALISM Apart from the links between the Protestant and nationalistethos, there are the direct consequences of industrialization itself. The general and pervasive consequences of an established industrial order have already been discussed, in connection with our general model linking the industrial division of labour with the irnplementation of the nationalist principle. But certain specific consequences of early industriahation which do not generally persist later nevertheless have a signScant role to play. Early industrialism means populationexplosion, rapid urbanization, labour migration, and also the economic and political penetration of previously more or less inward-turnedcommunities, by a global economyand a centralizing polity. It means that the at least relatively stableand insulated Babel system of traditional agrarian communities, each inward-turned, kept separate by geography sideways, and by an enormous social distanceupwards, is replacedby quitea new kind of Babel, with new cultural boundaries that are not stable but in constant and dramatic movement, and which are seldom hallowed by any kind of custom. There is also a link between nationalism and the processes of colonialism, imperialism and de-colonization. The emergence of industrial society in Western Europe had as its consequence the virtual conquest of the entire world by Europeanpowers, and sometimes by Europeansettler populations. In effect the whole of Africa, America, Oceania, and very large parts of Asia came under European domination; and the parts of Asia which escaped this fate were often under strong indirect influence. This global conquest was, as conquests go, rather unusual. Normally, political empire is the reward of a military orientationand dedication. It is perpetrated by societies strongly committed to warfare, either because, let us say, their tribal form of life includes an automatic military training, or because they possess a leading stratum committed to it, or for some such similar reason. Moreover, the activity of conquest is arduous and takes up a large part of the energy of the conquering group. None of this was true of the European conquest of the world. It was eventually carried out and completed by nations increasingly oriented towards indusuy and trade, not by a militaristic machine, nor by a swarm of temporarily cohesive tribesmen. It was achieved *&out any total preoccupation with the process on the part of the conqueror nations. The point made about the English, that they acquired their Empire in a state of absence of mind, can to some extent be generalized. (The English also, most laudably, lost the THE TRANSITION TO NATIONALISM 43 Empire with a similar lack of attention.) When Europe was conquering and dominatingthe world, it had, on the whole, other, more pressing and internal things to occupy its attention. It did not even pay the conquered nations the compliment of being specially interested in the conquest. A few untypical periods of self-consciousand vaingloriousimperialismapart, and disregarding the early conquest of Latin America, which was inspired by good old-fashioned noncommercial rapacity, that was how it was. The conquest had not been planned, and was the fruit of economic and technological superiority, and not of a military orientation. With the diffusion of this technological and economic might, the balance of power changed, and between about 1905 and 1960 the pluralisticEuropean empire was lost or voluntarilyabandoned. Once again, the specificcircumstancesof all this cannot be ignored; even if the core or essenceof nationalism flows from the general, abstractly formulable premisses which were initially laid out, nevertheless the specific forms of nationalist phenomena are obviously affected by these circuqstances. A mte on rhe weakness of ~ ~ h 0 n a ~ k m It is customary to commenton the strengthof nationalism.Thisis an important mistake, though readily understandable since, whenever nationalism has taken root, it has tended to prevail with ease over other modem ideologies. Nevertheless, the clue to the understanding of nationalism is its weaknessat least as much as its strength. It was the dog who faded to bark who provided the vital clue for SherlockHolmes. The numbers of potential nationalismswhich failed to bark is far, far larger than those which did, though they have captured all our attention. We have already insisted on the dormant nature of this allegedly powerful monster during the pre-industrialage. But eTJenwithin the age of nationalism, there is a further importanf sense in which nationalism remains astonishingly feeble. Nationalism has been defined, in effect, as the striving to make culture and polity congruent, to endow a culture with its own political roof, and not more than one roof at that. Culture, an elusive concept, was deliberately left undefined. But an at least provisionally acceptable criterion of culture might be language, as at least a sufficient, if not a necessary 44 THETRANSITION TO NATIONALISM touchstone of it. Allow for a moment a difference of language to entail a difference of culture (though not necessarily the reverse). If this is granted, at least temporarily, certain consequences follow. I have heard the number of languages on earth estimated at around 8000. The figure can no doubt be increased by counting dialects separately. If we allow the 'precedent' argument, this becomeslegitimate: if akindof differentialwhich insomeplacesdefines a nationalism is allowed to engender a 'potential nationalism' wherever else a similar difference is found, then the number of potential nationalisms increases sharply. For instance, diverse Slavonic, Teutonic and Romance languages are in fact often no further apart than are the mere dialects within what are elsewhere conventionally seen as unitary languages. Slav languages, for instance, are probably closer to each other than are the various forms of colloquial Arabic, allegedly a single language. The 'precedent' argumentcan also generate potential nationalisms by analogies invoking factors other than language. For instance, Scottish nationalism indisputably exists. (It may indeed be held to contradict my model.) It ignores language (which would condemn some Scots to Irish nationalism,and the rest to English nationalism), invoking instead a shared historical experience. Yet if such additional links be allowed to count (as long as they don't contradict the requirement of my model, that they can serve as a base for an arenmlly homogeneous, internally mobile culmelpolity with one educational machine servicing that culture under the surveillance of that polity), then the number of potential nationalismsgoes up even higher. However, let us be content with the figure of 8000, once given to me by a linguist as a rough number of languages based on what was no doubt rather an arbitrary estimateof languagealone. The number of states in the world at present is somefigureof the order of 200. To this figure one may add all the irredentist nationalisms, which have not yet attained their state (and perhaps never will), but which are struggling in that direction and thus have a legitimate claim to be counted among actual, and not merely potential, nationalisms. On the other hand, one must also subtract all those states which have come into being without the benefit of the blessing of nationalist endorsement, and which do not satisfy the nationalistcriteria of political l e g i b c y , and indeed defy them; for instance, all the diverse mini-states dotted about the globe as survivals of a pre-nationalist THE TRANSITION TO NATIONALISM 45 age, and sometimes brought forth as concessions to geographical accident or political compromise. Once all these had been subtracted, the resulting figure would again, presumably, not be too far above 200. But let us, for the sake of charity, pretend that we have four timesthat number of reasonablyeffectivenationalismson earth, in other words, 800 of "them.Ibelieve this to be considerablylarger than the facts would justify, but let it pass. This rough calculation still gives us only one effective nationalism for ren potential ones! And this surprising ratio, depressing presumably for any enthusiasticpan-nationalist, if such a person exists, could be made much larger if the 'precedent' argumentwere applied to the full to determinethe number.of potential nationalisms,and if thecriteriaof entry into the classof effectivenationalismswere made at all stringent. What is one to conclude from this? That for every single nationalism which has so far raised its ugly head, nine others are still waiting in the wings? That all the bomb-throwing, martyrdoms, exchangeofpopulations, and worse, which haveso far bet humanity, are still to be repeated tenfold? I think not. For every effective nationalism, there are n potential ones, groups defmed either by shared culture inherited from the agrarian world or by some other link (on the 'precedent' principle) which could give hope of establishing a homogeneous industrial community, but which neverthelessdo not bother to struggle, which fail to activate their potential nationalism, which do not even try. So it seems that the urge to make mutual cultural substitutability the basis of the state is not so powerful after all. The members of some groups do indeed feel it, but members of most groups, with analogous claims, evidently do not. To explain this, we must return to the accusation made against nationalism: that it insists on imposing homogeneity on the populations unfortunate enough to fall under the sway of authorities possessed by the nationalist ideology. The assumption underlying this accusation is that traditional, ideologically uninfected authorities, such as the Ottoman Turks, had kept the peace and extracted taxes, but otherwise tolerated, and been indeed profoundly indifferent to, the diversity of faiths and cultures which they governed. By contrast, their gunman successors seem incapable of resting in peace till they have imposed the nationalist principle of cuius regio, eius lingua. They do not want merely a fiscal surplus and obedience. 46 THE TRANSITION TO NATIONALISM They thirst after the cultural and linguistic souls of their sub- jects. This accusation must be stood on its head. It is not the case that nationalism imposes homogeneity out of a wilful cultural Machtbediifiiss; it is the objectiveneed for homogeneity which is reflected in nationalism.If it is the case that a modem industrialstate can only function with a mobile, lirerate, culturally standardized, interchangeable population, as we have argued, then the illiterate, halfstarved populations sucked from their erstwhile rural cultural ghettoes into the melting pots of shanty-towns yearn for incorporation into someoneof those cultural pools which already has, or looks as if it might acquire, a state of its own, with the subsequent promise of full cultural citizenship, access to primary schools, employment,and all. Often, these alienated, uprooted, wandering populations may vacillatebetween diverseoptions, and they may often come to a provisional rest at one or another temporary and transitional cultural resting place. But there are some options which they will refrain from trying to take up. They will hesitate about trying to enter cultural pools within which they know themselves to be spurned; or rather, within which they expect tocontinue to be spurned. Poor newcomersare, of course, almost always spurned. The question is whether they will continue to be slighted, and whether the same fate will await their children. This will depend on whether the newly arrived and hence least privileged stratum possessestraits which its membersand their offspring cannot shed, and which will continue to identify them: genetically transmitted or deeply engrained religious-culturalhabits are impossible or dillicult to drop. The alienated victims of early industrialism are unlikely to be tempted by cultural pools that are very small-a languagespoken by a coupleof villagesoffers few prospects- or very diffused or lacking in any literary traditions or personnel capable of carryingskills, and so on. They require cultural pools which are large, and/or have a good historic base, or intellectual personnelwell equipped to propagate the culture in question. It is impossible to pick out any single qualiiication, or set of qualitications, which will either guarantee the success as a nationalist catalyst of the culture endowed with it (or them), or which on the contrary will ensure its failure. Size, historicity, reasonably compact territory, a capable and energetic intellectualclass: allthesewillobviously help; but no singleoneis necessary, THE TRANSITION TO NATIONALISM 47 and it is doubtful whether any fm predictive generalization can be established in these terms. That the principle of nationalism will be operative can be predicted; just which groupings will emerge as its carriers can be only loosely indicated, for it depends on too many historic contingencies. Nationalism as such is fated to prevail, but not any one particular nationalism. We know that reasonably homogeneous cultures, each of them wid its own political roof, its own political servicing, are becoming the norm, widelyimplemented but for few exceptions; but we cannot predict just which cultures, with which political roofs, will be blessed by success. On the contrary, the simple calculations made above, concerning the number of cultures or potential nationalisms and concerning the room available for proper national states, clearly shows that most potential nationalisms must either fail, or, more commonly, will refrain from even trying to fmd political ex- pression. This is precisely what we do find. Most cultures or potential nationalgroups enter the age of nationalism without even the feeblest effort to benefit from it themselves. The number of groups which in terms of the 'precedent' argument could try to become nations, which could defme themselves by the kind of criterion which in some other place does in fact definesome real and effective nation, is legion. Yet most of them go meekly to their doom, to see theirculture(though not themselvesasindividuals)slowlydisappear, dissolving into the wider culture of some new national state. Most cultures are led to the dustheap of history by industrial civilization without offeringany resistance. The linguistic distinctivenessof the Scottish Highlands within Scotland is, of course, incomparably greater than the cultural distinctivenessof Scotland within the UK; but there is no Highland nationalism. Much the same is m e of Moroccan Berbers. Dialectal and cultural differences within Germany or Italy are as great as those between recognized Teutonic or Romance languages. Southern Russians differ culturally from Northem Russians, but, unlike Ukrainians, do not translate thisinto a sense of nationhood. Does this show that nationalism is, after all, unimportant? Or even that it is an ideologicalartefact, an invention of febrile thinkers which has mysteriously captured some mysteriously susceptible nations? Not at all. To reach such a conclusion would, ironically, comecloseto a tacit, obliqueacceptanceof the nationalistideologue's 48 THE TRANSITION TO NATIONALISM most misguided claim: namely, that the 'nations' are there, in the very nature of things, only waiting to be 'awakened' (a favourite nationalist expression and image)from their regrettableslumber, by the nationalist 'awakener'. One would be infening from the failure of most potential nations ever to 'wake up', from the lack of deep stirrings waiting for reveille, that nationalism was not important after all. Such an inference concedes the social ontology of 'nations', only admitting, with some surprise perhaps, that some of them lack the vigour and vitality needed if they are to the destiny which history intended for them. But nationalism is wr the awakening of an old, latent, dormant force, though that is how it does indeed present itself. It is in reality the consequence of a new form of social organization, based on deeply internalized, education-dependent high cultures, each protected by its own state. It uses some of the pre-existent cultures, generally transforming them in the process, but it cannot possibly use them all. There are too many of them. A viable higher culturesustaining modem state cannot fall below a certain minimal size (unlessin effect parasitic on its neighbours); and there is only room for a limited number of such states on this earth. The high ratio of determined slumberers, who will not rise and shine and who refuse to be woken, enables us to turn the tables on nationalism-as-seen-by-itself. Nationalismseesitself as a natural and universal orderingof the politicallife of mankind, only obscured by that long, persistent and mysterious somnolence. As Hegel expressed this vision: 'Nations may have had a long history before they f d y reach their destination - that of forming themselves into state^'^ Hegel immediately goes on to suggest that this pre-state period is really 'pre-historical' (sic): so it would seem that on this view the real history of a nation only begins when it acquiresits own state. If we invoke the sleeping-beautynations, neither possessing a state nor feeling the lack of it, against the nationalist doctrine, we tacitly accept its social metaphysic, which sees nations as the bricks of which mankind is made up. Critics of nationalismwho denounce the politicalmovement but tacitly accept the existence of nations, do not go far enough. Nations as a natural, God-given way of classifying men, as an inherent though long-delayed political destiny, are a 'G.W.F. Hegel,Lecturesa thePhiIosophy of W'orIdHisroty,tr. H.B. Nisbet, Cambridge, 1975, p. 134. THE TRANSITION TO NATIONALISM 49 myth;nationalism, which sometimes takes pre-existing cultures and turnsthem into nations, sometimes invents them, and often obliterates pre-existingcultures: rhat is a reality, for better or worse, and in general an inescapable one. Those who are its historic agents know not what they do, but that is another matter. But we must ndt accept the myth. Nations are not inscribed into the nature of things, they do not constitutea political version of the doctrine of natural kinds. Nor were national states the manifest ultimate destiny of ethic or cultural groups. What do exist are cultures, often subtly grouped, shading into each other, overlapping, intertwined; and thereexist, usually but not always, political unitsof all shapes and sizes. In the past the two did not generally converge. There were good reasons for their failing to do so in many cases. Their rulers established their identity by differentiating themselves downwards, and the ruled micro-communities differentiated themselves laterally from their neighbours grouped in similar units. But nationalism is not the awakening and assertion of these mythical, supposedlynatural and given units. It is, on the contrary, the crystallization of new units, suitable for the conditionsnow prevailing, though admittedly using as their raw material the cultural, historical and other inheritancesfrom the pre-nationalistworld. This force - the drive towards new units constructed on the principles corresponding to the new division of labour- is indeed very strong, though it is not the only force in the modem world, nor altogether irresistible. In most cases it prevails, and above all, it determines the nmm for the legitimacy of political units in the modem world: most of them must satisfy the imperativesof nationalism, as described. It sets the accepted standard, even if it does not prevail totally and universally, and some deviant cases do succeed in defying the norm. The ambiguity of the question - is nationalism strong or not? arises from this: nationalism sees and presents itself as the affirmation of each and every 'nationality'; and these alleged entities are supposed just to be there, like Mount Everest, since long ago, antedating the age of nationalism. So, ironically, in its own terms nationalism is astonishinglyweak. Most of the potential nations, the latent differentiable communities which could claim to be nations by criteria analogous to those which somewhere else have succeeded, fail altogether even to raise their claim, let alone press it effectively and make it good. If, on the other hand, one interprets nationalism in the manner which I hold to be correct, and which indeed contradicts and offends its own self-image, then the conclusion must be that it is a very strong force, though not perhaps a unique or irresistible one. Wild and garden cultures One way of approaching the central issue is this. Cultures, like plants, can be divided into savage and cultivated varieties. The savage kindsare produced and reproduce themselvesspontaneously, as parts of the life of men. No community is without some shared system of communication and norms, and the wild systems of this kind (in other words, cultures) reproduce themselves from generation to generation without conscious design, supervision, surveillance or special nutrition. Cultivated or garden cultures are different, though they have developed from the wild varieties. They possess a complexity and richness, most usually sustained by literacy and by specialized personnel, and would perishif deprivedof their distinctivenourishment in the form of specialized insti~ti0nSof learning with reasonably numerous, full-time and dedicated personnel. During the agrarian epoch of human history the high culturesor great traditions became prominent, important, and in one sense, but one sense only, dorninant. Though they could nor altogether impose themselves on the totality, or even the majority of the population, nevertheless they generally succeeded in imposing themselves on it as authoritative, even if (or because) they were inaccessible and mysterious. They sometimes strengthened, and sometimes competed with, the centralized state. They could also deputize for that state, when it weakened or disintegrated during times of troubles or a dark age. A church or a ritual system could stand in for the shadow of a past or ghost empire. But the high cultures did not generally define the limits of a political unit, and there are good reasons why, in the agrarian age, they should not have been able to do so. In the industrial age all this changes. The high cultures come to dominate in quite a new sense. The old doctrines associated with them mostly lose their authority, but the literateidiomsand styles of communication they carried become far more effectively authoritative and normative, and, above all, they come to be pervasive and universal in society. In other words, virmally everyone becomes THE TRANSITIONTO NATIONALISM 51 literate, and communicates in an elaborate code, in explicit, fairly 'grammatical' (regularized) sentences, not in context-bound grunts and nods. But the high culture, newly universalized in the population, now badly needs political support and underpinning. In the agrarian age, it sometimes had this and benefited from it, but at other times it could dispense with political protection, and that was indeed one of its strengths. In a dark age when anarchy prevailed and the king's peace was no longer kept, Christian or Buddhist monasteries, dervish zawiyus and Brahmin communities could survive and in some measure keep alive the high culture without benefit of protection by the sword. Now that the task of the high culture is so much greater and so much more onerous, it cannot dispense with a political infrasuucmre. As a character in No Orchidsfor MissBlandish observed, every girl ought to have a husband, preferably her own; and every high culture now wants a state, and preferably its own. Not every wild culture can.become a high culture, and those without serious prospects of becoming one tend to bow out without a struggle; they do not engender a nationalism. Those which think they do have a chance-or, if anthropomorphictalk about culturesis to be avoided, those whose human carrierscredit them wirhgood prospects-fight it out among themselves for available populations and for the available state-space. This is one kind of nationalist or ethnic conflict. Where existing politicalboundaries, and those of old or crystallizing high cultures with political aspirations, fail to be in harmony, another kind of conflict so highly characteristicof the age of nationalism breaks out. Another analogy, in addition to the above botanical one, is available to describe the new situation. Agrarian man can be compared witha naturalspecieswhich survivein the natural environment. Industrial man can be compared with an & d y produced or bred species which can no longer breathe effectively in the naturegiven atmosphere, but can only functioneffectivelyand survive in a new, specially blended and dicially sustained air or medium. Hence he livesin specially bounded and constructed units, a kind of giant aquarium or breathing chamber. But these chambers need to be erected and serviced. The maintenance of the life-giving and life-preservingair or liquid within each of these giant receptaclesis not automatic. It requires a specialized plant. The name for this --u7~--lvlrrv1mm1-1~~N~15 plant is a national educationaland communications system. Its only effective keeper and protector is the state. Ir would not in principle be impossible to have a single such culturaYeducationalgoldfish bowl for the entire globe, sustained by a single political authority and a single educational system. In the long run this may yet come to pass. But in the meantime, and for What is a Nation? very good reasons yet to be discussed, the global norm is a set of discontinuous breathing chambers or aquaria, each with its own proprietary, not properly interchangeable, medium or atmosphere. We are now at last'in a position to attempt some kind of plausible They do share some general traits. The fo~~nulafor the medium of answer to this question. Initially there were two especiallypromising the fully developed industrialgoldfish bowis is fairly similar in type, candidates for the construction of a theory of nationality: will and though it is rich in relatively supe cial, but deliberately stressed, culture. Obviously, each of them is important and relevant; but, just brand-differentiating characteristics. as obviously, neither is remotely adequate. It is insmctive to conThere are some good and obvious reasons for this new pludism, sider why this is so. which will be exploredfurther. The industrialage inherited both the No doubt will or consent contitutes an important factor in the political units and the cultures, high and low, of the preceding age. formationof most groups,large and small. lllankindhasalways been There was no reason why they should allsuddenly fuse into a single organized in groups, of all kinds of shapes and sizes, sometimes one, and thereweregood reasons why they should not: industrialism, sharply defined and sometimes loose, sometimes neatly nested and in other words the type of production or of the division of labour sometimes overlapping or intertwined. The variety of these possiwhich makes these homogeneous breathing tanks imperative, did bilities, and of the principleson whichthe groups were recruitedand not arrive simultaneously in all parts of the world, nor in the same main~ined,is endless. But two generic agents or catalysts of group manner. The differential timing of its arrival divided humanity into formation and maintenance are obviously crucial: will, voluntary rival groups very effectively. These differences in arrival-rime of adherence and identification, loyalty, solidarity, on the one hand; utilize some cultural, genetic or similar differentiae, left behind by constitute extreme poles along a kind of spectrum. A few communithe agrarianworld. The datingof 'development' constitutes a crucial ties may be based exclusively or very predominantly on one or the political diacritical mark, if it can seize upon some cultural differ- other, but they must be rare. Most persisdng groups are based on a ence inherited from the agrarian age, and use it as its token. mixture of loyalty and identification (on willed adherence), and of The process of industrialization took place in successive phases extraneous incentives, positive or negative, on hopes and fears. Ewe define nations as groups which will themselves to persist as with new gains and losses to be made and avoided. Internationalism communities,' the defdon-net that we have cast into the sea will was often predicted by the prophetsand commentatorsof the indus- bringforth far too rich a catch. The haul whichweshall have trawled trial age, both on the left and on the right, but the very opposite in wi. indeed include the communities we may easily recognize came to pass: the age of nationalism. as effective and cohesive nations: these genuine nations do in effect will themselves to be such, and their life may indeed constitute a kind of continuous, informal, ever self-reaffirming plebiscite. But (unfortunately for this definition) the same also applies to many 'Ernest Renaa, 'Qu'estse qu'une Nation', republished in Ernen Renan et P A l h g n e , Textes receuillis et comment6s par Emile Bure, NY, 1945. 54 WHAT IS A NATION? other clubs, conspiracies, gangs, teams, parties, not to mention the many numerous communities and associations of the pre-industrial age which were nor recruited and defmed according to the nationalist principle and which defy it. Will, consent, identifcation, were not ever absent from the human scene, even though they were(and continue to be) also accompanied by calculation, fear and interest. (It is an interesting and moot question whether sheer inertia, the persistence of aggregates and combinations, is to he counted as tacit consent or as something else.) The tacit self-identifiation has operated on behalf of all kinds of groupings, larger or smaller than nations, or cutting across them, or defined horizontally or in other ways. In brief, even if will were the basis of a nation (to paraphrase an idealist definition of the state), it is also the basis of so much else, that we cannot possibly define the nation in this manner. It is only because, in the modem, nationalist age, nationalunits are thepreferred, favouredobjects of iden cation and willed adherence, that the definition seems tempting, because those other kinds of group are now so easily forgotten. Those who take the tacit assumptions of nationalism for granted erroneously also credit them to humanity at large, in any age. But a d e f ~ t i o n tied to the assumptions and conditions of one age (and even then constituting an exaggeration), cannot usefully be used to help to explain the emergence of that age. Any d e f ~ t i o nof nations in terms of shared culture is another net which brings in far too rich a catch. Human historyis and continues to be well endowed with cultural differentiations. Cultural boundaries are sometimes sharp and sometimes fuzzy; the patterns are sometimes bold and simple and sometimes tortuous and complex. For all the reasons we have stressed so much, this richness of differentiation does not, and indeed cannot, normally or generally converge either with the boundaries of political units (the jurisdictions of effective authorities) or with the boundaries of units blessed by the democratic sacraments of consent and will. The agrarian world simply could not he so neat. The industrial world tends to become so, or at least to approximate to such simplicity; but that is another matter, and there are now special factors making it so. The establishment of pervasive high cultures (standardized, literacy-and education-basedsystems of communication), a process rapidly gathering pace throughout the world, has made it seem, to anyone too deeply immersed in our contemporaryassumptions, that WHAT IS A NATION? 55 nationality may be defmble in terms of shared culture. Nowadays people can live only in units defmed by a shared culture, and internallymobileand fluid. Genuine cultural pluralism ceases to be viable under current conditions. But a little bit of historical awareness or sociological sophistication should dispel the illusion that this was always so. Culturally plural societies often worked well in the past: so well, in fact, that cultural plurality was sometimesinvented where it was previously lacking. If, for such cogent reasons, these two apparently promising paths towards the definition of nationality are barred, is there another way? The great, but valid, paradox is this: nations can be defmed only in terms of the age of nationalism, rather than, as you might expect, iheother way round. It is not the case that the 'age of nationalism' is a mere summation of the awakening and political self-assertion of this, that, or the other nation. Rather, when general social conditions make for standardized, homogeneous, cenrrally sustained high cultures, pervadingentire populationsand not justelite minorities, asituationarisesin which well-defmededucationally sanctioned and unified cultures constitute very nearly ihe only kind of unit with which men willingly and often ardently identify. The cultures now seem to be the natural repositoriesof political legitimacy. Only then doesit come to appear that any defmce of their boundaries by political units ~0nStituteSa scandal. Under these conditions, though under these conditions only, nations can indeed he defmed in terms both of will and of culture, and indeed in terms of the convergence of them both with political units. In these conditions, men will to be politically united with all those, and only those, who share their culture. Polities then will to extend their boundaries to the limits of their cultures, and to protect and impose their cultur~with the boundaries of their power. The fusion of will, culture and polity becomes the norm, and one not easily or frequently defied. (Once, it had been almost universally defied, with impunity, and had indeed passed unnoticed and undiscussed.) These conditionsdo not definethe human situationas such, but merely its industrial variant. It is nationalism which engenders nations, and not the other way round. Admittedly, nationalism uses the pre-existing, historically erited proliferation of cultures or cultural wealth, though it uses em very selectively, and it most often transforms them radically. 56 WHATIS A NATION? Dead languages can be revived, traditions invented, quite fictitious pristine purities restored. But this culturally creative, fanciful, positively inventive aspect of nationalist ardour ought not to allow anyone to conclude, erroneously, that nationalism is a contingent, artificial, ideological invention, which might not have happened, if only those damned busy-body interferingEuropean thinkers, not content to leave well alone, had not concocted it and fatefully injected it into the bloodsmm of otherwise viable political communities. The cultural shreds and patches used by nationalismare often arbitrary historical inventions. Any old shred and patch would have served as well. But in no way does it follow that the principle of nationalism itself, as opposed to the avatars it happens to pick up for its incarnations, is itself in the least contingent and accidental. Nothing could be further from the truth than such a supposition. Nationalism is not what it seems, and aboveallit is not what it seems to itself. The cultures it claims to defend and reviveareoften its own inventions, or are modified out of all recognition. Nonetheless the nationalist principle as such, as distinct from each of its specific forms, and from the individually distinctive nonsense which it may preach, has very very deep roots in our shared cnrrent condition, is not at all contingent, and will not easily be denied. Durkheim taught that in religious worship society adores its own camouflaged image. In a nationalist age, societies worship themselves brazenly and openly, spurning the camouflage. At Nuremberg, Nazi Germany did not worshipitself by pretendingto worship God or even Wotan; it overtly worshipped itself. In milder but just as significantform,enlightenedmodernisttheologiansdo not believe, or even take much interest in, the doctrines of their faith which had meant so much to their predecessors. They treat themwith a kind of comic auto-functionalism,as valid simplyand only as the conceprual and ritual tools by means of which a social tradition affirms its values, continuity and solidarity, and they systematically obscure and play down the difference between such a tacitly reductionist 'faith', and the real thing which had preceded it and had played such a crucial part in earlier European history, a part which could never have been played by the unrecognizably diluted, watered-down current versions. But the fact that social self-worship, whether virnlent and violent or gentle and evasive, is now an openly avowed collective selfworship, rather than a means of covertly revering society though the WHAT IS A NATION? 57 image of God, as Durkheim insisted, does not mean that the current style is any more veridical than that of a Durkheimian age. The community may no longer be seen through the prism of the divine, but nationalism has its own amnesias and selections which, even when they may be severelysecular, can be profoundlydistortingand deceptive. The basic deception and self-deception practised by nationalism is this: nationalism is, essentially, the general imposition of a high culture on society, where previously low cultures had taken up the lives of the majority, and in some cases of the totality, of the population. It means that generalized diffusion of a school-mediated, academy-supervised idiom, codified for the requirementsof reasonably precise bureaucratic and technologicalcommunication. It is the establishment of an anonymous, impersonal society, with mutually substitutable atomized individuals, held together above all by a shared culture of this kind, in place of a previous complex structure of local groups, sustained by folk cultures reproduced locally and idiosyncratically by the micro-groupsthemselves. That is what really happens. But this is the very opposite of what nationalism affirmsand what nationalists fervently believe. Nationalism usually conquers in the name of a putative folk culture. Its symbolism is drawn from the healthy, pristine, vigorous life of the peasants, of the Volk, the narod. There is a certain element of truth in the nationalist selfp~esentationwhen the narod or Volk is ruled by officialsof another, an alien high culture, whose oppression must be resisted fmt by a culturalrevivaland redfurnation, andeventually bya war of national liberation. If the nationalism prospers it eliminates the alien high culture, but it does not then replaceit by the old local low culture; it revives, or invents, a local high (literate, specialist-transmitted) cultureof its own, though admittedlyone which will have somelinks with the earlier local folk styles and dialects. But it was the great ladies at the Budapest Opera who really went to town in peasant dresses, or dresses claimed to be such. At the present time in the Soviet Union the consumers of 'ethnic' gramophone records are not the remaining ethnic rural population, but the newly urbanized, appartment-dwelling,educated and multi-lingual population,' who 'YU. V. Bromley er al., Sovrmnye Emcheskre Protsessy v SSSR (Contmporary E h c Processesin the USSR),Moscow, 1975. like to express their real or imaginedsentimentsand roots, and who will no doubt indulge in as much nationalist behaviour as the political situation may allow. So a sociological self-deception,a visionof reality through a prism of illusion, still persists, but it is not the same as that which was analysed by Durkheim. Society no longer worships itself through religious symbols; a modem, streamlined, on-wheels high culture celebrates itself in song and dance, which it borrows (stylizing it in the process) from a folk culture which it fondly believes itself to be perpetuating, defending, and reaffirming. The course of true nationalism m e 7 did mn m o t h I A characteristic scenario of the evolution of a nationalism -and we shall have cause to return to this kind of scenario -ran something like this. The Ruritanians were a peasant population speaking a group of related and more or less mutually intelligible dialects, and inhabiting a series of discontinuous but not very much separated pockets within the lands of the Empire of Megalomania. The Ruritanian language, or rather the dialects which could be held to compose it, was not really spoken by anyone other than these peasa,~ts. The aristocracy and officialdom spoke the language of the Megalornanian court, which happened to belong to a language group &ferentfromthe oneof which theRuritaniandialectswerean offshoot: Most, but not all, Ruritanian peasantsbelonged to a church whose limgy was taken from another linguisticgroup again, and many of the priests, especially higher up in the hierarchy, spoke a language which was a modem vernacular version of rhe liturgicallanguage of this creed, and which was also very far removed from Ruritanian. The petty traders of the small towns servingthe Ruritaniancounnyside were drawn from a different ethnic group and religion still, and one heartily detested by the Ruritanian peasanny. In the past the Ruritanian peasantshad had many griefs, movingly and beautifnlly recorded in theu iament-songs (painstakingly colIected by village schoolmasterslatein the nineteenthcentury, and made well known to the international musical public by the compositions of the great Ruritanian national composer L.). The pitiful oppression of the Ruritanian peasantry provoked, in the eighteenth centnry, the guerrilla resistance led by the famous Ruritanian s o d WHAT IS A NATION? 59 bandit K., whose deeds are said still to persist in the local folk memory, not to mention several novels and two fdms, one of them produced by the nationalartist Z., under highestauspices, soon after the promulgation of the Popular Socialist Republic of Ruritania. Honesty compels one bo admit that the social bandit was captured by his own compatriots, and that the tribunalwhich condemnedhim to a painful death had as its president another compatriot. Furrhermore, shortly after Ruritania frst attained independence, a circular passed between its Ministries of the Interior, Justice and Education, considering whether it might not now be more politic to celebrate thevillage defence units which had opposedthe social bandit and his gangs, rather than the said social bandit himself, in the interest of not encouraging opposition to the police. A careful analysis of the foik songs so painstakingly collected in the nineteenth century, and now incorporated in the repertoire of the Ruritanian youth, camping and sports movement, does not disclose much evidence of any serious discontent on the part of the peasanuywirhtheirlinguistic and culturalsituation, howevergrieved they were by other, more earthy matters. On the contrary, such awareness as there is of linguistic pluralism within the lyrics of the songs is ironic, jocular and good-humoured, and consists in pan of biigual puns, sometimes in questionable taste. It must also be admitted that one of the most moving of these songs- I often sang it by the camp fire at the holiday camp to which I was sent during the summer vacations- celebrates the fate of a shepherd boy, grazing three bullocks on the seigneurial clover (sic) near the woods, who was surprised by a group of social bandits, req ng him to surrender his overcoat. Combining reckless folly with lack of political awareness, the shepherd boy refused and was killed. I do not know whether this song has been suirably re-written since Ruritania went socialist. Anyway, to return to my main theme: though the songs do oftencontain complaints about the condition of the peasantry, they do not raise the issue of cultural nationalism. That was yet to come, and presumablypost-dates the composition of the said songs. In the nineteenth century a population explosion occurred at the same time as cenain other areas of the Empire of Megalomania - but not Ruritania - rapidly indusuialized. The Ruritanian peasants were drawn to seek work in the indusuially more developed areas, and some secured it, on the dreadful terns prevailingat the time. As backward rustics speakingan obscureand 60 WHATIS A NATION? seldom written or taught language, they had a particularly rough deal in the towns to whose slums they had moved. At the same time, some Ruritanian lads destined for the church, and educated in both the court and the liturgicallanguages, becameinfluenced by the new liberalideas in the courseof their secondaryschooling, and shifted to a secular training at the university, ending not as priests but as journalists, teachers and professors. They received encouragement from a few foreign, non-Ruritanian ethnographers, musicologists and historians who had come to explore Ruritania. The continuing labour migration, increasingly widespread elementaryeducationand conscription provided these Ruritanian awakeners with a growing audience. Of course, it was perfectly possible for the Ruritanians, if they wished to do so (and many did), to assimilate into the dominant language of Megalomania. No genetically transmitted trait, no deep religious custom, differentiated an educated Ruritanian from a similar Megalomanian. In fact, many did assimilate, often without bothering to change their names, and the telephone directory of the old capital of Megalomania (now the Federal Republic of Megalomania) is quite fullof Ruritanian names, though often rather comically spelt in the Megalomanian manner, and adapted to Megalomanian phonetic expectations. The point is that after a rather harsh and painful start in the first generation, the life chances of the offspring of the Ruritanian labour migrant were not unduly bad, and probably at least as good (given his willingness to work hard) as those of his non-Ruritanian Megalomanian fellow-citizens. So these offspring shared in the eventually growing prosperity and general embourgeoisement of the region. Hence, as far as individual life chances went, there was perhaps no need for a virulent Ruritanian nationalism. Nonetheless something of the kind did occur. It would, I think, be quite wrong to attribute conscious calculation to the participants in the movement. Subjectively, one must suppose that they had the motives and feelings which are so vigorously expressed in the literature of the national revival. They deplored the squalor and neglectof their home valleys, while yet also seeing the rustic virtues still to be found in them; they deplored the discrimination to which their conationals weresubject, and the alienationfrom their nativeculture to which they were doomed in the proletarian suburbs of the industrial towns. They preached against these ills, and had the hearing of at least many of their fellows. The manner in which, when the international political situation came to favour it, Ruritania eventually attainedindependence, is now part of the historical record and need not be repeated here. There is, one must repeat, no need to assume any consciouslongterm calculation of interest on anyone's part. The nationalist intellectuals were full of warm and generousardour on behalf of the conationals. When they d o ~ e dfolk costume and trekked over the hills, composing poems in the forest clearings, they did not also dream of one day becoming powerful bureaucrats, ambassadors and ministers. Likewise, the peasants and workerswhom they succeeded in reaching felt resentment at their condition, but had no reveries about plans of industrial developmentwhich one day would bring a steel mill (quite useless, as it then turned out) to the very heart of the Ruritanian valleys, thus totally ruining quite a sizeable area of surrounding arable land and pasture. It would be genuinely wrong to try to reduce these sentiments to calculations of material advantage or of social mobility. The present theory is sometimes travestiedas a reduction of national sentiment to calculation of prospects of social promotion. But this is a misrepresentation. In the old days it made no sense to ask whether the peasants loved their own culture: they took it for granted, like the air they breathed, and were not conscious of either. But when labour migration and bureaucratic employment became prominent features within their social horizon, they soon learned the difference between dealing with a co-national, one understanding and sympathizing with their culture, and someone hostile to it. This very concrete experience taught them to be aware of their culture, and to love it (or, indeed, to wish to be rid of it) without any conscious calculation of advantages and prospects of social mobility. In stable self-containedcommunitiesculture is often quite invisible, but when mobility and context-free communication come to be of the essence of social life, the culture in which one has been taught to communicate becomes the core of one's identity. So had there been such calculation (which there was not) it would, in quite a number of cases (though by no means in all), have been a very sound one. In fact, given the at least relative paucity of Ruritanian intellectuals, those Ruritanians who did have higher quafications secured much better posts in independent Ruritania than most of them could even have hoped for in Greater Megalomania, where they had to compete with scholastically more developed 62 WHAT IS A NATION? ethnic groups. As for the peasants and workers, they did not benefit immediately; but the drawing of a political boundary around the newly defined ethnic Ruritania did mean the eventual fosteringand protection of industries in the area, and in the end drastically diminished the need for labour migration from it. What all this amounts to is this: during the early period of industrialization,entrants into the new order who are drawn from cultural and linguistic groups that are distant from those of the more advanced centre, suffer considerable disadvantages which are even greater than those of other economically weak new proletarianswho have the advantage of sharing the culture of the political and economic rulers. But the culturalllinguistic distance and capacity to differentiate themselves from others, which is such a handicap for individuals, can be and often is eventually a positive advantage for entire collectivities, or potential collectivities, of these victims of the newly emergent world. It enables them to conceive and express their resentments and discontents in intelligible terms. Ruritanians had previously thought and felt in terms of family unit and village, at most in terms of a valley, and perhaps on occasion in terms of religion. But now, swept into the melting pot of an early industrial development, they had no valley and no village: and sometimes no f d y . But therewere other impoverished and exploited individuals, and a lot of them spoke dialects recognizably similar, while most of the better-off spokesomethingquite alien; and so the n e i concept of the Ruritanian nation was born of this contrast, with some encouragement from those journalists and teachers. And it was not an illusion: the attainment of some of the objects of the nascent Ruritanian national movement did indeed bring relief of the ills which had helped to engender it. The relief would perhaps have come anyway; but in this national form, it also brought forth a new high culture and its guardian state. This is one of the two important principlesof fission which determine the emergence of new units, when the industrial world with its insulated cultural breathing tanks comes into being. It could be called the principle of barriers to communication, barriers based on previous, pre-industrial cultures; and it operates with special force during the early period of industrialization. The other principle, just as important, could be called that of inhibitors of social entropy; and it deserves separate treatment. Social Entropy and Equality in Industrial Society The transition from agrarian to industrial society has a kind of entropy quality, a shift from pattern to systematic randomness. Agrarian society, with its relatively stable specializations, its persisting regional, kin, professional and rank groupings, has a clearly marked social structure. Its elements are ordered, and not distributed at random. Its sub-cultures underscoreand fortify thesestructural differentiations,and they do not by setting up or accentuating cultural difference within it in any way hamper the functioning of the society at large. Quite the contrary. Far from frnding such cultural differentiations offensive, the society holds their expression and recognition to be most fitting and appropriate. Respect for them is the very essence of etiquette. Industrial society is different. Its territorial and work units are ad hoc: membership is fluid, has a great turnover, and does not generally engage or commit the loyalty and identity of members. In brief, theold structures are dissipatedand largely replaced by an internally random and fluid totality, within which there is not much (certainly when compared with the preceding agrarian society) by way of genuine sub-structures. There is very little in the way of any effective, binding organization at any level between the individual and the total community. This total and ultimate political community thereby acquires a wholly new and very considerable importance, beinglinked (as it seldom was in the past) both to the state and to the cultural boundary. The nation is now supremely important, thanks both to the erosion of sub-groupingsand the vastly increasedimportance of a shared, literary-dependent culture. The state, inevitably, is charged with the maintenance and supervision of an enormous socialinfrastructure (the cost of which characteristically comes close to one half of the total income of the society). The educational system becomes a very crucial part of it, and the maintenance of the culturalllinguistic medium now becomes the central role of 64 SOCIAL ENTROPY AND EQUALITY education. The cirizens can only breathe conceptually and operate within that medium, which is co-extensive with the territory of the state and its educationaland cultural apparatus, and which needs to be protected, sustained and cherished. The role of culture is no longer to underscore and make visible and authoritative the structural differentiationswithin society (even if some of them persist, and even if, as may happen, a few new ones emerge); on the contrary, when on occasion cultural differences do tie in with and reinforce status differences, this is held to be somewhat shameful for the society in question, and an index of partial failure of its educationalsystem. The task with which that system is entrusted is to turn out worthy, loyaland competentmembersof the totalsociety whose occupancyof postswithin it will not be hampered by factional loyalties to sub-groups within the total community; and if some part of the educational system, by default or from surreptitious design, actually produces internal cultural differences and thereby permits or encourages discrimination, this is counted as something of a scandal. Obstacles to entropy All this is only a reformulationof our general theory of the bases of nationalism, of the new role of culture in mobile, educated, anonymous societies. But an important point is brought out by stressing the need for this random-seeming, entropic mobility and distribution of individualsin this kind of society. Within it, though subcommunities are partly eroded, and their moral authority is much weakened, nevertheless people continue to differ in all kinds of ways. People can be categorized as tall and short, as fat and thin, dark and light, and in many other ways. Clearly, there is simply no limit to the number of ways in which people can be classified. Most of the possible classificationswill be of no interest whatever. But some of them become socially and politically very important. They are those which I am tempted to call entropy-resistant. A classification is entropy-resistant if it is based on an attribute which has a marked tendency not to become, even with the passageof time since the initial establishment of an industrial society, evenly dispersed throughout the entire society. In such an entropy-resistant SOCIAL ENTROPY AND EQUMITY 65 case, those individuals who are characterized by the trait in question will tend to be concentrated in one part or another of the total society. Suppose a society contains a certain number of individuals who are, by an acciden~ofheredity, pigmentationally blue; and suppose that, despite the passage of a number of generations since the initial establishment of the new economy, and the official promulgation and enforcement of a policy of la cam-&-eouverte aux talents, most blues stubbornly persist in occupying places either at the top, or at the bottom, of the society in question: in other words, the blues tend to capture either too many, or too few of the advantagesavailable in this society. That would make blueness a social-entropy-resistant trait, in the sense intended. Note, by the way, that it is always possible to invent traits which, at any given moment, may seem entropy-resistant. It is always possibleto invent a concept which will applyonly to this or that class of people. But the entropy-resistanceof a concept, in this sense, will normally be of interest only if it is a reasonably natural notion, one already in use in the society in question, rather than artificially invented for the present purpose. Then, if it is unevenly distributed in the wider society, trouble may well ensue. The rest of this argument can now easily be anticipated: entropyresistant traits constitute a very serious problem for industrial society. Almost the reverse was true of agrarian society. Far from deploring entropy-resistant traits, that kind of society habitually invented them, whenever it found itself insufficiently supplied with this commodity by nature. It liked to suppose that certain categories of men were natural rulers, and that others were natural slaves, and sanctions were deployed-punitive, ideological- to persuademen eo conformwith theseexvectations and indeed to internalizethem. The society invented dubious human attributes or origins whose main purpose was, precisely, to be entropy-resistant.The religiouselitein Muslim tribal lands is often defined and legitimated in terms of descent from the Prophet; status among central Asian tribes is often expressed in terms of descent from Genghiz Khan's clan; European aristocracies frequently believe themselves to be descended from a distinct conquering ethnic group. Entropy-resistance creates fissures, sometimes veritable chasms, in the industrial societiesin which it occurs. How does this fissurepronenessdifferfrom that engenderedmerely by cultural differences 66 SOCIALENTROPY AND EQUALITY and communication problems which take place in early industrial society, and which were discussed in the preceding section? The two phenomena do have a certain affmity and overlap. But the differences are also important. The differential access to the languagelcultureof the moreadvancedpoliticaland economiccentre, which hampers natives of more peripheral cultures and impels them and their leaders towards a cultural and eventually political nationalism, is, of course, also an entropy-resistance of a kind. The migrant labourers who do not even speak a dialectal variant of the main state languageused by bureaucratsand entrepreneurs, will, for that very reason, be far more likely initially to remain at the bottom of the social hierarchy, and hence incidentally be less able to correct and compensate the disadvantages which haunt them, either for themselves or for their children. On the other hand, when their language(or rather, a standardizedand streamlinedversionof one of its dialects) becomes the educational, bureaucraticand commerciallanguage o'f a newly independent nationalist state, these particular disadvantages wiU disappear, and their cultural characteristics will cease to be entropy-resistant. But it is important to note that in our hypothetical case they could also have escaped their handicap by assimilatingto the old dominant language and culture; and in fact, many men did take this path. There is no reason to suppose that thosewho have trodden it are less numerous than thosewho took the nationalist option. Indeed, many must have taken both paths, successively or simultaneously.' For instance, many have become irredentist nationalists on behalf of a culture which was not that of their genuine origins, assimilating first, and then taking up political cudgels to ensure full high culture status, and its own political state roof, for their new culture. But what differentiates this kind of case, crucially important though it is, from other kinds of entropy-resistance, is this: if all that is really at stake is a communication gap (but crucially linked to general status and economic disadvantage), then this can be remedied by either of the two methods discussed: a successful nationalism, or assimilation; or an overlap of both. But there are forms of entropy-resistance whose fissiparous social consequences cannot be remedied by correctingthe communication disadvantagealone. The secondoption, of assimilationthrough education, is barred. Thereis 'F. Colonna, InstituteursAlgh-iens, 1883-1939, Paris, 1975. more than a communication barrier involved. If the first option (successful irredentism, in effect) also happens to be closed by the balanceof politicalpower, the situationis grave, and will continueto fester. Failure to communicate, such as arises between entrants from an alien culture into an industrializing area, is one form of entropyinhibition (though one which can often easily be overcome in a generationor so); but the obverse does not hold, and not all entropyinhibitions are due to a mere failure to communicate. Those which are not due to a mere communication failure, and are remediable neither by assimilationinto the dominant pool, nor by the creationof a new independent pool using the native mediumof the entrants, are correspondinglymore tragic. They constitute a problem whose solution is not yet in sight, and which may well be one of the gravest issues that industrial society has to face. Let us return to our hypothetical case of a pigmentationally blue sub-population within the wider society, and let us suppose that for one reason or another this population is concentrated near the bottom of the social scale. Industrial societies are quite inegalitarian in providing their citizens with a wide variety of social positions, some very much more advantageous than others; but they are also egalitarian in that this system of posts forms a kind of continuum (there are no radical discontinuities along it), and that there is a widespread belief, possibly exaggerated but not wholly devoid of truth, that it is possibleto move up and down, and that rigid barriers in the system are illegitimate. Compared at any rate with most agrarian societies, industrial society is astonishingly egalitarian, and there is, in developed industrial society, a marked convergence of life-stylesand a great dimunitionof social distance. But in our hypothetical case of a blue-colouredpopulation, which is concentrated at the bottom, the conjunction of easy idensability (blue is a conspicuous colour) with the non-random, counter-entropic distribution of this category of people (the blues) has some very unfortunate consequences. It is' safe to assume that populations frequently differ in some measure in their innate talents. The supposition that all talents are distributed with absolute equality is about as probable as a land which is totally flat. It is equally obvious that when it comes to the deployment of talents, social factors are far more important than innateendowment. (Some of the populations most closely associated with theachievementsof humanityin recent centurieswere backward savagesnotso manygenerationsearlier, thoughitisunlikelythat their genetic equipment could have changed much in the brief period which elapsed between their barbarism and their world-historical prominence- which seems to prove this pcint.) The whole question does not matter too much, in as far as it is obvious that the spans of abilityoccurringwithin given'ethnic' or'racial' groups are far greater than the differences between the averages of such diverse groups. Something very important follows from all this. The blues are concentrated at the bottom, and it may even be that their performance is, on average, inferior to that of groups more randomly distributed. No-one knows whether this is due to genetic differences or to social factors. But one thing is certain: within the blue population, there will be many who are much abler, much more fit in terms of whatever criteria of performance may currently be relevant and applied, than very many members of non-blue segments of the total population. What will now happen, in the situation as described and defined? The association of blueness with low position will have created a prejudice against blues. When those at the bottom appear to be, chromatically or in whatever way you choose, a random sample of the population, then the prejudice against them cannot spread to some other specific trait, for occupancy of the lowest position is not specifically connected with any other trait, ex hypothesi. But if so many of those at the bottom are blue, then the prejudice which is engenderedamongslightlyhigher strata against those below them by the fear of being pushed downwards, inevitablyspreads to blueness. Infact, non-bluegroups low down the s d ewill be speciallyprone to anti-blue feelings, for they will have precious little else to be proud of, and they will cling to their only and pathetic distinction, nonblueness, with special venom. However, very many of the blues will be on the way up, in spite of prejudiceagainst them. The concentrationof the bluesat the bottom is only statistical, and many blues (even if they are themselves but a minority within their own blue sub-population)will, by dint of hard work, ability or luck be on the way up and have achieved a higher position. What happens to them? We have assunled that blueness is, for one reason or another, ineradicable. So the condition of the ascending blues will be painful and fraught with tension. Whatever their individual merits, to their SOCIALENTROPY AND EQUALITY 69 random non-blue acquaintances and encounters (and it is of the essence of a mobile complex industrial society that so many human contacts are random, fleeting, but nonetheless sign5cant), they will still be the dirty, lazy, poor, ignorant blues; for these traits, or similar ones, are associated with the occupancy of positions low down on the social scale. In all this, the rising blue is perhaps not much worse off than the rising Ruritanian migrant worker in our previousexample; but there is one overwhelminglyimportant difference. Ruritanian culture can be shed; blueness cannot. We have also assumed that the Ruritanians had a territorial base: there is an area, the Ruritanian heartland, where peasants speaking some version of Ruritanian were in a majority. So, onceagain, Ruritanians had two ways out: assimilation into Megalomanian language or culture, or the establishment of a glorious independent Ruritania, where their patois would be turned intoan officialand literarylanguage. Each of the two alternativeshas been successfully tried in different places and by different people. Ex hypothesi, however, the blues are devoid of the first of these two options. Their give-away blueness stays with them, do what they will. Moreover, Megalomanian culture is old and has a wellestablished self-image, and blueness is excluded from it. What aboui the second option, the establishment of national independence? As a matter of historical and contemporary fact, populations finding themselves in the kind of situation corresponding to those of our blues sometimes do, and sometimes do not, possess a territorial base of their own. In the former case, they thereby do have at least one of the two options availableto the Runtanians, and if it is politicallyand militarilyfeasible they may take it. If, however, the hypothetical blues possess no territorial base in which they can plausibly hope to establish an independent blue land, or alternatively, if they do have one, but this blue homeland is, for one reason or another, too exiguous and unattractive to secure the returnto it of the bluesdispersedin other regions), then the plight of the blues is serious indeed. In this kind of situation grave sociological obstacles, not easily removable by mere good will and legislation or by political irredentism and activism, block the way to that cultural homogeneity and social entropy which is not merely the norm of advanced industrial society, but also, it seems, a condition of its smooth functioning. Where this systematicentropy-inhibitionoccurs, it may wellconstituteone of the gravest dangersthat industrialsociety must face. Conversely, while the blue populations are blocked in both directions, neither smooth assimilation nor independence being easily available to them, some other populations may be doubly blessed. In a federal state, populations such as our hypothetical Ruritaniansmay simultaneously possessan autonomous Ruritania in which Ruritanian is the official language, and yet also, at the same time, thanks to the small cultural distance between them and other cultures in the federal state, and to the non-identifiability of assimilated Ruritanians, be able to move smoothly, frictionlessly, in an entropic way, in the wider state. It is, I suppose, for Ruritanians to decide whether this double advantage is worth the price they pay; namely, that the Ruritanian canton or federal autonomous republic is not fully independent. Some cases which fit this general description remain within the widerfederal state voluntarily, and some have been deprived of this option by force. Quebec would seem to exemplify the fist situation; Iboland, in Nigeria, the second. The question then arises: what are the kinds of attribute in the reali world which resemble the 'blueness' of our hypothetical example? Geneticallytransmitted traits are one specimenof such blueness, but one specimen only; and the other, non-genetic species of it are at least as important. One must also add that not any genetically transmitted trait will have the effect of producing a fissure in society. Ginger-headedness, for example, causes some people to be teased as children; and on the other hand, redheads among women are sometimes deemed specially attractive. Moreover, some ethnic groups are said to have a disproportionatenumber of red-headed members; but despite these facts andlor folk beliefs, red hair does not, all in all, generate conflicts or social problems. Part of the explanation must be, to use the term previouslyintroduced for this purpose, that red hair is fairly entropic, notwithstandingany allegedethnic correlation. Physicaltraits which, though genetic, have no strong historic or geographicalassociations tend to be entropic; and even if they do d d l y correlatewith social advanI tage or disadvantage, this tends to remain socially unperceived. By contrast, in Ruanda and Urundi physical height related to ethnic fiation and political status in a very marked way, both in fact and in ideology, the conquering pastoralists being taller than the local agriculturalists,and both being taller than the pygmies. But in most other societies, this correlationis looseenough not to becomesociallyI SOCIAL ENTROPY AND EQUALITY 71 significant. Etonians, it appears, are on average taller than others; but tall guardsmen in the ranks are not deemed upper class. Physicalor geneticallytransmitted traits are but one kind of 'blueness'. What of the others? It is a supremely important and interesting fact that some- deeply engrained religious-cultural habits possess a vigour and tenacity which can virtually equal those which are rooted in our genetic constitution. Language and formal doctrinal belief seem less deep rooted and it is easier to shed them; but that cluster of intimate and pervasive values and attitudes which, in the agrarian age, are usually linked to religion (whether or not they are so incorporated in the official high theology of the faith in question) frequently have a limpet-like persistence, and continue to act as a diacritical mark for the populations which carry them. For instance, at the time when Algeria was legally counted as a part of France, the assimilation of Algerian migrant workers in France was not hampered by any physical, genetic difference between, say, a Kabyle and a southern French peasant. The generally impassable fissure between the two populations, precluding an assimilationist solution, was cultural and not physical. The deeply rooted communal conflict in Ulster is not based, obviously, on any communications gap between the two communities, but on an identification with one of two rival local cultures which is so firm as to be comparable to some physical characteristic, even if, in reality, it is sociallyinduced. Terrorist organizations.whosenominal doctrine, or rather verbiage, is some kind of loose contemporary revolutionary Marxism, are in fact exclusively recruited from a community once defined by a religious faith, and continuing to be defined by the culture which had been linked to that faith. A fascinating and profoundly revealing event recently occurred in Yugoslavia: in Bosnia the ex-Muslim population secured at long last, and not without arduous efforts, the right to describe themselves as Muslim, when filling in the 'nationality' slot on the census. This did not mean that they were still believing and practising Muslims, and it meant even less that they were identifying as one nationality with other Muslims or ex-Muslims in Yugoslavia, such as the Albanians of Kosovo. They were Serbo-Croat speakers of Slav ancestry and Muslim cultural background. What they meant was that they could not describe themselves as Serb or as Croat (despite sharing a language with Serbs and Croats), because these identifications carried the implications of having been Orthodox or Catholic; and to describe oneself as 'Yugoslav' was too abstract, generic and bloodless. They preferred to describe themselves as 'Muslim' (and were now at last officially allowed to do so), meaning thereby Bosnian, Slav ex-Mushs who feel as one ethnic group, though not differentiable linguistically from Serbs and Croats, and though the faith which does distinguish them is now a lapsed faith. Justice Oliver Wendell Holmes once observed that to be a gentleman one does not need to know Latin and Greek, but one must have forgotten them. Nowadays, to be a Bosnian Muslim you need not believe that there is no God but God and that Mohamed is his Prophet, but you do need to have lost that faith. The point of transition from faith to culture, to its fusion with ethnicity and eventually with a state, is neatly illustrated by an exchange in that classic study of the role of the military in a developing country, Anton Chekhov's Three Sisters: Tuzenbach:Perhaps you think- this German is getting over-excited. Buton mywordof honour,I'm Russian. I cannot evenspeak German. My father is Orthodox. The Baron, despite his Teutonic name and presumably ancestry, defends his Slav status by reference to his Orthodox religion. To say this is not to claim that each and every pre-industrial religion will tend to make a new appearance as an ethnic loyalty in the industrial melting-pot. Such a view would be absurd. For one thing, as in the case of languages and of cultural differentiations, theagrarianworld is often far too well providedwith religions. There were too many of them. Their number was too large, when compared with the number of ethnic groups and nationalstatesfor which there can possibly be room in the modern world. So they simply could not all suryive (even in transmogrified form, as ethnic units), however tenacious they might be. Moreover, as in the case of languages, many of them are not really so very tenacious. It is the high religions, those which are fortified by a script and sustained by specializedpersonnel, whichsometimes, but by no meansalways, become the basis of a new collectiveidentity in the industrial world, making the transition, so to speak, from a culture-religion to a culture-state. Thus in the agrarian world, high culture co-exists with low cultures, and needs a church (or at least a clerkly guild) to sustain it. In the industrid world high cultures prevail, but they need a state not a church, and they need a state each. That is one way of summing up the emergence of the nationalist age. High cultures tend to become the basis of a new nationality(as in Algeria) when before the emergence of nationalism the religion defined fairly closely all the under-privileged as against the privileged, even or especiallyif the under-privilegedhad no other positive shared characteristic (such as language or common history). There had previously been no Algerian nation prior to the nationalist awakening in this century, as Ferhat Abbas, one of the principal early nationalist leaders in that country, observed. There had been the much wider community of Islam, and a whole set of narrower communities, but nothing corresponding even remotely to the inhabitants of the present national territory. In such a case a new nation is in effect born, defined as the totalityof all the adherents of a givenfaith, within a given territory. (In the case of the Palestinians today, language and culture and a shared predicament, but not religion, seem to be producing a similar crystallization.) To perform the diacritical, nation-definingrole, the religion in question may in fact need to transform itself totally, as it did in Algeria: in the nineteenth century, Algerian Islam with its reverence for holy lineages was for all practical purposes co-extensive with rural shrine and saint cults. In the twentieth century it repudiated all this and identified with a reformist scripturalism, denying the legitimacy of any saintly mediation between man and God. The shrines had defined tribes and tribal boundaries; the scripturalism could and did defme a nation. Fissures and barriers Our general argument might be re-stated as follows. Industrialization engenders a mobile and culturally homogeneous society, which consequently has egalitarian expectations and aspirations, such as had been generally lacking in the previous stable, stratified, dogmatic and absolutist agrarian societies. At the same time, in its early stages, industrial society also engenders very sharp and painful and conspicuous inequality, all the more painful because accompanied by great disturbance, and because those less advantageously placed, in that period, tend to be not only relatively, but also absolutely miserable. In that situation - egalitarian expectation, nonegalitarian reality, misery, and cultural homogeneity already desired but not yet implemented - latent political tension is acute, and becomes actual if it can seize on good symbols, good diacritical marks to separate ruler and ruled, privileged and underprivileged. Characteristically, it may seize on language, on genetically transmitted traits ('racism'), or on culture alone. It is very strongly impelled in this direction by the fact that in industrializingsocieties\ communicationand henceculture assumesa new and unprecedented importance. Communication becomes important because of complexity, interdependence and mobility of productive life, within which far more numerous, complex, precise and context-free messages need to be transmitted than had ever been the case before. Among cultures, it is the ones linked to a high (literate) faith which seem most likely to fill the role of crystallizer of discontent. Local folk faiths and cultures, like minor dialects, are less likely to aspire so high. During the early period of industrialization, of course, low cultures are also liable to be seized on and turned into diacritical markers of the disadvantaged ones, and be used to identifyand unite them, if they look politicallypromising, notablyif they define large and territorially more or less compact populations. During that early stage, several contrasts are liable to be superimposed on privilege and underprivilege: ease of access to the new style of life and.its educational precondition, as opposed to hampered access (easy or inhibited communication), a high and low culture. This is the type of fissure-generation where the lack of actual communication is crucial, because it marks out and highlights an objective difference. Later, when owing to general development the communication barrier and the inequalities are no longer so great, and when a shared industrial style enables people to communicate even across diverse languages, it is rather the persistent unevenly distributed ('counter-entropic') traits which become really crucial, whether they be genetic or deep-cultural. At that stage, the transformation of erstwhile low cultures into a new high one, in the interests of providing a banner for a whole wide category of the underprivilegedwho may previously have lacked any way of hailing each other and uniting, is no longer quite so probable; the period of acute misery, disorganization, near-starvation,total alienation of the lower strata is over. Resentment is now engendered less by some objectively intolerable condition (for deprivation now is, as the phrase goes, relative); it is now brought about above all by the SOCIAL ENTROPY AND EQUALITY non-randomsocialdistribution of somevisibleand habituallynoticed trait. The difference between the two stages, early and late, can be put as follows.In the earlystage there is a terrible difference between the life chances of the well-off and the starving poor, those who can swim in the new industrial pool and those who are only painfully learning to do so. Even then, the conflict will seldom become acute or escalate indefinitely, contrary to Marxist predictions, unless the privileged and the others can identify themselves and each other culturally, 'ethnically'. But if they can so tell each other apart, then, generally speaking, a new nation (or nations) is born; and it can organize itself around either a high or a previously low culture. If a high culture is not ready-made and available, or has already been taken over by a rival group, why then a low oneis transformed into a high one. This is the age of the birth (or allegedly 'rebirth') of nations, and of the transmuting of low cultures into newly literate high ones. The next stage is different. It is no longer the case that an acute objective social discontentor a sharp social differentiation is seeking out any old cultural differentiationthat may be to hand, and will use it if it can to create a new barrier, indeed eventually a new frontier. Nowit is only a genuineprior barrier to mobility and equality which will, having inhibited easy identifcation, engender a new frontier. The difference is considerable. A diversity of focus Some special cases desemespecific comment. Islamic civilization in the agrarian age conspicuously illustrated our thesis that agrarian societiesare not prone to use culture to definepoliticalunits; in other words, that they are not given to being nationalistic. The loose guild of ulam, of scholars-lawyers-theologiansY 1 who set the tone and morally dominated the traditional Muslim world, was trans-poltical and trans-ethnic, and not tied to any state (once the Khalifatewith its monopolistic pretensions to providing the unique political roof for the entire community had disintegrated), nor to any 'nation'. IN. Keddie (ed.), Scholars, Sain~and Sufi, Berkeley, 1972; E. Gelher, Muslim Society, Cambridge, 1981. 76 SOCIAL ENTROPY AND EQUALITY The folk Islam of shrine and holy lineage, on the other hand, was sub-ethnic and sub-political (as far as major units, resembling historic and 'national' states, are concerned), serving and reinforcing instead the vigorous local self-defence and self-administrationunits (tribes). So Islam was internally divided into a high and a low culture, the two flowing into each other, of course, and intimately related and intertwined, but also periodically erupting into conflict, when 'remembrancers' revived the alleged pristine zeal of the high culture, and united tribesmen in the interests of purification and of their own enrichment and political advancement. But the changes produced in this way did not, in the traditional order (though they occurred quite often) produce any deep, fundamental structural change. They only rotated the personnel, they did not fundamentally alter the society.' With the comingof the travail of modernization, things turned out quite differently. We have argued that in general this means, among other things, the replacement of diversified, locality-tied low cultures by standardized, formalized and codified, literacy-carried high cultures. But Islamic society was ever ideally prepared, by an accident of history, for this development. It possessed within itself both a high and a low culture. They had the same name, and were not always carefully distinguished, and were often deliberately conflated and fused; they were linked to each other. Both, in the past, could be and were the means of a whole-hearted, passionate identification with a (supposedly unique). Islam, as an absolute, uncompromising and final revelation. Islam had no church perhaps, but the church it did not have was a broad one. In the modern world, the low or folk variant can be and is disavowed, as a corruption, exploited if not actually invented or instigated by the alien colonialist enemy, while the high variant becomes the culture around which a new nationalism can crystallize. This is particularly easy in the case of the one linguisticgroup whose language is linked to that of the unique revelation; it is also easy in those cases in which the entire nation is idened with Islam and is surrounded by non-Muslim neighbours (Somalis, Malays); or when the entire discriminated-againstpopulation, though not linguistically homogeneous, is Muslim and opposed to non-Muslim privileged power-holders (Algeria), or when the nation is habitually defined in terms of one Muslim sect, and its 'Ibn Khaldun, The Muqaddimah, tr. F. Rosenthal, London, 1958. resentment directed against a provocatively secularized and Westernized ruling class and against non-Mush foreigners (Iran). The uniqueness of Islam can perhaps be brought out best if we recapitulate our general theme. The agrarian age of mankind is a period in which some tan read and most cannot, and the industrial ageis onein whichall can and must read. In the agrarianage, literate high cultures co-exist with illiterate low or folk cultures. During the period of transition between the two ages, some erstwhile low cultures become new high cultures; and on occasion a new high culture can be invented, re-createdby political willand cultural engineering, based on elements drawn from a distant past, and reassembled to create something in effect quite new, as in Israel. But the high cultures which survive the period of transition cease to be the medium and hallmark of a clerisy or a court and becoxie instead the medium and emblem of a 'nation', and at the same time undergoanother interesting transformation. When they were carried by a court or courtly stratum or a clerisy, they tended to be transethnic and even trans-political, and were easily exportable to wherever that court was emulated or that clerisy respectedand employed; and on the other hand, they were liable to be closely tied to the usually rigid, dogmatictheology and doctrinal corpus, in terms of which the clerisy in question was defined, and the court legitimated. As is the way of literate ideologiesof the agrarian age, that corpus of doctrine had absolutist pretensions, and was reinforced by claiming on its own behalf not merely that it was true (what of that?) but that it was the very norm of truth. At the same time it issued virulent imprecations against all heretics and infidels, whose very doubts about the unique and manifest truth was evidence of their moral turpitude, of 'corruption on earth', in the vivid phrase used in death sentences by the agrarian-faith-revivingregime at present in control of Iran. These ideologiesare like fortresses-Einefeste Burg kt mein Gon- which retain all sources of water within their bastion and thus deny them to the enemy. They hold not merely a monopoly of truth (a trivial matter, that), but above all, of the very sources and touchstones of truth. The wells are all located within the ramparts, and that settles the matter, for the enemy cannot reach them. This was all very well, and a great advantage to them in the agrarianage, when they only encountered enemies at worst similar to themselves, and often feebler, unsophisticated, unfortified folk religions. The industrial age is based on economic growth. This in turn 78 SOCIAL ENTROPY AND EQUALITY hinges on cognitive growth, which was ratified (and perhaps even significantly aided) by Cartesian and empiricist philosophies. Their essence was to de-absolutize all substantive conviction about the world, and to subject all assertions, without exception, to neutral scrutiny by criteria ('experience7 , 'the light of reason') located beyond the bounds and the ramparts of any one belief system. That puts paid to their absolutist pretensions, for they must bow to a judge outside their control. Evidence becomes king, or at least king-maker. The wells of truth are henceforth located in neutral territory, and no-onecan claim to own them. That, at any rate, is the purely intellectual, doctrinal aspect of a complexstory, the wholeof which cannot be pursued here, by which the absolutist high cultures of the agrarian age are obliged to shed their absolutism, and allow the wells of truth to pass into public, neutral control. In brief, the price these high cultures pay for becoming the idiom of entire territorial nations, instead of appertaining to a clerkly stratum only, is that they become secularized. They shed absolutist and cognitive pretensions, and are no longer linked to a doctrine. Spain was one of the most retarded exceptions to this, having retained at a remarkablylate date a nationalistregime which incorporated the endorsement of absolutist Catholic claims in its image of the nation. During the earlier and timid stages of Francoist liberalization, the legalization of public Protestant worship was opposed as a kind of provocative disturbance of Spanish unity and identity. An absolute doctrine for all and a high culture for some, becomes an absolute culture for all, and a doctrine for some. The Church must surrender and dissolveitself if it is to capture the entire society. TheGreatTradition must throw off its erstwhilelegitimating doctrine, if it is to becomethe pervasiveand universal culture. In general, what had once been an idiom for some and an obligatory and prized idiom for all becomesan obligatory belief for all, and a watered-down, nsn-serious, Sunday-suitfaith for some. That is the generic fate of high culmes, if they survive the great transition. In the classical North-West European case, one may say that the process had two stages: the Reformation universalized the clerisy and unified the vernacular and the liturgy, and the Enlightenment secularized the now universalized clerisy and the now nation-wide linguisticidiom, no longer bound to doctrine or class. It is interesting to reflect what would have happened in Western Europe had industrialization and all it involves begun during the SOCIAL ENTROPY AND EQUALITY 79 High Middle Ages, before the development of vernacularliteratures and the emergence of what was eventually destined to become the basis of the various national high cultures. There would clearly have been the prospect of a clerkly-led Latin, or perhaps Romance, nationalism, as opposed to the relatively more local nationalisms which did eventually crystallize, secularizing no longer a transpolitical clerkly high culture, but a half-clerkly, half-courtly one. Had it all happened earlier, a pan-Romance nationalism would have been as plausibleas the pan-Slavismwhich was taken seriouslyin the nineteenth century, or the pan-Arab nationalism of the twentieth, which were also based on a shared clerkly high culture, co-existing with enormous differences at the low or folk level. Islam is precisely in this condition, experiencing a number of transformations simultaneously. The most protestant of the great monotheisms, it is ever Reformation-prone (Islam could indeed be described as Permanent Reformation). One of its many successive self-reformations virtually coincided with the coming of modern Arab nationalism, and can only with great difficulty be disentangled from it. The emergence of the nation and the victory of the reform movement seem parts of one and the same process. The dissolution of the vigorousold local and kin structures, whose strong and sometimes deadly shadows survive as pervasive patronage networks dominating the new centralized political.structures, goes hand in hand with the elimination of the saint cults which had ratified the mini-communal organization, and their replacement by a reformed individualistunitarian theology, which leaves the individual believer to relate himself, singly, to one God and one large, anonymous, mediation-freecommunity- all of which is virtually the paradigmof the nationalist requirement. Other high cultures which make the transition need to pay the price of abandoning their erstwhiledoctrinal underpinning and support. The bulk of the doctrines they had carried so longare so utterly absurd, so indefensible in an age of epistemic (evidence-revering) philosophies, that they become an encumbrance rather than the advantage which they had been. They are gladly, willingly shed, or turned into 'symbolic' tokens meant to indicatea link to the past, the continuity of a cormunity over time, and evasively ignored as far as their nominal doctrinal content goes. Not so with Islam. Islam had been Janus-faced in the agrarian days. One face was adapted to the religiouilyand socially pluralistic 80 SOCIALENTROPY AND EQUALITY country folk and groupings, the other set for the more fastidious, scholarly, individualistand literate urban schoolmen. Moreover, the dogma made obligatory for the latter was purified, economical, unitarian, sufficiently so to be at least relatively acceptable even in the modem age, when the baroque load carried by its rival on the north shore of the Mediterranean is pretty intolerable, and needs to be surreptitiously toned down and cast away, bit by bit. Little of this underhand purification is required south of the Mediterranean - or rather, the purification had already been carried out, loud and clear, in the nameof freeing the true faith from ignorant, rural, if not alieninspired superstition and corruption. Janus has relinquished one of his two faces. So, within the Muslim world, and particularly of course within the Arab part of it (but also among what might be called the Arab-surrogate nations, who happen locally to define themselves as the Muslims of a given area), a nationalism based on a generalized anonymous territorial community can perpetuate the specific doctrines previously carried by a clerkly stratum, proudly and without disavowingthem. The ideal of the ulama comes closer to reality, at leastwithin various nation-sizererritories, thanit had been in the days of the kin-defined fragmentation. Doctrinal elegance, simplicity, exiguousness, strict unitarianism, without very much in the way of intellectuallyoffensive frills: these helped Islam to survive in the modem world better than do doctrinally more luxuriant faiths. But if that is so, one might well ask why an agrarianideology such as Confucianism should not havesurvived even better; for such a belief system was even more f d y centred on rules of morality and the observance of order and hierarchy, and even less concerned with theological or cosmological dogma. Perhaps, however, a strict and emphatic, insistent unitarianism is better here than indifference to doctrine coupled with concern for morality. The moralities and political ethics of agro-literate polities are just a little too brazenlydeferentialand inegalitarianfor a modern taste. This may have made the perpetuation of Confucianism implausible in a modern society, at least under the same name and under the same management. By contrast, the stress on the pure unitarianism of Islam, jointly with the inevitable ambiguity of its concrete moral and political precepts, could help to create the situation where one and the same faith can legitimate both traditionalist regimes such as Saudi Arabia or Northern Nigeria, and socially radical ones such as Libya, South SOCIAL ENTROPY AND EQUALITY 81 Yemen or Algeria. The political conjurers could build their patter around the strict theology, while they shuffledthe cards dealing with political morality according to their own preference, without attracting too much attention. The unitarianism, the (sometimes painful) forswearing of the solaces of spiritual mediation and middlemen, took the believers' minds awayfrom the intellectualtransformations, which were turning a faith that had oncedealt with the inheritanceof camelsinto one prescribing or proscribing, as the case might be, the nationalization of oil wealth. If Islam is unique in that it allows the use of a pre-industrial great tradition of a clerisy as the national, socially pervasive idiom and belief of a new-style community, then many of the nationalisms of sub-Saharan Africa are interesting in that they exemplify the opposite extreme: they often neither perpetuate nor invent a local high culture (which could be difficult, indigenous literacy being rather rare in this region), nor do they elevate an erstwhilefolk culture into a new, politically sanctioned literate culture, as European nationalisms had often done. Instead, they persist in using an alien, European high culture. Sub-Saharan Africa is one of the best, and certainly the most extensive, testing grounds for the attribution of great power to the principle of nationalism, which requires ethnic and political boundaries to converge. Sub-Saharan political boundaries defy this principle h o s t without exception. Black Africa has inherited from the colonial period a set of frontiers drawn up in total disregard (and generally without the slightest knowledge) of local cultural or ethnic borders. One of the most interesting and striking features of the postcolonial history of Africa has been that nationalist, irredentist attempts to remedy this state of affairs, though not totally absent, have nevertheless been astonishinglyfew and feeble. The efforts either to replace the use of European languages as the state administrative medium, or to adjust inter-state boundaries so as to respect ethnicity, have been weak and infrequent. What is the explanation? Is nationalism not a force in black Africa after all? Wehavesuggesteda dichotomybetween'early' or communicationgap nationalisms (in which the additional disadvantagea dislocated ex-rural population incurs through not sharing the dominant culture exacerbates its resentment over its other, 'objective' deprivations), and a 'late' nationalism, engendered by obstacles other than those of communication. In terms of this important contrast, African nationalism on the whole belongs to the latter or counter-entropic type. At its core we do not find labour migrants maltreated at the factory gate by foremen speaking a different language; what we do find is intellectuals capable of fluent communication, but debarred as a categoryfrom positionsof real power by ashareddistinctivetrait: colour. They are united by a shared exclusion, not a shared culture. The phenomena associated with other early and communication-gap types of nationalism are of course not absent, and are often very important. The flashpoint of the South African conflict is obviously the conditionof the Africanindustrial proletariat;and the role of the urban lower classes in, for instance, the rise of Nkrumah was con- spicuous. The typical situation created by European domination in Africa was this: effective administrations, political units controlling and maintaining the peace in extensive and well-defined, stable areas, were set up. These administrations were extremely, conspicuously and indeed paradigmaticallycounter-entropic. The rulers and a few others were white, and everyoneelse was black. It could hardly have been simpler or more conspicuous. Seldom has there been a political system whose guiding principle was so easily intelligible, so easy to read. In the traditional agrarian world this could have been counted a positive advantage, a great aid in the avoidance of status-ambiguity and all the ills of obscure, uncertain power-relations which that can bring in its train. It would have augured well for the stability and survival-worthiness of the system. The principle was not alien to Africa, and some indigenous political structures had indeed used variants of it. The Azande were a conquering aristocracy superimposed on ethnically distinct subjects. A Fulani aristocracy ruled many of the Northern Nigerian city states. But this was no longer the traditional agrarian order. The Europeans in Africa, though occasionally respectfd of local custom and endorsing its authority, were there to set up a market- and tradeoriented, educated ('civilized') and eventually industrial type of society. But, for reasons which we have stressed at length and need not now repeat, industrial or industrializing society is profoundly allergic to counter-entropicinstitutions. Here there was an outstandingly clear, conspicuousexampleof just that! This was not a case, as in our earlier example, of a category of 'blues' being statistically too frequently located in the lower layers of society, as in the European irredentist nationalisms. Here there was a case of a small number of whites ruling large, occasionally enormous black populations. The nationalism which this engendered was simply the summation of all the blacks, the non-whitesof a given historicallyaccidental territory, now unified by the new administrativemachinery. The adherents of the new nationalism did not necessarily share any positive traits. After Independence, in the struggle for control of the newly won states, the contestantsgenerally had their power-base in this or that traditional, pre-existingethnic group. Nevertheless, the strikingfact remains the stabilityof the ethnicity-defyingfrontiers that had been arbitrarily drawn up by the colonialists, and the perpetuationof the colonial languages as the media of government and education. It is perhaps too soon to speculate whether these societies will reach the age of internal homogeneity, mobility and generalized education while continuing to use the colonial language, or whether at some point they will brave the ardours of cultural self-transformation involved in modernizing, adapting and imposing one of the indigenous languages. This process has been pioneered, for instance, in Algeria, with its extremely painful 'Arabization', which in practice means imposing a distant literary languageon local Arab and Berber dialects.' In black Africa, the linguistic indigenization is hampered not merely by the conveniencesof the alien language, with its textbooksand internationallinks, and with the heavy time-investmentin it on the part of the ruling elite, but also by the local linguistic fragmentation, far more extreme than that which had prevailed in Europe; and by the fact that the selectionof any one of the rivallocal languages would be an affront to all those to whom it is not a native tongue- and this residue generally constitutes a majority, often an overwhelminglylarge one. For these reasonsthoseAfricanethnicgroups that werelinked to a literatehigh culture through conversionto a world religion, Islam or Christianity,werebetter equippedtodevelopaneffectivenationalism ugh Roberts, 'The Unforeseen Developmentof the Kabyle Question in Contemporary Algeria', in G o v a m t and Opposition, XVII (1982), No. 3- The emergent Kabyle nationalism is interesting in that it expresses the feeling of an erstwhile small-holding peasantry which has done well out of urban migration, without losing its rural base. A similar case may be that of the Basques. See Marianne Heiberg, 'Insiders/ outsiders: Basque nationalism', in European Jam1of Sociology, XVI (1975), No. 2. 84 SOCIAL ENTROPY AND EQUALITY than the others. The region in which the struggle between these two faiths had traditionally gone on without a decisive victory for either, the Horn of Africa, is also the area with the best examples of what may be called classical nationalisms. It has been said of the Boers that the only things which really distinguished them from their Bantu enemies, when both were entering South Africa from different directions, was the possession of the Book, the wheel and the gun. In the Horn of Africa both the Amharas and the Somalis possessed both gun and Book (not the same Book, but rival and different editions), and neither bothered greatly with the wheel. Each of these ethnic groups was aided in its use of these two pieces of cultural equipment by its links to other members of the wider religious civilization which habitually used them, and were willing to replenish their stock. Both the Somalis and the Amharas were aided by these bits of equipment in state-formation. The Somalis created a few of those characteristicMuslim formations based on urban trade and tribal pastoralcohesion, brought together by some religious personage; the Amharas created in Ethiopia the one really convincing Africanspecimenof a feudalism, a looseempire with local territorial power-holders, linked to a national Church. The gun and the Book, with their centralizing potential, enabled these two ethnic groups to dominate the political history of this large region, though neither of them was numerically predominant. Other ethnic grups without the same advantages, even when far more numerous - notably the Oromo (more commonly known as the Galla)- were unable to stand up to them. At the time of the temporarily successfidSomaliadvance against the Ethiopians in the 1970s, it was plausible, and from the Somaliviewpoint attractive, to present the Oromoas a kind of human population without a set form, a preethnic raw material, waiting to be m e d either into Amharas or into Somalis by the turn of political fortune and religious conversion. This would make sense of their Somalization,shouldit come to pass. The Oromo were to be seen as an enormous population of Adams and Eves, from whom the apple of ethnicity had as yet been withheld, and who were familiar only with the rudimentary fig leaf of age-set organization. When incorporated in the Amhara state, their local chiefs would become its officials and eventually go Christian and M a r a ; but if brought into the Somali sphere, Islamization in the name of the great local saint cults would eventually mean Somalization. Since the Somali defeat in the war, however, the prospects SOCIAL ENTROPY AND EQUALITY 85 of resistingAmhara domination in the Horn hinge largely on stimulating the various national liberation fronts at long last emerging within the Ethiopian empire, including that of the Oromo, who as the largest group are also emerging as the most important; and hence we are now less likely to hear of their pre-cultural status as ethnic raw material. The Amhara empire was a prison-house of nations if ever there was one. When the old Emperor was toppled in 1974, the new rulers promptly announced, as new rulers are liable to do, that henceforth all ethnic groups were equal, and indeed free to choose their own destiny. These admirable liberal sentiments were followed fairly soon by a systematic liquidation of intellectualsdrawn from the nonAmharic group, a regrettably rational policy from the viewpoint of inhibiting the emergence of rival nationalisms within the empire.' In brief, both these vigorous and, for the present, dominant nationalismsillustrate the advantage of the availabilityof an old high culture, once an invaluable asset for state-formation, but now also crucial for fie attaining of an early political sense of ethnicity. In each of these cases the ethnic group in question seems, within the local area, co-extensive with its own faith, thus greatly aiding self- definition. The Somalis are also interesting in that they are one of the examples (like the Kurds) of the blending of old tribalism based on social structure with the new, anonymous nationalism based on shared culture. The sense of lineage affiliationis strong and vigorous (notwithstanding the fact that it is officially reprobated, and its invocation actually proscribed), and it is indeed crucial for the understanding of internal politics. This does not, I think,contradict our general theory, which maintains that the hold of a shared literate culture ('nationality') over modern man springs from the erosion of the old structures, which had once providedeach man with his identity, dignity and material security, whereas he now depends on education for these things. The Somalis possess a shared culture, which, when endowed with its own state (as indeed it is), can ensure for each Somali access on good terms to bureaucratic employment. '1oan Lewis, 'The Western SomaliLiberation Front (WSLF)and thelegacy of Sheikh Hussein of Bale', in J. Tubiana (ed.), Modern Ethiopia, Rotterdam, 1980; and I.M. Lewis (ed.), Nationalism and SeIf-detmination in the Horn of Afia, Indiana, 1983. The life chances and psychic comfort of an individual Somali are manifestly better within such a state, based on his culture, than they are within a neighbouring state not so based. At the same time, however, many Somalis remain pastoralists with an interest in the pasture rights defined in the old terms, and retain reciprocal links with kinsmen, links which appear not to be altogether forgotten in the give and take of political life. What it all amounts to is this: in most cases, theappeal of the new, education-transmittedethnicity comes from both push and pull: the attraction of the new employment opportunities and the repulsion arising from the erosion of the old security-giving kin groupings. The Somali case is not unique, even if it is particularlyconspicuous. Persistenceof pastoralismand certainkinds of labour migration or of trade networks may cause extensive kin organization to survive in the modem world. When this happens, we get a juxtaposition of tribal loyalty to structure and of nationalloyalty to culture (and a literate culture at that). But it is scarcely conceivable that the modern world could have emerged had the structural, mini-organizational rigidities remained strong everywhere. The great stories of successful economic development were about societies whose wealth and power had the demonstration effect which pointed humanity towards the new style of life; and those stories or paradigms were not and could not be of that kind. The general emergence of modernity hinged on theerosionof the multiplepetty b&ding localorganizationsand their replacement by mobile, anonymous, literate, identity-conferring cultures. It is this generalized condition which made nationalism normative and pervasive; and this is not contradicted by the occasional superimposition of both of these types of loyalty, the occasional use of kin links for a kind of interstitial, parasitic and partial adaptation to the new order. Modern industry can be paternalistic, and nepotisticat the top; but it cannotrecruit its productiveunits on the basis of kin or territorial principles, as tribal society had done. The contrast I am here drawing between culture-mediatednationalism and structure-mediated tribalismis, of course, meant to be a genuine analytical distinction between two objectively distinguishable kinds of organization; it must not be confused with the relativistic or emotive opposition between my nationalism and your tribalism. That is merely the languageof praise and invectiveby means of which rival potential nationalisms combat each other, in which 'I am a patriot, you are a nationalist and he is a tribalist', and that remains so whoever happens to be speaking. In this sense nationalismsare simply those tribalisms, or for that matter any other kind of group, which through luck, effort or circumstance succeed in becoming an effectiveforce under modern circumstances. They are only identifiableex pbstfactum. Tribalism never prospers, for when it does, everyone will respect it as a true nationalism, and no-onewill dare call it tribalism. A Typology of Nationalisms A useful typology of nationalisms can be constructed by simply working out the various possible combinations of the crucial factors which enter into the making of a modern society. The first factor to be introduced into this deductively established model is that of power.Here there is no need to play with binary or any other alternatives. There is no point in considering the possibility of the absence or diffusion of centralized power in a modern society. Modern societies are always and inevitably centralized, in the sense that the maintenanceof order is the task of one agency or group of agencies, and not dispersed throughout the society. The complex division of labour, the complementarity and interdependence and the constant mobility: all these factors prevent citizens from doubling up as producers and participants in violence. There are societies - notably some pastoral ones - where this is feasible: the shepherd is simultaneously the soldier, and often also the senator, jurist and minstrel of his tribe. The entire culture, or very nearly, of the whole society seems encapsulated in each individualrather than distributed among them in different forms, and the society seems to refrainfrom specialization, at least in its male half, to a very remarkable degree. The few specialists whom this kind of society tolerates it also despises. Whatever may be feasible among near-nomadic pastoralists, it is not remotely possible in complex modem industrial society. The specialists who compose it cannot take time off to shoot their way from home to office, take precautionary measures against a surprise raid by membersof a rival corporation,or join in a nocturnal reprisal raid themselves. Bootleggers may have done this, but they did not become the model for the modem Organization Man. M a-type businessflourishes on the whole only in areas where illegality makes theinvocationof officialenforcement agencies dficult. There would seem to be more movement from this kind of enterprise into legitimate business, than the other way. In fact, members of modem societies have little training or practice in applying or resisting A TYPOLOGY OF NATIONALISMS 89 violence. Some sectors of modern society on occasion escape this generalization, like those who must live with urban violence in decaying urban centres; and there is at any rate one economically complex society, namely Lebanon, which so far seems to have survived the disintegrationof effective central authority with astonishing resilience and success. But these relatively minor exceptions do not undermine the basic contention that in a modern society the enforcement of the social order is not something evenly diffused throughout society - as is characteristically the case among tribesmen with segmentary social organization- but is concentratedin the hands of some of the membersof society. In simpler terms, it is always the case that somewield this power and some do not. Some are closer to the command posts of the enforcement agencies than others. This engenders the admittedly loose, but nevertheless useful distinction between the powerholders and the rest, a contrast which provides us with the first element in our simplified model of modern society, which is to generate, through diverse combinations of the further elements, the various possible types of nationalism. The next element in the model is access to education or to a viable modern high culture (the two here being treated as equivalent). The notion of education or a viable modern high culture is once again fairly loose but nonetheless useful. It refers to that complex of skills which makes a man competent to occupy most of the ordinary positionsin a modem society, and which makes him, so to speak, able to s w h with ease in this kind of cultural medium. It is a syndrome rather than a strict list: no single item in it is, perhaps, absolutely indispensable. Literacy is no doubt central to it, though on occasion skilful and dbbrmillardindividuals can get by in the modern world, or even amass fortunes, without it. The same goes for elementary nurneracy and a modicum of technical competence, and a kind of non-rigid, adaptablestate of mind often encouraged by urban living, and inhibited by rural traditions. By and large, one can say-and this is, of course, important for our argument - that suitably gifted individuals or well-placed sub-communities can sometimes acquire this minimal syndrome independently, but that its wide and effective diffusion presupposes a well-maintained and effective centralized educational system. In connection with this access to education (in this sense), there are alternatives and different possible situations. With regard to power there are none: it is always the case, in an industrial society, that some have it and some do not. This provided us with our baseline situation, a society loosely divided into power-holders and the rest. But in connection with access to education, there is no such predetermined distinction. In terms of the given power-bifurcated society, there are now four distinct possibilities: it may be that only the power-holdershave access, that they use their power-privilege to preservefor themselvesthe monopolyof this access; or alternatively, that both the power-holders and the rest have this access; or again, only the rest (or some of them) have such access, and the powerholders do not (a situation not as absurd, implausible or unrealistic as might appear at first sight); or fmally, as sometimeshappens, that m i t k party enjoysthe benefitsof such access, or to put it in simpler terms, that the power-holders, and those over whom the power is exercised, are both of them packs of ignoramuses, sunk, Karl Marx's phrase, in the idiocy of rural life. This is a perfectly plausible and realistic situation, not uncommon in the course of past human history, and not totally unknown even in our age. The four possibilities envisaged or, rather, generated by our assumptions (each with two sub-alternatives in figure 2, to be explained) do correspond to realistic historic situations. When the category of those who have power roughly correspondsto those who also have access to the kind of educational training fitting them for the new life, we have something corresponding, all in all, to early industrialism. The powerless new migrants, newly drawn in from the land, are politically disenfranchized and culturally alienated, helpless vis-a-vis a situation in which they have no leverage and which they cannot understand. They constitute the classical early proletariat, as described by Marx and Engels (and as quite wrongly attributed by them to the subsequent stages of industrial society), and such as is often reproduced in the shantytowns of lands which were submerged by the wave of industrialism later. The second combination, on the other hand, corresponds to late industrialismas it actually is (and not as was erroneously predicted): great power inequality persists, but cultural, educational, life-style differenceshave diminishedenormously. The stra cation systemis smoothand continuous, not polarized, nor consistingof qualitatively differentlayers. There is a convergenceof life-style and a diminution of social distance, and the access to the new learning, to the gateway of the new world, is open to virtually all, and if by no meanson terms of perfect equality, at least without seriously debarringanyone eager to acquire it. (Only possessors of counter-entropic traits, as described, are seriously hampered.) The third and seemingly paradoxical siruaticin, in which those who wield power are )ata disadvantage when it comes to acquiring the new skiUs, does in fact occur, and represents a by no means unusual historicconstellation. In traditionalagrarian societies ruling strata are often imbued with an ethos which values warfare, impulsive violence, authority, land-owning, conspicuous leisure and expenditure, and which spurns orderliness, time or other budgeting, trade, application, thrifr, systematic effort, forethought and book learning. (The manner in which some of these traits could nevertheless become fashionableand dominant, and come to characterize the dominant strata of society, is after all rhe subject matter of the most famous of all sociological speculations, namely Weber's account of the origin of the capitalist spirit.) In consequence, these latter traits are then normally found only among more or less despised urban, commercial,+learning-orientedgroups, which may be tolerated and intermittently persecuted by their rulers. So far so good: within the traditional order, the situation acquires a certain stability. Personnel may change, the structure remains. The thrifty work-oriented accumulators are not normally permitted to displace the leisured class oriented to conspicuous consumption, because the latter regularlyfleece and occasionallymassacre them. (In the Indian case those who acquired a surplus tended to put all their money in temples to mitigate or to avoid fleecing.) But with the coming of the industrial order, in the form of the diffusion of market relations, new military and productive technologies, colonial conquest and so forth, the erstwhile stability is lost forever. And within this new unstable and turbulent world it is the values and style and orientationof those despised urban commercial groups which provide a great advantage and easy access to new sources of wealth and power, while the old compensatory mechanisms of expropriationmay no longer be availableor effective.' The '~lbert0. Hirschman, The Passim and the Interests, Princeton, 1977. It is, of course, possible that the individualist, mobile spirit preceded by many centuries, in one society at any rate, the coming of industrial order: see Alan Macfariane, The Origins of English Individualism, Oxford, 1978. That would not contradict our thesis, though it mighr throw light on the early emergence of national sentiment in England. For a summary of the counting house becomes more powerful than the sword. The singleminded use of the sword no longer takes you very far. The old rulers may, of course, sense the wind of changeand mend their ways. They did so in Prussia and Japan. But it is not at all psychologicallyeasy for them to do it quickly (or, sometimes, to do it at all), and quite often they may not do it fast enough. The result then is the situation envisaged: it is now the ruled, or at least some of them, who are at a positiveadvantage, when it comes to access to the new education and skills. Finally, there is the fourth scenario: neither rulers nor ruled may have any access to the relevant skills. This is the standard situation in any stagnant agrarian society, unaffected by the industrial world, in which both rulers and ruled are sunk in whatever combination of conspicuous display, superstition, ritualism, alcoholism or other diversion may be locallyfavoured, and when neither of them wish or are able to take the new way out. By combining the (ever-present) inequality of power with the various possible patterns of the distribution of the access to education, we have obtainedfour possiblesituations: equalaccess, equal lack of access, and access tilted either in favour of or against the power-holders.But we have as yet not introduced the element which is most crucial from the viewpoint of nationalism: identity or diversity of culture. It goes without saying here that the term 'culture' is being used in an anthropological, not a normativesense: what is meant by the term is the distinctive style of conduct and communication of a given community. The term 'culture' on its own is never used in this discussion in its other sense, as Kultur, high culture or great tradition, a style of conduct &d communication endorsed by the speaker as superior, as setting a norm which should be, but alas often is not, satisfied in real life, and the rules of which are usually codified by a set of respected, norm-givingspecialistswithin the society. 'Culture' without qualification means culture in the anthropological, nonnormative sense; Kultur appears as high culwe. The relationship between the two kinds of 'culture' is of course a matter of central importancefor our subject. The high (normative) cultures or traditions which specially concern us are, of course, literate ones. Hence way in which the present theory of nationalism fits into a wider social philosophy, see John A. Hall,Diagnoses of Our Time,London, 1981. A TYPOLOGY OF NATIONALISMS 93 the problem of access to them appears, in the present discussion, as access to education. The phrase 'access to a culture' consequently means access to culture (anthropologicalsense) which is denied to a person in virtue of his membership of another culture, and not in virtue of lack of 'education'. This perhaps pedanticclarificationwas essential if misunderstanding of the argument was to be avoided. To avoid premature complications, the diversity of cultures is introduced in the simplest possibleform. Emulating the economists who sometimes discuss worlds containingonly one or two comrnodities, we assume that in each case our society is either mono-cultural (everyone endowed with the same culture, in the anthropological sense), or alternatively, that there are two such cultures, the powerholders being a different culture from the rest. The complicationsin the real world arising from the simdtaneous presence in one sphere of three, four or more cultures, does not very seriously affect the argument. The imposition of this further binary opposition 'cultural unity1 cultural duality' on our already established four-fold typology, immediately generates eight possible situations (see Figure 2). Note first of all that lines 1, 3, 5 and 7 correspond to situations where, whatever inequalities of power or access to education may prevail, nationalism has no grip, for lack of (ex hypothexz2 cultural differentiation. Other conflicts may occur, and it is an interesting question whether indeed they do. The evidence seems to indicate that the classes engendered by early industrialism (let alone the smoother, milder stratificationproduced by its later form), do not take off into permanent and ever-escalating conflict, unless cultural differentiationprovides the spark, theline-upas it were, the means of identifying both oneself and the enemy. Clearly there was a good deal of straight class conflict in, say, 1848: Tocqueville, who did not like it, saw it as unambiguously as did Marx, who did. But it did not go on becoming ever sharper and more uncontrollable. Marxism, on the other hand, likes to think of ethnic conflict as camouflagedclass conflict, and believes that humanity would somehow benefit if the mask were tom off, if only people became clearsighted and thereby freed from nationalist prejudice and blinkers. This would seem to be a misreading both of the mask and of the reality beneath it. 'Anti-Semitism is the socialism of the stupid', the phrase once went, though it was not conspicuously echoed in the days of the Slansky trial or of the Polish purges of 1968, when a socialist regime fomented anti-Semitism. The workers, allegedly, have no country; nor, presumably, a native culture separating them from other workers, especially immigrants; nor, it would seem, any skin colour. Unfortunately the workers generally appear to be unaware of these interesting and liberating sensitivity-deprivationsthough not for any lack of being told of them. In fact, ethnicity enters the political sphere as 'nationalism' at times when cultural hcmogeneityor continuity (not classlessness)is required by the economic base of sociallife, and when consequently culture-linkedclass differences become noxious, while ethnically unmarked, gradual class differences remain tolerable. 1 A A early industrialism without ethnic catalyst 2 A B 'Habsburg' (and points east and south) nationalism E E 3 A A mature homogeneous industrialism 4 A B classical liberal Western nationalism -E E 5 A A Decembrist revolutionary, but not nationalist situation 6 A B diaspora nationalism 7 A A untypical pre -nationalist situation 8 A B typical pre-nationalist situation Figure 2 A typology of nationalism-engendering and nationalism-thwarting social situations -standsfor negation, absence. Pstandsfor power, E for access to modem-styleeducation, and A and B for names of individualcultures. Each numbered line representsone possible situation; a line containing both A and B shows a situationin which two culturesco-existin a single temtory, and a line with A and A stands for cultural homogeneity in a similar temtory. If A or B stand underan E andlora P, then the culturalgroupin question doeshaveaccessto educationor power; if it stands under -E or -P, it lacks such access. The siruation of any group is indicated by the nearest E and P above it. Line 1 corresponds to classical early industrialism, where both power and educational accessare concentratedin the hands of some; k"' but in line 1 the deprived ones are not culturallydifferentiated from the privileged ones, and consequently nothing, or at least nothing very radical, happens in the end. The conflict and cataclysm predicted by Marxism do not occur. Line 3 corresponds to late industrialism, with generabed access to education, and absence of cultural difference; and here there is even less reason to expect conflict than in line 1. We shall yet have to discuss the difficult and important question whether advanced industrialism as such in any case constitutes a shared culture, overruling the - by now - irrelevant differences of linguistic idiom. When men have the same concepts, more or less, perhaps it no longer matters whether they use different words to express them, you might say. If this is so, line 3 might characterize the shared future of mankind, after the general consummation of industrialism,if and whenit comes. This questionwill be discussed later. Line 5, once again, gives rise to no nationalist problemsand conflicts. A politicallyweaksub-groupis economically or educationally privileged, but being indistinguishable from the majority, is capable of swimmingin the general pool without detection, and, like the proverbial Maoist guerrilla, it does not attract hostile attention. Lines 7 and 8 are jointly exempt from the nationalist Problmtik for quite another reason: because the question of access to a new high culture, which is a pre-condition ofentry into and benefitsfrom thenew style of life, simply doesn't arise. Here, no-onehas it, so noone has it more than anyone else. This, of course, is the element which is crucial and central to our theory: nationalismis about entry to, participation in, identificationwith, a literate high culture which is co-extensive with an entire political unit and its total population, and which must be of this kind if it is to be compatiblewith the kind of division of labour, the type or mode of production, on which this society is based. Here, in lines 7 and 8, this mode is absent, even in the form of any awareness of it or aspiration towards it. There is no high culture, or at any rate none which possesses a tendency and capacity to generalize itself throughout the whole of society and to become the condition of its effective economicfunctioning. Line 7 is excluded from the nationalist issue twice over; once for the reasons just given, and once because it also lacks cultural differentiation which could give bite to its other problems, whatever they might be. Line 8 is more typical of complex agrarian societies than line 7: the ruling stratum is identifiableby a distinct culture, which serves as a 96 p p pppp K T ~ ~ o ~ o ~ ~OF NAT~O-MS badge of rank, diminishingambiguity and thus strain. Line 7, with access to the acquisition of the bundle of skills which enable men to its cultural continuity, is untypical for the agrarian world. perform well in the general conditions of an industrial division of Note a further difference between the picture underlying this labour, as defied. I hold this approach to be entirely justified. The typology, and the one customarily offered by Marxism. As already point is one much invoked by economistsof development of a laisser indicated, our model expects and predicts vertical conflict, between faire persuasion. Quite impecunious populations (indentured transdiverse horizontal layers, in a way which is quite different from planted Chinese coolies, for example) do astonishingly well when Marxism. It anticipatesit only in those cases where 'ethnic' (cultural endowed with the apposite attitudes; while capital poured into unor other diacritical marks) are visible and accentuate the differences suitable human contexts as an aid to development achieves nothing. in educational access and power, and, above all, when they inhibit Capital, like capitalism, seems an overrated category. the free flow of personnel across the loose lines of social stratification.' It also predicts conflict sooner rather than later in the development of industrialism (with the proviso that without ethic/ The varieties of nationalist experience cultural differentiationvirulent and decisively explosive conflict will not arise at all, early or late). But these differences in prediction are Our model was generated by the introduction of the three factors best seen not in isolation, but as consequences of the differences in that alone really matter: power, education,and shared culture, in the underlying interpretation. senses intended. Of the eight possible situations which the model At this level there are at least two very important differences generates, five are as it were non-nationalist, four of them because between the two viewpoints. One concerns a theme well explored there is no cultural differentiation, and two because the question of and much commented on among critics of Marxism: its views on the access to a centrally sustained high culture does not arise (and one of social stratification engendered by industrialism (or, in its own the specimens, of course, is included both in the four and in the terms, 'capitalism'). Our model assumes that a sharp polarization two). That leaves us with three forms of nationalism. and social discontinuitydoesindeed occur in earlyindustrialism, but Line 2 c6rresponds to what one may call the classical Habsburg that this then becomes attenuated by social mobility, diminution of (and points south and east) form of nationalism. The power-holders social distance, and convergence of life-styles. It is not denied that have privileged access to the central high culture, which indeed is great differencesin ownership persist, but it suggests that the effec- their own, and to the whole bag of tricks which makes you do well tive social consequencesof this, both hidden and perceived, become under modem conditions. The powerless are also the educationvery much less important. deprived. They share, or groups of them share, folk cultures which, Even more si&icant is the nature of the polarization that occurs withagood dealof effortandstandardizedandsustainedpropaganda, in industrial society. What distinguishesour model from the Marxist can be turned into a rival new high culture, whether or not sustained one is that control or ownership of capital wasn't even mentioned. by thememory, realor invented, of a historical politicalunit allegedly Identity of culture, accessto power, and accessto education were the once build around that same culture or one of its variants. The reonly elements fed as premisses into the model, and used for gener- quired effort is, however, very energeticallyput into this task by the ating our eight possible situations. Capital, ownership and wealth intellectuals-awakeners of this ethnic group, and eventually, if and were simply ignored, and deliberately so. These once so respected when circumstances are propitious, this group sets up a state of its factors were replaced by another one, generically designated as own, which sustains and protects the newly born, or re-born as the accessto education, by which was meant, as explained, possessionor case might be, culture. The resultingsituation is of immediateand immense advantage to 'This fact about thecrucialfiskresin society seems to havebeenrecognized the said awakeners, and eventually may also be of someadvantage to by an author who nevertheless continues to class himself as a Marxist. the other speakers of the culture, although it is hard to say whether I See Tom Nairn, The Break-up of Britain, London, 1977. they might not have done just as well out of assimilation into the I AwlYPOI;OGPPOF~A~ONALISMS A TWOLOGYOF NATIONALISMS culture of the original power-holders. Non-speakers of the new cul- So the political protection of Italian and German culture was ture who happen to live in the territory now controlled by the new visibly and, to the Italiansand Germans offensively, inferior to that state themselves in turn now face the options of assimilation, irre- whichwas provided for, say, French or English culture. But when it dentist effort, emigration, disagreeable minority status and physical came to access to education, thefacilitiesprovided by these two high liquidation. This model has been emulated in other parts of the culmes, to those who were born into dialectal variants of it, were world, with occasionally the significant modification of what one not really in any way inferior. Both Italian and German were literary may call the 'African' type (though it is not restricted to Africa), languages, with an effectivecentralized standardizationof their corwhich arises when the local folk cultures are incapable of becoming rect forms and with flourishing literatures, technical vocabularies the new high culture of the emergent state, either because they are and manners, educational institutions and academies. There was too numerousor too jealous of each other, or for some other reason. little if any cultural inferiority. Rates of literacy and standards of This has already received some discussion in connection with the education were not significantly lower (if lower at all) among Gerpseudo-hypothetical Ruritania, above (chapter 5). But at that stage mans than they were among the French; and they were not signifiof the discussion I was concerned primarily with the difference cantly low among the Italians, when compared with the dominant between this Ruritanian (or line 2) type, and aspecialproblemfacing Austrians. German in comparison with French, or Italian in comadvanced industrial societies through the presence of mobility- parison with the German used by the Austrians, were not disadvanresisting, counter-entropic traits in their populations: the contrast taged cultures, and their speakers did not need to correct unequal between brakes on mobility due to difficulties of communication, access to the eventual benefits of a modem world. All that needed to and brakes due to difficultiesof cultural iden tifi cation, or if you like, be corrected was that inequality of power and the absence of a polidue to thefacility of the identification of inequality, the tar-brushing tical roof over a culture (and over an economy), and institutions effect or the giving-a-dog-a-bad-name effect. whichwould be identifiedwith it and committed to its maintenance. The barrier on mobility due to persistent clusteringof some traits The Risorgimento and the udication of Germany corrected these in underprivileged strata is a very serious problem, particularly for developed industrial societies, and the distinction is an important There is a difference, however, between this kind of uificatory one; but it is not identical with the one which concerns us now; n~tionalism,on behalf of a fully effective high culture which only namely, the difference between lines 2 and 4. The situation symbo- needsanimprovedbitof politicalroofing, andtheclassicalHabsburglized by line 4 is interesting: some have power and somedo not. The and-east-and-southtype of nationalism. This difference is the subdifference correlates with, and can be seized in terms of, differences ject of a fascinating and rather moving essay by the late Professor of culture. But when it comes to access to education, there is no John Plamenatz, an essay which might well have been called 'The significant difference between the relevant populations. What hap- Sad Reflections of a Montenegrinin Oxford'.' Plamenatz called the two kinds of nationalism the Western and the Eastern, the Western The historic reality to which this model corresponds is the unifi- type being of the Risorgirnento or mificatory kind, typical of the cation nationalisms of nineteenth-century Italy and Germany. Most nineteenth century and with deep links to liberal ideas, while the Italians were ruled by foreigners, and in that sense were politically Eastern, though he did not stress it in so many words, was exempliunderprivileged. The Germans, most of them, lived in fragmented fiedby the kind of nationalismhe knew to existin his nativeBalkans. states, many of them small and weak, at any rate by European great There can be no doubt but that he saw the Western nationalism as power standards, and thus unable to provide German culture, as a relatively benign and nice, and the Eastern kind as nasty, and centralized modem medium, with its political roof. (By a further doomed to nastiness by the conditions which gave rise to it. (It paradox, multi-national great power Austria was endeavouring to do something of that kind, but much to the displeasure of some of its 'John Plamenatz, 'Two types of Nationalism', in E. Kamenka (ed.), N a h l i s m , The Nature and Evolution of an Idea, London, 1973. would be an interesting question to ask him whether he would have consideredthemarkedly un-benignformstaken by theseonce-benign or relatively liberal and moderateWestern nationalisms in the twentieth century, as accidental and avoidable aberrations or not.) The underlying logic of Plamenatz's argument is clear. The relatively benign Western nationalisms were acting on behalf of welldeveloped high cultures, normatively centralized and endowed with a fairly well-defined folk clientele: all that was required was a bit of adjustment in the political situation and in the international boundaries, so as to ensure for these cultures, and their speakers and practitioners,thesamesustainedprotectionas that which was already enjoyed by their rivals. This took a few battles and a good deal of sustained diplomatic activity but, as the making of historical omelettes goes, it did not involve the breaking of a disproportionate or unusual number of eggs, perhaps no more than would have been broken anyway in the course of the normal politicalgame within the general political framework and assumptions of the time. By way of contrast, consider the nationalismdesignated as Eastern by Plamenatz. Its implementationdid, of course, require battles and diplomacy, to at least the same extent as the realization of Western nationalisms. But the matter did not end there. This kind of Eastern nationalism did not operate on behalf of an already existing, welldefined and codified high culture, which had as it were marked out and linguistically pre-converted its own territory by sustained literary activities ever since the early Renaissance or since the Reformation, as the case might be. Not at all. This nationalism was active on behalf of a high culture as yet not properly crystallized, a merely aspirant or in-the-makinghigh culture. It presided, or strove to preside, in ferocious rivalry with similar competitors, over a chaotic ethnographic map of many dialects, with ambiguous historical or linguo-genetic allegiances, and containing populations which had only just begun to identify with these emergent national high cultures. Objectiveconditionsof the modem world were bound, in due course, to oblige them to identify with one of them. But till this occurred, they lacked the clearly defined cultural basis enjoyed by their German and Italian counterparts. These populations of eastern Europe were still locked into the complex multiple loyalties of kinship, territory and religion. To make them conform to the nationalist imperative was bound to take more than a few battles and some diplomacy. It was bound to takea great deal of very forceful cultural engineering. In many cases it was also bound to involve population exchanges or expulsions, more or less forcible assimilation, and sometimes liquidation, in order to attainthatcloserela$on betweenstateandculturewhichistheessence of nationalism. And all these consequences flowed, not from some unusual brutality of the nationalistswho in the end employed these measures (they were probably no worse and no better than anyone else), but from the inescapable logic of the situation. If the nationalist imperative was to be implementei in what Plamenatz generically designated as Eastern conditions, then these consequencesfollowed. A modem type of society cannot be implemented without the satisfaction of something pretty close to the nationalist imperative, which follows from the new style of division of labour. The hunger for industrial affluence, once its benefits and their availability are known and once the previous socialorder has in any case been disrupted, is virtually irresistible. The conclusion to which this series of steps leads us cannot be avoided. With luck, understandingand determination, the price can be mitigated; but its payment cannot be altogether avoided. Diaspma nationalism Our discussion of the difference between lines 2 and 4 of figure2 in a way repeats Plamenatz's distinction between Western and Eastern nationalisms; but it claims certain advantages over his treatment. For one thing, the contrast is not simply asserted as a contingently, historicallyencountered distinction, but is a derived consequenceof a simple model into which, by way of hypothesis, certain very basic and elementaryfactors have been fed. This constitutesan advantage at any rate for those who, like myself, believe that such modelbuilding should at least be attempted. But there is a further benefit: this 'constructive' approach engenders a further, third variant of nationalism, left out by Plamenatzaltogether, but cogently generated by a further combination of those self-same elements which also account, in different combinations, for the two species which did preoccupy him. This third species can best be called diaspora nationalism, and it is, as a matter of historical fact, a distinctive, very conspicuous and important sub-species of nationalism. 102 A TYPOLOGY OF NATIONALISMS Traditional agrarian society, we have stressed, uses culture or etbnicity primarily to distinguish privileged groups, thus underscoring their distinctiveness and legitimacy, enhancing their aura, and diminishing the danger of status ambiguity. If the rulers speak one kind of languageor have one kind of accent and wear one kind of habit, it would be a solecism, or much worse, for non-members of the d i n g stratum to use the same mode of communication. It would be a presumption, he-majeste', pollution or sacrilege, or ridiculous. Ridicule is a powerful sanction. It constitutes a most powerfulsocial sanctionagainst which reason is specially powerless, even or particularly when the verdictis passed by the least quaMied of juries. Other and possibly more brutal punishments can also be deployed. But thesamesocial marker deviceof culture or ethnicityis used to identify and separate off not merely privileged, but also underprivileged, ambivalently viewed or pariah groups. And it is socially most useful to have such groups. As we have noted, in pre-industrial societies bureaucratic functions can best be performed by eunuchs, priests, slaves and foreigners. To allow free-bornnative citizensinto such key positionsis too dangerous. They are far too much subject to pressures and temptations from their existing local and kin links to use their position to benefit their kinsmen and clients, and to use their kinsmen and clients in turn to strengthen their own positions further. It is not till the coming of our own modem society, when everyone becomes both a mamluk and a clerk, that everyonecan also perform reasonably as a bureaucrat, without needing to be emasculated, physidy or socially. Now men can be trusted to honour what had been the politically awkward and untypical norms of agrarian society, but have become the pervasiveand acceptable ones in ours. We are now all of us castrated, and pitifully trustworthy. The state can trust us, all in all, to do our duty, and need not turn us into eunuchs, priests, slaves or mamluks frrst. But the manningof posts in an administrativestructure is not the only reason for having pariahs in the agrarian order. Pariah bureaucracies are not the only form of exemption from full humanity, and bureaucracy is not the only source of social power. Magic, the forging of metals, finance, elite military corps, various other such mysteriesand in some circumstancesany kind of key specialism may confer dangerous power on the specialist whd has access to it. One way of neutralizingthisdanger, whileat the same time toleratingthe specialism and possibly confirming the monopoly of the guild or A TYPOLOGY OF NATIONALISMS 103 caste, is to insist that this social niche may be occupied only by a group easily idensiable culturally, destined for avoidance and contempt, and excluded from political office, from the ultimate control of the tools of cop-cion, and from honour. Clear examples of such positions, often too dangerous to be given to locals and full citizens, and consequently reserved for foreigners, are palace guards and the providers of financial services. The handling of large sums of money obviously confers great power, and if that power is in the hands of someoneprecludedfrom using it for his own advancement, because he belongs to a category excluded from high and honourableoffice and from being able to command obedience, then so much the better. In the traditional order, groups occupying these positions take the rough with the smooth, accepting with resignation the benefits, the perils and the humiliations of their situation. They are generally born into it and have little choice in the matter. Sometimes they may suffer a great deal, but often there are benefits as well as losses involved in their position. The situ'ationchangesradicallyand profoundly with the comingof mobile, anonymous, centralized mass society. This is particularly true for minorities specializingin fmancid, commercial, and generally urban specialist occupations. With pervasive mobility and occupational change, it is no longer feasible to retain the monopoly of some activity for a particular cultural group. When so many members of the wider society aspire to these often comfortable, and in themselves (if not subject to co scation)lucrativeoccupations, they can hardly be reserved for a minority, and still less for a stigmatized one. At the same time, however, these previously specialized and segregated populations are liable to have a marked advantage when it comes to the new pursuits and the new style. Their urban style of life, habits of rational calculation, commercial probity, higher rates of literacy and possibly a scriptural religion, all fit them better than either the members of the old ruling class, or of the old peasantry, for the new life-style. It is often asserted, even by sophisticated sociologists such as Max Weber, that these minorities have a double standard, one for their own group, and another, instrumental and &oral, for outsiders. They do indeed have a double standard, but it is exactly the other way round. Their entire standing with the outside world previously hinged on performing some specific service or supplying some them perform much more successfully than their rivals in the new economic free-for-all. Their background fits them for it so much better. But at the same time their background also contains a tradition of political impotence, and of the surrender of the communal was inevitably always far more than a mere commercial deal. The right of self-defence. That, after all, had been the price of their two partners in it were also kinsmen, clansmen, allies, enemies, and entering the profession in the first place: they had to make themso forth; hence the deal was never restricted to a simple delivery of selves politically and militarily impotent, so as to be allowed to this good at this price. There was alwaysa promise or a fear of greater handle tools that could be, in the wrong hands, so very powerfuland advantagesor possiblebetrayal. Both sideswere involvedin bargains dangerous. But even without such a tradition, the politicaland miliand calculationsfar more long-term and intangible, and thus had to tary weakness of such a group follows from its minority status and, try to deliver more. If on the other hand they were dissatisfied with very often, from its dispersal among a variety of urban centres, and the deal, powerfulconsiderations operated to inhibit complaints, lest its lack of a compact defensible territorial base. Some economically all the other strands in the relationshipwere thereby also put at risk. brilliant groups of this kind have behind them a long tradition of The advantage on the other hand of dealing with a minority, one dispersal, urbanizationand minority status: this is clearly the case of with whom you could not eat, marry, or enter into political or mili- the Jews, Greeks, Armenians or Parsees. Other groups come to tary alliance, was that both parties could concentrate on a rational occupy similar positions only as a result of recent migrations and cost-benefit analysis of the actual specific deal in question, and aptitudes (or educational opportunities)only acquired or deployed in expect, on the whole, to get what they bargained for, neither more modern times. Such is the situation of overseasChineseand Indians, nor less. Within the minority community, of course, relationships or the Ibos in Nigeria. were once again many-stranded, and hence deals were less rational The disastrous and tragic consequences, in modem conditions, of and reliable, and more many-sided. But in the wider society, those the conjunction of economic superiority and cultural identif~ability who lack status can honour a contract. Those on the other hand with political and military weakness, are too well known to require who enjoyed a social station, and had to respectits rights and duties, repetition. The consequences range from genocide to expulsion. were thereby deprived of much of the elbow-room required for nego- Sometimesa precarious and uneasy balance is maintained. The main tiatingand observing specific contracts. Status and honour deprive a point is that the central power now finds itself in a very different man of options, by imposingtoo many obligationsand commitments. situation, and subject to very different temptations and pressures Deprivation of status enables a man to attend to the business at I from those which prevailed in the days of the agrarian division of I hand, negotiate a rational deal, and observe its terms. labour. Then, there was no question of everyone becoming mobile, So it is indeed true that the minority community had a double educated, specialized or commercial-minded; who would then have standard, but in the oppositesense from what is normally supposed. tilled the land? To the outsider they displayed that reliability which is the presupposed anticipation of single-strandedmodern relations. It was with When Adam delved and Eve span, Who was then the businessman? their fellows that their dealings had that rich many-strandedquality which, to our modern sensibility, smacks of corruption. But, of Well, there were some. But they could not constitute the majorityor course, with the coming of anonymous mobile mass society, single- the norm. An almost universally embourgeoised society was inconstranded, one-shot deals have become quite normal, and not a special feature of dealings between non-commensal groups. The general population then did not covet the minority role, Under conditionsof modernizationthe erstwhilespecialized min- which was in any case stigmatized. The rulers welcomed a defenceority groups bse their disabilities, but also alas their monopoly and less, fairly easily taxable, economically specialized group, tied to the their protection. Their previous training and orientation often make rulers by its strictly sustained and reinforced defencelessness. But A TYPOLOGY OF NATIONALISMS now, the national 'development 7 requires precisely that everyone should movein the directionwhich was once open only to a minority problem by creating an Asian one, about which the Israelis have and stigmatized group. Once the state had an interest in protecting barely begun to think. In the diaspora, the Jewish religion referred to Jerusalem; once back in Jerusalem, semi-secular Zionism for a the minority, which was easy to milch. Now the state has more time used the dated socialist or populist clichCsof nineteenth century interest in depriving the minority of its economic monopolies, and, because of the minority's visibility and wealth, it can buy off a great Europe.) Nearly two thousand years of history had left no Jewish deal of discontent in the wider population by dispossessing and territorial base whatever, least of all in the land of Israel, and had moreover left Jews as a set of discontinuousand fairly highly specipersecutingit; and so the inevitable happens. This provides a most enjoyable(exceptfor its victims)and pathetic theatre of humiliation, alized strata within the structures of other societies, rather than the inflicted on the once-envied group, to the delectation of the majorkind of balanced population which can be the base of a more or less autarchic modem state, of a geschlossener Handelstaat. Nevertheless, ity. This pleasure can be savoured by a far larger category than just this extraordinary transformationwas achieved, no doubt thanks in the restricted group of inheritors of the positions vacated by the large part to the incentive provided by the persecutions, first in persecuted minority, and that too is a politically important coneastern Europeand then throughout Europe during the period of the sideration, making this course a politically attractive option for the Holocaust. These persecutions illustrate, better than any others, the Under these circumstances the minority is faced with the same kind of fate which is likely to befall culturally distinguishable, economically privileged and politically defenceless communities, at a kind of options (though under different circumstances) as those time when the age of specialized communities, of the traditional which faced our Ruritanian labour migrants. It can assimilate; and form of organic division of labour, is over. sometimesindeed the entire minority, or some considerable parts of The human transformation involved in the Jewish case went it, succeed in doing just that. Alternatively, it canendeavour to shed counter to the global trend: an urban, highly literate and sophistiboth its specializationand its minoritystatus, and createa state of its cated, co&opolitan population was at least partly returned to the own, as the new protector of a now un-specialized, generic, newly land and made more insular. Normally the nationalist process is national culture. For a dispersed urban population the major probinversely related to its own verbiage, talking of peasants and making lem is, of course, the acquisition of the required territorial base. The townsmen. Here it was r d y necessary to make a few surrogate Ruritanian peasants, being peasants, inevitably had a territorial peasants. In fact, they turned out to be peasants with certain crucial base, destined soon to become the kingdom of Ruritania, and later tribal traits: a form of local organizationwhich was made up of units to becomethe SocialistPeople's Republicof Ruritania. But what was that were simultaneously productive and military in their effective an urban, specialized and dispersed group, with few or no rural role. The manufacture of such tribesmen-peasants from an urban links, to do? background could not conceivably be an easy matter, and the surroFor these kinds of nationalism, the acquisition of territory was the gate peasant-soldiers were in fact formed by a species of secular first and perhaps the main problem. The Helienes initially thought monastic order. This needed an ideology, and by a historicaccident not so much in terms of secession from the Ottoman Empire, as of the suitable mixture of socialism and populism was indeed available inverting the hierarchy within it and taking it over, thereby reviving and pervasive in the intellectual miiieux in which the order did its Byzantiurn. The first Greek rising took place not in Greece, but in recruiting. The pro-rural,anti-division-of-labour,collectivist themes what is now Rumania, where the Greeks were a minority, and more- in this ideology were i d d y suited for the purpose. Whether the I over one doing rather well out of the Ottoman system. The use kibbutzim do indeed providethe good life for modem man, as their of what is now southern Greece as a territorial basis only came founders believed and hoped, remains an open question; but as a I later. The most famous and dramatic case of a successful diaspora %ugh Trevor-Roper,Jezoish and OfhaNatioMlism, London, 1962. nationalism is Israel. It is also the 'last, least typical of European piece of machinery for effectively re-settling the land by people drawn from heavily urbanized and embourgeoised populations, and effectively defending it in a military crisis with minimal and exiguous means, they proved to be quite outstanding, and indeed unequalled. The problems of social transformation, cultural revivification, acquisitionof territory, and coping with the natural enmity of those with previous claims on the territory in question, illustrate the quite special and acute problems faced by diaspora nationalisms. Those of them which retain some residue of an ancient territory may face problems which are correspondingly less acute. But the problems which face a diaspora culture which does not take the nationalist option may be as grave and tragic as those which face it if it does adopt nationalism. In fact, one may say that it is the extreme peril of the assimilationist alternative which makes the adherents of the nationalist solution espouse their cause in this situation. The gravity of the situation faced by diaspora populations if they do not choose nationalism, and the manner in which the whole situation can be deduced from the very general characteristics of the transition from an agrarian to an industrial order, show that it is quite wrong to invoke diaspora nationalismsas counter-examplesto our theory of nationalism: Greek and Armenian nationalism arose among populations which were generally more prosperous and better able to understand the wealth-generating economies of modem Europe than their Ottoman Muslim overlords.' In our Ruritaniancase, nationalismwas explained in terms of an economically and politically disadvantaged population, able to distinguish itself culturally, and thus impelled towards the nationalist 'ATatioMlismin Asia and Africa, ed. Elie Kedourie, London, 1970, p. 20. In the same volume (p.132) Professor Kedourie challenges the doctrine that industrial social organization makes for cultural homogeneity: 'Large industrial enterprises have taken root and flourished in multi-lingualsocieties: in Bohemia and the United Statesin the nineteenth century; in Hong Kong, Israel, French Algeria, India,.Ceylon, and Malaya in the twentieth. It has never been claimed that you can only haveindustrial enterprisein a society which is already culturally homogeneous. What the theory does claim is that if an industrial economy is establishedim a culturally heterogeneous society (or if it even casts its advance shadow on it), then tensions A TYPOLOGY OF NATIONALISMS 109 option. But the intolerable position, once the process of industrialization begins, of culturally distinguishable populations which are not at an economic disadvantage (quite the reverse), only at a political disadvantage which is inherent in their minority status, follows from the same general premisses, and points to the same conclusion, though naturally by its own specificpath. To concentrateexclusively on economic disadvantage, which admittedly is prominent in the most typical cases, is to travesty our position. The industrial order requires homogeneity within political units, at least sufficient to permit fairly smooth mobility, and precluding the 'ethnic' identification of either advantage or disadvantage, economic or political. result which will engender nationalism. With the possible and temporary exception of Hong Kong, whose population is recruited from Chinese not wishing to live under the present mainlandChinesereglme, so that the very principle of recruitment of the community selectsfor absenceof irredentist longing, every single other country cited in Kedourie's list, far from constituting a counter-example to the theory, in fact illustratesit, and indeed provides veritable paradigms of the model which the theory proposes. Bohemia was the sourceof much of the early nationalist activityand theory, both German and Czech; the educational system of the United States was notoriously geared to turning a heterogeneous immigrant population into an ethnically homogeneous one, with the warm concurrence of the population so processed. All the other countries listed illustrate the story of nationalism, some of them in extreme and tragic form. It is true that in India, cultural homogeneity sometimescuts across linguisticdiversity: Hindus 'speak the same language' even when *y do not speak the same language. But the theory does not preclude that. The Future of Nationalism Our general diagnosisof nationalismis simple. Of the three stages of human history, the second is the agrarian, and the third is the industrial. Agrarian society has certain general features: the majority of the population is made up of agricultural producers, peasants. Only a minority of the society's population are specialists, whether military, political, religious or economic. Most agrarian populations are also affected by the two other great innovations of the agrarian age: centralized government and the discovery of writing. Agrariansociety- unlike, it would seem, both its predecessorand successor societies - is Malthusian: both productive and defence necessities impel it to seek a growing population, which then pushes close enough to the available resources to be occasionallystricken by disasters. The three crucial factors operating in this society (food production, political centralization and literacy) engender a social structure in which cultural and political boundaries are seldom con- gruent. Industrial society is quite different. It is not Malthusian. It is based and dependent on cognitiveand economicgrowth which in the end both outstrips and discourages further dramatic population growth. Variousfactorsin it - universalliteracy, mobility and hence individualism, political centralization, the need for a costly educational infrastructure - impel it into a situation in which political and cultural boundaries are on the whole congruent. The state is, above all, the protector, not of a faith, but of a culture, and the maintainer of the inescapably homogeneous and standardizing educational system, which alone can turn out the kind of personnel capable of switching from one job to another within a growing economy and a mobile society, and indeed of performing jobs which involve manipulating meanings and people rather than things. For most of these men, however, the limitsof their culture are the limits, not perhaps of the world, but of their own employabilityand hence dignity. THE FUTURE OF NATIONALISM 111 In most of the closed micro-communities of the agrarian age the limits of the culture were the limits of the world, and the culture often itself remained unperceived, invisible: no-one thought of it as the ideal political boundary. Now, with mobility, it has become visible and is the limit of the individual's mobility, circumscribing the newly enlarged range of his employability; and thus it becomes the natural political boundary. To say this is not to reduce nationalism to mere anxiety about the prospects for social mobility. Men really love their culture, because they now perceive the cultural atmosphere(instead of taking it for granted), and know they cannot really breathe or fulfil their identity outside it. The high (literate) culture in which they have been educated is, for most men, their most precious investment, the core of their identity, their insurance, and their security. Thus a world has emerged which in the main, minor exceptions apart, satisfies the nationalist imperative, the congruence of culture and polity. The satisfaction of the nationalist principlewas not a precondition of the first appearanceof industrialism, but only the product of its spread. A transition has to be made from a world which does not encourage even the formulation of the nationalist ideal, let alone even remotely make possibleits implementation,to an age which makesit seem (erroneously) a self-evident ideal valid for all times, thus turning it into an effective norm, which in most cases is implemented. The period of this transition is inevitably a period of nationalist activism. Mankind arrived in the industrial age with cultural and political institutions which generally contradictedthe nationalist requirements. Bringing society into line with the new imperatives was inevitably a turbulent process. The most violent phase of nationalism is that which accompanies early industrialism, and the diffusion of industrialism. An unstable social situation is created in which a whole set of painful cleavages tend to be superimposed on each other: there are sharp political, economic and educational inequalities. At the same time, new culture-congruentpolities are emerging. In these conditions, if these multiple and superimposed inequalities also coincide, more or less, with ethnic and cultural ones, which are visible, conspicuous and easily intelligible, they impel the new emerging units to place themselves under ethnic banners. Industrialization inevitably comes to different places and groups at different times. This ensures that the explosive blend of early industrialism(dislocation, mobility, acute inequalitynot hallowed by time and custom) seeks out, as it were, all the available nooks and crannies of cultural differentiation, wherever they be. Few of those that can be effectively activated for nationalism, by coinciding however loosely with the septic inequalities of the time, and defining viable potential industrial states, fail so to be activated. As the tidal wave of modernization sweeps the world, it makes sure that almost everyone, at some time or other, has cause to feel unjustly treated, I and that he can identify the culprits as being of another 'nation'. If he can also identify enough of the victims as being of the same I 'nation' as himself, a nationalism is born. If it succeeds, and not all of them can, a nation is born. There is a further element of economic rationality in the political system of 'lateral boundaries' which nationalism engenders in the I modem world. Territorial boundaries are drawn and legally enforced, while differences of status are neither marked nor enforced, but rather camouflaged and disavowed. Notoriously, advanced economies can swamp and inhibit newly emergingones, unless theseare effectively protected by their own state. The nationalist state is not the protector only of a culture, but also of a new and often initially fragile economy. (It generally loses interest in protectinga faith.) In those cases where a modern nation is born of what had previously I been a mere stratum - peasants only, or urban specialists only- the state's concerns with making its ethnic group into a balancednation, 1 and with developing its economy, become aspects of one and the same task. I The question now arises whether nationalism will continue to be a major force or a general political imperative in an age of I advanced, perhaps even in some sense completed industrialism. As ~ the world is not yet too close to a satiation of the craving for economic growth, any answer to this question will inevitably be speculative. The speculation is nevertheless well worth attempting. The I implications of growth for occupational and social mobility were prominent in our argument. Constant occupational changes, reinforced by the concern of most jobs with communication, the mani-I pulation of meaning rather than the manipulation of things, makes for at least a certain kind of social equality or diminished social distance, and the need for a standardized, effectively shared medium of communication. These factors underlie both modern egalitarianism and nationalism. But what happens if a satiated industrial society becomes once again stabilized, un-mobile?The classicalimaginativeexploration of this occurs in Aldous Huxley's Brave N m World. A satiated industrial society is indeed conceivable: though there is no reason to suppose that all possible technological innovations will one day be exhausted, there is reason to suppose that beyond a certain point further technical innovations may cease to have any significant further impact on social structure and society generally, on the analogy of a man who, beyond a certain point of wealth, can no longer in any way alter his life-style in response to further enrichment. This analogy may or may not be valid, and it is difficult to be coddent about the answer to this question. The age of wealth-saturation for mankind at large stillseems fairly distant, and so the issue does not affect us too urgently at present. But it is worth stating that much of our argument did hinge on the implicationsof continuing commitment to global economic growth, and hence to innovation and occupational change; it also presupposed the persistence of a society based on the promise of affluence and on generalized Danegeld. These assumptions, though valid now, cannot be expected to remain so indefinitely (even if we exclude the possibility of the termination of this kind of society by some nuclear or similar disaster). Our culturally homogeneous, mobileand, in its middle strata, fairly unstructured society may well not last for ever, even if we disregard the possibility of cataclysms; and when this kind of society no longer prevails, then what we have presented as the social bases of nationalism will be profoundly modified. But that is not something which will be visible in our lifetimes. In the shorter run, without looking ahead so far, we can expect nationalism to become modified. Its acute stage arose, as stated, at the time of the maximal gap between the industrially incorporated, politically and educationally enfranchised populations, and those at thegateof the new world but not yet insideit. As economic development proceeded, this gap narrowed (pessimistic assertions to the contrary notwithstanding).The gap may even continueto increasein absoluteterms, but once both the privilegedand the underprivileged are above a certain level, it is no longer felt and perceived to be so acute. The difference between starvation and sufficiency is acute; the difference between sufficiencywith more, or with fewer, largely symbolic, -cia1 frills, is not nearly so great, especially when, in an at least nominally egalitarian industrial society, those frills are all made in the same style. The diminution of the acuteness of nationalist fervour does not mean, however, that counter-entropicminoritieswillnecessarilyfare well. Their fate in the modem world has often been tragic, and to be confident that these tragedies will not be repeated would be an indulgence or facile, unwarranted optimism. A mature industrial society requires smooth communication and smooth mobility for its members. Attainmentof the former is the conditionof maturity; the latter seems to be more elusive. Obstruction of mobility, where it occurs, is one of the most seriousand intractable problems of industrial society. The gap in prosperity may also increase between nations, but when a frontier already exists between the haves and have-nots, the tension between them cannot, as it were, create it twice over, so from the viewpoint of nationalism this is irrelevant. (I leave aside for the time being the possibility of some collective hostility by an entire class of 'proletarian nations', politically sovereign, towards the rich nations. If this occurs, it will in any case be something other than nationalism. It would manifest an international solidarity of the poor.) So what happens to later nationalism, if disparities of wealth between populations diminish with the extension of the indusmal system?The answer to this question is not yet clear, but it does concern us far more closely than the more distant vistas; for a fair number of countriesalready at least approachthis condition.We can look both at the implications of our theoreticalpremisses, and at the concrete empirical, historical evidence. Afair amount of it is already available. It all hinges, in effect, on the nature of industrial culture. Industrial culture - one or many? There are two possible visions of the future of culture in industrial societies, and any number of intermediate compromise positions between the poles which they represent. My own conception of world history is clear and simple: the three great stages of man, the hunting-gathering, the agrarian and the industrial, determine our problems, but not our solution. In other words, Marxismwas wrong twice over, not merely in multiplyingthe stages beyond the elegant, economical and canonical three (trinitarians such as Comte, Frazer or Karl Polanyiwere right, whether or not they had correctly identified the elements of the trinity), but above all in suggesting that the solution as well as the problem was determined for each stage: The mode of production of material life determines the general character of the social, political and spiritual processes of life. ... In broad outlinewecandesignatethe'Asiatic, the ancient, thefeudaland the modem bourgeois modes of production can be indicated as progressive epochs in the economic formation of society.' But, in general, the determinationof society by the available economic base does not seem to hold. Neither hunting nor agrarian societies are all alike. What is specifically disastrous for the Marxist philosophyof history is that the crucial superstructural features (the state and literacy) do not correlate with the appearance of the really decisive infrastructure change, namely the beginning of food production. If James Woodburn is right, a crucial structural change occurs already within the category of hunting societies, which can be divided into those practising immediate return, and those with delayed return hunting and gathering economies. The latter, by acquiring the moral and institutional basis for long-term obligation, already possess the organizational pre-conditions for developing agriculture, if and when the pressures in that direction operate and the technical means become a~ailable.~Division of tasks over time engendersthe habitsof thought and action which then make possible the permanentspecializationof rolesbetween individualsinvolved in food production. Ifthis is so, then one great socio-structural change precedes the past great leap to food production; while there is no doubt but that the other great structural change, state-formation, follows it, and is not in any immediate or single way linked to it.3 'K. Marx, IntroductiontoA Contributiontothe Critiqueof PoliticalEconomy, in numerous editions and translations. *James Woodburn, 'Hunters and gathers today and reconstruction of the past', in E. Gellner (ed.), Soviet and WesiernAnthropology, London and New York, 1980. ?he problems, empirical and theoretical, which face the doctrine of a regular relation between social base and superstructure in Marxism, and their greater acuteness once a milineal view of social development is dropped, do receivesomeattentionin Soviet thought. Seefor instanceEero Loone, Sm-iQ Filosofw Iswri (Contemporary Philosophy of History), Tallin, 1980, especially Part IV. 116 THE FUTURE OF NATIONALISM Mankind moved from a hunting-gatheringstate when all had leisure, to an agrarian one when only some (the ruling elite) had it, to an industrial age governed by the work ethic, when none have it. Or you might say we moved from no delay in gratificationto some delay and fmally to eternal delay. So the idea of the material determination of society would seem to be out, in general. But is it also out for industrial society, in the long run? Is the general form of industrial society, at least, uniquely determined by its productive infrastructure? The answer is not obvious, and certainly not predetermined by the clear evidence to the contrary for hunting and agrariansocieties. It could be that industrial man will, in the end, have fewer social options than his hunter and peasant ancestor. It could be that the thesis that all industrial societies eventually come to resembleeach other is correct, or at any rate will in the long run turn out to be such. With specificreference to culture and nationalism, what may we expect? It may be convenient to explore first this convergence thesis. Suppose it were indeed the case that the industrial mode of production uniquely determines the culture of society: the same technology canalizes people into the same type of activity and the same kinds of hierarchy, and that the same kind of leisurestyles were also engendered by the existing techniques and by the needs of productive life. Diverse languages might and probably would, of course, survive: but the social uses to which they were being put, the meanings available in them, would be much the same in any language within this wider shared industrial culture. In such a world, a man moving from one language to another might indeed need to learn a new vocabulary, new words for familiar things and contexts, and he might also, at worst, have to learn a new grammar, in a more or less purely linguisticsense; but this would be about the limit of the adjustment demanded of him. No new thought styles would be required of him. He could all in all comport himself like a tourist with a phrase book, confident that all he needed was to locatethe new phrasefor an old and familiar need. The tourist would move from one area to another, knowing that within each of them human requirements are bounded by the want of a room, meal, drink, petrol, tourist office, and a few other things. Likewise, in a world in which the convergence thesis were wholly valid, interlinguistic adjusunent would be a simple matter of exchanging one verbal currency for another, within a well-run international conceptual system in which exchange rates were fairly stable, fured and reliable. There is clearly an elementof truth in this. Industrial society has a complex division of labour and interdependence internationally as well as internally. Notwithstanding the care national states take not to be too specializedand hence too dependent on others, the amount of international trade is very great, and so is the accompanying conceptual and institutional convergence. It is deeply significant that credit cards are valid across Iron Curtains. You can freely use your credit card in countries where you cannot freely speak your mind. The dollar is quite legally used as currency in at least one socialist system. Thereis notoriouslyan international, trans-ideologicalyouth culmre. In the industrial age only high cultures in the end effectively survive. Folk cultures and little traditions surviveonly artificially, kept going by language and folklore preservation societies. Moreover, the high cultures of industrial societies are a special breed among high cultures in general, and resemble each other more than do agrarian high cultures. They are tied to a shared cognitivebaseand a consciously global economy. They probably overlap more closely than did the old high cultures that were once deeply pervaded by distinctive theologies, by their culturally private, idiosyncratic cognitive systems. Is this the whole truth? Should one expect that eventually, with the consummation of effective industrialization, inter-cultural and inter-linguistic differences will degenerate into merely phonetic ones, when only the superficial tokens of communication are variable, while the semantic content and the social context of utterances and actions become universal, non-regional?If that came to be, the communication gap between diverse 'languages' could become negligibly small, and the correspondingsocialgap, the counter-entropic, mobility-inhibiting effect of diverse linguistic and cultural backgrounds could become correspondinglyinsignificant. No nationalist inhibitions would then impede inter-cultural amity and inter- nationalism. To some extent and in some areas, somethingof this kind does in fact already happen: two equally sophisticatedwell-trained members of the upper professionallayers of developedindustrial countriesfeel little strain and need to adjust when visiting each other's lands, irrespective of how competent they are at speaking each other's language, in the literal sense. They happily co-operate in the multinational corporation. They already 'speak each other's language', even if they do not speak each other's language. At that level something like an international labour market and interchangeability already obtain. But can or will this situation become generalized?It is ironic that intellectuals, the drivingforceof initialnauonalism, are now, in a world of nation-states, often the ones who move with the greatest ease between states, with the least prejudice, as once they did in the days of an international inter-state clerisy. If this freedom of international movement became general, nationalism would cease to be a problem; or at any rate, communication gapsengenderedby cultural differenceswould cease to be significant and would no longer produce nationalist tensions. Nationalism as a permanent problem, as a Damocles' sword hanging over any polity which dares to d e b the nationalist imperative of the congruence of politicaland cultural boundaries, would be removed, and cease to be an ever-present and acute threat. In this hypothetical global continuum of a basically homogeneousindustrial culture, differentiated by languages which are distinct only phonetically and superficially but not semantically, the age of nationalism would become a matter of the past. I do not believe that this will come to pass. I am inclined to follow J.-F. Revel on this point. Les peuples ne sont pas tous les msmes. 11sne I'etaient pas dans la mi&re, ils ne le sont pas dans le luxe.' (Nationsare not all alike. They weren't alikein poverty, and they are not alike in luxury.) The shared constraintsof industrial production, of a unique background science, and of a complex internationalinterdependenceand sustained continuous contact and communication, will no doubt produce a certain measure of global cultural convergence, a fair amount of which we can see already. This will prevent failure of communication arising from cultural divergence from being quite such a major factor in exacerbating tension between the more and the less privileged. (It will not prevent other counter-entropictraits from aggravating or provoking tensions.) Within developed countries, countries within which the great majority of the citizens have 'J.F. Revel, En Frame, Paris, 1965. reasonably good and not very unequal access to the dominant economically effectivehigh culture, and where the existing inequalities cannot be dredged to the surface and activated politically by a cultural or 'ethnic' net, a certain amount of secondary cultural pluralism and diversity may emerge again, and be politically innocuous. Given generalized development, and something like equal access to social perks, then related cultures, or those with a shared history, will be able to cohabit amicably. The linguistic pluralityof the Swiss canton of the Grisonsdoes not seem to have put the political unity of that canton under stress. The same cannot be said of canton Bern, where the inhabitants of the Jura were sufficientlydiscontented with the German-speakingunit to effect, not without conflict, a reorganization of-the Swiss Confederacy. But it remains difficult to imagine two large, politically viable, independence-worthy cultures cohabiting under a single political roof, and trusting a single political centre to maintain and service both cultureswith perfect or even adequateimpartiality. The degree of sovereignty which national states will retain in various circumstances can be foreseen - the restrictions on sovereignty by bodies such as the United Nations, regional confederations and alliances and so forth -is not a subject of this study, nor a topic which absolutely needs to be discussed here; but it would seem overwhelmingly likely that differences between cultural styles of life and communication, despite a similar economic base, will remain large enough to requireseparateservicing, and hencedistinct cultural-politicalunits, whether or not they will be wholly sovereign. How about the other extreme possibility? The alternative pole corresponds to a situation in which distinct cultures would remain just as incommensurateand incompatible as they are alleged to have been among pre-industrialcultures, if not more so. This question is complicated by the fact that it is by no means clear, among anthropologists or others, just hozo totally incommensurate and selfsufficient pre-industrial cultures were. In its extreme form, the (recently quite fashionable) incommensurability thesis runs something as follows: each culture or way of life has its own standards not merely of virtue, but also of reality itself, and no culture may ever legitimately be judged, let alone condemned, by the standards of another, or by standards pretending to be universal and above all cultures (for there are no such higher and external norms). This position is usually urged by romantics, using I 120 THE FUTURE OF NATIONALISM it as a premiss for defendingarchaic beliefs and customs from rational criticism, and insisting that the idea of extraneous, universally rational standards is a myth. In this form, such a position would seem to entaila virulent nationalism, in as far as it clearly entailsthat the subjection of one culture to the political management administered by members of another must always be iniquitous. I am deeply sceptical about the applicability of the incommensurability thesis even to agrarian societies. I do not believe it can legitimately be used to deny the possibility of inter-cultural communication, or of the comparative evaluation of agrarian and industrial cultures. The incommensurability thesis owes some of its plausibility to a tendency to take too seriously the self-absolutizing, critic-anathematizing official faiths of late agrarian societies, which indeed are generally so constructed as to be logically invulnerable from outside and perpetually self-csnfiinning from inside. Despite these notorious traits, which have now become repellent to men of liberal inclinations, the adherents of these faiths have, in practice, known how to transcend their own much advertised blinkers. They are and were conceptually bilingual, and knew how to switch from commensurate to incommensurate idioms with ease and alacrity. Functionaries of nominally exclusive, truth-monopolizing faiths nonetheless participateamicably in discussionsat the World Council of Churches. The question concerning just how we manage to transcend relativismis interestingand difficult, and certainly will not be solved here. What is relevant, however, is that we somehow or other do manage to overcome it, that we are not helplessly imprisoned i within a set of cultural cocoons and their norms, and that for some very obvious reasons (shared cognitive and productive bases and greatly increased inter-social communication) we may expect fully industrial man to be even less enslaved to his local culure than was his agrarian predecessor. On this issue the truth seems to me to lie somewhere in the middle. The shared economic infrastructure of advanced industrial society and its inescapable implications will continue to ensure that men are dependent on culture, and that culture requires standardization over quite wide areas, and needs to be maintained and serviced by centralized agencies. In other words, men will continue to owe their employability and social acceptability to sustained and complex training, which cannot be supplied by kin or local group. This being so, the definition of political units and boundaries will THE FUTURE OF NATIONALISM 121 not be able to ignore with impunity the distribution of cultures. By and large, ignoring minor and innocuousexceptions, the nationalist imperativeof the congruenceof politicalunit and of culture will continue to apply. In that sense, one need not expect the age of nationalism to come to an end. But the sharpness of nationalist conflict may be expected to diminish. It was the social chasms created by early industrialism, and by the unevenness of its diffusion, which made it acute. Those social chasms were probably no worse than those which agrarian society tolerates without batting an eyelid, but they were no longer softened or legitimated by longevity and custom, and they occurred in a context which in other ways encouraged hope and the expectation of equality, and which required mobility. Whenever cultural Mferences served to mark off these chasms, then there was trouble indeed. When they did not, nothing much happened. 'Nations', ethnicgroups, were not nationalist when states were formed in fairly stable agrarian systems. Classes, however oppressed and exploited, did not overturn the political system when they could not define themselves'ethnically'. Only when a nation became a class, a visible and unequally distributed category in an otherwise mobile system, did it become politically conscious and activist. Only when a class happened to be (more or less) a 'nation' did it turn from being a class-in-itself into a class-for-itself, or a nation-for-itself. Neither nations nor classes seem to be political catalysts: only nation-classes or class-nations are such. Aninterestingauthor whoattempts tosalvageMarxism, or unearth or invent a new viable form of it, recognizes this fact.' Late industrial society no longer engenders such deep social abysses, which could then be activated by ethnicity. (It will continue to encounter difficulties, sometimes tragic ones, from counter-entropictraits such as 'race' which visibly contradict its overt egalitarianism.) It will have to respect cultural differences where they survive, provided that they are superficid and do not engender genuine barriers between people, in which case the barriers, not their cultures, constitute a grave problem. Though the old plethora of folk cultures is unlikely to survive, exceptin a token and cellophane-packagedform, an international plurality of sometimes fairly diverse high cultures will no doubt (happily) remain with us. The infrastructural 'Nab, The Break-up of Britain. investmentmadein them can be relied on to perpetuate them. Partly because many boundaries have already adjusted themselves to the boundaries of these cultures, and partly because the nationalist imperative is now so widely respected that developed societies seldom defy it brazenly, and try to avoid head-on confrontationswith it: for these various reasons, late industrial society (if mankind is spared long enough to enjoy it) can be expected to be one in which nationalism persists, but in a muted, less virulent form. Nationalism and Ideology A conspicuous feature of our treatment of nationalism has been a lack of interest in the history of nationalist ideas and the contributions and nuances of individual nationalist thinkers. This is in marked contrast to many other approaches to this subject. This attitude does not spring from any generalized contempt for the role of ideas in history. Some ideas and belief systems do make a very great difference. (It is not necessarily the good ideas which make the greatest impact. Some ideas are good and some bad, and some make a great impact and some make none, and there is no systematic relationshipbe+meenthese two oppositions.) For instance, the belief systems known as Christianity and Marxism, are both of them contingent: each of them consists of a complex of themes, which individually may have been inherent in the situationin which it came into being, but which, as a particular combination endowed with a name and a historic existence and continuity, were only forged into some kind of unity by a set of thinkers or preachers. This unity in some measure survives the selective use made of them subsequently. Moreover, once they emerged, rhey came on occasion to dominate societies which happened to take their docnines with great seriousness, and applied them (or some of them) with great determination. This being so, if we are to understand the fate of these societies, we are sometimes obliged to look carefully at the words, doctrines and arguments of the thinkers who forged the faiths that dominatethem. For instance, the particularethnographic doctrines which happened to influence Marx and Engels in the 1870s, about the survival of the communalspirit in villages of backward countries and the conditions of its perpetuation, are incorporated in a crucial manner in Marxism, and probably hada decisive and disastrous effect on Soviet agrarian policy. But this does not seem to me to be the casewith nationalism. (This incidentally may help to explain why nationalism, notwithstanding its indisputable importance, has received relatively little attention -luATlONAnSICTAND7DEOLOG principle, accessible as such to all men, and violated only through used to like, for them to get their teeth into.)' It is not so much that some perverse blindness, when in fact it owes its plausibility and the prophets of nationalism were not anywhere near the First Divi- compelling nature only to a very special set of circumstances, which sion, when it came to the business of thinking: that in itself would do indeed obtain now, but which were alien to most of humanity not prevent a thinker from having an enormous, genuine and crucial and history. It preaches and defendscontinuity, but owes everything influence on history. Numerous examples prove that. It is rather to a decisive and unutterably profound break in human history. h a t these thinkers did not really make much difference. If one of It preaches and defends cultural diversity, when in fact it imposes them had fallen, others would have stepped into his place. (They homogeneity both inside and, to a lesser degree, between political liked saying something rather like this themselves, though not quite units. Its self-image and its true nature are inversely related, with in the sense intended here.) No-one was indispensable. The quality an ironic neatness seldom equalled even by other successful ideoof nationalistthought would hardly have been affected much by such logies. Hence it seems to me that, generally speaking, we shall not substitutions. learn too much about nationalism from the study of its own Their precisedoctrines are hardly worth analysing. We seem to be in the presence of a phenomenon which springs directly and inevi- Shall we learn more from studying its enemies? A little more, but tably from basic changes in our shared social condition, from we need to be cautious. Their main merit seems to me that they changes in the overall relation between society, culture and polity. teach us not to take nationalism at its own valuation, on its own The preciseappearanceand local form of this phenomenonno doubt terms, and as something self-evident. The temptation to do so is so depends a very great deal on local circumstances which deserve deeply built into the modern condition, where men simply assume study; but I doubt whether the nuancesof nationalistdoctrineplayed that culturally homogeneous units, with culturallysimilar rulers and much part in modifying those circumstances. ruled, are a norm whose violation is inherently scandalous. To be Generally speaking, nationalist ideology suffers from pervasive shocked out of this pervasive assumption is indeed something for false consciousness. Its myths invert reality: it claims to defend folk which one must be grateful. It is a genuine illu~nination. culture while in fact it is forging a high culture; it claims to protect But it would be just as disastrous to follow a declared enemy of an old folk society while in fact helping to build up an anony- nationalism such as Elie Kedourie all the way, and treat nationalism mous ~ m s ssociety. (Pre-nationalist Germany was made up of a as a contingent, avoidable aberration, accidentally spawned by multiplicity of genuine communities, many of them rural. Post- European thinkers. Nationalism - the principle of homogenous cdnationalistunited Germanywas mainlyindustrial and a masssociety.) mal units as the foundations of political life, and of the obligatory cultural unity of rules and ruled - is indeed inscribed neither in the he disproportionbetween the importanceof nationalismand the mount nature of things, nor in the hearts of men, nor in the pre-condicons of thought given to it is noted by Professor Eric Hobsbawm in his 'Some of social life in general, and the contention that it isso inscribed is a Reflections on Nationalism', in Imaginatwn and P r e e in t h Social falsehood which nationalist doctrine has succeeded in presenting as S&a, Essays in Memmy of Peter Nettl, T.J. Nossiter, A.H. Hanson self-evident. But nationalism as a phenomenon, not as a doctrine and Stein Rokkan, et al. (eds.), Atlantic Heights, NJ, 1972. He quotes presented by nationalists, is inherent in a certain set of social confrom D. Mack Smith's I1 Risorgimmto (1968), some truly bizarre views ditions; and thoseconditions, it so happens, are the conditionsof ourof M a z G on the proper nationalist organizationof Europe, which would have included Slovenia in a kind of Greater Switzerland, and joined up Magyars, lhmanians and Czechs with, for some reason, Herzegovina. To deny this is at least as great a mistake as to accept nationalism All in all Mazzini, outside Italy, seemed to have more senseof the polirical on its own terms. There is somethingbizarrein the suggestion that a economies of scale and of territorial compacmasthan of culturalsensibili- forcesowidespread and pervasive,a flamethat springsupso strongly ties. and spontaneously in so many disbnnected places, and which needs so very little fanning to become a devouring forest blaze, should spring from nothing more than some extremely abstruse lucubrations of philosophers. For better or for worse, our ideasseldom have quite such power. In an age of cheap paper, print, and widespread literacy and easy communication, any number of ideologies arespawnedand compete for our favour; and they are often formulated and propagated by men with greater literary and propagandist gifts than those which nature chose to bestow on the prophets of nationalism. Yet these other forms of nonsense have never had a remotely comparable impacton mankind. This was not due to lesserliterarymerit on their part. Nor can it be a matter of luck; the experiment has been repeated in so many parts of the globe that, if chance were the king here, one might com5dently expect a far more motley overall pattern, with one kind of doctrine prevailing in one place and quite another kind somewhere else. But it is not so: the trend of events points much the same way in most places. And as we can trace a clear and manifest connection between the general social conditions of our age and this overwhelmingly predominant trend, then surely we are justifiedin invokingthat link, rather than the accidentalappealof an arbitrary idea, thrown up by the play of Europeanintellectual fancy at the turn of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries! In the case of nationalism (though the same is not always true of other movements), the actual formulation of the idea or ideas, the question concerning who said or wrote precisely what, doesn't matter much. The keyidea is in any case so very simpleand easy that anyonecan makeit up almost at any time, which is partly why nationalism can claim that nationalism is always natural. What matters is whether the conditions of life are such as to make the idea seem compelling, rather than, as it is in most other situations, absurd. In this connection it is worth saying something about the role of communication in the dissemination of the nationalist idea. This term plays a crucial part in the analysisof nationalismof at least one noted author.' But the usual formulationof the connection between nationalismand the facility of modern communicationsis somewhat misleading. It gives the impression that a given idea (nationalism) happens to be there, and then the printed word and the transistor and other media help this notion to reach audiencesin distant valleys 'K.w. Deutsch, Nationalismand Social Communication, New York, 1966. NATIONALISM AND IDEOLOGY 127 and self-containedvillages and encampments,audienceswhich in an age not blessed with mass media would have remained untouched by it. That is altogether the wrong way to see it. The media do not transmit an idea which happens to have been fed into them. It matters precious little what has been fed into them: it is the media themselves, the pervasiveness and importance of abstract, centralized, standardized, one to many communication, which itself automaticallyengendersthe coreidea of nationalism, quite irrespective of what in particular is being put into the specific messages transmitted. The most important and persistent message is generated by the medium itself, by the role which such media have acquired in modern life. That core message is that the language and style of the transmissions is important, that only he who can understand them, or can acquire such comprehension, is included in a moral and economic community, and that he who does not and cannot, is excluded. All this is crystal clear, and follows from the pervasiveness and crucial role of mass communicationin this kind of society. What is actually said matters little. The manner in which conditions have changed, turning an idea which was once bizarre into one which is compellingand seemingly self-evident, can perhaps best be conveyed by invoking Kedourie's own concluding and crucial words: The only criterioncapableof publicdefenceis whether the new rulers are less corrupt and grasping, or more just and merciful,or whether there is no change at d,but the corruption, the greed, and the tyranny merely find victims other than those of the departed rulers. (E. Kedourie, Nationalism, p. 140) The question which Professor Kedourie asks with such eloquence is indeed one which a typical burgher in an agrarian society would ask himself, if one morning he just heard that the local Pasha had been overthrown and replaced by an altogether new one. If, at that point, his wife dared ask the burgher what language the new Pasha spoke in the intimacy of his home life - was it Arabic, Turkish, Persian, French or English?- the hapless burgher.would give her a sharp look, and wonder how he would cope will all the new dEculties when, at the same time, his wife had gone quite mad. Probably he would send her to a shrine that specialized in acute mental aberration. 128 NATIONALISM AND IDEOLOGY The question commended by Kedourie did indeed make sense in societies in which government on the one hand, and economy and society on the other, were distinct, where cultural continuity between the two was an irrelevancy, and where, as the quotation clearly implies, one may hope at best for merciful and just government, but not for an accountable, participatory and representative one. (Are these totally illusory aspirations among us, then?) But something other than the dissemination of the words of obscure European scribblers must have happened to make the wife's query, once so manifestly mad, become the question which is now uppermost in almost everyone's mind. And something has indeed happened. The economy is now such as to require sustainedand precise communication between all those who take part in it, and between them and government, and the maintenance of the educational and culturalinfrastructure has become one of the central tasksof government. Hence the home idiom of the new Pasha, once so irrelevant, is now the crucial sign as to whom the new power will favour and whom it will exclude. In a later book, Nationalism in Asia and Afn'ca (1970), Kedourie does indeed ask questions about the European colonial domination of the world which are, quite rightly, totally and ~ i ~ c a n t l ydifferent from the question recommended at the end of Nationalism. He comments at length on the failure of the European conquerors to accept as equals those members of the conquered populations who had acquired the necessaryqualifications and skills, and he evidently considers this exclusiveness to be at least part of the explanation of why European rule produced the nationalist reaction which in fact it elicited. It is not entirely clear whether this is a criticism or merely a neutral diagnosis, though it is difiicult not to feel that the former element is present; and if so, it would seem that a question is now being asked about rulers which is not only about their mercy and rapacity! The new question is whether the rulers are willing and able to run a mobile society, one in which rulers and ruled can mergeand form a cultural continuum. This, on my argument, is indeed the crucial question which under modern conditionsis bound to be asked of all rulers, and to complement and largely overshadow the older question. But without these special modern conditions, why should their exclusiveness have been a demerit or a weakness? Some past rulers (Romans and Greeks) may at times have been open and receptive NATIONALISM AND IDEOLOGY 129 (though the Romans did not exactly rush about offeringfree Roman citizenship to any newly conqueredarea); but many others were not, without necessarily suffering for it. On the contrary, under traditional conditions, easy identifiability and seclusion of rulers must often have been a great asset, conducive to stability. The Mamluks did not benefit, as a class, when they intermarried with the market. Why should exclusiveness suddenly have become so disastrous and why should it have provoked such a virulent, widespreadand shared reaction? Kedourie himself provides the answer: There is no gainsaying the fact that Europe has been the origin and centre of a deep radical disturbance spreading over the world in everwidening ripplesand bringing unsettlement and violence to the traditional societies of Asia and Africa, whether these societies did or did not experience direct European rule . .. This pulverization of traditional societies, this bursting open of self-sufficient economies .. . If one supplements this account, with which one could hardly disagree, with the question of what kind of new re-organizaion is feasible, given modem productive methods and the society which they imply, then, I contend, one comes out with an answer which makes modem nationalism more than either an ideological accident or the fruit of mere resentment, and which shows it, in its general forms if not in its details, to be a necessity. It may be worth giving a short, no doubt incomplete, list of false theories of nationalism: 1 It is natural and self-evidentand self generating. If absent, this must be due to forceful repression. 2 It is an artificial consequence of ideas which did not need ever to be formulated, and appeared by a regrettable accident. Political life even in industrial societies could do without it. 3 The Wrong Address Theory favoured by Marxism: Just as extreme Shi'ite Muslims hold that Archangel Gabriel made a mistake, delivering the Message to Mohamed when it was intended for Ali, so Marxists basically like to think that the spirit of history or human consciousness madea terrible boob. The awakeningmessage was intended for classes, but by some terrible postal error was delivered to nations. It is now necessary for revolutionary activists to persuade the wrongful recipient to hand over the message, and the zeal it engenders, to the rightful and intended recipient. The unwillingnessof both the rightful and the usurping recipient to fall in with this requirement causes the activist great irritation. 4 Dark Gods: Nationalism is the re-emergence of the atavistic forces of blood or territory. This is the view shared often by both lovers and haters of nationalism. The former think of these dark forces as life-enhancing, the latter as barbarous. In fact, man of the ageof nationalismis neither nicer nor nastier than men of other ages. There is some slight evidence that he may be nicer. His crimes are equalled by those of other ages. They are more conspicuous only because, precisely, they have become more shocking, and because they are executed with more powerful technologicalmeans. Not one of these theories is remotely tenable. I I Who isfor Nurembng? An author committed to the view that the ideological or doctrinal history of nationalism is largely irrelevant to the understanding of it should not perhapsindulgein debatesabout its intellectualancestry. If it has no doctrinalancestryworth discussing, why should we argue about who does and who does not figure in its genealogy?Nevertheless, some remarksseem calledfor by Kedourie's influentialaccount of its ideal origins. Leaving aside the strange implicit exculpation of Hegel, what seems both perplexing and unfair is the inculpation of Kant. Certainly the notion of self-determinationis absolutely central to Kant's , thought. Kant7 s main problem was the validation (and circumscription) of both our scientific and our moral knowledge. The main philosophic device he employs for the attainment of this end is the contention that our guiding cognitive and moral principles are selfgenerated, and inescapably so. As there is no final authority or validation to be found outside, it must be inside. That is the core of his thought. The authority of the principles we live by resides in the fact that our minds necessarily have a certain structure, which inescapably engenders them. This gives us, among other things, an ethic of impartiality, and also the just ed hope of finding exceptionlessregularitiesin nature. An orderly ethic and an orderly science are thus, both of them, underwritten. The fact that I the structure of our minds is given and rigid frees us from the fear I that these bases of science and morality might be at the mercy of I caprice, that they might turn out to be quicksands. Though they are based on us only, yet, on this view, we can be trusted, and provide a reliable base. The fact that it is we, or rather, each single one of us individually (though mutually respectful of each other) who assumes responsibility for these principles, frees Kant from the fear of a regression which was repellent both to the logician and to the protestant within him: if the auaority and the justification were outside us, (however elevated it might be), how could that authority in turn be justified? The authority of the self, unsusceptible to caprice, final and absolute, terminatesthe regression. It avoids the scandal, intolerably repugnant both to the logician and the moralistin Kant, of accepting some outside authority, however elevated: the scandal of heteronomy, as he himself called it, which is the antithesis of selfdetermination. At the same time, the fortunate rigidity of the self makes its authority reliable and usable. Thatis the essenceof Kant7 s philosophy, the picture contained in iris notion of 'self-determination'. What connection, other than a purely verbalone, doesit havewith theself-determinationof nations, which so concerns the nationalists? None. It is individual human nature which is really sovereign for Kant - the transference of sovereignty to it constituted his Copernican revolution - and it is universaland identicalin all men. It is the universalin man which he revered, not the specific, and certainly not the culturally specific. In such a philosophy, there is no place for the mystique of the idiosyncratic culture. There is in fact hardly any room for culture in the anthropological sense at all. A person's identity and dignity is for Kant rooted in his universal humanity, or, more broadly, his rationality, and not in his cultural or ethnic specificity. It is hard to think of a writer whose ideas provide less comfort for the nationalist. On the contrary: Kant7 s identification of man with that which is rational and universal in him, his fastidious and persistent, highly characteristic distaste for basing anything of importance on that which is merely contingent, historical or specific, makes Kant a very model for that allegedly bloodless, cosmopolitan, emaciatedethic of the Enlightenment, which romantic nationalists spurned and detested so much, and which they so joyously repudiated in favour of a more earthy, shamelessly specific and partial commitment to kin or territory or culture. 132 NATIONALISM AND IDEOLOGY This point is of some generalinterest. Kant is the very last person whose vision could be credited with having contributed to nationalism. Nevertheless, this accusation is not simply an error, but springsfrom somethingdeeper which deserves note. What is true is that Kant felt an acute need to base our central values on ideas, on ssmething less fragile, less contingent, less world-bound than the mere tradition which happens to prevail in this land or that. His whole philosophical strategy reflects this need and the acuteness with which he felt it. He thought he could satisfy it by invoking the universal structure of the human mind. From the viewpoint of a crypto-romantic traditionalism which spurns such pursuit of external, 'rational' bases for the practices of life, which wishes to teach men to stay content within the limits of concrete praxis, to accept the contingency of history, and to refrain from seeking the illusory comfort and support of extraneous and abstract ideas, Kant is certainly a deeply misguided figure. He was most certainly a 'rationalist' in the sense in which Professor Michael Oakeshott pejoratively uses the term, and Nationalism in Asia and Africa seems to be argued within this general framework. In other words, Kant most certainly does belong to the Prometheanstrand in Europeanthought, whichperhapsreacheditsapogeein theeighteenth century, which strives to steal the divine fire and will not be content with the makeshift accidental compromises contained in specific traditions. Kant makes his deep contempt for such attitudes, for allowing oneself to be satisfied with merely contingent, historic foundations, utterly plain. Kant's insistence on individual self-determination as the only genuinely valid morality was neither wilful nor romantic. It was, on the contrary, a despairing attempt to preserve a genuine, objective, binding, universal ethic (and knowledge). Kant accepted H u e ' s argument that necessityand universalitysimply were not there to be found in the empirical data; hence, he reasoned, they could only be rooted in the ineluctablyimposed structure of the individual mind. Admittedly, this faute de m k x solution also fitted in neatly with a kindof protestant individualistpride, which scorns to find authority outside. But the main reason why authority had to be inside the individualwas because it simply could not be found anywhere else. Nationalists, when they invoke the abstract principle of nationalism against the traditional local institutions which had once worked tolerably well, are indeed fellow-Prometheans. In fact, NATIONALISM AND IDEOLOGY 133 nationalism has a Janus-like quality. It is Promethean in its contempt for politicalcompromisewhichignores the nationalistimperative. But it is also anti-Promethean, when it sees the nation and its cultural development as something which, just because it is concrete and historically specific, rightly overrides the abstract morality of the internationalistsand humanists. In this very, very generic, and above all negative sense, Kant and the nationalistscan perhaps be classed together. Neither of them are, in the required sense, respecters of tradition. (Or rather, nationalism is opportunistically selective in the respect which it accords to tradition.) Both are, in this wide sense, 'rationalists', seekingthe bases of legitimacy in something beyond that which merely is. Nationalists, in fact, might well acclaim conservative traditionalists as brothers, as fellow-repudiators of the abstract rationalism of the Enlightenment, and very often do so. Both of them wish to respect or revere the concrete realities of history, and refuse to subject them to the verdictof a bloodlessabstractpan-human reason. Far from revelling in the defiant individualwill, nationalists delight in feelings of submission or incorporation in a continuous entity greater, more persistent and more legitimate than the isolated self. In a curious way, Kedourie not only credits nationalism with a theory of wilful self-determination, but also (erroneously in my view) concedes the historical success of such a nationalism. A theory sprang from the heads of certain philosophers, and those who became converted to it succeeded, by sheer will, in imposing the theory on hapless humanity! This stark version of his view, which initially makes few concessions to the social circumstances which favoured nationalism, would make its success seem a veritable triumph of the wiU. It just so happens, it seems to me, that nationalists or conservativesselect different parts of the concretefor their reference: in the one case, continuous institutions, and in the other, allegedly continuouscommunitiesor speech, race, or other notion. But is that not a disagreement on detail rather than principle? This affinty of underlying attitude does not, of course, prove either of these positions to be necessarily in error. I only invoke it to show that one man's sense of concrete historical reality'is another man's trahison des clercs. How are we to choose our realists? So not all those who spurn a given position (traditionalism) thereforenecessarily resembleeach other in any other way. This mistaken - -- -NATIIONALISMAND~DEOLOGY inference, reinforced by the homonym 'self-determination', seems to Zealand convenient and mandatory, and the separation does not be at the base of the accusation of Kant. Kant did indeed speak of provoke resentment in anyone's breast, notwithstanding the techself-determination (autonomy). But then, he also spoke a great deal nical violation of the national principle. Why not? There are Arabs about the synthetic a p- status of our categories. It is well- who deplore the failure of the Arabs to unite, though Arabs of difestablished history that no bombs have been ever thrown on behalf ferent countries differ culturallyfar more than Englishmen and New of Kant's doctrine of the a pn'ori status of categories. But the Zealanders. The obvious answer seems to be that the international same is just as true of his views on self-determination. If a connec- standingand general position of the English and of the New Zealantion exists between Kant and nationalismat all, then nationalismis a ders does not s fer significantly from their failure to present themreaction against him,and not his offspring. selves to the world as one unit. In fact, their standing does not suffer from this fact at all, and the inconveniences of the alternative arrangementwould be very considerable. By contrast, it is arguable One nation, ow state that the political strength of Arabs, Latin AmericansY3and preunification nineteenth-centuryItalians and Germans did suffer from Nationalist sentiment is deeplyoffended by violations of the nationa- the fragmentation of their political roofs. list principleof congruence of state and nation; but it is not equally Nevertheless, this particular violation of the national principle, offended by all the various kinds of violation of it. It is most acutely the one nation-many states case, is clearly the least septic, the least offended by ethnic divergence between d e r s and ruled. As Lord irritant of all the possible violations. The obstacles lying in the way of its correction are obvious and powerful. If a given nation is blessed with n states, it follows rigorously that the glorious dcaThen began a time when the text simply was, that nationswould not be governed by foreigners.Powerlegitimately attained,and exercised tion of the nation will mean the diminutioh of the number of its with moderation, was declared invalid.' prime e s t e r s , chiefsof staff, presidentsof theacademy, managers and skippers of its football team, and so on, by a factor of n. For Note that Acton shows that &is time began, whereas nationalists every person occupying a post of this kind after udication, there pretend it was ever presentin a latent, suppressedform. But when it will be n-1 who will have lost it. In anticipation, all those n-1 comes to the arithmetical non-correspondence between nation and stand to lose by unification, even if the nation as a whole benefits. state, it is more offended if, so to speak, thestateis toofew, than if it Admittedly the one fortunate enough to have retained or acquired is too many. A culturally homogeneous population which has no the post in question is now laureate, director of the national theatre, state at all to call its own is deeply aggrieved. (Its members are ob- and so on, of something bigger, more glorious, and associated with liged to live in a state, or in states, run by other and alien cultural far greater resources than before. All the same, there can be little groups.) A group which, on the other hand, has more than one state doubt that while it is better to be head of a big 'un than a little 'un, associated with its culture, though it is also technicallyviolating the the difference is not so drastic as that between being a head, never national principle, yet has less grievance, except perhaps in special mind of how much, and not beinga head at all. Even allowingfor the circumstances. What are they? effect of the iunsionwhich may haveencouraged a lot more than one Most New Zealanders and most citizens of the United Kingdom of the little 'uns EO expect that they will be the big 'un when the day are so continuous culturally that without any shadow of doubt the comes, the fact remains that on balance, the rational opposition to two units would never have separated, had they been contiguous must be considerable. Unification succeeds, neverthegeographically. Distance made the effective sovereignty of New less, only in those cases where the external disadvantages of 'The continuedcomplaisanceof Latin Americansin thefaceof thissituation 'Quotec! in Nationalism, Its Meaning and History,by Hans Kohn, Princeton, is cogently invoked against our theory by Jos6 Merquior in 'Politics of 1955, pp. 122-3. Transition', Goventmt and Opposition, XVI (1981), No. 2, p. 230. 136 NATIONA~ISMAND ~ E O L O G Y fragmentation are very great and visible, and those who suffer from them can make their interests felt against those who will lose out in the n-fold diminution of political jobs, and when the new leaders of the larger unity somehow succeed in imposing themselves on the others, by force or by political glamour. Conclusion A book like this, which argues a simple and sharply defmed case, nevertheless(or perhapsall the more) risks being misunderstood and misrepresented. Attempts to present earlier and simpler versions of this argument on previousoccasionshaveconvincedmeof the reality of this danger. On the one hand, the very simplicity and starknessof the position may lead readers to add to it their own associations, which were not intended by the author. On the other hand, any new position (which is what I fondly believe this one to be) can be articulated only if the framefor assertingit is first set up, however quietly. No originalassertion can be made, I think, by simply drawingon the cards already available in the language pack that is in use. The pack has been dealt too often, and all simple statements in it have been made many times before. Hence a new contribution to a topic is possible only by re-designing a pack so as to make a new statement possible in it. To do this very visibly is intolerably pedantic and tedious. The overt erection of a new scaffolding is tolerable in mathematics, but not in ordinary prose. Good presentation consists in fairly unobtrusively looseningthe habitualassociations, setting up new ones on principles which becomeevident from the context, until at last the context has been set up in which an assertion can be made which is simple, and yet not a trite repetition of the old wisdom. What is not being said Only others can judge whether I have succeeded in this endeavour. But experience has taught me that one is seldom if ever wholly successful in this. Hence I wish to list a few assertions which have neither been asserted nor are in any way required for the views which have been propounded. It is no part of my purpose to deny that mankind has at all times lived in groups. On the contrary, men have always lived in groups. 138 CONCLUSION Usually these groups persisted over time. One important factor in their persistence was the loyalty men felt for these groups, and the fact that they identified with them. This element in human life did not need to wait for some dis~ctivekind of economy. This was, of course, not the only factor helpingto perpetuate thesegroups, but it was one among others. If one calls this factor, generically, 'patriotism', then it is no part of my intention to deny that some measure of such patriotism is indeed a perennial part of human life. (How strong it was in relation to other forces is somethingwe need not try to decide here.) What is being claimed is that nationalism is a very distinctive species of patriotism, and one which becomes pervasive and dominant only under certain social conditions, whichin fact prevailin the modem world, and nowhere else. Nationalism is a species of patriotism distinguished by a few very important features: the units which this kind of patriotism, namely nationalism, favours with its loyalty, are culturallyhomogeneous, basedon a culture strivingto be a high (literate)culture; they are largeenough to sustain the hope of supporting the educationalsystem which can keep a literate culture going; they are poorly endowed with rigid internal sub-groupings; their populationsare anonymous, fluid and mobile, and they are unmediated; the individual belongs to them directly, in virtue of his cultural style, and not in virtue of membershipof nestedsub-groups. Homogeneity, literacy, anonymity are the key traits. It is not claimed that cultural chauvinism was generally absent from the pre-industrial world, but only that it did not have its modem political clout or aspirations. It is not denied that the agrarian world occasionally threw up units which may have resembled a modern national state; only that the agrarian world could occasionallydo so, whilst the modem world is bound to do so in most cases. It is not claimed that, evenin the modem world, nationalismis the onlyforceoperating, or an irresistibleone. It is not. It is occasiohally defeated by some other force or interest, or by inertia. It is not denied that one may on occasion have an overlay of preindustrial structures and national sentiment. A tribal nation may for a time be tribal internallyand nationalexternally. It is infact easy to think of one or two marked cases of this kind (for example, Somalis and Kurds). But a man may now claim to belong to one of these national units simply in virtue of his culture, and he need not disclose (and eventually, need not even have) a mediating sub-group membership. It is not claimed that the present argument can explain why some nationalisms, notably those of the Hitler and Mussolini period, should have become so specially virulent. It only claims to explain why nationalism has emerged and become pervasive. All these disclaimers are not an insurance against counterexamples, which would at the same time covertly reduce the content of the centralthesis to something approachingnaught. They are only the recognition that in a complex world, at the macro-level of institutions and groupings, exceptionless generalizations are seldom if ever available. This does not prevent overall trends, such as nationalism, from being conspicuous - or being sociologically explicable. Summary In this matter as in some others, once we describe the phenomenon we are ipterested in with precision, we come close to explaining it correctly. (Perhaps we can only describe things well when we have already understood them.) But consider the history of the national principle; or consider two ethnographicmaps, one drawn up before the age of nationalism, and the other after the principle of nationalism had done much of its work. The fist map resembles a painting by Kokoschka. The riot of diversepointsof colour is such that no clear patterncan be discerned in any detail, though the picture as a whole does have one. A great diversity and pluralityand complexitycharacterizesall distinct parts of the whole: the minute socialgroups, which are the atomsof which the picture is composed, have complex and ambiguous and multiple relations to many cultures; some through speech, others through their dominant faith, another still through a variant faith or set of practices, a fourth through administrative loyalty, and so forth. When it comes to painting the politicalsystem, the complexity is not less great than in the sphere of culture. Obedience for one purpose and in one context is not necessarily the same as obediencefor some other end or in some other season. Look now insteadat the ethnographicand politicalmap of an area of the modem world. It resembles not Kokoschka, but, say, Modigliani. There is very little shading; neat flat surfaces are clearly separatedfrom each other, it is generally plain where one beginsand - --- c O N C ~ S ~ N N p another ends, and there is little if any ambiguity or overlap. Shifting to move from one occupational position to another, even within a from the map to the reality mapped, we see that an overwhelming single life-span, and certainly between generations. They need a part of political authority has been concentratedin the hands of one shared culture, and a literate sophisticated high culture at that. It kind of institution, a reasonably large and well-centralizedstate. In obliges them to be able to communicate contextlesslyand with pregeneral, each such state presides over, maintains, and is identified cision with all comers, in face-to-face ephemeral contacts, but also with, one kind of culture, one style of communication, which pre- through abstract means of communication. All this - mobility, vails within its borders and is dependent for its perpetuation on a communication, size due to refmement of specialization- imposed centralized educational system supervised by and often actually run on the industrial order by its thirst for affluenceand growth, obliges by the state in question, which monopolizes legitimate culture its social units to be large and yet culturally homogeneous. The almost as much as it does legitimate violence, or perhaps more so. maintenance of this kind of inescapably high (because literate) culAnd when we look at the society controlled by this kind of state, ture requires protection by a state, a centralized order-enforcing we also see why all this must be so. Its economy depends on mobility agency or rather group of agencies, capable of garnering and deand communication between individuals, at a level which can only ploying the resources which are needed both to sustain a high culbe achieved if those individualshave been socialized into a high cul- ture, and to ensure its diffusion through an entire population, an ture, and indeed into the same high culture, at a standard which achievement inconceivable and not attempted in the pre-industrial cannot be ensured by the old waysof turning out human beings, as it were on the job, as part of the ordinary business of living, by the The high cultures of the industrial age differ from those of the local sub-communities. It canonly be achieved by a fairly monolithic agrarian order in a number of important and conspicuous ways. educationalsystem. Also, the economic tasks set these individuals do Agrarian high cultures were a minority accomplishment carried by not allow them to be both soldiers and citizens of local petty com- privileged specialists, and distinguished from the fragmented, uncodified majority folk cultures over which they presided and which they strdve to dominate. They defined a clerkly stratum seldom tied So the economy needs both the new type of centralculture and the to a single political unit or linguistically delimited folk catchment central state; the culture needs the state; and the state probably area. On the contrary, they tended and strove to be trans-ethnicand needs the homogeneouscultural branding of its flock, in a situation trans-political. They frequently employed a dead or archaic idiom, in which it cannot rely on largely eroded sub-groupseither to police and had no interest whatever in ensuring continuity between it and its citizens, or to inspire them with thatminimum of moral zeal and the idiom of daily and economic life. Their numerical minority and social identification without which social life becomes very difficult. their politicaldominance were of their essence; and it is probably of Culture not community provides the inner sanctions, such as they the essence of agrarian society that its majority is constituted by are. In brief, the mutual relationshipof a modem culture and state is food-producers excluded both from power and from the high culsomething quite new, and springs, inevitably, from the require- ture. They were tied to a faith and church rather than to a state and ments of a modem economy. pervasive culture. In China a high culture linked more to an ethic What has been asserted is very simple. Food-producing society and a state bureaucracy than to a faith and church was perhaps was above all a society which allowed some men not to be food- untypical, and in that way, but that way only, anticipated the producers, but (excepting parasitic communities) nevertheless ob- modem linkage of state and culture. There the high literate culture I liged the majority of men to remain such. It is Industrial society has co-existed, and continues to co-exist, with a diversity of spoken succeeded in dispensing with this need.1 It has pushed the division of labour to a new and unprecedented By contrast, an industrial high culture is no longer linked level, but, more important still, it has engendered a new kind of whateverits history- to a faith and a church. Its maintenance seems divisionof labour: one requiring the men taking part in it to be ready to require the resources of a state co-extensive with society, rather - --- - -- C O N C L U S T O 7 ~ than merely those of a church superimposed on it. A growth-bound economydependent on cognitive renovationcannot seriously link its and cannot normallysurvivewithout its own politicalshell, the state. cultural machinery (which it needs unconditionally) to some doctrinal faith which rapidly becomes obsolete, and often ridiculous. So the culture needs to be sustained as a culture, and not as the carrier or scarcely noticed accompaniment of a faith. Societycan and does worship itself or its own culture directly and not, as Durkheim taught, through the opaque medium of religion. The transitionfrom one kind of high culture to the other is visible outwardly as the coming of nationalism. But, whatever the truth about this complex and crucial issue, the emergence of the industrial world was somehow intimately linked to a Protestantism which happened to possess some of the important traits that were to characterize the newly emergingworld, and which also engendernationalism. The stress on literacy and scripturalism, the priestless unitarianism which abolished the monopoly of the sacred, and the individualism which makes each man his own priest and conscienceand not dependent on the ritual services of others: all foreshadowedan anonymous, iadividualistic, fairly unstructured mass society, in which relativelyequal access to a shared culture prevails, and the culture has its norms publicly accessible in writing, rather than in the keeping of a privileged specialist. Equal access to a scripturalist God paved the way to equal accessto high culture. Literacyis no longer a specialism, but a pre-condition of all the specialisms, in a society in which everyone is a specialist. In such a society, one's prime loyalty is to the medium of our literacy, and to its political protector. The equal access of believers to God eventually becomes equal access of unbelievers to education and culture. Such is the world of modern state-sustained, pervasive and homogeneous high cultures, within which there is relatively little ascription of status and a good deal of mobility, presupposing a welldiffused mastery of a shared sophisticated high culture. There is a profound irony in Max Weber's celebrated account of the origins of this world: it was engendered because certain men took their vocation so very seriously, and it produced a world in which rigidly ascribed vocations have gone, where specialisms abound but remain temporary and optional, involving no final commitment, and where the important, identity-conferring part of one's education or formation is not the special skill, but the shared generic skills, dependent on a shared high culture which defines a 'nation'. Such a 1 Select Bibliography Anderson, B., Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism, London, 1583. Armstrong, John A., Nations before Nationalism, Chapel Hill, N.C., 1982. Avineri, Shlomo, The Making of Modern Zionism: The Intellectual Origins of The Jmish State, London, 1981. Banton, Michael, Rational Choice: Theory of Racial and Ethnic Relations, Bristol, 1977. Barth, Fredrik (ed.), Ethnic Groups and Boundaries: The Social Organization of Culture Difference, London, 1969. Bendix, Reinhard, Max Weber: An Intellectual Portrait, London, 1960. Breuilly, J. J., Nationalism and the State, Manchester, 1982. Bromley, Yu. V., et al., Sovremennye Etnicheskie Protsessy v SSSR, (Contemporary Ethnic Processes in the USSR), Moscow, 1975. Cohen, Abner, Two-Dimensional Man, London, 1974. Cohen, Percy, Jmish Radicals and Radical Jews, London, 1980. Cole, J.W.,and Wolf, E.R., The Hidden Frontier, Ecology and Ethnicity in an Alpine Valley, New York, 1974. Deutsch, K., Nationalism and Social Communication, New York, 2nd edn., 1966. Emerson, R., From Empire to Nation, Boston, 1960. Fromkin, David, The Independence of Nations, New York, 1981. Geertz, C. (ed.), Old Societies and New States, New York, 1962. Giddens, Anthony, The Nation-State and Violence: Volume 11 of A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism, Cambridge, 1985. Glazer, N. and Moynihan, D. (eds.), Ethnicity: Theory and Experience, Cambridge, Mass., 1975. GriUo, P., Nation and State in Europe: Anthropological Perspectives, London, 1981. Haim, Sylvia, Arab Nationalism, An Anthology, Berkeley, 1962. Hall, John A., Powers and Liberties: The Causes and Consequences of the Rise of the West, Oxford, 1985. Hechter, M., Internal Colonialism, London, 1975. Hroch, M. Die Vmkampferder nationalen Bewegung dei den kleinen Volkern Europas, Prague, 1968. Kamenka, E. (ed.), Nationalism, London, 1976. Kedourie, Elie, Nationalism, London, 1960. Kedourie, Elie (ed.), Natimlism in Asia and Africa, London, 1971. Kohn, Hans, The Idea of Nationalism, New York, 1944. Kohn, Hans, Nationalism, Its Meaning and History, Princeton, 1955. Kohn, Hans, The Age of Nationalism, New York, 1962. Loizos, P., Heart Grown Bitter: Chronicle of Cypriot War Refugees, Cambridge, 1981. Lukes, Steven, Emile Durkheim, His Life and Work: a Historical and Critical Study, London, 1973. Minogue, K.R., Nationalism, London, 1969. Nairn, Tom, The Break-up of Britain, London, 1977. Olson, Mancur, The Rise and Decline of Nations, New Haven, 1982. Seton-Watson, Hugh, Nations and States, London, 1977. Smith, A.D., Theories of Nationalism, London, 1971. Smith, A.D. (ed.), Nationalist Movements, London, 1976. Smith, A.D., Nationalist Movements in the TwentiethCentury, Oxford,1979. Smirh, A.D., The Ethnic Revival, Cambridge, 1981. Sugar, P. (ed.), Ethnic Diversity and Conflict in Eastern Europe, Santa Barbara, 1980 Tilly, C. (ed.), The Formation of National States in Western Europe, Princeton, 1975. Wallman, S., Ethnicity at Work, New York, 1979. Weber, E., Peasants into Frenchmen, London, 1979. Weber, Max, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, trans. Talcott Parsons, 2nd edn., London, 1976.