Social Inclusion: Perspectives, Practices and Challenges within the Visegrad Region SOC607 Literature Reader Content 1. Theoretical Introduction – What is Social Inclusion? 2. Social Innovations as a Practical Inclusive Tool 3. Inclusive Workplace 4. Dynamics of Social Inclusion/Exclusion in Public Space 5. Inclusive Education 6. Political aspects of social inclusion – What are inclusive policies? 7. How to Write a Research Proposal? 1 Theoretical Introduction – What is Social Inclusion? 1 1. Alexander, Jeffrey C. 1988. "Core Solidarity, Ethnic Outgroup and Social Differentiation." Pp. 78 - 106 in Action and its Environments: Toward a New Synthesis. New York: Columbia UP. 2. Allman, Dan. 2013. "The Sociology of Social Inclusion." SAGE Open. DOI: 10.1177/2158244012471957. 3. Collins, Hugh. 2003. "Discrimination, Equality and Social Inclusion." The Modern Law Review 66(1):16-43. 4. Levitas, Ruth. 2005. "Three Discourses of Social Exclusion." Pp. 7-28 in The Inclusive Society?: Social Exclusion and New Labour. 2nd ed. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. 5. Levitas, Ruth. 2005. "Delivering Social Inclusion." Pp. 159-177 in The Inclusive Society?: Social Exclusion and New Labour. 2nd ed. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan. SAGE Open January-March 2013: 1­–16 © The Author(s) 2012 DOI: 10.1177/2158244012471957 http://sgo.sagepub.com We live in the state and in society; we belong to a social circle which jostles against its members and is jostled by them; we feel the social pressure from all sides and we react against it with all our might; we experience a restraint to our free activities and we struggle to remove it; we require the services of other [people] which we cannot do without; we pursue our own interests and struggle for the interests of other social groups, which are also our interests. In short, we move in a world which we do not control, but which controls us, which is not directed toward us and adapted to us, but toward which we must direct and adapt ourselves. Gumplowicz, 1963, p. 6 This article considers the concept of social inclusion from the perspective of sociology. In doing so, it aims to complement the work of historians, economists, psychologists, and natural scientists to better understand the origins of the social inclusion concept. It argues that action and efforts to include or exclude individuals and social groups are fundamental to society as forces that govern through the oppressive or liberating effects such inclusionary or exclusionary actions promote. As a discipline from which to consider the social inclusion and exclusion concepts, sociology offers an excellent vantage. Sociology is well oriented to consider facets of social equality and inequality, social integration and stratification, social mobility as it relates to social inclusion and exclusion, and the functional contributions of the periphery relative to the social core. Sociology provides a needed vantage from which to consider social inclusion as it lends itself to extension beyond economic or natural fitness. In the social world, whether one is welcomed, represented, or provided for by the mainstream, or whether one is ostracized, ignored, or bemired, the outcome is a collection of social practices. These social practices result from various degrees of intimacy and interactions between friends, strangers, families, colleagues, kinship groups, communities, cultures, and even whole societies—all of which lend themselves to sociological study. This article begins with a consideration of exclusion and inclusion societies across time and place, including gated communities, closed institutions, and caste systems. The article delves into what is described as the natural order of social inclusion and exclusion. It explores some of the theories and findings that have come out of such an approach, including the evolutionary and sociobiological work in the area. To make its case for a sociology of social inclusion, the article then gazes back in time to three examples: ostracism in 5th-century Athens, solidarism in 19th century France, and contemporary considerations of stigma as influenced by the work of Goffman. Building on this, the article proposes that societies which emphasize differences in social integration are structured by architectures of inclusion that govern and manage how marginal women and men inhabit social space, while functioning to maintain many of the attributes of the status quo. Exclusion Hierarchies More than 50 years ago, the anthropologist and sociologist David Pocock (1957) reflected that processes of inclusion and exclusion were features of all hierarchies. Pocock felt 471957SGOXXX10.1177/21 58244012471957SAGE OpenAllman 2012 1 University of Toronto, Ontario, Canada Corresponding Author: Dan Allman, University of Toronto, Dalla Lana School of Public Health, 155 College Street, Room 524,Toronto, Ontario, Canada, M5T 3M7 Email: dan.allman@utoronto.ca The Sociology of Social Inclusion Dan Allman1 Abstract This article looks at social inclusion from a sociological perspective.It argues that sociology complements biological and other natural order explanations of social stratification.The article interrogates a variety of forms of social integration, including ostracism within 5th century B.C. Greece, 19th-century solidarism, and Goffman’s mid-20th-century work on stigma. It does so to demonstrate how in each of these contexts, social inclusion and exclusion can function as apparati that problematize people on the margins, and by extension, contribute to their governance and control.The article proposes that sociology provides a valuable orientation from which to consider social inclusion because it illuminates how social integration maintains and manages the ways in which people move about and through their socially stratified worlds. Keywords social inclusion, social exclusion, social integration, social stratification, sociology by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from 2 SAGE Open that in general terms, the discussion of inclusion and exclusion fed into efforts to define what might be called a social ontology, or the way that the existence and social positioning of groups in a hierarchically structured society would be explained. Such a social ontology has been described by Sibley (1995) as a landscape of exclusion; a form of social and philosophical geography that melds ideology with place in an exercise of social, economic, and political power that invariably results in forms of oppression, and in many instances, exploitation (Towers, 2005). Fredericks (2010) suggested that belongingness as experienced in everyday relations constructs the kinds of sentiments on which societies of exclusion (and inclusion) are based. Referencing the work of De Certeau (1984), Fredericks makes the case for the importance of the everydayness of belonging and attachment, and the memory and tradition it reinforces as means of appropriation and territorialization. One example of such a landscape of exclusion is a gated community (Hook & Vrdoljak, 2002). Grant and Rosen (2009) proposed these communities exist as exclusion societies. They cite Flusty’s (2004) argument that the community gates that enclose act to protect those inside from unforeseen and largely unwanted encounters with otherness. Examples given range from urban gated communities where exclusion is legitimized as spatial inequity (Flusty, 2004) to the present security fences undulating across Israel, or separating the United States from Mexico (Kabachnik, 2010). Herbert (2008) reflected on the ways in which urban spaces in the United States and elsewhere are turned into exclusion societies through the criminalization of public spaces outside the rarefied protected enclaves shielded within gates and walls. Focusing on the disorderly, Herbert describes this exclusion as a form of modern day prohibition that cedes out the homeless, the transient; and those who loiter, panhandle, and display public drunkenness (Douglas, 1966). Herbert found that these practices of creating exclusion societies are not new; that they have and continue to be used as justifications for forms of social cleansing (Cresswell, 2006; Dubber, 2005; Duncan, 1978; Spradley, 1970). Essentially the physical embodiment of territorial actions, exclusion societies seek to separate and compound the favored from the disfavored, and the hygienic from the dirty (Douglas, 1966; Sibley, 1995). To do this, they collectively create spaces of inclusion and exclusion, even if not all parties cede to such collectivism. Disability, like gated communities, is another example of the ways societies create cultural spaces structured by exclusion. Kitchin (1998) described the reproductive nature of disablist practices, as assemblies that seek to ensure disabled people are kept in certain places from where they come to understand when they may be out of place. For Kitchin, social relations between the disabled and the able-bodied function to keep disabled people in their place and to signal when they may be stepping beyond this space. Prisons, like asylums and other places that remove individuals from broader social life are additional if somewhat more extreme forms of exclusion societies. These institutions enclose the daily lives of certain social actors from broader society, replacing wider interaction with complex subcultures (Baer, 2005). An altogether different type of exclusion society is a caste system, which relies less on geographical separation and more on social distance. A notable example is the caste system of India (Nayar, 2007). At the root of India’s exclusion society are the untouchable castes whose marginal social position is owed to their relationship to impurities associated with death and organic pollution (Deliege, 1992). Berreman (1967, referencing Davis & Moore, 1945; Lenski, 1966; Mills, 1963; Tumin, 1953), held that caste systems—unlike gated communities, inner cities, orphanages, leper colonies, asylums, and prisons—are fundamentally structures through which power and privilege are allocated via interdependent social classifications ordered by stratified and ranked divisions of labor. Mencher (1974) referenced Leach (1960) in suggesting that India’s caste classifications facilitate divisions of labor free of the competition and expectations of mobility inherent in other systems. As exclusion societies, caste systems perpetuate themselves and the positions of privilege provided to those included within them. Yet they are different from other exclusion societies because across many noncaste landscapes of exclusion, mobility is conceivable and emulation of status is possible. However, in caste systems, place within the exclusion or inclusion hierarchy is ascribed at birth (Berreman, 1967, referencing Bailey, 1957; Sinha, 1959, 1962; Srinivas, 1956, 1966). Such exclusion by ascription has an economic dimension also through the way in which untouchables are “denied control of the means of production” (Deliege, 1992, p. 170, referencing Oommen, 1984). This results in forms of deprivation and poverty that enforce dependence, deference, and ultimately acceptance. Exclusion societies are identifiable at different places in time, space, and geography. Such societies tend to be associated with differential access to social and economic well-being, and differential proximity to illness and disease. Inclusion societies, however, evolve from within such contexts. They are characterized by movements toward greater social justice, equality, and collectivism in response to the kinds of global oppressions exclusion societies embody and perpetuate. A Natural Order Mechanisms of social inclusion and exclusion and the effects of these have been thoroughly investigated within the field of psychology and related disciplines. Work in this area has sought to better understand possible evolutionary origins of social inclusion and exclusion, and potential by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from Allman 3 sociobiological purposes to these different explanations of integration (Kurzban & Leary, 2001). Eisenberger and Lieberman (2005) and MacDonald and Leary (2005) have approached inclusion and exclusion from a psychosocial and physiological perspective in which they consider how the impacts of these social practices share overlapping characteristics with our physical pain systems. Eisenberger and Lieberman reflected that our social interconnectivity is as fundamental as our most basic human needs for fire, sustenance, and shelter and that the absence of such connectivity is experienced, literally, as pain. They propose that the pain of social exclusion, separation, or rejection share many of the experiential attributes of forms of physical pain. Referencing Baumeister (2000), Eisenberger and Liberman described how across many centuries and cultures, various forms of storytelling and artistic expression reflect how the interruption, loss, or absence of social bonds can manifest as intense experiences of human pain and suffering. They point out that the pain and suffering associated with the loss of social bonds is recognized by many legal systems also. To help explain the social, psychological, and physical pain experienced by exclusion, Eisenberger and Lieberman (2004) developed pain overlap theory. This theory holds that different kinds of pain utilize elements of shared processing systems. As reflected by MacDonald and Leary (2005), among our less developed ancestors, both physical and social pain were functional in that they steered kin and other social groups from environmental and other threats, reorienting them in the direction of helpful others. As such, the social pain of exclusion was seen to have evolved as a means of responding to danger. In detailing their sociometer theory, Leary, Tambor, Terdal, and Downs, (1995) explained why inclusionary and integrational practices are so fundamentally important to social interactions and how we are designed to detect them. They note that many writers have suggested that the human need to seek inclusion and to avoid exclusion is essential, and furthermore, that as a developmental trait, this orientation likely can be traced to its survival benefit (Ainsworth, 1989; Barash, 1977; Baumeister & Leary, 1995; Baumeister & Tice, 1990; Bowlby, 1969; Hogan, 1982; Hogan, Jones, & Cheek, 1985). For Leary et al. (1995), an individual’s sociometer is managed through self-esteem where social inclusion and exclusion are used as mechanisms to monitor the well-being of an individual or group’s social relations. These authors use the sociometer to underscore pain overlap theory by suggesting that self-esteem is a kind of inclusion detector that meters changes in the inclusionary or exclusionary positioning of individuals. From this perspective, it would be this need for detection that ultimately drives individuals to maximize their quest for inclusion while minimizing the possibility of exclusion. Along with the overlapping pain thesis and the sociometer/self-esteem thesis, Baumeister and Leary (1995) have posited a belongingness thesis. This suggests the need to belong is a fundamental human motivation. Here, along with base needs like food and shelter (Bernstein, Sacco, Young, Hugenberg, & Cook, 2010), belongingness is held to be a foundational human need that results in a general pattern whereby social inclusion is used to reward, and social exclusion to punish. The outcome is a gauge that structures both social values and comportment (Baumeister & Leary, 1995). Whereas a sociological perspective might suggest at the societal level that there exist a series of motivations to design inclusive frameworks for the betterment of social life, a natural order perspective would suggest that basic human survival and reproduction benefit from the evolution of cohesive group living; that to an extent, inclusion and exclusion as components of a behavioral repertoire may have helped to ensure evolutionary and reproductive fitness (Leary et al., 1995). This thinking suggests that such fitness at the level of kin networks or community groups may mirror existing physiological traits for responding to physical pain, to also structure responses to social pain. From this perspective, the exclusion/inclusion continuum exists alongside a biologically driven, psychological reaction that leads to the adoption of a generalized dislike of social exclusion and a favoring of the maintenanceofadequateinclusion(Eisenberger&Lieberman, 2005; MacDonald & Leary, 2005). Such arguments present another perspective as to why different societies and social groupings across diverse historical periods and geographical locations develop intense drives to create and strengthen social institutions around various aspects of social integration and exclusion. Yet, as the examples of ostracism, solidarism, and stigmatism will reflect, any biological push with regards to social stratification is accompanied by a social world pull. The examples of ostracism, solidarism, and stigmatism will demonstrate how at different intervals in history, it is not necessarily biological forces but instead social architectures that become employed in the creation and continuance of inclusion societies. Ostracism Acts and practices of including or excluding others as aspects of systems of stratification may be as old as much of humanity itself. Certainly, most societies display some degree of taboos and customs concerning forms of both social rejection and social acceptance (Douglas, 1966, Gruter & Masters, 1986; Lévi-Strauss, 1963; Radcliffe-Brown, 1952). In institutional terms, a very early form of social exclusion is evident in the scholarship of the role of ostracism in Athens, Greece, during the 5th century b.c., when the provision of an official mechanism to institutionalize ostracism was enacted. Although there is some debate within the works of Aristotle and Androtion as well as subsequent scholars about whether the law of ostracism originated with Cleisthenes by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from 4 SAGE Open prior to the first official ostracism of Hipparchos, son of Charmos, in 488 b.c. (Kagan, 1961; Raubitschek, 1951; Robinson, 1939, 1945, 1946, 1952), there is consensus that the law appeared sometime in the 20 years surrounding the battle at Marathon. The law of ostracism was instituted as a means to protect young democratic institutions from the resurgence of tyranny (Raubitschek, 1951). It did so through the enactment of an ostrakophoria (Goligher, 1910, p. 558, referencing Carcopino, 1909; Rehbinder, 1986, p. 323). Thus, ostracism was considered a democratic process in which those who were qualified to vote would “scratch onto a clay shard the name of a party leader to be banned (hence the name ostrakismos = shard judgment)” (Rehbinder, 1986, p. 323). As an initial incident in a series of expulsions driven by the desire for political control (Kagan, 1961), the very first political ostracism was followed by the successive exclusion of Magakles in 487-6, Xanthippos in 485-4, andAristeides in 483-2. As institutionalized more than 25 centuries ago, ostracism was used almost exclusively as a political weapon against male generals (Raubitschek, 1951), as a means to mitigate the influence of political rivals (Kagan, 1961) and to police and control the well-being of the state. Rehbinder (1986) suggested the main aim of ostracism was to “exclude the losing party leader from the state” as “early democracy could not integrate the continuous action of opposition parties into the political process” (p. 321). To address this and to solve party conflicts, a law of ostracism essentially functioned to banish the leader of the opposition. Importantly, Athenian ostracism was levied against an already elite class who for tyrannical activities or suspicions of tyranny were considered political liabilities or dangers. These acts did not bring shame on the recipient, but rather were prestigious, even honorable—a status reflected in the convention for the ostracized individual to retain his property, and, after his return, to regain his elite personal and social status (Rehbinder, 1986). As Aristotle wrote in Politics: Democratic states institute the rule of ostracism [because] such states are held to aim at equality above anything else; and with that aim in view they used to pass a sentence of ostracism on those whom they regarded as having too much influence owing to their wealth or the number of their connexions or any other form of political strength. (Barker, 1952, p. 135, referenced in Masters, 1986, p. 390) Ostracism as it came to be enacted in Attic democracy was not an event applied lightly or arbitrarily. It required careful deliberation, a large quorum, and the immunity of an ostracized person’s family. In essence, ostracism acted like a safety valve that ensured a smoother, more peaceful, and less tumultuous running of the state (Kagan, 1961). As instituted at the time, the law of ostracism was seen to be successful. It so weakened the ability of potentially disruptive subversive groups to wreak havoc on society and its political systems, that in the more than 90 years between 508 and 417 b.c., no more than 20 official ostracisms took place (Ostwald, 1955). Given that modern industrial societies increasingly tend to frown on the kinds of excluding practices as reflected in the legal practice of ostracism (Rehbinder, 1986), it can be challenging to acknowledge that ostracism exists in contemporary societies also, legally through, for example, formal punishments such as imprisonment, or racial prejudice, scapegoating, and xenophobia (Gruter & Masters, 1986). For Kort (1986), ostracism can be considered as coerced or involuntary exit of an individual or individuals from the society in which they live that manifests as a range of exclusions. Thus, a society demonstrating variation in ostracism practices reflects a society with solidaristic strategies for the exclusion of its members from participation and from occupying positions of respect (Kort, 1986, referencing Masters, 1986). Solidarism To turn from the ostracism of 5th-century Athens to the solidarism of late-19th-century France, allows for the contrast of an early institutional approach to social exclusion with an equally enlightening historical era of inclusion. The concept of solidarism evolved in the late-19th-century in France during a period of social, epistemological, and ontological change. It was an age when understandings of autonomy were being reconsidered by “scientism, political ideologies (especially Marxism) and the Roman Catholic Magister,” entities united in their intent to denounce an increasing vanity-like individualism (Vincent, 2001, p. 414). Although, within this period, the idea of solidarity was not an established ethical reference, French Protestants united around this new form of solidarity known as solidarism. In doing so, the Protestants defined a path forward in their transformed identity as a social minority (Vincent, 2001). For this underclass, being an excluded minority was not seen as a stance from which to claim social or human rights. Rather, exclusion was seen as igniting the kind of freedoms of thought and associations, which lent themselves to the reconciliation of identity-lending conceptualizations like justice and liberty (Vincent, 2001). Although French Protestants were bound by religion, their move to solidarism is not seen as being directly related to religious teachings or directives. If anything, French Protestantism of this period was wary of “religious pietism and political liberalism and generally suspicious of any institutional expression of the desire for social justice” (Vincent, 2001, p. 415). As a result, they turned instead to groups not known as religious in connotation, such as trade associations, unions, and left-of-centre political parties. by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from Allman 5 It has been suggested that the story of solidarism is essentially the story of France’s move to the welfare state. In opposing collectivism because it potentially threatened individual liberty, while promoting the empowerment of the working class, the new philosophy of solidarism countered the individualism of laissez-faire liberalism and social Darwinism. In time, solidarism would come to help to dismantle existing resistance to social reform and to usher in this new era of Welfarism (Sheradin, 2000). Léon Bourgeois’s book Solidarité (1998), which first appeared in 1896, is held to be a form of manifesto for the solidarism movement. In the decades prior to the First World War, the newly empowered French Radical Party were looking for a philosophy that would help them to maintain central power against the right-leaning individualists and the left-leaning collectivists (Hayward, 1961, 1963). In 1895-1896, during the short-lived Radical government of Bourgeois, he published a pamphlet titled Solidarité based on a series of his public letters that had appeared earlier. The main intent of this document was to advocate for a new approach, between “retreating laissez-faire liberalism and ascendant socialism.” The aim of the particular piece of writing was to shine a light on “the duties that citizens owed to each other” (Koskenniemi, 2009, p. 285). Bourgeois’s Solidarité is seen as representing what has been described as a belle époque within the Third Republic (Hayward, 1963). Solidarism became the main social philosophy of his new radical party (Koskenniemi, 2009), orienting it and the nation toward what in time would become a new more inclusive state. As a new political and collective philosophy, solidarism was seen as reflective of a modernization of the revolutionary maxim: liberty, equality, and fraternity. Notably, solidarism’s narrative features the influences of democracy and humanism, through its belief in the development and contributions of every individual, and through its assertion of the inherent dignity of all of humanity (Sheradin, 2000). Solidarism was committed to democracy, to the empowerment of the working class, and to 19th-century understandings of human reliance and interdependence (Sheradin, 2000). In being so committed, one can find a second meaning in this movement, one interwoven with concern over balancing selfinterest with the era’s philosophical humanistic ideals. It is not surprising that among the principles of French solidarism was the belief that the liberty of human kind was not freedom absolute, but rather an understanding that free individuals were also in debt to society, to every other citizen, and to future generations (Koskenniemi, 2009). In time, with the passing of World War I, the French Radical Party fell from favor as many of the working class shifted their allegiance to the Socialists following the Bolshevik Revolution of 1917 (Hayward, 1963). Ultimately, the harshness of World War I ended much of the utopian inclusivity inherent within the solidarist approach, and by the 1920s, much of the impact and influence of solidarism had been depleted (Koskenniemi, 2009). However, for the generation or two of those in France moved by the solidarist approach to social integration, one of the most persuasive elements of the philosophy and one that lent to its fashionableness was what Hayward (1961) described as an open sesame inclusive approach to mitigating the social conflicts of the era. The philosophy was meaningful to the time also because as an approach, it was not really radical at all. Rather, it melded elements of community, inclusivity, and social solidarity—all useful mechanisms to help the populace attain security against poverty, illness, unemployment, and war (Hayward, 1961). The broad solidarism movement was oriented to the reconciliation of individual and social ethics with the belief that all citizens had the free will to interact and develop relationships with others (Vincent, 2001). Solidarism in essence acted as a shared and uniting philosophy—a precondition of the era’s new approaches toward social contractuality (Foschi & Cicciola, 2006) For Koskenniemi (2009), the influences of these preconditions would be felt at home and abroad, playing a defining role in solardistic evolutions throughout the Spanish Civil War, World War II, the beginning forays across the continent toward the establishment of the European Union (EU), and ultimately, as the sociological lens helps reveal, trickling through Goffman’s 1950s work on stigma and France’s 1970s social inclusion as promoted by René Lenoir. Stigmatism Stigma and the act of stigmatizing is a common and recognizable form of social exclusion, yet, efforts to contend with some of the prejudices and discriminations recognized as components of stigmatization reflect forms of social inclu- sion. Inherent within Goffman’s (1963) work: Stigma: Notes on the Management of Spoiled Identity, is a belief in the universality of stigma and social exclusion. Stigma as a process leads certain individuals to be “systematically excluded from particular sorts of social interactions because they possess a particular characteristic or are a member of a particular group” (Kurzban & Leary, 2001, p. 187). The concept embodies the functionality of “outsiderderness”; and the utility of why humans, as “an inherently social species with a strong need for social acceptance should be so inclined to reject members of its own kind” (Kurzban & Leary, 2001, p. 187). For Goffman and those influenced by him (Crocker, Major, & Steele, 1998; Elliott, Ziegler, Altman, & Scott, 1982; Jones et al., 1984; Kleinman et al, 1995; Schneider, 1988), stigmatization occurs when the evaluation of an individual results in that person being discredited (Kurzban & Leary, 2001). As a sociologist, Goffman’s approach was both dramaturgical and oriented toward a symbolic interactionist by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from 6 SAGE Open perspective. His main interest was in the structure of social interactions and the rules that governed them (Goffman, 1967). For Goffman, social structures provided the context for interactions, as it was social structure that steadied and sustained social hierarchies (Scambler, 2009). Yet some have suggested that Goffman may not have sufficiently attended to political economy, or to elements considered traditionally beyond the foci of symbolic interactionists such as class, power, gender, and ethnicity (Scambler, 2006, 2009). From a functional perspective, stigma in the natural world reflects certain biological elements. Kurzban and Leary (2001) suggested that this world is structured by a series of interconnected interactions that result in variable costs and benefits (see Whiten & Byrne, 1988, 1997). As reflected earlier, there is a universality to stigma in the sense that it has been observed in most human cultures and even in the animal kingdom (Behringer, Butler, & Shields, 2006; Buchman & Reiner, 2009; Dugatkin, FitzGerald, & Lavoie, 1994; Oaten, Stevenson, & Case, 2011). Examples of this near universality include territoriality in fish, birds, reptiles, and mammals, and cross-species status hierarchies and social ostracism. Some like Kurzban and Leary (2001) sought to frame the exclusion of stigma from the perspective of biological determinism. That is, as psychological rather than social systems structured by natural selection to ease some of the challenges of sociality. The proposition is that these systems or exclusionary mechanisms often influence individuals to subconsciously exclude dangerous others from social structures and interactions (Archer, 1985). Thus, from this biologically deterministic perspective, stigma is not so much owing to the kind of negative evaluation as theorized by Goffman and colleagues, but rather to a form of protective disassociation. Another deterministic approach to stigmatism has considered the exclusion of stigma from the perspective of disease, and specifically as a mechanism of disease avoidance. Here, the basic claim derives from several observations. First, that we tend to evaluate those who are infectious in the same way as we would evaluate other kinds of stigmatized individuals (Snyder, Kleck, Strenta, & Mentzer, 1979). Second, that the most severely stigmatized groups (i.e., those who are most avoided) are individuals who are evidently ill or who demonstrate characteristics of the ill or diseased (Oaten et al., 2011 referencing Bernstein, 1976; Heider, 1958; Kurzban, & Leary, 2001; Schaller, & Duncan, 2007). Leprosy and smallpox are but two examples. For these authors, envisioning stigma as disease-avoidance does not negate other processes that contribute to discriminatory or exclusionary behavior. Rather, it suggests that beneath or antecedent to other processes is an avoidance system that seeks to limit possible contact with infectiousness and disease (Oaten et al., 2011). Parker and Aggleton (2003) reflected that often stigma goes undefined in academic scholarship or reverts to somewhat of a stereotypical, two-dimensional description of exclusion. In a series of articles, these authors have argued for the development of a more nuanced conceptual framework that would go beyond the works of Goffman and of biological determinists (Parker, 2012, referencing also Parker & Aggleton, 2003, and Maluwa, Aggleton, & Parker, 2002), to think beyond evolutionary stigma or differentially valued stigma and more directly about stigma as a “social process fundamentally linked to power and domination” (Parker, 2012, pp. 165-166). Parker (2012, referencing Stuber, Meyer, & Link, 2008) reflected that theory and research has tended to operationalize stigma either as discrimination (as in the work of Goffman, 1963) or as prejudice (as in the work of Allport, 1954). Subsequently, over the second half of the 20th century, the two foci evolved along parallel but distinctly separate directions, with the work on prejudice tending much more to tackle race, ethnicity, and associated social relations. Yet as Parker (2012), Parker and Aggleton (2003), Link and Phelan (2001), and others have argued, discrimination and prejudice, as components or forms of stigma, share key relations with the production and reproduction of power relations. It is arguably owing to this revisioning beyond dramaturgical performance and biological determinism that stigma can be envisioned as a somewhat supplanted component of the contemporary discourse of social exclusion and inclusion. The suggestion that stigma is not (or not only) performed and not (or not only) determined but rather is culturally produced as a social, relational, and powerful artifact is a compelling argument (Buchman & Reiner, 2009). Equally compelling is Scambler’s (2009) reflection that stigma can be a very convoluted social process, one for which sociology is well-oriented to imagine as a combination of experience, anticipation, and perception, of the harms of blame and devaluation; the fears and pain of rejection and exclusion; and the hopes and desires for acceptance and inclusion. Social Inclusion How cultures and societies stratify and divide; how they account for customs around inclusion, exclusion, belonging, and togetherness; and how the processes that include and exclude are talked about, described, understood, and experienced, all provide some clues as to the role of social integration and stratification within a given society. Indeed, how stratification is conceived and discussed can obscure the very nature of the processes by which such divisions come to be. This is precisely why the discipline of sociology is so useful. Unlike natural order sciences, it does more than identify and posit explanations for social divisions. Sociology, in addition to this, can reflect also on the disciplinary discourses encircling discussions of these social partitions. For example, one of the means by which stratification is conceptualized and discussed could take as a by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from Allman 7 reflective example, the pre–World War II writings of Sorokin (1998), who in considering stratification differentiated between horizontal and vertical social mobility. Sorokin suggested that horizontal mobility related to changes in occupational position or role, but not to changes within a social hierarchy, whereas vertical mobility did describe changes within the social hierarchy. Sorokin summarized his theory by reflecting that within systems of vertical and horizontal mobility, there could be individual social infiltration as well as collective social movement. Furthermore, that although it was possible to identify forms of mobile and immobile societies within different geographical and historical contexts, it was rare for a society’s strata to be closed absolutely, and rare for the vertical mobility of even the most mobile society to be completely free from obstacles. As proposed by Sorokin, these types of social movements could often vary across time and space, yet even across time, trends—particularly as they might apply to vertical mobility—were unlikely to be writ in stone. Although autocratic societies might be less mobile than democratic societies, the rule was not fixed and could have exceptions (Sorokin, 1998). While often used to describe low or zero labor market involvement (Foster, 2000), early definitions of social exclusion in time broadened to consider barriers to effective or full participation in society (Du Toit, 2004). These types of barriers were considered to contribute to progressive processes of marginalization that could lead to deprivation and disadvantage (Chakravarty & D’Ambrosio, 2006). As the exclusion concept took on currency, it began to reflect more than a simple material nature and to begin to encompass the experience of individuals or communities who were not benefitting or were unable to benefit relative to others in society (Davies, 2005; Levitas, 1998). In time, the concept would evolve to reflect lapses in social integration and social cohesion that plagued advanced capitalist societies (Chakravarty & D’Ambrosio, 2006). It would evolve also to refer to processes that prevent individuals or groups from full or partial participation in society, as well as the crippling and reifying inability to meaningful participation in economic, social, political, and cultural activities and life (de Haan & Maxwell, 1998; Duffy, 1995, 2001; Horsell, 2006)—a definitional approach that imbues exclusion in terms of neighborhood, individual, spatial, and group dimensions (Burchardt, Le Grand, & Piachaud, 1999, referenced in Percy-Smith, 2000). March, Oviedo-Joekes, and Romero (2006) suggested that one of the elements that unify the divergent definitional approaches to social exclusion and inclusion is that social exclusion is a process as opposed to a static end state. Further, that inclusion, in addition to being a context-based social and historical product reflective of social and national history, tends to mirror also what Silver (1995) proposed were the very limits of the borders of belonging. Despite attempts at globally applicable definitions of social exclusion and inclusion, it has been suggested that there will always be patterns of border shaping that are particular to specific contexts. This is in part because the weight of inclusion versus exclusion is dependent on the particulars of any given society (de Haan & Maxwell, 1998; March et al., 2006; O’Brien, Wilkes, de Haan, & Maxwell, 1997). Such society-specific particulars might take the form of traditional and historic patterns of stratification, or be based on how individual groups and/or characteristics may be valued over others. Less clear, however, is which, if any, elements of a given society or social structure may mitigate the kinds of exclusion/inclusion dynamics that may be held aloft as representative of normative practice. For example, in some social contexts, patterns of inclusion and exclusion may reflect different stages of social and economic development. Alternately, these patterns may vary by type and/or political orientation of governments, or by the religious, ethnic, or cultural makeup of a given society. Ultimately, however, the use of inclusion and exclusion concepts has evolved to the point where within a number of contexts, they are used as a descriptor for those who represent a particular kind of threat to social harmony (Silver & Miller, 2003). In sum, the terms social inclusion and social exclusion have been used throughout the social science and humanities literature in a number of different ways—to describe acts of social stratification across human and animal societies, as a principle to reflect the ordering that occurs within societies to determine social position, and as a narrative to explain and at times justify why one or more groups merit access to the core or the periphery, to the benefit or expense of others. Initial discourses of social inclusion are widely attributed to having first appeared in France in the 1970s when the economically disadvantaged began to be described as the excluded (Silver, 1995). The preliminary uses of this new parlance appeared as a means to refer to a variety of disabled and destitute groups. The government of France was among the earliest adapters of exclusion terminology, and it is there that most often the concept is suggested to have found its contemporary meaning (Silver & Miller, 2003). As a fully documented policy response, the concept of social inclusion to counteract social exclusion emerged toward the end of the 1980s, when the European Community (EC) first used the term social exclusion (Wilson, 2006). The appearance of the term social inclusion in the rhetoric of the EC was in itself a key point of departure, in that exclusion was suddenly held to be a reflection that “poverty was no longer the right word to use to describe the plight of those marginalized from mainstream society” (Williams & White, 2003, p. 91). Ascertaining the contemporary use of the terms social inclusion and social exclusion involves a study of diffusion of, most importantly, the applications of René Lenoir, France’s Secretary of State for Social Welfare in the Chirac government of the 1970s (Davies, 2005, citing Lenoir, 1974; Pierce, 1999; Silver, 1995). by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from 8 SAGE Open L’Inclusion Sociale In 1965, a French social commentator, Jean Klanfer, published L’Exclusion sociale: Étude de la marginalité dans les sociétés occidentales [Social exclusion: The study of marginality in Western societies] (Béland, 2007). Described as an anthropology of poverty (Cl, 1968), Klanfer’s work argued that society rewarded personal responsibility with inclusion and personal irresponsibility with exclusion. If the work of Bourgeois was a primary influence on the soldarism movement almost 100 years earlier, the writings of Klanfer would fuel the imagination of René Lenoir (1974), most notably in his book Les exclus. In his political tome, Lenoir contended social exclusion was a result of France’s postwar transition from a largely agricultural society to an urban one (Davies, 2005). While the belief was that these events could lead to poverty, Lenoir argued that they could lead to a brand of social polarization also, which challenged the Liberté, Egalité, and Fraternité ideals of the French Republican project. Many have suggested that if there were a birth of the modern rhetoric of social inclusion, it would be here, in French thought that sought a means to reintegrate the large numbers of ex-industrial workers and a growing number of young people excluded from opportunities to join the labor force in the new economies of the 1970s and beyond. According to Silver (1995) and Silver and Miller (2003), one of the reasons the inclusion and exclusion concepts resonated so strongly for the French was that in their society, the Anglo-Saxon idea of poverty was seen to essentially insult the equality of citizenry contained within the Liberté manifesto—an equality that, as reflected in France’s late-20thcentury welfare state, operationalized charity as basic social assistance in response to poverty, and as essentially a right of citizenry. Furthermore, what would come to be seen as an inclusive welfare state was held to be the most effective and civilized way to eliminate absolute material deprivation and the risks to well-being such deprivation could cause. However, as the 1970s progressed, and as unemployment became endemic, the passage of time brought even greater numbers of those considered excluded, and with them everincreasing reiterations of the new exclusion discourse (Silver, 1995). The result in France was a movement to protect les exclus. The movement was so strong that by 1998, the French posited legal codification to prevent and combat social exclusions (note the plural) as a means to foster universal access to fundamental human rights. Within French Republican thought in particular, social exclusion was seen to reflect ruptures in solidarity and the social bond (lien social), something essentially tantamount to heresy within the French social contract. Heresy because the French social contract of the time was seen to hold (and some may argue continues to hold) reciprocity, both between the social obligations French citizens have for the French state and the obligations that society has in return, to provide reasonable livelihoods for its members. Here, though, the accepted exceptions, as in many welfare regimes, were restricted to those who could not work due to older age, disability, or ill health, and did not extend to those whose deliberate actions and/or deliberate tendencies toward illicit pleasure, removed them from broader labor force opportunities or expectations. In some respects, the mutuality and reciprocity evident in elements of French Republican thought reflected a social contract that favored the already-included in its definition of society. For the positioning of reciprocity within the social contract, such a context has implications for the creation of biases against the failings of the excluded. In particular, against those who vary from society’s includable norms. In the place of any such consideration leading to action, appeared a sort of stoic romanticism. Thus, for the French, the excluded came to represent a martyred or punished sector of a society against whom the included had failed to live up to their side of the social contract. As the concept of exclusion grew to gain broader credence beyond France, the EC and the subsequent EU, it increasingly incorporated target groups who were not simply poor or without sufficient resources. It incorporated those segregated also from the social core through attributes such as ethnicity or race, age, gender, and disability, and whose characteristics could contribute to justify the need for deliberate social inclusion programs (Omidvar & Richmond, 2003). That these attributes tended to be noncriminalized and relatively politically correct, as opposed to criminalized and/or contested, is a feature that should not be lost. Even though the concepts of citizenship and social integration in the French tradition may present some challenges for Anglo-Saxon manners of thinking, this did not, according to Gore, Figueiredo, and Rodgers (1995), prevent the wider adoption of exclusion frameworks across Western Europe. These authors suggested that in appropriating the concept as integral to modern and meaningful social development, the EC was linking the concept of social exclusion more closely with evolving thoughts around the implications of unrealized social rights. While EC and EU directives sought to carve out greater social inclusion, other countries, particularly Commonwealth countries—notably the United Kingdom, Australia, New Zealand, Canada, and South Africa—were beginning to roll out their own interpretations of this rhetoric. In its initial contemporary use, the exclusion terminology adopted in France and subsequently diffused elsewhere, was meant to refer to those individuals who were considered to be on the margins of French society of the 1970s. That is, individuals considered society’s social problems, who tended to share a particular social reality, a less than successful material existence compounded with real barriers in accessing benefits provided by the French welfare state (Daly, 2006). by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from Allman 9 So great were the social problems, that Lenoir, would suggest that a full 10% of the French population were exclu, or outcast. According to Davies (2005), “the novel characteristic of les exclus was not that they were poor (although most were), but that they were disconnected from mainstream society in ways that went beyond poverty” (p. 3). This disconnect, it was argued, was facilitated by their relative social positioning and by factors related to poor health and social, economic, and geographical isolation from active engagement in politics. From this perspective, to be socially excluded was paramount to being of the underclass; to be among those people who did not fit into the norms of industrial societies, who were not protected by social insurance and who were essentially considered social misfits. (Silver, 1995; Stegemen & Costongs, 2003). Beliefs about social conformity aside, Silver’s (1995) near definitive list of the socially excluded reads in some regards as a full 50% of the world’s population. In doing, so it lends credence to Labonte’s (2004) assertion that the socially excluded are liable to comprise everyone who is not middleaged, middle class, and male. It follows that just naming who is at risk of social exclusion, based on identity, vulnerability, membership, or biology will not suffice without some reflection as to who is naming the excluded, where those who label or define the excluded stand ontologically relative to their own or others’ exclusion, and what if any the influences of personal, political, stereotypical, or xenophobic biases may be. It is an element of the conceptualization of social inclusion and exclusion particularly well-suited to sociology’s contribution. A Sociological Lens In many ways, despite the contribution of the psychological and life sciences, and even the contributions of social policy, the concepts of social inclusion and exclusion are profoundingly sociological. This is because at the very root of both classic and contemporary sociological thinking are concerns with social stratification, social inequality, and social class— key concepts which the social inclusion literature repeatedly touches upon. Witcher (2003, referencing Burchardt et al., 1999) reflected that social inclusion and exclusion were concepts that were often poorly defined or theorized. Daly (2006) has suggested that although there is nothing inherent in the inclusion and exclusion concepts that defy or negate theorization, in general, sociology’s attempts at their theorization could be inconsistent or facile. Horsell (2006) referenced Crowther (2002) in suggesting that the contemporary interest in social exclusion and inclusion were reflective of similar attempts to conceptualize the dual influences of poverty and social deprivation. As such, these concepts signaled that somehow the cumulative impacts of poverty and social deprivation (or the cumulative effects of social exclusion in the absence of social inclusion) could represent a threat to social order. Horsell’s (2006) suggestion was that, in purely operational terms, the exclusion/inclusion paradigm acted to reinforce neoliberal ideas about social actors and agency as well as to harness principles of mutual obligation and active participation; that the discourse, broadly speaking, had both symbolic and physical dimensions. In its consideration of the ways in which contemporary social policy analysis treats social position as stratification, deprivation, and inequality, attempts to tease out the causes and consequences of social exclusion relative to inclusion could risk becoming muddled by mixing together attempts to better the lives and living conditions of people living below poverty lines, with the illusion that more were being done than might be. Horsell’s suggestion of illusion hinged on the reflection that those who may ultimately benefit from the application of such inclusion-speak when operationalized as policy could tend to be those who already enjoyed a number of inclusion’s benefits. Levitas (1996, 1998) has reflected that the overall flavor of the social inclusion rhetoric is strongly Durkheimian. She has stressed that Durkheim and the exclusion/inclusion discursive continuum demonstrate a tendency to repress conflict as well as a tendency toward an approach to inclusion that subversively critiques capitalism in a way that would be lacking from a purely Durkheimian analysis. Owing in part to this, Levitas (1998) labeled the rhetoric of social inclusion “a new Durkheimian hegemony” (p. 178), given that most contemporary views of inclusion correspond to scholarly interpretations of Durkheim’s sociology, including Durkheim’s emphasis on an alternative attempt to navigate an understanding of society between unacceptable free market capitalism and an unacceptable state socialism. Such hegemony, according to Bowring (2000), leads us to think of elements of exclusion like deprivation and inequality as phenomena that occur at the very margins of society, and by extension, to ignore social structures that influence the included as well as the excluded. Bowring’s point was that the exclusion/inclusion rhetoric risks being somewhat of a red herring, because exclusion at the societal level could be indicative of systemic deprivation and not just a deprivation experienced or reported by those defined as socially excluded. For Wilson (2006), it was important to recall that social integration per se was not a focus of Durkheim. For Durkheim, inequality and social stratification were natural results of society, components of a solidary system he divided into mechanical and organic: the former being a fountain of social cohesion and the latter a well of social inclusion. Together, they were envisioned as the kinds of dependencies that social actors within advanced societies share with one another. Wilson’s point was that although Durkheim associated increases in solidarity with social progress, he would not by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from 10 SAGE Open necessarily associate the same solidarity with social inclusion, since in theory, advanced societies characterized by mutual dependence would exhibit the kinds of mutual and shared bonds that would defy the need for social inclusion in the first place. The emphasis of these authors, and arguably of a Durkheimian perspective as applied to social inclusion also, is that new or reborn ways are not necessarily different ways. That despite its focus on the socially disenfranchised and their position relative to a status quo, there remains a hollow echo to the rhetoric around social inclusion. A void that is both redolent of discussion of the hollow state (Barnett, 1999; Davies, 2000; Della Sala, 1997; Holliday, 2000; London Edinburgh Weekend Return Group, 1980; Rhodes, 1994; Roberts & Devine, 2003; Skelcher, 2000), as well as a void that references one of Levitas’s (2000) and Labonte’s (2004) salient points: that it is one thing to promote an inclusionary utopia. However, in the event that such a utopian vision comes to pass, how likely is it that the result will be the kind of social world foreseen? In other words, even if a utopian ideal were within the reach of real-world, applied social policy, what are the odds, as Kenyon (2003) suggested, that attaining an inclusive society would result in the banishment of all inequality. It was Young’s (1999) argument, and Wilson’s (2006) reiteration that although much of the West’s social inclusion rhetoric may address many things, the root cause of social exclusion is not one of them. In this, the rhetoric fails because to address these causes would require acknowledgment that even within real-world inclusion societies, people frequently continue to experience poverty in a context that envelops them with messages of the meritocracy that surrounds them—a meritocracy that suggests that anyone with desire and ambition can succeed through acceptable behavior and hard work. For these authors, this represents a relative process of deprivation—one that includes an encounter with a form of culture shock where the culture in which the excluded experience their day-to-day existence actively reinforces the notion that they are receiving a much lower standard of living than others. Here then, one could contend, is reflected the relative deprivation that leads to social exclusion “through a subjective experience of inequality and unfairness as materially deprived people seek to obtain the unobtainable” (Young, 1999, p. 401, cited in Wilson, 2006, p. 342). In a twist on the variations in social inclusion discourses presented earlier, this view holds that social exclusion morphs into “a cultural phenomenon arising from dialectic relationships between identity and social acceptance and the contradiction of a supposed meritocracy in which the poor lack the material means to meet the aspirations they are encouraged to embrace” (Wilson, 2006, p. 343). In other words, exclusion becomes social status contested between a hierarchical valuation of different kinds of social identities (socially hazardous vs. socially accepted) within a social world attempting to remedy the inherent challenges embedded in an inequitable division of resources within an acquisitive, material world. Residuus Exclusion In discussing the problematization of exclusion, the sociologist Nikolas Rose wrote that the mid-19th century wore the mantle of “a succession of figures that seem to condense in their person, their name, their image all that is disorder, danger, threat to civility, the vagrant, the pauper, the degenerate” (Rose, 1999, p. 254). As the 19th century gave way to the 20th, there appeared efforts to create universally shared forms of social citizenship. Yet even within this drive toward universality, there were those who were cast as unincludable, just as there are today. Within the new liberal thinking, universal citizenship did not emulate fully the fact that the notion of universal was still a somewhat relative concept and that a boundary between the includable and the excludable would not only continue to exist but would be reinforced also. From this arose “notions such as ‘the residuum,’ ‘the unemployable’ and ‘the social problem group’” (Rose, 1999, p. 254), that is, states of embodied being, through social roles, social strata, and entire classes that would, in time, become integral to these new forms of liberal thinking. From such vantage, the rhetoric of exclusion/inclusion, and the array of notions and underlying beliefs about the utility of integration, would become parts of the organizing, and traceable mainstays of reform. From older, perhaps simpler conceptualizations of inequality were born new ways of understanding what Rose, citing Levitas (1996), described as a “two-thirds, one-third social order” where a seemingly continually widening gap between the included two thirds and the excluded one third would continue to unfurl (Rose, 1999, p. 258). Rose (1999) differentiated the new excluded from previous form of unequals. Whereas minorities that arose from the welfare state had claims to unity and solidarity, the new excluded have few of these, and it is perhaps from this lack of unification that the new expertise underlying inclusion’s emphasis is born. Challenged from forging identity and right of place based on shared exclusion, this new underclass is “like Marx’s peasants, individualized like potatoes in a sack, incapable of forming themselves into a single class on the basis of a consciousness of their shared expropriation” (Rose, 1999, pp. 254-255). In moving from a welfare to a postwelfare, advanced liberal order, social control is reconfigured into control that moves beyond repressing or containing individual pathology. It becomes both about knowledge and access to the production of knowledge. This is because—to paraphrase Marx— access to the production of knowledge provides for the definition of what is and is not includable (Rose, 1999, referencing Ericson & Haggerty, 1997). Thus, the new labor force of control is no longer one that is either purely reactive or purely punitive. Rather, it takes on a form of administrative function whereby it oversees the marginalia comprising the by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from Allman 11 bounds (and bonds) of inclusion and exclusion, of risk and safety and permissibility (Rose, 1999). It was Rose’s vision that for the excluded underclass “a politics of conduct is today more salient than a politics of class” (Rose, 2000, p. 335, citing Mead, 1991, p. 4, and Procacci, 1999, p. 30). Although Rose’s discourse is compelling, one should consider also whether all of the excluded are created equal. Do they all share the same position within the underclass? For example, across the Western world, special interest groups have sprung up since the softening of the welfare state, groups which include not only those that are socially excluded—drug users, sexual deviants, the poorly socialized—but also the physically excluded such as those who are bodily or mentally challenged. In order for the work of Rose and those who have influenced his arguments regarding the inclusion/exclusion divide to be applicable (these influences include the works of Foucault, 1979a, 1976/1979b, 1985, 1991; Mead, 1991; O’Malley, 1992, 1999, 2004; Valverde, 1998), the work will need, in part, to account for diversity and social stratification within the underclass—that is, to help shed light on how and why certain social hierarchies of the status quo become replicated within the margins, leading to some of the marginal experiencing, in a sense, double marginality. At the same time, even those who achieve core or nonperipheral social status risk facing constraining hierarchies and limits to social mobility that function to either deny or defy full integration. Extrapolating from the work of Rose, the inclusion society would not be a utopian dream, but rather a development that to varying extents would further institutionalize themes of inclusion, permissible rights, and the breadth of acceptable conduct. Conclusion This article has reflected on social inclusion from the vantage of sociology. It has reflected on exclusion and inclusion societies, across time and place and has demonstrated the importance of considering the physical world’s exclusion and inclusion societies not only from a natural order perspective but from a social order perspective also. Many of the considerations explored here have embodied measurable, objective approaches to the sociological conception and consideration of exclusion and inclusion. Du Toit (2004) has suggested current definitions, and their applications within individual country contexts allow social scientists and policy makers to present social exclusion as a single outcome of potentially multiple determinants of deprivation. Yet, this article has considered arguments that position inclusion and exclusion as much more than the fodder of contemporary policy. Indeed, it has demonstrated how human integration and expulsion are both highly historical and deeply sociological; that forms of social deprivation as well as social entitlement span many hundreds of years, if not the full course of human history itself. For all that is known about social stratification, the tendency, particularly from the perspective of sociology, has been to consider inclusion and exclusion from an observational standpoint. This has occurred through policy analysis, historical analysis, and even consideration of some of the sociobiological correlates of inclusion and exclusion. What is less well known and less well developed are approaches for understanding the subjective experiences of social inclusion and social exclusion. For example, how exclusion and inclusion are experienced socially? How experiences of inclusion and exclusion are produced and reproduced socially? How different social labels impact the experience of inclusion and exclusion, and what the role of stigma may be? For the reader, understanding the journey from social exclusion to social inclusion sociologically is an undertaking across potentially difficult terrain. Among other things, it requires a critical eye capable of accounting for individual and group participation and lack thereof (Daly, 2006). And what of poverty? For some writers who have sought to unpack social inclusion and exclusion, these concepts are but alternate ways of recasting the notion of poverty. Others suggest economic poverty need be seen either as only one of an interrelated group of dimensions which work in tandem together to contribute to an individual’s inability to successfully access the overall labor market. Such an approach would envision poverty as one factor in a multifaceted approach to understanding the experiences of society’s lower strata (Sirovátka & Mare, 2006; Woodward & Kohli, 2001). As prescribed approaches to policy and practice, efforts to contend with contemporary social exclusion often come to be framed by a rhetoric of reformation, imbued with different traditions in terms of how poverty is framed around either relational or distributional issues (Murie & Musterd, 2004, referencing van Kempen, 2002). It is a vantage that capitalizes on Marshall’s (1963) model of postwar social rights, where, rather than focus on forms of postwar poverty, the focus on social exclusion is on redistribution, access, and participation (Murie & Musterd, 2004). Then and now, sociologically speaking, when poverty rather than social structure is held up as the cause and consequence of exclusion, such deprivation is presented as a failure of capabilities as opposed to a manner of being within a social structure or society. Chakravarty and D’Ambrosio (2006) suggested that an emphasis on the shortfalls of economic thresholds as an explanation for exclusion is not the same as emphasizing structured inabilities to participate. This is because a focus on structural inabilities allows for a more complex, multidimensional understanding of the interplay, overlap, and social distance between money, work, and belonging. As a reconceptualization of social disadvantage, such a perspective provides an important framework for thinking out alternatives to the welfare state. It links poverty, productivity by means of employment and social integration that in turn emphasizes integration and insertion into a labor market, active and personalized participation, and a multicultural national citizenry (Gore et al., by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from 12 SAGE Open 1995). It broadens also the notion of inclusion beyond biological or economic fitness alone. In this regard, the suggestion that social inclusion exists not necessarily as a mechanism of sociobiological well-being only but more viscerally as a reflection of outcome of economic empowerment holds much in common with Richard Parker and PeterAggleton’s post-Goffman work on stigma.Although good arguments exist—and many have been presented here— about why integration and ostracism can be interpreted through both natural order and economic lenses, inclusion and exclusion do not represent free-floating views. Like stigma, inclusion and exclusion also exist at “the historically determined nexus between cultural formulations and systems of power and domination” (Parker, 2012, p. 166). As systems of social power, these formations constitute architectures of inclusion; that is, means and ways that inclusion and exclusion are both enacted and talked about. Such architectures exist as literal and figurative coalitions of action, reaction, governance, control, and power which together comprise how a policy aim like social inclusion is wound, entwined, draped, and displayed for public rendering and consumption. In what can be described as a political economy of inclusion, the hierarchies embedded in these architectures of inclusion not only ascribe value to who is to be considered includable but also reflect value structures that can lead to forms of ideologically based interpretations about whether inclusion is as good or better than exclusion (Rodgers, 1995) based on variation in social power, the ability to hold rights, and the representation or embodiment of hazard. As with more traditional, physical forms of architecture, inclusion’s architectures function to both limit and facilitate the movement and interaction of people through hierarchies of integration. Enclosed within these architectures are worlds of inclusion and exclusion that push and pull amid new forms of allowance, constraint, and conflict (Gumplowicz, 1963). Parallel yet interconnected worlds in which, are reflected, the socially excluded, reduced, and idealized as somewhat two-dimensional occupiers of social space (Spina, 2005). Gillies (2005) reflected that societies have a tendency to normalize the sins of the included while penalizing the sins of the excluded. This suggests that even if discourses about social inclusion are effectively rendered as policy and translated into practice, the act of revaluating the biases society’s hold for marginal underclasses of excluded social actors may well remain. This is to say that were society able to find room within its social architectures for its marginal women and men (Park, 1928), the fact of their powerlessness coupled with their comportment could still relegate them to the periphery, occupying colonized spaces stratified on one side by accusations of nonnormative or deviant behavior and on another by power relations. For the contemporary open thinker trying to grapple with social inclusion and exclusion as a set of potentially complex concepts between those who study and profess a natural, an economic, or a social order, ideas about power would seem to be of particular importance—be it the power of the elite or the empowerment of those with special needs. Power seems to fuel the wheels of integration. Although power can be shown to have a decisive role in both the natural and the economic orders, it is in the arena of the social where it is perhaps best understood. One only need look at the history of philosophy and social theory for evidence of how power and proximity to it can enable or bar integration. Power allows proximity to the means of inclusion—essentially, to inclusion’s apparati. Of course, simply thinking openly about social worlds as variations of inclusionary or exclusionary societies does not lead to societies that are more inclusive. It does, however, allow for a more open lens with which to consider the past as well with which to view the present. Author’s Note Portions of this article were written during visits to the University of Port Harcourt, Nigeria; the University of Pretoria and the University of the Western Cape, South Africa; and the University of Namibia. Acknowledgments This work acknowledges the important contributions of Professors Lynn Jamieson, Angus Bancroft, Alex Robertson, Esther Breitenbach, and Anthony Coxon at the University of Edinburgh; Professors Ted Myers and Liviana Calzavara at the University of Toronto; and Professor Avril Taylor at the University of the West of Scotland. Thanks to Professor Donald Sacco for deftly ushering this manuscript through the review process at SAGE Open, and to the anonymous reviewers for their perceptive and very useful comments. Declaration of Conflicting Interests The author declared no potential conflicts of interest with respect to the research, authorship, and/or publication of this article. Funding The author disclosed receipt of the following financial support for the research and/or authorship of this article: The author received financial support from the Canadian Institutes of Health Research (CIHR) Funding Reference Number 68356. References Ainsworth, M. D. S. (1989). Attachments beyond infancy. American Psychologist, 44, 709-716. Allport, G. W. (1954). The nature of prejudice. Cambridge, MA: Addison-Wesley. Archer, C. (1985). Social deviance. In G. Lindzey & E. Aronson (Eds.), Handbook of social psychology (Vol. 2, 3rd ed., pp. 743- 804). New York, NY: Random House. Baer, L. D. (2005). Visual imprints on the prison landscape: A study on the decorations in prison cells. Tijdschrift voor Economische en Sociale Geografie, 96, 209-217. by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from Allman 13 Bailey, F. G. (1957). Caste and the economic frontier. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press. Barash, D. P. (1977). Sociobiology and behavior. New York, NY: Elsevier. Barker, E. (1952). Aristotle: Politics. London, England: Oxford University Press. Barnett, J. R. (1999). Hollowing out the state? Some observations on the restructuring of hospital services in New Zealand. Area, 31, 259-270. Baumeister, R. F., & Leary, M. R. (1995). The need to belong: Desire for interpersonal attachments as a fundamental human motivation. Psychological Bulletin, 117, 497-529. Baumeister, R. F., & Tice, D. M. (1990). Anxiety and social exclusion. Journal of Social & Clinical Psychology, 9, 165-195. Behringer, D. C., Butler, M. J., & Shields, J. D. (2006). Avoidance of disease by social lobsters. Nature, 441, 421. Béland, D. (2007). The social exclusion discourse: Ideas and policy change. Policy & Politics, 35, 123-139. Bernstein, M. J., Sacco, D. F., Young, S. G., Hugenberg, K., & Cook, E. (2010). Being “in” with the in-crowd: The effects of social exclusion and inclusion are enhanced by the perceived essentialism of ingroups and outgroups. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin, 36, 999–1009. Bernstein, N. R. (1976). Emotional care of the facially burned and disfigured. Boston, MA: Little, Brown. Berreman, G. D. (1967). Caste as social process. Southwestern Journal of Anthropology, 23, 351-370. Bourgeois, L. (1998). Solidarité [Solidarity]. Arras, France: Presses Universitaires du Septentrion. Bowlby, J. (1969). Attachment and loss: Vol. 1: Attachment. New York, NY: Basic Books. Bowring, F. (2000). Social exclusion: Limitations of the debate. Critical Social Policy, 20, 307-330. Buchman, D., & Reiner, P. B. (2009). Stigma and addiction: Being and becoming. American Journal of Bioethics, 9(9), 18-19. Burchardt, T., Le Grand, J., & Piachaud, D. (1999). Social exclusion in Britain 1991-1995. Social Policy & Administration, 33(3), 227-244. Carcopino, M. J. (1909). Histoire de l’ostracisme athénien. Mélanges d’Histoire ancienne. Paris, France: Alcan. Chakravarty, S. R., & D’Ambrosio, C. (2006). The measurement of social exclusion. Review of income and wealth, 52, 377-398. Cl, C. (1968). Review of L’exclusion sociale. Étude de la marginalité dans les sociétés occidentales by Jules Klanfer. Population (French ed.). 6, 1137-1138. Cresswell, T. (2006). On the move: Mobility in the modern Western world. New York, NY: Routledge. Crocker, J., Major, B., & Steele, C. (1998). Social stigma. In D. T. Gilbert, S. T. Fiske, & G. Lindzey (Eds.), The handbook of social psychology (Vol. 2, 4th ed., pp. 504-553). Boston, MA: McGraw-Hill. Crowther, C. (2002). The politics and economics of disciplining an inclusive and exclusive society. Social Policy Review, 14, 199-225. Daly, M. (2006). Social exclusion as concept and policy template in the European Union. Belfast, UK: Queen’s University. Davies, J. S. (2000). The hollowing-out of local democracy and the “fatal conceit” of governing without government. British Journal of Politics and International Relations, 2, 414-428. Davies, J. S. (2005). The social exclusion debate: Strategies, controversies and dilemmas. Policy Studies, 26, 3-27. Davis, K., & Moore, W. E. (1945). Some principles of stratification. American Sociological Review, 10, 242-249. De Certeau, M. (1984). The practice of everyday life. Berkeley: University of California Press. de Haan, A., & Maxwell S. (1998). Poverty and social exclusion in north and south. IDS Bulletin, 29(1), 1-9. Deliege, R. (1992). Replication and consensus: Untouchability, caste and ideology in India. Man, 27(1), 155-173. Della Sala, V. (1997). Hollowing out and hardening the state: European integration and the Italian economy. West European Politics, 20(1), 14-33. Douglas, M. (1966). Purity and danger: An analysis of concept of pollution and taboo. London, England: Routledge. Dubber, M. (2005). The police power: Patriarchy and the foundations of American government. New York, NY: Columbia University Press. Duffy, K. (1995). Social exclusion and human dignity in Europe: Background report for the proposed initiative by the Council of Europe. Strasbourg, France: Council of Europe. Duffy, K. (2001). Risk and opportunity: Lessons from the human dignity and social exclusion initiative for trends in social policy. Canadian Journal of Law & Society/Revue Canadienne Droit et Societe, 6(2), 17-41. Dugatkin, L. A., FitzGerald, G. J., & Lavoie, J. (1994). Juvenile three-spined sticklebacks avoid parasitized conspecifics. Environmental Biology of Fishes, 39, 215-218. Duncan, J. (1978). Men without property: The classification and use of urban space by tramps. Antipode, 10, 24-33. Du Toit, A. (2004). “Social exclusion” discourse and chronic poverty: A South African case study. Development and Change, 35, 987-1010. Eisenberger, N. I., & Lieberman, M. D. (2004). Why rejection hurts: The neurocognitive overlap between physical and social pain. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8, 294-300. Eisenberger, N. I., & Lieberman, M. D. (2005). Why it hurts to be left out: The neurocognitive overlap between physical and social pain. In K. D. Williams, J. P. Forgas, & W. van Hippel (Eds.), The social outcast: Ostracism, social exclusion, rejection, and bullying (pp. 109-127). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. Elliott, G. C., Ziegler, H. L., Altnan, B. M., & Scott, D. R. (1982). Understanding stigma: Dimensions of deviance and coping. Deviant Behavior, 3, 275-300. Ericson, R., & Haggerty, K. (1997). Policing the risk society. Toronto, Canada: University of Toronto Press. Flusty, S. (2004). De-Coca-colonization: Making the globe from the inside out. London, England: Routledge. by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from 14 SAGE Open Foschi, R., & Cicciola, E. (2006). Politics and naturalism in the 20th century psychology of Alfred Binet. History of Psychology, 9, 267-289. Foster, J. (2000). Social exclusion, crime and drugs. Drugs: Education, Prevention and Policy, 7, 317-330. Foucault, M. (1979a). Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison. New York, NY: Vintage. Foucault, M. (1979b). The history of sexuality: An introduction (Vol. 1, R. Hurley, Trans.). London, England: Allen Lane. (Original work published 1976) Foucault, M. (1985). The use of pleasure. London, England: Penguin Viking. Foucault, M. (1991). Governmentality. In G. Burchell, C. Gordon, & P. Miller (Eds.), The Foucault effect (pp. 87-104). Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Fredericks, B. (2010). What health services within rural communities tell us about Aboriginal people and Aboriginal health. Rural Society, 20, 10-20. Gillies, V. (2005). Meeting parents needs? Discourses of “support” and “inclusion” in family policy. Critical Social Policy, 25, 70- 90. Goffman, E. (1963). Stigma: Notes on the management of spoiled identity. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Goffman, E. (1967). Interaction ritual: Essays on face-to-face behaviour. New York, NY: Doubleday. Goligher, W. A. (1910). Review of Mélanges d’Histoire ancienne. English Historical Review, 25, 556-559. Gore, C., Figueiredo, J. B., & Rodgers, G. (1995). Introduction: Markets, citizenship and social exclusion. In G. Rodgers, C. Gore and J. B. Figueiredo (Eds.), Social exclusion: Rhetoric, reality, responses (pp. 1-42). Geneva, Switzerland: International Institute for Labour Studies, United Nations Development Programme. Grant, J. L., & Rosen, G. (2009). Armed compounds and broken arms: The cultural production of gated communities. Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 99, 575-589. Gruter, M., & Masters, R. D. (1986). Ostracism as a social and biological phenomenon: An introduction. Ethology and Sociobiology, 7, 149-158. Gumplowicz, L. (1963). Outlines of sociology (2nd ed.). New York, NY: Paine-Whitman. Hayward, J. E. S. (1961). The official social philosophy of the French third republic: Léon Bourgeois and solidarism. International Review of Social History, 6(Pt. 1), 19-48. Hayward, J. E. S. (1963). Educational pressure groups and the indoctrination of the radical ideology of solidarism, 1895-1914. International Review of Social History, 8, 1-17. Heider, F. (1958). The psychology of interpersonal relations. New York, NY: John Wiley. Herbert, S. (2008). Contemporary geographies of exclusion I: Traversing skid road. Progress in Human Geography, 32, 659-666. Hogan, R. (1982). A socioanalytic theory of personality. In M. Page (Ed.), Nebraska symposium on motivation (pp. 55-89). Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press. Hogan, R., Jones. W. H., & Cheek, J. M. (1985). Socioanalytic theory: An alternative to armadillo psychology. In B. R. Schlenker (Ed.), The self and social life (pp. 175-198). New York, NY: McGraw-Hill. Holliday, I. (2000). Is the British state hollowing out? Political Quarterly, 71, 167-177. Hook, D., & Vrdoljak, M. (2002). Gated communities, heterotopia and a “rights” of privilege: A “heterotopology” of the South African security-park. Geoforum, 33, 195-219. Horsell, C. (2006). Homelessness and social exclusion: A Foucauldian perspective for social workers. Australian Social Work, 59, 213-225. Jones, E. E., Farina, A., Hastorf, A. H., Markus, H., Miller, D. T., & Scott, R. A. (1984). Social stigma: The psychology of marked relationships. New York, NY: Freeman. Kabachnik, P. (2010). Place invaders: Constructing the nomadic threat in England. Geographical Review, 100, 90-108. Kagan, D. (1961). The origin and purposes of ostracism. Hesperia: The Journal of the American School of Classical Studies at Athens, 30, 393-401. Kenyon, S. (2003). Understanding social exclusion and social inclusion. Municipal Engineer, 156, 97-104. Kitchin, R. (1998). “Out of place,” “knowing one’s place”: Space, power and the exclusion of disabled people. Disability & Society, 13, 343-356. Klanfer, J. (1965). L’Exclusion sociale: Étude de la marginalité dans les sociétés occidentales [Social exclusion: The study of marginality in western societies]. Paris, France: Bureau de Recherches sociales. Kleinman, A., Wang, W. Z., Li, S. C., Cheng, X. M., Dai, X. Y., Li, K. T., & Kleinman, J. (1995). The social course of epilepsy: Chronic illness as social experience in interior China. Social Science & Medicine, 40, 1319-1330. Kort, F. (1986). The politics of ostracism. Ethology and Sociobiology, 7, 367-377. Koskenniemi, M. (2009). International law as sociology: French “solidarism” 1871-1950. In M. Koskenniemi (Ed.), The gentle civilizer of nations: The rise and fall of international law 1870– 1960 (pp. 266-352). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Kurzban, R., & Leary, M. (2001). Evolutionary origins of stigma: The functions of social exclusion. Psychological Bulletin, 127, 187-208. Labonte, R. (2004). Social inclusion/exclusion: Dancing the dialectic. Health Promotion International, 19, 115-121. Leach, E. R. (1960). Introduction. In E. R. Leach (Ed.), Aspects of caste in South India, Ceylon, and Northwest Pakistan (pp. 1- 10). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Leary, M. R., Tambor, E. S., Terdal, S. K., & Downs, D. L. (1995). Self-esteem as an interpersonal monitor: The sociometer hypothesis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 68, 518-530. Lenoir, R. (1974). Les exclus: Un Français sur dix [The excluded: One Frenchman out of ten]. Paris, France: Le Seuil. by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from Allman 15 Lenski, G. (1966). Power and privilege: A theory of social stratification. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill. Lévi-Strauss, C. (1963). Totemism. Boston, MA: Beacon. Levitas, R. (1996). The concept of social exclusion and the new Durkheimian hegemony. Critical Social Policy, 16(1), 5-20. Levitas, R. (1998). The inclusive society? Social exclusion and new labour. London, England: Macmillan. Levitas, R. (2000). Discourses of risk and utopia. In B. Adam, U. Beck, & J. van Loon (Eds.), The risk society and beyond: Critical issues for social theory (pp. 198-209). London, England: SAGE. Link, B., & Phelan, J. (2001). Conceptualizing stigma. Annual Review of Sociology, 27, 363-385. London Edinburgh Weekend Return Group. (1980). In and against the state. London, England: Pluto. MacDonald, G., & Leary, M. R. (2005). Why does social exclusion hurt? The relationship between social and physical pain. Psychological Bulletin, 131, 202-223. Maluwa, M., Aggleton, P., & Parker, R. (2002). HIV and AIDSrelated stigma, discrimination, and human rights. Health and Human Rights, 6, 1-18. March, J. C., Oviedo-Joekes, E., & Romero, M. (2006). Drugs and social exclusion in ten European cities. European Addiction Research, 12, 33-41. Marshall, T. H. (1963). Citizenship and social class in sociology at the crossroads. London, England: Heinemann. Masters, R. D. (1986). Ostracism, voice, and exit: The biology of social participation. Ethology and Sociobiology, 7, 379-395. Mead, L. (1991). The new politics of the new poverty. Public Interest, 103, 3-20. Mencher, J. P. (1974). The caste system upside down, or the not-somysterious East. Current Anthropology, 15, 469-493. Mills, C. W. (1963). The sociology of stratification. In I. Horowitz (Ed.), Power, politics and people: The collected essays of C. Wright Mills (pp. 305-323). New York, NY: Ballatine. Murie, A., & Musterd, S. (2004). Social exclusion and opportunity structures in European cities and neighbourhoods. Urban Studies, 41, 1441-1459. Nayar, K. R. (2007). Social exclusion, caste & health: A review based on the social determinants framework. Indian Journal of Medical Research, 126, 355-363. Oaten, M., Stevenson, R. J., & Case, T. I. (2011). Disease avoidance as a functional basis for stigmatization. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, 366, 3433-3452. O’Brien, D., Wilkes, J., de Haan, A., & Maxwell, S. (1997). Poverty and social exclusion in North and South (IDS Working Paper No. 55). Institute of Development Studies and Poverty Research Unit, University of Sussex. Retrieved from http:// www.ids.ac.uk/files/Wp55.pdf O’Malley, P. (1992). Risk, power and crime prevention. Economy and Society, 21, 252-275. O’Malley, P. (1999). Consuming risks: Harm minimization and the government of “drug-users.” In R. Smandych (Ed.), Governable places: Readings on governmentality and crime control (pp. 191-214). Brookville, VT: Ashgate. O’Malley, P. (2004). The uncertain promise of risk. Australian and New Zealand Journal of Criminology, 37, 323-343. Omidvar, R., & Richmond, T. (2003). Immigrant settlement and social inclusion in Canada. Toronto, Ontario, Canada: The Laidlaw Foundation. Retrieved from http://www.laidlawfdn. org/sites/default/files/laidlaw_publications/working_papers_ social_inclusion/wpsosi_2003_jan_immigrant-settlement.pdf Oommen, T. (1984). Sources of deprivation and styles of protest: The case of the Dalits in India. Contributions to Indian Sociology, 18, 45-61. Ostwald, M. (1955). The Athenian legislation against tyranny and subversion. Transactions and Proceedings of the American Philological Association, 86, 103-128. Park, R. E. (1928). Human migration and the marginal man. American Journal of Sociology, 33, 881-893. Parker, R. (2012). Stigma, prejudice and discrimination in global public health. Cadernos de Saúde Pública, 28, 164-169. Parker, R., & Aggleton, P. (2003). HIV and AIDS-related stigma and discrimination: A conceptual framework and implications for action. Social Science & Medicine, 57, 13-24. Percy-Smith, J. (2000). (Ed.), Policy responses to social exclusion: Towards inclusion? Philadelphia, PA: Open University Press. Pierce, R. (1999). Social exclusion: A literature review. York, UK: University of York. Pocock, D. F. (1957). Inclusion and exclusion: A process in the caste system of Gujarat. Southwestern Journal of Anthropology, 13, 19-31. Procacci, G. (1999). Poor citizens: Social citizenship and the crisis of welfare states. In S. Hänninen (Ed.), Displacement of social policies (pp. 7-30). Jyväskylä, Finland: University of Jyväskylä. Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. (1952). Structure and function in primitive society: Essays and addresses. London, England: Cohen & West. Raubitschek, A. E. (1951). The origin of ostracism. American Journal of Archaeology, 55, 221-229. Rehbinder, M. (1986). Refusal of social cooperation as a legal problem: On the legal institutions of ostracism and boycott. Ethology and Sociobiology, 7, 321-327. Rhodes, R.A. W. (1994). The hollowing out of the state: The changing nature of the public service in Britain. Political Quarterly Review, 65, 137-151. Roberts, J. M., & Devine, F. (2003). The hollowing out of the welfare state and social capital. Social Policy and Society, 2, 309-318. Robinson, C. A., Jr. (1939). The struggle for power at Athens in the early fifth century. American Journal of Philology, 60, 232-237. Robinson, C. A., Jr. (1945). Athenian politics, 510-486 B.C. American Journal of Philology, 66, 243-245. Robinson, C. A., Jr. (1946). The date of Themistocles’ ostracism. American Journal of Philology, 67, 265-266. Robinson, C. A., Jr. (1952). Cleisthenes and ostracism. American Journal of Archaeology, 56, 23-26. Rodgers, G. (1995). What is special about a “social exclusion” approach? In G. Rodgers, C. Gore, & J. B. Figueiredo (Eds.), Social exclusion: Rhetoric, reality, responses (pp. 43-56). by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from 16 SAGE Open Geneva, Switzerland: International Institute for Labour Studies, United Nations Development Programme. Rose, N. (1999). Powers of freedom: Reframing political thought. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Rose, N. (2000). Government and control. British Journal of Criminology, 40, 321-339. Scambler, G. (2006). Sociology, social structure and health-related stigma. Psychology, Health & Medicine, 11, 288-295. Scambler, G. (2009). Health-related stigma. Sociology of Health & Illness, 31, 441-455. Schaller, M., & Duncan, L. A. (2007). The behavioral immune system: Its evolution and social-psychological implications. In J. Forgas, M. G. Haselton, & W. von Hippel (Eds.), Evolution and the social mind: Evolutionary psychology and social cognition (pp. 293-307). New York, NY: Psychology Press. Schneider, J. W. (1988). Disability as moral experience: Nepilepsy and self in routine relationships. Journal of Social Issues, 44, 63-78. Sheradin, K. A. (2000). Reforming the republic: Solidarism and the making of the French welfare state, 1871-1914 (Doctoral thesis). Department of History, The College Arts and Sciences, University of Rochester, Rochester, NY. Sibley, D. (1995). Geographies of exclusion: Society and difference in the West. London, England: Routledge. Silver, H. (1995). Reconceptualizing social disadvantage: Three paradigms of social exclusion. In G. Rodgers, C. Gore, & J. B. Figueiredo (Eds.), Social exclusion: Rhetoric, reality, responses (pp. 57-80). Geneva, Switzerland: International Institute for Labour Studies, United Nations Development Programme. Silver, H., & Miller, S. M. (2003). Social exclusion: The European approach to social disadvantage. Indicators, 2(2), 1-17. Sinha, S. (1959). Bhumij-Kshatriya social movement in south Manbhum. Bulletin of the Department of Anthropology (University of Calcutta), 8, 9-32. Sinha, S. (1962). State formation and Rajput myth in tribal central India. Man in India, 42, 35-80. Sirovátka, T., & Mare, P. (2006). Poverty, social exclusion and social policy in the Czech republic. Social Policy & Administration, 40, 288-303. Skelcher, C. (2000). Changing images of the state: Overloaded, hollowed-out, congested. Public Policy and Administration, 15(3), 3-19. Snyder, M. L., Kleck, R. E., Strenta,A., & Mentzer, S. J. (1979).Avoidance of the handicapped:An attributional ambiguity analysis. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 37, 2297-2306. Sorokin, P. A. (1998). Social and cultural mobility. London, England: Routledge. Spina, F. A. (2005). The faith of the outsider: Exclusion and inclusion in the biblical story. Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans. Spradley, J. (1970). You owe yourself a drunk: An ethnography of urban nomads. Long Grove, IL: Waveland Press. Srinivas, M. N. (1956). A note on Sanskritization and Westernization. Far Eastern Quarterly, 15, 481-496. Srinivas, M. N. (1966). Social change in modern India. Berkeley: University of California Press. Stegemen, I., & Costongs, C. (2003). Health, poverty and social exclusion in Europe: Literature review on concepts, relations and solutions. Brussels, Belgium: EuroHealthNet. Retrieved from http://eurohealthnet.eu/sites/eurohealthnet.eu/files/publi- cations/pu_5.pdf Stuber, J., Meyer, I., & Link, B. (2008). Stigma, prejudice, discrimination and health. Social Science & Medicine, 67, 351-357. Towers, G. (2005). West Virginia’s lost youth: Appalachian stereotypes and residential preferences. Journal of Geography, 104(2), 74-84. Tumin, M. M. (1953). Some principles of stratification: A critical analysis. American Sociological Review, 18, 387-394. Valverde, M. (1998). Diseases of the will: Alcohol and the dilemmas of freedom. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press. van Kempen, E. (2002). “Poverty pockets” and social exclusion: On the role of place in shaping social inequality. In P. Marcuse & R. van Kempen (Eds.), Of States and Cities (pp. 240-257). Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Vincent, G. (2001). The engagement of French Protestantism in solidarism. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 4, 401-421. Whiten, A., & Byrne, R. W. (1988). Machiavellian intelligence: Social expertise and the evolution of intellect in monkeys, apes, and humans. Oxford, UK: Clarendon. Whiten, A., & Byrne, R. W. (1997). Machiavellian intelligence II: Extensions and evaluations. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Williams, C. C., & White, R. (2003). Conceptualising social inclusion: Some lessons for action. Municipal Engineer, 156, 91-95. Wilson, L. (2006). Developing a model for the measurement of social inclusion and social capital in regional Australia. Social Indicators Research, 75, 335-360. Witcher, S. (2003). Reviewing the terms of inclusion: Transactional processes, currencies and context (Case Paper 67). London, England: London School of Economics. Woodward, A., & Kohli, M. (2001). European societies: Inclusions/ exclusions? In A. Woodward & M. Kohli (Eds.), Inclusions and exclusions in European society (pp. 1-17). London, England: Routledge. Young, J. (1999). Cannabilism and bulimia: Patterns of social control in late modernity. Theoretical Criminology, 3, 387-407. Bio Dan Allman’s work focuses on the social and structural production of risk and well-being, particularly for those considered marginal, vulnerable, or peripheral to a society’s core. His interests include social stratification and equity, the sociology of health and medicine, and global health. by guest on September 19, 2016Downloaded from HughCollins* Althoughlawsagainstdiscriminationhaveconventionallybeenjustifiedand articulatedaccordingtovariousconceptionsofequality,tensionsbetweendifferent notionsofequalityunderminethecoherenceoftheseexplanations.Theaimof socialinclusionisproposedaspartofanalternativejustificationfordiscrimination laws.As wellas exploringthemeaningandimplicationsofthepolicyofsocial inclusionfordiscriminationlaws,theextenttowhichthelawalreadyembodiesthis ideaisassessedwithparticularreferencetothescopeofanti-discriminationlaws, proofofdiscrimination,justificationdefences,andpositivediscrimination.It is concludedthatthegoalofsocialinclusionhasthepotentialtoprovidea vital ingredientina morecoherent,thoughnotuncritical,accountoftheaimsofanti- discriminationlegislation. The aimofequality Whatisthegeneralaimofanti-disonminationlaws?Atfirstsight,legislationin theEuropeanUnionandtheUnitedStatesadvancesa conceptionofequalityas itsgeneralaim.Indeedeanti-discriminationlawshaveoftenbeendubbed'equality laws'.lThecentralcaseofprohibitedconductis lessfavourabletreatmentof anotherpersonongroundsofsorbecauseof)theirrace,sex,oroneoftheother protectedgroupclassifications.Thisstandardinsistsuponequaltreatmenttothe extentthatpeopleshouldbeassessedwithoutregardtocertaincfiaracteristicssuch as sexandracethathaveoftenbeena sourceofdisadvantageinthepast.Equal treatmentdemandsimpartialityinthesenseofforbiddingcriteriasuchas sexor racefromprovidinggroundsfordifferentiation.3Yettheaimofanti-discrimina- tionlawscannotbereducedtoequaltreatment. A closerinspectionofthelegislationrevealsthreekindsofdeviationsfroma simpleequaltreatmentprinciple.In somecases,differentratherthanthesame treatmentisrequired.Inthecaseofdiscriminationagainstpregnantwomen,for instance,thelawmandatesdifferenttreatmentofwomenratherthanthesame treatmentasmen.4Similarly,differenttreatmentofdisabledpersonsisrequiredin manyrespects,in orderto enablethemto gainaccessto workand other opportunities.5In a secondtypeof deviation,equal treatmentis itselfnot * Law Department,LondonSchoolofEconomics.Thanksareowedtomanywhocommentedon carlicrdraftsofthisessay,especiallyOonaghReitmannRichardNobles,and Nicola Lacey. 1 S. Fredman,'Equality:A NewGeneration?'(2001)30ILJ145-C. McCrudden,'TheEffectiveness ofEuropeanEqualityLaw: NationalMechanismsforEnforcingGenderEqualityLaw in the LightofEuropeanRequirements'(1993)13OJLS320;B.Hepple,M. CousseyandT. Choudhury, Eqnality:A NewFramework,ReportoftheIndependentReviewoftheEnforcementofUK Anti- DiscriminationLegislation(Oxford:Hart,2000). 2 Eg EC Directive2000/78,Art2.2(a) CivilRightsAct1964,TitleVII, 42 USC s 2000e-2(a)(1). 3 I. M. Young,J"sticeandthePolitzesofDifference(Princeton:PrincetonUniversityPress,1990) Chapter4 4 Eg EC Directive92/85,OJL348,28.11.92;EC Directive2002/73,OJL269,5.10.2002. S AmericansWithDisabilitiesAct1990,42 USC s 1201,especiallys 12112(b)(5)(A)-EC Directive 2000/78,Art5; DisabilityDiscriminationAct 1996,especiallys 6-therequirementfordifferent treatmentis consideredbelow. 16 g TheModernLawReviewLimited2003.PublishedbyBlackwellPublishingLtd., 9600GarsingtonRoad,OxfordOX42DQ,UK and350MainStreet,Malden,MA02148,USA. Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion permitted,ifitcausesunjustifiable'indirectdiscrimination'or--'disparateimpact'.6 Here formalequal treatmentbecomesunlawfulwherea ruleor practice disproportionatelyoperatestothedisadvantageofoneoftheprotectedgroups, andtheruleorpracticecannotbeobjectivelyjustified.A thirdkindofdeviation permitspreferentialtreatmentforprotectedgroupsincertaincircumstances,in ordertoredressa priorhistoryofdisadvantage.Theexactscopeofpermitted positivediscriminationisdeeplycontroversial,nodoubtbecauseitisperceivedas conflictingsharplywiththeequaltreatmentprinciple.7Thesethreedeviations revealthatwecannotunderstandtheaimofanti-discriminationlawsbyreference toa straightforwardequaltreatmentprinciple.Thequestionbecomeshowcanwe accountforthelawina waythatbothrecognisestheforceoftheequaltreatment principleandacknowledgesitsdeficienciesas a completeexplanationoftheaims ofthelaw? Conventionalaccountsoftheaimofanti-discriminationlawstrytoanswerthat questionbyusinganotherconceptionofequality,onethatfurthersa substantive ordistributivegoal.Deviationsfromequaltreatmentarejustifiedbyreferenceto thepursuitofgoalssuchasequalityofresults,equalityofresources,orequalityof opportunity.For example,it is arguedthatpermittingclaimsfor'indirect discrimination'or'disparateimpact'servesthepurposeofreducinginstitutional barrierstotheachievementofa distributivegoalsuchasmoreequalityinresults orfairerequalityofopportunity.8Similarly,inEuropeanlawthepermittedscope forpositivediscriminationis determinedinpartbyreferencetoa substantive conceptionofequality:'Witha viewto ensuringfullequalityinpractice,the principleofequaltreatmentshallnotpreventanyMemberStatefrommaintaining oradoptingspecificmeasurestopreventorcompensatefordisadvantageslinked to[sex,race,etc.]...'9 Althoughthepreciseconceptionofsubstantiveequality remainsambiguousinsuchformulations,itcertainlyseemspossibletojustify deviationsfromtheequaltreatmentprinciplebyreferencetosomedistributive conceptionofequality.Theproblemforjustifyingtheaimsofanti-discrimination lawsbecomesrathertorestrainorconfinetheforceofa substantiveconceptionof equality. Thisproblemarisesbecausethereis alwaysa tensionbetweentheequal treatmentprincipleand substantiveconceptionsof equality.Becauseequal treatmentdeterminesa procedureratherthananoutcome,equaltreatmentcan alwaysbechallengedasobstructingtheachievementofa particularoutcome.This tensionismostobviouswithrespecttoa strongegalitarianversionofequality.If theaimofthelegislationisperceivedtobestrictequalityofoutcomes,anyruleor practiceincludingequaltreatmentthatpreventstheachievementofanegalitarian 6 EgECDirective2000/78,Art2.2(6);CivilRightsAct1964,TitleVII,42USCs2000e-2(a)(2)and (k). 7 M. B. Abram,'AffirmativeAction:FairShakersandSocialEngineers'(1986)99HarvardLaw Review1312.ThisconflictwastheconceptualframeworkwithinwhichUS constitutionallaw addressedtheissueofreversediscrimination:RegentsofUniversityofCaliforniav Bakke,438US 265,98S Ct2733(1978)(SupremeCtUS). 8 C. McCrudden,'ChangingNotionsofDiscrimination'inS. GuestandA.Milne(eds),Equality andDiscrimination:EssaysinFreedomandJusticeARSPVol21(Stuttgart:FranzSteiner,1985) 86;J.Gardner,'LiberalsandUnlawfulDiscrimination'(1989)9 OJLS1.Thevarietyofpossible distributivesensesofequalityfoundinthelawisexploredinS. Fredman,Discrim1nationLaw (Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,2002)Chapter1;C. BarnardandB. Hepple,'Substantive Equality'(2000)59CLJ562. 9 Directive2000/78/ECof27 November2000,OJL 303,2.12.2000,16establishinga general frameworkforequaltreatmentinemploymentandoccupation,article7(1),seealsoon sex discriminationinparticularTreatyEstablishingtheEuropeanCommunityArticle142(4). 17t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol.66 outcomemustbequestioned.Forexample,iftheegalitarianoutcomeisdefinedas anequaldistributionofjobsbetweenmenandwomen,anyruleorpracticethat obstructsthatgoalwouldhavetobechallenged,includingan equaltreatment principlethatinsiststhatmenandwomenshouldbe assessedon theirmerits, disregardingtheirsex.Butthesameproblemarisesin connectionwithany substantiveconceptionofequality,includingtheapparentlylessambitiousgoals ofequalityofopportunityandequalityofresources.Wheneverthelegislation seeksa particularsubstantiveoutcomethatconcernsa distributionofadvantages amongsocialgroups,a proceduralrulethatforbidsconsiderationofmembership ofgroupsas a relevantcriterionfordecisionsmustobstructthepursuitofthat goal. Courtshavetoresolvethistensionbetweentheequaltreatmentprincipleand substantiveconceptionsofequalityin particularinstances.The predominant methodinEuropeis tousea testof'proportionality'.10In theUnitedStates, courtsapplytheequivalenttestof'strictscrutiny'.11Thegistofthesetestsisthat specificmeasuresdesignedto achievesubstantiveequalitymustnot be disproportionateviolationsof theequal treatmentprinciple.Althoughthis formulationprovidesa toolforjudicialexaminationoftheissue,itdoesnot resolvethetensionbetweentheequal treatmentprincipleand substantive conceptionsofequality.Themorea sI3ecificmeasureis likelyto achievethe desiredsubstantiveequality,thegreaterwillbe thetensionwiththeequal treatmentprinciple,and theharderit willbe to justifyunderthetestof proportionality.A courthastoproducefinedistinctionsbetweenmeasuresthat representonlyminorandnecessarydeviationsfromtheequaltreatmentprinciple andmeasuresthatgo toofarinthepursuitofa desiredegalitarianoutcome. Whereverthelineisdrawn,a decisioncanalwaysbecriticisedasdisplayingeither a slavishadherencetotheequaltreatmentprincipleora dangeroussacrificeofthe principle.Thetensionremainsbetween,ontheonehand,anaimofensuringequal treatmentforallcitizensregardlessofcertaincharacteristicssuchassexandrace, andontheotherhand,anaimofachievinga moreequaldistributionofwelfareor resourcesamongallcitizensthatmayrequireinsomeinstancesdifferenttreatment onthegroundsofthosesamecharacteristics. Manypossiblerouteshavebeenproposedasprovidinga betterreconciliationof thetensionbetweentheequaltreatmentprincipleandsubstantiveconceptionsof equality.HereI donotwanttoenterintothedetailsoftheseproposals,exceptto drawoutofthema senseofthestrategicchoicesthatcanbemadeandlessonsthat maybelearnedfromfollowingvariouspaths. Onerouteforresolvingthetensionis to seeka substantiveconceptionof equalitythatis sufficientlylimitedthatitrarely,ifever,clasheswiththeequal treatmentprinciple.Theideaof'equalityofopportunity'providesanexampleof thisapproach.Leavingasidetheindeterminacyofthisnotion,thestrategyof 10Abrahamsson& AndersonvFogelqvistC- 407/98[2000]ECR 1-5539,[2002]ICR 932;Application byBadeck,C-158/97[2000]ECR I-1875,[2000]IRLR 432;Lommersv MinisterVanLandbouw, NatuurbeheerEn VisserijC-476/99[2002]IRLR 430;S. Fredman,DiscriminationLaw (Oxford: OxfordUniversityPress,2002)136 143.ThesecasesdiscusstheapplicationoftheearlierEqual TreatmentDirective76/207Art2(4),whichislimitedtosexdiscrimination,andusestheslightly differentwordingoftheconceptof'equalopportunity'rather'equalityinpractice'.However,this provisionhas to be readinthecontextofEC TreatyArt142(2),as amendedbytheTreatyof Amsterdam,thatusestheformulationof 'fullequalityin practice',nowimplementedby EC Directive2002/73,creatingnewArt2(8). 11 'Strictscrutiny'requiresthata discriminatorylaworadministrativeactmustfurthera compelling stateinterestbythemostnarrowlytailoredmeansavailable:Korematsuv UnitedStates(l994)323 US 214,65 S Ct 193(SupremeCt US). 18 t) The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion defininga goalthatlessfrequentlyrequiresdeviationfromtheequaltreatment principleisplainlya steptowardsa betterresolutionoftheproblem.Nevertheless, thisroutecanneverbeentirelysuccessful.Ifthenarrowdistributiveaimhasany substantivecontentat all,it mustat somepointcomeintotensionwitha proceduralrulethatisblindtooutcomes. A secondstrategyconsistsin confiningthestrictapplicationof theequal treatmentprincipletocertaindistributiveallocations.Forexample,itmightbe proposedthatequaltreatmentshouldberigorouslyobservedinhiringdecisions, butwithrespecttotrainingandother'outreach'measures,equaltreatmentshould besacrificedinthepursuitofa substantivegoalsuchasfairequalityofopportunity. Theproblemthatthisstrategyencountersistoexplaintheprincipleonwhichthe divisionofdistributiveallocationsshouldbedrawn.Inpractice,thelawdoesnot seektodrawsucha division,butratherappliestheequaltreatmentprincipleacross theboard.Thelegalquestionremainswhetherthedeparturefromequaltreatment in theallocationof trainingand otherbenefitsrepresentsa disproportionate violationoftheequaltreatmentprinciple.Forexample,legislationintheUnited Kingdompermitsemployersandtrainingbodiesto grantpreferentialaccessto trainingtoa particularracialgroup,butonlyifthereareeithernomembersofthe racialgroupdoingtheworkforwhichtrainingissupplied,ortheirproportionis comparativelysmall.l2Similarly,in a caseconcerningan employer'schild-care facilityreservedexclusivelyforwomenemployees,theEuropeanCourtofJustice concludedthattheemployer'smeasurefailedthetestofproportionality,becauseit excludedmaleemployeeswhotakecareofchildrenbythemselves.l3Thestrategyof isolatingsomedistnbutivedecisionsfromtheapplicationoftheequaltreatment pnnciple,thoughpossibleintheory,appearstobeunacceptableinpracticeowingto theforceoftheequaltreatmentideal. A thirdstrategyforresolvingthetensiontriesto dispensewiththeequal treatmentprinciplealtogetherbyredefiningitas 'equalworth','equalrespect',or 'treatmentas an equal'.l4Undertheseformulations,differenttreatmentinthe pursuitofa distributivegoalisunobjectionableprovidedthatitdoesnotinvolve disrespectforanygroup.Indeed,equalrespect,particularlzwhenformulatedasa claimforrecognitionandempowermentofan identity,lmayrequiredifferent treatment,becauserespect(orrecognitionorculturalempowerment)mayinvolve acceptingand accommodatingdifference.l6Althoughthisstrategyavoidsthe tensionwehavebeenconsidering,itachievesthisresultonlybydiscardingthe equaltreatmentprinciple.A whitemaleatthereceivingendofadversetreatment arisingfroman affirmativeactionquotacanperhapsacceptthathistreatment maynotinvolvebad motivesor disrespect,butit certainlyinvolvesunequal treatment,partialtreatment,ordifferenttreatmentonthebasisofgenderorrace. Hisrighttobetreatedwithrespectanddignitymaynothavebeeninfringed,but hisotherrighttoequaltreatmenthasbeenplainlyviolated.Radicalvoicesin favourofdiversitymaynotbeconcernedabouttheabandonmentofan equal treatmentprinciple,becauseofitstendencytoimposea hegemonicwhite,male, 12 Race RelationsAct1976ss 37,38. 13 Lommersv MinsterVanLandbouw,Natuurbeheeren VisserijC-476/99[2002]IRLR 430. 14 R. Dworkin,A MatterofPrinciple(Oxford:ClarendonPress,1986)301;R. Kennedy,'Persuasion andDistrust:A CommentontheAffirmativeActionDebate'(1986)99HarvardLawReview1327. 15 N. Fraser,JusticeInterruptus:CrticalReflectionson the'Postsocialist'Condition(New York: Routledge,1997);D. Cooper,"'And You Can't FindMe Nowhere":RelocatingIdentityand StructurewithEqualityJurisprudence'(2000)27 JournalofLaw andSociety249. 16 I. M. Young,aboven 3,Chapter6. 19t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol.66 heterosexualnorm.Yet anti-discriminationlawsin theirdefinitionsofdirect discriminationandtheapplicationofthetestofproportionalityinpracticeinsist upona processinvolvingequaltreatment,notmerelyequalrespect.Ifweaccept thatanequaltreatmentprinciplewillremainatthecoreofanti-discrimination laws,whatwecandrawoutofthisstrategyisrathertherecognitionthataswellas equaltreatment,anti-discriminationlawsmayalsoseektoupholda principleof equalrespect.Thesetwoprinciplesmayproducea newtensionwhenequalrespect requiresdifferenttreatment.I doubtwhetherthisnewtensioncouldbeadequately resolvedwithoutreferencetoa distributivegoalthatexplainswhenequalrespect shouldoverrideequaltreatment. A finalstrategyforresolvingthetensionbetweentheequaltreatmentprinciple anda substantiveaimofequalitythatI wanttohighlightisonethatdiminishes theprincipletoaninstrumentalrule.Thisinterpretationidentifiesa distributive goalas thedominantaimofthelegislation,andregardsequaltreatmentas a usefulguidetohowtheaimofthelawshouldbeimplemented,thoughwhenever thesubstantivegoalrequiresdifferenttreatment,theprincipleofequaltreatment shouldbeignored.Againthisstrategyprovidesa routeforresolvingthetension, thoughit encountersconsiderabledifficultyin explainingwhythe antidiscriminationlawsas currentlyformulatedseemtoplaceequaltreatmentas a dominantprinciple.Thisstrategymustalsoprovideanintelligibleandcoherent accountofthedistributivegoaltobeattributedtothelegislation,anditmusthave a plausibleexplanationofwhythepursuitofthisgoalnormallyinvolvesthe proceduraltestofequaltreatment. Fromthisperfunctoryreviewofthestrategicchoicesavailabletoaccountsofthe aimsofanti-discriminationlaws,I drawa numberoflessons.First,anyplausible interpretationoftheaimsoftheselawsmustawardtheequaltreatmentprinciple an importantrole.Thesecondpointis,however,thatan explanationofwhy differenttreatmentis sometimesrequiredorpermittedseemstonecessitatethe inclusionofa distributiveaimforthelegislation.Itis thedistributiveaimthat explainswhenandwhydeviationsfromequaltreatmentshouldbe requiredor permitted.Thirdly,an additionalprincipleof equal respector equal worth probablyshouldalsobeattributedtothelegislation,butnottotheexclusionofthe equaltreatmentprinciple.Nordoesthisadditionalprincipleremovetheneedfor attributinga distributiveaimto thelegislation.Fourthly,anydistributiveaim attributedtothelegislationwillhavea trajectorythatwilleventuallybringitinto tensionwiththeequaltreatmentprinciple.Althoughthistensioncanbereducedby diminishingtheambitionsofthedistributivegoal,itneverdisappearsentirely.The finallessontobedrawnisthatitmaybepossibletodefinea distributivegoalthat entailstheuseofequaltreatmentas itsoperationalprinciple,butwhichalsosets limitstoitsoperationbyreferencetothedistributivegoal.Thetwomaindifficulties confrontingsuchaninterpretationoftheaimsoftheanti-discriminationlegislation aretodefineanappropriatedistributivegoalandtoexplainwhythisgoalrequires considerableweighttobeattachedtotheequaltreatmentprinciple. All theseconsiderationspointtowardsa solutionthatattributesa weak egalitariandistributivegoaltothelegislation,suchas equalityofopportunity. Sucha phrasebothimpliesthatequaltreatmentshouldbethenormalpractice, butalsoadmitsthepossibilitythattorenderopportunitiesequalinpracticeitmay benecessarytoaffordunequaltreatmentinsomeinstances.Oncloserinspection, however,sucha solutionprovespainfullyinadequate.We knowthatequal treatmentwillin practicenotensureequalityof opportunity.Applyingthe standardofequaltreatmenttopeoplewhohavebeendisadvantagedinacquiring 20 t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion thetypesofskills,education,andexperiencethatcountasmeritforthepurposeof qualifyingforjobs merelytendsto confirmor reinforcethe effectsof disadvantage.l7In pursuitofthegoalofequalityofopportunity,therefore,we needto interveneto glvepreferentialtreatmentto disadvantagedgroups.The problemistoknowhowfartotakethisintervention,becauseitisarguablethat wheneverinequalitiesinresultscanbediscerned,theremustbesomeinequalityof opportunitythatoughtto be remedied.Thisproblemis oftenaddressedby refiningthegoaltobeoneoffairequalityofopportunity,whichofcoursemerely restatestheproblemundertherubricoffairness.Thequestionbecomeswhenisit fairtotreatpeopleinexactlythesameway,andwhenis itfairtotreatthem differently. Whatinterestsmeaboutthisformulatiollofthepossibledistributivegoalfor anti-discriminationlegislationis thatit eschewsany directreferenceto conceptionsofequality.Somenotionofequalitymayformpartoftheideaof fairness,butthatisnota necessaryconclusion.Thisstepopensupthepossibility thatthedistributiveaimofthelegislationcanbeadequatelydescribedwithout referenceto conceptionsof equality.Butifnotsomenotionof substantive equality,whatkindofdistributiveaimmightbeattributedtothelegislation? Atthispointintheargument,wemayturntowardsan examinationofthe explicitpoliticaljustificationsforthelegislationthatcan be discoveredin contemporarygovernmentdocuments.As we mightexpect,thesedocuments includefrequentreferencesto variousconceptionsof equality,particularly equalityofopportunityandequalworth.Buttherearealsotwootherstrands inthepoliticaljustificationsfortheleglslation.Onestressestheeconomicbenefits tobeobtainedbyenablingallmembersofa nation'sworkforcetoparticipatein theeconomytothefullestextentoftheirpotential.Thisargumentcomprisesa standardjustificationputforwardby governmentsforregulationof labour marketsthattheproposedregulationwillimprovethecompetitivenessof business.l8A secondstrandofjustification,however,shouldinterestus more, becauseitismoredirectlyaimedatexplainingtheaimofanti-discriminationlaws. Thiselementoftheofficialdiscoursereferstothenotionofsocialinclusionas a keyjustificationforanti-discriminationlawsB Socialinclusion 'Discriminationusuallyamountsto exclusionin someform.'l9No doubtwe shouldbewaryofattachingtoomuchsignificancetopoliticalrhetoric.Somemay be merefroth,andmostmay& deliberatelyambiguous.ButI thinkthatthe notionofsocialinclusionrepresentsa significantshiftinpoliticalthought,because itfitsneatlyintoa generalstrategicneedof'ThirdWay'politics.20TheThirdWay 17 B. Hepple,'Discr}minationand Equalityof Opportunity- NorthernIrishLessons'(1990) 10 OJLS408-I. M. Young,aboven 3,Chapter7-B. Parekh,'TheCase forPositiveDiscrimination' inB. HeppleandE. Szyszczak(eds),Discrimination:TheLimitsofLaw(London:Mansell,1992) 272. I8 tI. Co}Rins,'RegulatingtheEmploymentRelationforCompetitiveness'(2001)30 ILJ 17. 19 DepartmentoiCTradeand Industry,TowardsEqualityandDiversity:ImplementingtheEmploymentandRace Directives,ConsultationDocumenthttp://www.dti.gov.uk/er(2001)para 1.2. 20 For elucidationof the'ThirdWay',see A. Giddens,The ThirdWay:TheRenewalofSocial Democracy(Cambndge:PolityPress, 1998),A. Giddens,The ThirdWay and its Critics (Cambndge:Polity,2); and theessayscollectedin A. Giddens(ed), TheGlobalThirdWay Debate(Cambridge:PolityPress,2001). t The MosiernLaw ReviewLiIIiited3 2 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol.66 triestodistanceitselffromegalitarianidealsassociatedwithtraditionalsocialist movements,whilstpromisingmorepracticalandeffectivemeasurestowardsa fairersocietythanthoseofferedbytraditionalsocialdemocraticparties.The categoryof thesociallyexcludedis moreprecisethanthosesufferingfrom economicpoverty.Thegroupofthesociallyexcludedisdefinedratheras people whoareeffectivelypreventedfromparticipatinginthebenefitsofcitizenshipor membershipofsocietyowingtoa combinationofbarriers,ofwhichpovertyis merelyone.Otherbarriersincludepooreducationalopportunities,membershipof a disfavouredracialminority,aninaccessiblelocation,responsibilityforfamily dependants,or,morecommonlya combinationofsuchfactors.2lByaimingto eradicatesocialexclusion,thecentre-leftpoliticalpartiescansteera pathbetween, ontheonehand,promisingstrongegalitarianmeasuresinvolvingsubstantialtax andtransfermeasures,and,ontheother,merelyofferinga protectionofrights withoutanysubstantivecommitmentstodistributivejusticeora fairersociety. Althoughthephrasesocialexclusionspinscontinuouslyfromthelipsof politlciansin Europeandhasbecomea centrepieceofEuropeanCommunity SocialPolicy,22itisseldomdefined.Whenclarificationisgiven,therearecertainly convenientambiguitiesandpuzzlingdivergencesin meanings.23Yet thesame mightbesaidabouttheconceptofequality,andthatdoesnotpreventusfrom takingtheidealofequalityseriously.Theproblemisratherthattheconceptof socialinclusionislessfamiliarthanequality,sothatitsmeaningsandimplications appearevenmurkier.Itis notpartofthefamiliarrepertoireofliberalpolitical theoryor inscribedroutinelyin constitutionsand declarationsof rights. Sometimesappealstotheprincipleofsocialinclusionamounttonomorethan codeddemandsforequalityofresultsora moreegalitariansociety.HereI will concentrate,however,on thestrandsinthisdiscoursethatdistinguishitfrom conceptionsofequalityincludingegalitariannotionsofwelfare. Socialinclusionis an aimorprincipleofjustice.It is oftenmistakenforan egalitariannotionofdistributivejustice.Thismistakeisunderstandable,because thedemandsofsocialinclusionmayrequirehelptobegiventothesamegroups suchas thepoorwhoarefavouredbylawsbaseduponegalitarianjustifications. Socialinclusionand egalitarianidealssharea concernaboutoutcomesor distributivepatterns.Yetthereisalsoa fundamentaldifference.Socialinclusion does not seek the same or broadlyequivalentoutcomesforcitizens.It concentratesitsattentionnotonrelativedisadvantagebetweengroups,butrather ontheabsolutedisadvantageofparticulargroupsinsociety.Theobjectiveisnot somenotionofequalityofwelfare,butoneofsecuringa minimumlevelofwelfare foreverycitizen.Itstypicaltargetsare'childpoverty','unemployedyouth',or 'racialminoritiesindeprivedneighbourhoods',nota moregeneralequalisationof welfare. 21 Fora guidetotherangeofpolicyissuesencapsulatedintheideaofsocialinclusion:Social ExclusionUnit,CabinetO5ce,PreventingSocialExclusion,(March2001)http:l/www.cabinetoffice.gov.uklseul20011pselPSE%20HTMLldefault.htm.Fora globalperspectiveontheorigins andsignificanceofthenotionofsocialinclusion:G.Rodgers,C.GoreandJ.B.Figueiredo(eds), Social Exclusion:Rhetoric,Reality,Responses(Geneva:InternationalInstituteforLabour Studies,InternationalLabourOfEce,1995). 22 DecisionNo 50/2002/ECoftheEuropeanParliamentandoftheCouncilof7 December2001 establishinga programmeofCammunityactionto encouragecooperationbetweenMember StatestocombatsocialexclusioneOJL10,12/Q1.20021. 23 R.Levitas,TheInclusiveSociety?SocialExclusionandNewLabour(London:MacmiHan,1998)R. Lister,'StrategiesforSocialInclusion:promotingSocialCohesionor SocialJustice?'in P. AskonasandA. Stewart(eds),Social Inclusion:Possibilitiesand Tensions(Basingstoke: Macmillan,2000)37. 22 t The Modem Law ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion Thisdifferencefromtheidealofequalityofoutcomescanleadanothermistaken viewthatsocialinclusionmustthereforebeconcernedwithequalityofresources. Theideaofequalityofresourcesisthatindividualsshouldbeassuredas faras possibleanequalchanceinsocietytoachievetheirgoalsorthatthereshouldbe equalityofopportunity.Withoutinvestigatingfurtherthecontroversialquestions ofwhatmightbemeantby'resources'or'opportunity'inthoseformulations,we candistinguishtheaimofsocialinclusionontwogrounds.First,socialinclusion doesnotsetitselfthetaskofensuringan equaldistnbutionofresourcesor opportunities.Thepointisratherthatbecausesomegroupshavesofewresources oropportunities,weshouldredressthatpositionwithoutundertakinga broader redistribution.Many advocatesof the 'ThirdWay' supportequalityof opportunityinordertodistancethemselvesfromegalitariangoalsandtostress theirrespectforindividualautonomy.24Giventheiracceptanceofthelimited capacitiesofgovernmentseffectivelytoredistributeresourcesoropportunitiesina marketsociety,however,theirambitionsforregulationseemtobeconfinedin practicetohelpingthosewhoarecompletelyexcluded.Thesecond,fundamental, differencefromequalityofresourcesconsistsintheconcernforsocialinclusionas an outcome.Itisnotenoughundertheaimofsocialinclusiontogivea bigger shareofresourcesoropportunitiestodisadvantagedgroups,andleavethemto choosewhetherto takeup thepossibilitiestheyprovide.Socialinclusionis committedtotheachievementofoutcomes,notjustlife-chances.Thesignificance ofthispointemergesmoreclearlyifweconsiderthenatureoftheoutcometo whichsocialinclusionaspires. Theaimofsocialinclusionisa typeofwelfarisminthesensethattheoutcome soughtistoimprovethewelfareofdisadvantagedgroups.Yetitisnotthesameas utilitarianismorthemaximisationofwelfare,forsocialinclusiongivespriorityto thewelfareofthetargetedgroups,evenifredistributionintheirfavourdoesnot maximiseutility.25Furthermore,weshoulddistinguishthetypeofwelfaresought bysocialinclusionfromthatusedfrequentlyineconomicsandpolicysciences. The typeof welfarerequiredundertheaim of socialinclusionis notthe satisfactionofpreferencesformedexogenously,towhichthestateadoptsa neutral attitude.Thereis a perfectionistelementintheideaofsocialinclusion,inthat thereis a conceptionoftheessentialelementsof'well-being'.26Theseessential elementsof'well-being'includematerialgoodssuchasfoodandshelter,butalso includeopportunitiestoparticipateinmeaningfulwaysinsociallife.Thesenonmaterialgoodsincludea fulfillinglevelofeducation,participationinpolitics,27 culturalactivities,andwork.Individualsshouldbe abletopursuetheirchosen goalsinrelationtothesenon-matenalgoodsinordertoachievea stateof'well- being'.Thus'well-being'combinessubjectivistandobjectivistnotionsofwelfare. 'Well-being'is objectivistto theextentthatit identifiesparticularkindsof 24 A. Giddens(2000) above n 20, 85-89; R. Mullender,'TheorizingtheThirdWay: Qualified Consequentialism,theProportionalityPrinciple,and theNew Social Democracy'(2000) 27 Journalof Law and Society493; H. Collins,'Is Therea ThirdWay in Labour Law?' in J.Conaghan,M. Fischland K. Klare (eds),LabourLaw inAnEra ofGlobalization(Oxford: OxfordUniversityPress,2002)449. 25 I amdrawinghereonthedistinctionsdrawnbetweenegalitarianism,welfarism,anda principleof priority(of whichsocial inclusionis an example)by D. Parfitt,'Equalityor Priority?'in M. ClaytonandA. Williams(eds),TheIdea ofEquality(Basingstoke:Macmillan,2000)81. 26 Thisnotionofwelfareis usedby,amongstothers,J.Gray,'Inclusion:A RadicalCritique'in P. AskonasandA. Stewart(eds),aboven 22, 19,28;J.Raz, TheMoralityofFreedom(Oxford: ClarendonPress,1986)Chapter12;and,possibly,A. Giddens(2000)aboven 20,88. 27 I. M. Young,InclusionandDemocracy(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,2000). 23t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol.66 activitiessuchaswork,education,politics,andcultureasthemostsignificantsites fortheachievementof'well-being'.But'well-being'isalsosubjectivistbecausethe individualis permitteda rangeof choicesaboutgoalsin relationto these worthwhileactivities. Althoughnosharplinecanbedrawnthatdeterminestheminimumacceptable levelforthesematerialand non-materialgoods,socialinclusioninsiststhat whereverthelineisdrawn,everyoneshouldberaisedtothatlevel.Itistherefore notsufficientforgovernmentstoprovidematerialresourcesinordertotackle socialexclusion.Non-materialgoodssuchas workare,ifcomparisonscanbe made,moreessentialelementsof'well-being',andsocialinclusiondemandsthat disadvantagedgroupsshouldreceivethosenon-materialgoods.Accesstononmaterialgoodsrequires,first,thatthesocialorganisationof theseactivities permitseveryonetoenterthemwithoutinsurmountablebarriers,andsecondly, thateachpersonenjoystheabilitytochoosebetweena rangeofpossiblegoalsin relationtotheseactivities. Thisemphasisuponthedistributionofnon-materialgoodsderivesfromthe deepestambitionoftheaimofsocialinclusion.Althoughwehaveobservedthat socialinclusionshareswithequalitya concernwiththedistributiveallocationsto groupsandindividualsina society,itsmorefundamentalobjectiveistheoutcome ofsocialcohesion.Socialinclusionisa theoryofhowsocietycanbeintegrated andharmonious.Atitssimplest,thetheoryisthatifeveryoneparticipatesfullyin society,theyarelesslikelyto becomealienatedfromthecommunityandwill conformtoitssocialrulesandlaws.Socialinclusionfosterssocialcohesionor,to useanolderconcept,solidarity.Theoutcomesoughtbypoliciesofsocialinclusion isthereforenotmerelyjusticeforindividualsbutalsoa stablesocialorder. Thesignificanceoftheconnectionbetweensocialcohesionandsocialinclusion needsto be stressed.In contemporaryliberaltheoriesofjustice,itis usually presentedas sufficienttoestablishsocialorderthatweshouldestablisha justor nearlyjustsociety.28Iftheconditionsofjusticearemet,itisarguedthatweowea moralorpoliticaldutytoupholdthoseinstitutionsandtoobeythelawsthat expressthem.Inpractice,contemporarygovernmentsdo notappeartoplaceso muchfaithina senseofmoralduty.Theyrecogniseratherthatsocialorderis fragileandthattheyneedtotakemeasurestopromotesocialcohesion.Attimes thisrecognitionresultsinauthoritarianregimes,whichareindeedunacceptable anddonotdeservemoralsupport.Butgovernmentsinfluencedbythe'ThirdWay' usemoresubtlemethodstopromotesocialcohesion,which,thoughnotentirely freefromcoercion,avoidtheexcessesofauthoritarianstates.Theaimofsocial inclusionis preciselyto establishconditionsandopportunitiesthatinduceall citizensto participatein societyand to cometo valueitsinstitutionsand potentials.'Peoplewhoareeconomicallydisengagedoftenbecomemoregenerally disengaged,reinforcingthedemocraticdeficit'.9 Thisadditionalelementofsocialcohesionexplainsinpartthepresenceofthe objectivist(orperfectionist)dimensionof'well-being',anditalsoaccountsforthe paternaliststrandingovernmentpoliciesaboutsocialinclusion.Whereastheaim ofequalityofopportunityseekstoputpeopleina positioninwhichtheyareable toparticipateintheeconomyandotheraspectsofsociallife,theaimofsocial 28 J.Rawls,A TheoryofJustice(Oxford-OxfordUniversityPress,1971)Chapter6; R. Dworkin, Law'sEmpire(London:Fontana,1986)195-216. 29 BarbaraRoche,MinisterforWomen,'Equalityinthe21StCentury',speechtoInstituteofPublic PolicyResearch15thMay2002,http:/www.ippr.org/press/index. 24 t) The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] Discrimination,EqualityaS-SocialInclusion inclusionalso seemsto includean elementthatsometimesrequirespeopleto becomeincluded.Thereareno rightswithoutresponsibilities.Withrespectto work,forinstance,socialinclusionpolicies,thoughnotforcingpeopletowork, strenuouslytrywitha mixtureofcarrotsandstickstodrivepeopleintowork.The carrotsare 'in-work'benefitsand negativeearnedincometax,30whichare designedto ensurethatworkprovidesmorematerialbenefitsthanwelfare benefits;andthesticksaretheremovalofwelfarebenefitsfromthosewhodonot co-operateinseekingtofindemployment.3lThesepoliciescanbedescribedas paternalist,becausetheyassert,forinstance,thatworkisgoodfortheindividual andsociety,and,evenifyoudon'twanttowork,youshould,ifyoupossibly can.32Moreover,it is insistedthatnearlyeveryonecan work,providedthat individualsreceiveappropriatetrainingand education,and thatemployers dismantleunnecessaryexclusionaryrules.Thiscoerciveelementdistinguishesthe principleof socialinclusionfromeventhebroadestversionsof equalityof opportunity,whichleaveindividualswiththefreedomandtheresponsibilityto maketheirownlife-choices,includingindolence.33 Itfollowsthatthereisa differenceinscopebetweenegalitarianwelfaristpolicies andsocialinclusion.Anegalitarianobjectivesetstheoutcomesthatitwishesto achieve,buthaslittletosayaboutthemeansthatshouldbeused.Themethod couldbeoneofregulatingboththeinstitutionsofgovernmentandthemarket. Alternatively,themethodcouldbe one of progressivetaxationand welfare benefits,leavinguntouchedtheinstitutionsofcivilsocietyandthemarket.In contrast,socialinclusionrequiresregulationofsocialinstitutions.Moneyisnotan acceptablesubstituteforthenon-materialgoodsthatforma coreof'well-being'. In thecaseofwork,forinstance,havinga job differsfromreceivingthesame amountofmoneyinwelfarebenefits.Ajobprovidestheopportunitytoacquire knowledgeand skills?to participatein theworkplacecommunity,to achieve meaningfulgoals,toacquirestatusoridentityinthecommunity,andtoform friendships.Thepolicyofsocialinclusionwishestodistributethesenon-material goodstoallmembersofsociety.Workisnotregardedas a meanstoanendof materialwealth,butanendinitself,becauseitisa vitalingredientof'well-being'. Andtheachievementof'well-being'forall groupsis an essentialelementin constructinga civilandsafecommunity. I willneedtoaddfurtherelementstothisbriefdescriptionoftheaimofsocial inclusionasweconsideritsimplicationsasa potentialjustificationfortheaimsof anti-discriminationlaws.Whathasnotyetbeenmentioned,andwhichneedstobe recognisedat theoutset,is thatthetheoryofsocialinclusion,likeallpolitical theories,wasnotdevelopedina vacuum,butratherevolvedinresponsetoan analysisofcontemporarysocialproblems.Itisa productofthepoliticsofrich Westerncountriesinthelatetwentiethcentury.Inthosecountries,a majorityof thepopulationhadenjoyedsince1945an unprecedentedcontinuousperiodof 30 Tax CreditsAct1999. 31 WelfareReformand PensionsAct 1999;Social Security(Welfareto Work)Regulations1998, 1998SI 2231.On the'NewDeal', seeP. Cressey,'NewLabourandEmployment,Trainingand EmployeeRelations'inM. Powell(ed),NewLabour,NewWelfareState?(Bristol:PolicyPress, 1999)171,177. 32 DepartmentofSocialSecurity,NewAmbitionsforOurCountry:A NewContractforWelfare,Cm 3805(1998). 33 This elementof freedomand responsibilityin liberalnotionsof equalityis highlightedin R. Dworkin,'Does EqualityMatter?'inA. Giddens(ed),aboven 19,172,177.Fora critiqueof coercive(orcommunitarian)welfaretoworkprogrammesintheUSA: A. L. Alstott,'Workvs Freedom:A LiberalChallengeto EmploymentSubsidies'(1999)108Yale L J967. 25t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol. 66 growingprosperityandhadbeenabletoaffordtheinstitutionalarrangementsof theWelfareState.Butthesearrangementsseemedtobethreatenedbya minority whohadnotparticipatedinthatprosperityandwhoseemedunwillingtoaccept thenormsofcivilsociety.Althoughthematerialneedsofthisminoritywere usuallymetbytheWelfareState?theydidnotparticipateinsociety,andindeed appearedalienated.Therewasa concernaboutthebreakdownofsocialorderin innercities,andparticularlyabouta patternofyoungpeopleneverjoininginthe institutionsofcivilsociety- voting,working,marryingandformingfamilies. InsteadoftheWelfareStateprovidinga solution,itwasdiagnosedasa sourceof theproblem.34Itwasarguedthatwelfaredependencyactuallypromotedtheway oflifethatrejectedtheinstitutionsofa liberalandcivilsociety.Whereasequality hadbeenthepoliticalidealrequiredtoincorporatetheworkingclassintocivil society,theideaofsocialinclusionwasthepoliticalresponseto theneedto integratethenon-workingclass. Havingdescribedtheseelementsoftheaimofsocialinclusion,wecannow considerwhetherthisaiminformsanti-discriminationlaws.Recallthatthereason whysocialinclusioninterestsusisthatitmayprovideananswertothequestionof whenisitfairtoinsistuponequaltreatmentandwhenisitfairtodeviatefrom thatstandard.I approachthistaskbyidentifyingan architectureforanti- discriminationlawsthatseemstobeimplicitintheaimofsocialinclusion.My analysishighlightsfourpillars:howthesocialproblemtobeaddressedbyanti- discriminationlawsisconceivedwithinthepolicyofsocialinclusion;howsocial inclusionjustifiesdeviationfromtheequaltreatmentprinciple;themethodsof proofofunlawfuldiscrimination;andtheextentoftherequirementforpositive discriminationin thepursuitof socialinclusion.Thisanalysisenablesus to identifytheextenttowhicha socialinclusionjustificationmayexplaintheaims andthecontentofthecurrentlaw,thoughitalsoprovidesa criticalperspectiveon possibleinadequaciesinthelegislation. Structuraldisadvantage Whatistheproblemthatanti-discriminationlawsaddress?Theequaltreatment principledefinestheproblemnarrowlyas directdiscrimination,thatistreatinga persondifferentlyonthegroundofsex,race,orsomeothersuspectclassification. Butinsofarasanti-discriminationlawsdeviatefromthatstandard,itisclearthat the socialproblemis regardedas one involvingstructuralor systematic disadvantageforprotectedgroups.The notionof structuraldisadvantage combinestwo elements:first,an appreciationthatthereare patternsof disadvantageorthattherearegroupsthatseemto be disproportionatelyand persistentlyin worsepositions;andsecond,thattherearecertainpellllanent arrangements,practices,institutions,and socialstructuresthatproducethis outcome.The wayin whichwe definethenatureand sourcesof structural disadvantageprovidesa frameworkfortheambitofanti-discriminationlaws.To understandthisframework,itis helpfulto disentanglethreeelementsofthe problemofstructuraldisadvantage:thecompositionofthedisadvantagedgroups, thenatureoftheirdisadvantage,andthenatureofthestructuresthattendto producethatdisadvantage. 34 For a livelyanalysisoftheproblem:W. Hutton,TheState We'reIn (London:Vintage,1996) Chapter7. 26 g The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003J Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion Disadvantagedgroups Equalityjustificationsforanti-discriminationlawslacka determinateviewofhow to constitutethegroupsforcomparison.Theprinciplethatdifferentgroups shouldbetreatedequally(inotherwisesimilarcircumstances)doesnotdescribe howthesegroupsshouldbecomposed.Anygroupcanclaimthatitisnotbeing treatedequallyanddemandthatitshouldreceiveprotectionfromthelaw.The groupsmightbe comprisedby referenceto geneticendowments,socially constructedcategories,legalclassificationssuchas nationality,or someother criterionofclassification.Whatis crucialis thatthegroupis ableto claim plausiblythatmembershipofthegroupputsindividualsata disadvantage.One effectof theindeterminacyof protectedgroupsundertheequal treatment principleis thatthe provinceof anti-discriminationlaws alwaysremains contested.35 In contrast,socialinclusionprovidesa moredeterniinatecriterionforthe compositionofprotectedgroups.Thequestioniswhetherthegroupisonethatin practicehasbeendisproportionatelysociallyexcludedcomparedtothepopulation asa whole.Underthiscriterion,forinstance,singleparentsbecomea grouptobe protected,becausethelackofaffordableandadequatechild-carearrangements tendstoexcludethemfrommaterialandnon-materialbenefits.Theprincipleof equalityneitherrulesoutsingleparentsas a grouptobeprotected,nordoesit requirethemtobeconstitutedasa groupforthepurposesofdiscriminationlaw. Onthecriterionofsocialinclusion,however,sexisnotsoclearlya criterionfor thecompositionofa protectedgroup.Withinthecategoryofwomen,thereare certainlygroupsofwomenthatsufferfromsocialexclusion,suchasthosewhoare pregnantorparentsofyoungchildren.Itmaybeargued,furthermore,thatmost womensufferfromsomecomparativedisadvantageduringtheirlives,becausethe potentialforpregnancyhasanadverseeffectonallwomeninthelabourmarket, sothatallwomenshouldberegardedasa protectedclassunderthetestofsocial exclusion.Butthesocialinclusioncriterionfordisadvantagedgroupsseems unlikelytoincludemenas a class,so thatsexonitsownas a sourceofgroup composition,asopposedtodiscriminationagainstwomen,wouldnotqualifyasa relevantcriterionforthecompositionofa protectedgroup.Similarly,ifwe consideragediscriminationinemployment,justificationsforlegalintervention basedonequalitycertainlypermittheinclusionofthiscategory,butalsolackany justificationforconfiningittoparticularagegroups.Incontrast,a justification basedonsocialexclusionwouldnoticethedisproportionatelevelsofunemploymentof olderpeople,and,havingdeterminedwhenage becomesa serious disadvantageinthelabourmarket,thatis abouttheageof55,wouldregulate againstdiscriminationin hiringpracticesthatexcludedirectlyor indirectly workersaged55orabove.A similarfindingofdisadvantagemightalsoleadto protectionofworkersundertheageof22.Noticeas wellthatsocialinclusionis notinterestedinwhetherthegroupisclassifiedbyunalterablegenetics,socially constructedqualities,or legallyimposedcharacteristics,factorswhichare sometimesusedto determinethescopeofdiscriminationlawsunderequality 35 S. Fredman,aboven 10,76-82.Fredmanarguesthatequalitymustbeunderpinnedbytheideaof dignitytoprovidedeterminacy,followingconstitutionaldevelopmentsinthisdirectioninSouth Africaand Canada (at 119-121).Gardnerproposesalternativelya theoryofautonomyas the basisfortheidentificationofgroups:J.Gardner,'On theGroundofHerSex(uality)'(1998) 18 OJLS 168,a reviewof,and supportingin thisrespect,R. Wintemute,SexualOrientationand HumanRights(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,1995). 27t TheModernLawReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions [Vol. 66TheModernLaw Review justifications.Norisitinterestedinwhetherthegroupisregardedwithdisrespect. Thecompositionofgroupsisdeterminedbyreferencetotheobjectiveofsocial inclusion,whichcandrawuponanysystemofclassification.Examplesofthis varietymightincludesingleparents(regardlessofsex)orresidentsinparticular postcodesthatincludehighlevelsofminorityethnicexclusion. Consideringcontemporaryanti-discriminationlegislation,thereis certainlya patternofthedefinitionofprotectedgroupsthatreflectsanequalityjustification. Protectionisusuallyaffordedtobotha groupanditssymmetricalopposite,thus upholdinga principleofequaltreatment.Thereare,however,someexceptionsto thispattern,as inthecaseofdisability,36marriedpersons,37personsundergoing genderreassignment.38Theseexceptionsarecompatiblewitha socialexclusion approachtothedefinitionofprotectedgroups. Natureofdisadvantage Anequalityjustificationis alsoindeterminatewithrespectto thecharacterof problematicdisadvantage.Iftheaimofthelawis conceivedmorepreciselyas equalityofopportunity,orofresources,orofwelfare,thatadditionalelement providesa moredeterminatedescriptionof the natureof the required disadvantage,thoughthepossiblerangeof disadvantagesto be considered remainsbroad.Disadvantagesresultingfromdiscriminationmayoccurinany walkoflife.Forthepurposesofeliminatingdisadvantagesthatinfringesome standardof equality,thereis no reasonto limitthepotentialscopeof the disadvantagestobeaddressed,eveninthedarkcornersoftheprivatesphere.39 Yetwhendiscriminationlawsareenacted,theyaddressparticulartargetssuch as employment,education,theprovisionofpublicservices,andmanyother aspectsofbusinessandsocialassociations.Firstamongthesetargetsisinvariably accesstoemployment,or,moreprecisely,theabilitytoearna livingthroughthe provisionofservicestoothers.Whataccountsforthisfocusonwork?Theanswer cannotbethatdiscriminatorypracticesaremoreprevalentinemploymentthan othersocialcontexts.Thishypothesisseemsimprobable.Considerationsof efficiencypropelemployerstohirethemostproductiveworkersregardlessofsex orrace.Directorintentionaldiscriminationinhiringpracticesisnotusuallyan objectiveof employers,becauseit is likelyto be inefficient.Discrimination becomesefficientforemployersonlytotheextentthat,byusingcriteriaofgroup membershipasa proxyfora testforproductivityofajobapplicant,theemployer savesontransactioncosts(thecostsofinvestigatingtherelativeproductivityof jobapglicants)tosuchanextentthatthesavingsexceedthecostsofmistakenjob offers.° Discriminationseemsmuchmorelikelytoflourishwhentheeconomic consequencesareinsignificant,thatisindailysocialinteractions. 36 DisabilityDiscriminationAct1995. 37 SexDiscriminationAct1975s 3; butEC Directive2002/73,newArt2(1) impliesa symmetrical approachfor'martialorfamilystatus.' 38 SexDiscriminationAct 1975s 2A (as amendedbySex Discrimination(GenderReassignment) Regulations1999,SI 1999/1102. 39 Thereare otherreasonsforconfiningthescopeof discriminationlawsin theprivatesphere: J.Gardner,'PrivateActivitiesand PersonalAutonomy:AttheMarginsofAnti-discrimination Law',inB. HeppleandE. Szyszczak(eds),aboven 17,148. 40 G. S. Becker,TheEconomicsofDiscrimination(Chicago:UniversityofChicagoPress,1957); K. J.Arrow,'ModelsofJobDiscrimination'inA. Pascal(ed),RacialDiscriminationinEconomic Life(LexingtonMA, LexingtonBooks,D C FIeath,1972). 28 g The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion Theemphasisuponemploymentindiscriminationlawsisallthemorestriking whenweappreciatethathiringdecisionsbyprivateemployerscompriseoneofthe hardesttargetsforwhichtojustifylegalregulation.Ajustificationforregulationis easierwithinsubsistingcontractualrelations,fortheimpliedobligationsofthe contractarelikelyto ruleoutmostformsofdiscrimination.In employment contracts,discriminatorydecisionsprobablyamounttoa breachoftheimplied obligationontheemployernottoactina waythatdestroysmutualtrustand confidence(intheUK),ora violationofsomeothergeneralprivatelawprinciple suchas performancein goodfaithin theUSA, France,and Germany.In connectionwithhiringpractices,however,a privateemployercanrelyupona rightto freedomof associationor freedomof contractto resistanylegal regulation.4lIn othercontexts,such as the distributionof educational opportunitiesbyagenciesofthestate,thisobstacleto regulationis absent.It maybepossibletoarguethattherighttofreedomofassociationdoesnotinclude therightto discriminateinhiringdecisions,42butemployerswillnevertheless assertthattheirfreedomis beingunjustifiablyinvadedin costlyways.To overcomethatobjection,itisnecessarytohavea powerfulargumentforjustifying regulationofhiringpractices,suchasrespectfortherighttoequaltreatmentora compellingdistributiveobjective.43 Thereasonwhyaccesstoemploymentistheprimarytargetofdiscrimination lawssurelyliesinthesignificanceweattachtothedistributionofjobsinsociety. Thesignificanceofemploymentisexplainedinpartbyitswelfareeffects.Since mostofus dependuponemploymentas ourprinciplesourceofwealth,the distributionofjobsbyemployersis a keydistributivemechanisminsociety.If hiringpracticesin thelabourmarketleadto unequaldistributiveoutcomes, causingforexampledisproportionatelevelsofpovertyamongsomeminority groups,egalitarianargumentsmightleadus toconcludethatregulatinghiring practicesshouldbetheprincipalgoalofdiscriminationlaws.Yetthisdistributive argumentlacksanexplanationofwhytheegalitariangoalshouldnotbeachieved throughtaxationandwelfarepaymentsratherthanthroughtheregulationof hiringdecisions.Whatis requiredin additionis an explanationwhythe distributionofthejobsthemselvesmatters,notjusttheeconomicbenefitsflowing fromthem. Earlieritwasarguedthatthenotionofsocialinclusionattachesconsiderable significancetopossessionofa job.Theproblemofsocialexclusionisthatsome groupsinsocietyaredeniedtheopportunitytoparticipateinthemechanisms offeredbysocietythroughwhichtheymayestablishmeaningfortheirlives,the connectionsofa community,anda senseofself-respect.Workprovidesformost peopleoneoftheprincipalmechanismsforconstructingmeaning,community, andstatus.Redistributivewelfareprogrammes,thoughimportantforthereliefof economichardship,cannottackleexceptat themarginstheproblemofsocial exclusion.Socialinclusionthusprovidesan argumentfortargetingaccessto employmentastheprimaryconcernofdiscriminationlaws.Itexplainswhyaccess tojobsshouldbetheprincipaltargetofdiscriminationlaws.'Thebestdefence 41 R. A. Epstein,ForbiddenGrounds:The Case AgainstEmploymentDiscriminationLaws (Cambridge,MA: HarvardUniversityPress,1992). 42 Forexample,itmightbearguedthatinordertoprotectothervaluesorrights,limitsareplacedon thediscret10ntoselectcontractualpartners. 43 Gardnerexploresthisproblemand also arguesforquasi-publicnatureof employer'shiring decisionsas an instrumentof distributionin orderto diminishtheforceof theclaimof the employer'srightto freedomofcontract:J.Gardner,aboven 8, 5-8. 29t3 The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol. 66 againstsocialexclusionishavingajob,andthebestwa; togeta jobistohavea goodeducation,withtherighttrainingandexperience.'Thisargumentsuggests thatintheselectionofthenatureofthedisadvantagesthatshouldbeaddressedby discriminationlaws,thenotionof socialinclusionhas playeda roleas an underlyingjustificationfor legal regulationin determiningthe typesof disadvantagethatneedtobeaddressed. Structures Bothformaland informalinstitutionalarrangementsof oursocietytendto maintainexistingdistributivepatterns,even once directdiscriminationis eliminated.Forinstance,thenormalroleofchildcareperformedbywomen putsthemata competitivedisadvantageinseekingbetterjobs,whicharetypically designedwithhiringrulesthatfavourworkexperienceandsetrequirementsof longhoursofwork.Thiscombinationofformalinstitutionalrules(thetermsof employment)andinformalsocialnorms(womentakingprimaryresponsibilityfor childcare)resultsina predictablepatternofexclusionofwomenfromthebetter jobs,asevidencedinthecontinuingdisparitybetweenaverageratesofpayformen andwomen.Inordertoaddressthistypeofdistributivepattern,discrimination lawswerebroadenedto encompasstheformalinstitutionalrules,which,in combinationwithinformalsocialnorms,havea discriminatoryeffect.Through thetestsofindirectdiscriminationordisparateimpact,thelawquestionsthe validityoftheinstitutionalrules,thoughitleavesuntouchedandunquestionedthe informalsocialnorms. Underthetestsofindirectdiscriminationordisparateimpactthatthelawuses totacklestructuraldisadvantage,thosewhowanttobenefitfromdiscrimination lawshavetorelyuponstereotypesorsocialnormsthattheymaywishtoescapeor reject.45Forexample,a requirementoffull-timeworkmaybemoredifficultfor womento satisfyif theyfulfilchild-careresponsibilities.In orderto take advantageofa remedyforindirectdiscrimination,a womanhastodemonstrate thattheinstitutionalrulehastheeffectofdisproportionatelyexcludingwomen fromwork,becausetheycomplywiththesocialnormoffulfillingchild-care responsibilities.Thisreasoningis vulnerabletoattackfromthosewhowishto rejectthesocialstereotypeandargueinsteadthatwomenarenotnecessarilythe partnerwhoshouldtakechild-careresponsibilityorthatalternativemethodsof child-careareavailable.ThusinClymov WandsworthBoroughCouncil,46 a rule againstjobsharingthepostoflibrarianwasheldnottobediscriminatoryagainst women,becausetheclaimanthadhadthechoicetopayforfull-timechild-care.As soonas thecourtor tribunaldeniesor rejectsthesocialstereotype- in this instancewomentypicallystayathometotakecareofyoungchildren- thelegal challengeto institutionaldiscriminationbeginsto fallapart.Thisparadoxical relianceofthelawonindirectdiscriminationonthepersistenceofpatternsof 44 Tony Blair,'Forewordby thePrimeMinister',Social ExclusionUnit,Officeof thePrime Minister,BridgingtheGap.NewOpportunitiesfor16-18YearOldsNotinEducationJEmployment orTraining,July1999,Cm4405,6.Thedoctrinethat'thebestsafeguardagainstsocialexclusionis a job' isalsoat thecoreofEuropeanCommunityPolicy:DecisionNo 50/2002/EC,aboven21, Recitalspara8. Itshouldalsobenotedthataccesstoeducationandtrainingisalwaysthesecond importanttargetofdiscriminationlegislation. 45 N. Lacey,UnspeakableSubjects.FeministEssaysinLegalandSocialTheory(Oxford:Hart,1998) 46 [1989]IRLR 241EAT. 30 t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] DiscriminationsEqualityandSocialInclusion structuraldisadvantagethatit maybe attemptingto redressseemsto be determinedbytheunderlyingequalityjustificationforthelaw.Theidealof equalityrespectsthechoicesofindividualsabouthowtheyshouldleadtheirlives, butsaysthelawshouldinsistuponequalrespectforthosechoices.47Respectfor thosechoicesmeansthatthelawshouldnotquestionsocialnormsinsofarasthey areconventionsandpatternsproducedbythechoiceofindividuals.48Underthis equalityjustification,theprohibitionagainstinstitutionaldiscriminationshould concernonlythoserulesthat,thoughformallyneutral,haveintheirapplicationa disparateadverseimpactoncertaingroupsasa resultofattributesofthosegroups whichtheyhavenotchosen. In contrast,owingtothepaternalistandperfectionistelementinthegoalof socialinclusion,choicesmadeby excludedgroupsthathavetheeffectof reinforcingtheirexclusionarenotchoicesthatthegoalnecessarilyrespects.The socialnormsandconventionsarethemselvesa targetfordiscriminationlaws,if theyhavetheeffectthatthegroupswhomakesuchchoicesaretherebyexcluding themselvesfromemployment.Socialinclusionthusquestionsboththeinstitutionalruleandthesocialconvention.In respectofthesocialconventionthat womentendtotakecareofchildren,socialinclusionchallengesthisconventionto theextentthatit resultsin womenbecomingsociallyexcluded.Becausethe compositionof groupsis determinedbyreferenceto thecriterionof social exclusion,theargumentbecomesthatparentswithyoungchildrenwhodo not workandarenotsupportedfinanciallybya partnerin workshouldnotbe permittedtofollowthesocialnormoftakingresponsibilityforchildcaretothe extentofexcludingthemselvesfromthelabourmarket.49Giventhedifficultyof findingaffordablechild-care,parentsmayneedpart-timejobsinordertoachieve 'well-being',a needreflectedinthenewrighttoaskforchangesinworkingtime.50 Theproblemwitha hiringrulethatprecludesjobsharingfromthisperspectiveis notthatitdiscriminatesindirectlybetweenmenandwomen,butthatitobstructs peoplesuchasparentsofyoungchildrenwhoneedjobopportunitiesforpart-time workfromenteringthelabourmarket.Forthepurposesofindirectdiscrimination law,theimplicationofa socialinclusionjustificationisthatwhetherornotthe individualcouldhavechosentocomplywiththeformalrulebydepartingfrom socialconventionisirrelevant,becausetheaimisnotequalorfairopportunity, buttheeliminationofrulesthathaveanexclusionaryeffect.Itshouldbesufficient to establisha claimforindirectdiscriminationto provethatan institutional practicehasthateffect.Itispossibletodetectsucha changeinthenewtestfor indirectsexdiscriminationinemployment.TheamendedSexDiscriminationAct 1975sectionl(2)(b)dropstheformerelementthataskedwhethera dispropor- tionatenumberofwomencannotcomplywiththehiringrule,andasksmerely whethertherulehasa detrimentaleffectfora considerablylargerproportionof women,thusavoidingtheissueofchoiceandsocialconvention.5l Drawingtogethertheseobservationsaboutstructuraldisadvantage,social inclusionexplainswhyaccesstoemploymentisa primarytargetforthelaw,offers 47 R.Dworkin,aboven33. 48 S. Fredman,WomenandtheLaw (Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,1997)288-290. 49 InthisveintheEmploymentAct2002s49(addings 2AAtotheSocialSecurityAdministration Act1992)prescribeswork-focussedinterviewsfornon-workingpartnersofclaimantsforsocial securitybenefitswitha viewtoa reductionoftheclaimant'sbenefitsfordependants. 50 EmploymentAct2002s47. 51 SexDiscrimination(IndirectDiscriminationandBurdenofProof)Regulations2001,SI 2001No 2260,implementingthe'BurdenofProof'Directive97/80/EC. 31(¢ The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol.66 a differentand moredeterminateapproachto definingthecompositionof disadvantagedgroups,andoffersanalternativetothecurrentlaw'srelianceupon socialnormsinestablishingclaimsforindirectdiscrimination.Clearlytheaimof socialinclusiondoesnotprovidea satisfactoryexplanationofallaspectsofthe lawaddressingstructuraldisadvantage,butitdoeshelptoaccountforcertain featuresthatarepuzzlingfromtheperspectiveofequalityjustifications. Provingdiscrimination Anequalityprincipleinanti-discriminationlawsinvariablyrequiresa compara- tiveapproachtoproof.Inrelationtosexdiscrimination,forinstance,thelawof directdiscriminationlaunchesanenquiryas towhetherthewomanwastreated lessfavourablythana man.Thecomparativeapproachinitiatesa searchfora manora memberofthemajoritygroupinsimilarcircumstances,a searchthat oftenprovesfruitlessunlessone createsa hypotheticalman. This legal constructionis oftendifficultto build,becausea memberofthemajorityor privilegedgroupis unlikelyto haveexperiencedstructuraldisadvantagesin a similarway,sothatitishardtoenvisagehowmembersofthisgroupcouldfind themselvesinsufficientlysimilarcircumstancesfora faircomparisontobemade. Thelawofindirectdiscriminationoffersa routearoundthisproblem,thoughit retainsthecomparativeapproachtoproof.Itpermitswomenandminoritiesto challengean employer'shiringruleson thegroundthattheruleshavea disproportionateadverseimpactonthem. Incontrast,thegoalofsocialinclusiondoesnotdependupona comparisonwith a manorsomeotherprivilegedgroup.Thepolicyofsocialinclusionasksforproof thattheruleorpracticetendstoreinforcetheexclusionofanindividualmemberof an excludedgroupormostmembersoftheexcludedgroup.A comparisoncan supplyevidenceofexclusionaryeffect,butitisnotessentialtoproof.Forexample, iftheemployer'sruleforbidspart-timework,thisrulereinforcestheexclusionof anygroupssuchas singleparentsthatmayrequirepart-timejobs.Evenifitis demonstratedthatothergroupsaresimilarlyorequallyadverselyaffectedbythe rule,thefactthatthisparticularexcludedgroupis disadvantagedby the requirementissufficienttoprovidea basisfora challengetotherule. Itisevidentthattheformulationsincurrentlegislationreflecta comparative approachto proofofdiscriminationthatlinksthemto a notionofequality. Althoughthecomparativeapproachis notalwaysrequired,as inthecaseof discriminationongroundsofpregnancy,S2itisthedominanttest.Itisalsoworth notingthat,althougha notionofequalityholdsswayinrelationtoproofof discrimination,thepreciseconceptionofequalitythatshouldbeappliedisoften subjecttodispute.Thisdisputeemergesinconnectionwithstatisticalcomparisons usedtoestablishdisparateimpactorindirectdiscrimination.No doubtmuchof thedifficultyherecan be attributedto a combinationofthelackofprecise statisticalinformationcombinedwiththecomplexityofthetest.Thistestrequires a comparisonbetweentheratiosoftheprivilegedgrouptotheprotectedgroupin twostatisticalpools.53 Theequaltreatmentprincipletendstoconfinethepoolsfor 52 Webbv EMO AirCargo(UK) LtdC-32/93[1994] ICR 770, ECJ. 53 The clearestjudicialstatementofthecorrectcomparativemethodwas givenbyMustillLJin Jonesv ChiefAdjudicationOfficer[1990]IRLR 533 CA 537. Foranendorsementoftheviewthat comparativeproportionsarethecorrectstatisticalcomparison(thoughnotrigorouslyfollowedin thiscase): R v SecretaryofStateforEmploymentexp Seymour-Smith& PerezCase C-167/97 [1999] ECR 1-623ECJ para59)andC. BarnardandB. Hepple,aboven 8, 571. 32 t) The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion statisticalcomparison,whereasa substantiveequalityofresultsprinciplepointsto therelevanceofa broadlycomposedpoolofcomparison,usuallyconsistingofthe labourmarketas a whole.Inthecaseofa hiringconditionsuchas a particular educationalqualification,forinstance,thefocusoftheequaltreatmentprincipleis onwhethertheconditiondisproportionatelyadverselyaffecteda protectedgroup withinthesetofjob applicants.Therelevantstatisticalcomparisonunderthis approachistheproportionsbetweenprivilegedgroupanddisadvantagedgroupin thepoolofjob applicantscomparedto theproportionsin thepoolofthose employed.Fromtheperspectiveofequalityofresults,however,therelevant statisticalpoolshouldbedefinedatleastas thoseavailableinthelabourmarket whocouldsatisfyall therequirementsforthejob apartfromthedisputed educationalqualification.Itistheproportionsbetweenprivilegedanddisadvantagedgroupswhocanandwhocannotsatisfytheconditionthatservesas the comparisonforestablishingindirectdiscrimination.In respectofthisdifference betweentherelevantstatisticalpools,itispossibletodetecta contrastbetweenthe courtsintheUSA,whichfavourthelogicofequaltreatmentprincipleinthe selectionofstatisticalpoolsofcomparison,54whereasUK courtshavemore commonlyadoptedtheloglcofequalityofresults.55Thisdifferenceisobscured, however,bythecommonproblemoftheunavailabilityoftherelevantstatistics suchas theracialcompositionofjob applicants. As a distributiveprincipleconcernedwithresults,theaimofsocialinclusion supportsthelogicofselectingthebroaderpoolofstatisticalcomparison.Theaim ofsocialinclusionis toeliminateexclusionaryrulesandpracticesregardlessof whethertheyhaveinfactexcludedjob applicantsinthepast.Yetthestatistical poolfavouredbysocialinclusiondiffersslightlyfromthebroadestpoolfavoured bythegoalofequalityofresults.Thesocialinclusionprincipledoesnotfocuson thestatisticsforthelabourmarketas a whole,unlessthejobconcernedrequires minimalskills,becauseitsconcerniswiththosewhopossesstheskillstobenefit fromthejob orthosewhocouldacquirethemwithtraining. Aswellas supportingtheuseofbroaderstatisticalpoolsforcomparison,the aimofsocialinclusionmaythrowlightontwootherproblemsthatemergein thecomparativeapproachto proof.Onedifficultyconcernstheinterpretation ofstatisticaldifferences.Thetestfordiscriminationin EC lawis notoneof statisticalsignificanceina technicalsense,butratheronethatadoptsa formula thattheremustbe disadvantageto a 'substantiallyhigherproportion'ofthe protectedgroup.56Thepuzzleposedbythattestis whyitdetractsfromthe commitmentto equality,whichshouldrequiremerelya testof statistical significance.Theremaybe pragmaticconsiderationsatworkhere,suchas the unreliabilityof thestatisticsthemselves.But an additionalexplanationfor thisslightdeviationfromtheequalitystandardmaybe thatthelegislation implicitlyacknowledgesthatitsdistributiveaimhastobemorefocussedonrules thathavea considerableexclusionaryeffect,andhastorefrainfromassessments ofthemeritsofeveryrulethatproducesresultsthatdeviateslightlyfroma normal distribution. 54 HazlewoodSchoolDistrictv UnitedStates433US 299(1977). 55 UniversityofManchestervJones[1993]ICR 474CA; AllonbyvAccringtonandRossendaleCollege [2001]ICR 1189CA. 56 Art2 Directive97/80OJL14 20.1.19986. It is unclearwhetherthistestsurvivesafterthenew definitionsofindirectdiscriminationin EC Directives2000/78and 2002/73,whichuse a new formulaof'particulardisadvantage'. 33t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol.66 A secondproblemthatclaimsofindirectdiscriminationsometimeshaveto confrontis theexclusionaryeffectofa combinationofrules.Forexample,an employermayusetwohiringconditionssuchasa formaleducationalqualification and a skillacquiredthroughworkexperience.The approachto statistical comparisonundertheequalityprinciplerequiresa comparisonbetweenthegroup inthelabourmarketthatcancomplywithalltherequirementsforthejobandthe groupthatcancomplywiththoserequirementsexceptfortheomissionofa disputedcriterionsuchastheformaleducationalqualification.Theproblemmay arisethat,althoughanyone hiringconditionmaynotcreatea substantial differenceinthecompositionofthecomparativepools,a combinationoftwoor moremayhavea significantexclusionaryeffect.Thereisa dangerthatunderthe approachbasedonequality,anemployermaybeabletorejecttheinferenceof indirectdiscriminationbyinsistingthateachhiringrequirementshouldbeviewed inisolation.Theaimofsocialinclusionexplainswhythismethodofanalysisis unsatisfactory.Socialexclusionisoftentheproductofa combinationoffactors, suchas beinga memberofa minoritygroupina particularneighbourhood.A disadvantagedgroupisthereforeoftenidentifiedintheoriesofsocialexclusionby morethanonecriterion.Theaimofsocialinclusionthusperhapsexplainsour intuitionthatthemethodofanalysisthatexamineseachhiringconditionin isolationisunsatisfactory,becauseitdoesnotappreczatethemulti-facetedsources ofdisadvantageinmanyinstances.57 Directdiscriminationanda justificationdefence Inpursuitofthegoalofsocialinclusion,theeliminationofa strictcomparative approachtoproofofdiscriminationnecessitatestheintroductionofajustification defenceforbothdirectand indirectdiscrimination.Undermostcurrent discriminationlegislation,a generaljustificationdefenceis restrictedtoindirect discrimination,thoughnarrowerdefencessuchas a genuineoccupational qualificationareavailableinsomeinstancesofdirectdiscrimination.Thelimited availabilityof a justificationdefenceto directdiscriminationseemsto be mandatedbytheequaltreatmentprinciple.Byrequiringconsistenttreatment, theequaltreatmentprinciplecreatesa strongpresumptionagainstthepossibility ofjustifyingintentionaldiscrimination.Anyexceptionsmustbe explainedby referenceto someotherimportantright,suchas respectforprivacy,or an extremelytightrequirementofnecessityforjob performance.Incontrast,under theprincipleof socialinclusion,justificationsforhiringrulesthatdirectly discriminatecantoleratea broaderrangeofconsiderations,providedthatthe justificationsarecompatiblewiththeaimofsocialinclusion.It is helpfulto examineoneexampleofa justificationdefencetodirectdiscriminationingreater depth,foritrevealshowa discriminationlawbaseduponsocialinclusionrather thanequalityapproachesthetaskofdefiningdiscrimination. The exampleis the DisabilityDiscriminationAct 1995. Unlikemost discriminationlaws,thetestforlegalresponsibilityinthisActisnotessentially a comparativecriterionthatcontraststheresultofhiringdecisionsor rules betweendisabledpersonsandthoseinotherwisesimilarcircumstanceswithouta 57 D. Ashiagbor,'TheIntersectionofGenderand Race intheLabourMarket:LessonsforAntiDiscriminationLaw' inA. MorrisandT. O'Donnel(eds),FeministPerspectivesonEmployment Law (London:Cavendish,1999)139. 34 t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion disability.Forexample,ifanemployeroperatesa hiringrulethatrecruitsmust receivea satisfactorymedic'alreport,and a disabledpersonreceivesan unfavourablereportas resultofthedisability,thewayinwhichthelawanalyses thecaseistosaythatdisabilitydiscriminationhasoccurredunlesstheemployer candemonstratethatthehiringruleisjustified.58Itisirrelevantthatthehiring ruleappliesequallytopersonswithouta disability,59anditisnotnecessaryto provedisparateimpact.Onceitis shownthattherulehasexcludeda disabled person,thequestionisnotwhethertherewasunequaltreatment,butwhetherthe ruleisjustifiedinthesensethatthereasonfortheruleis bothmaterialtothe circumstancesoftheparticularcaseandsubstantial.60 Thisjustificationdefenceisfurtherrefinedinsection5(2)oftheAct,whichholds theemployerlegallyresponsiblefordisabilitydiscrimination,iftheemployer cannotjustifya failuretomakereasonableadjustmentstoarrangementsthatplace a disabledpersonat a substantialdisadvantage.Equaltreatmentis notgood enough.Whatthelegislationrequiresis a dutXto treatdisabledpersons differently,tomake'reasonableaccommodations',nottotreatthemequally. AlthouttheformaljustificationdefenceundertheDDA appearstoimposea low threshold,2 therealsubstanceofthejustificationissueis tobediscoveredinthe questionwhethertheemployerhasfailedtomakereasonableadjustmentforthe person'sdisability.Whatamountsto a reasonableadjustmentis guidedby thestatuteandanelaborateCodeofPractice.63Ifanemployerhascompliedwith theCodeandconsideredallthepossibleadjustmentsthatmightbemadeforthe disabledpersonandonlyrejectedthoseoneswhichitis reasonabletorejecton groundsofexcessivecost,impossibility,andperhapssafety,64thefinalquestionof whetherintheparticularcircumstancesofthecasethehiringdecisionwasjustified seemslikelytoimposeonlya lowadditionalhurdleforemployers.Theimportant questioniswhetherallreasonableadjustmentswereconsidered,andherethetribunals encountertheacutedifEcultyofbalancingthecoststotheemployerofassessingand makingadjustmentsagainsttheexclusionaryeffectsofthehiringrules. Underthepolicyofsocialinclusionitbecomespossible,therefore,torecognisea broadjustificationdefenceto directdiscrimination.Thecoreelementofthis justificationdefencerequiresa demonstrationthattheobjectiveoftheruleserves thegoalofsocialinclusion.Thepotentialwidthofjustificationscanbeillustrated bythefactsandlegalreasoninginJamesv EastleighBoroughCouncil.65The Counciloperateda rulethatpersonsofstatepensionableagewouldbeadmitted forfreetotheCouncil'sswimmingpool.Atthattimethestatepensionableage was60 forwomenand65 formen.Theapplicationofthisruleentailedthat MrJames,aged61,paidthefullchargewhereashiswifeofthesameageentered thepoolat theconcessionaryrate.Ifthisruleis assessedexclusivelyfromthe perspectiveofa comparativeequalityprinciple,itseemsto be an inescapable 58 LondonBoroughofHammersmith& Fulhamv Farnsworth[2000]IRLR 691EAT. 59 Clarkv TDG Ltd (t/aNovacold)[1999]IRLR 318CA. 60 DisabilityDiscrlminationAct1995s 5(3);seeArdenLJinPostOfficevJones[2001]ICR 805817 61 Thistermis usedin Article5 of EC Directive2000/78,above n 9, and The Americanswith DisabilitiesAct1990s 102(b)(5)(A)42 USC s 12,112(b)(5)(A). 62 See Heinzv Kendrick[2000]IRLR 141EAT. 63 DisabilityDiscriminationAct1995s 6; Code ofPracticefortheEliminationofDiscriminationin theFieldofEmploymentagainstDisabledPersonsorPersonswhohavehada Disability(1996). 64 For a critiqueofsuchsafetyjustifications:J.DaviesandW. Davies,'ReconcilingRiskandthe EmploymentofDisabledPersonsina ReformedWelfareState'(2000)29 ILJ347. 65 [1990]2 AC 751HL. 35t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol.66 conclusionthatthereis a differenceintreatmentbetweenthesexes.'Butfor' MrJames'sex,hewouldhavebeenentitledtothereducedcharge.Fromthepers- pectiveofsocialinclusion,however,theanalysisbecomesmorecomplex.Wecan understandtheCouncil'spolicyas one aimedat a group,personsof state pensionableage,whichfindsitdifficulttoaffordtotakeadvantageofthefacilities offeredbythecommunity.Ifthereasonforthisexclusionis thecost,a more inclusiveoutcomecanbeachievedbyintroducinga discriminatorychargingrulein favourofthatgroup.Althoughtheruleaboutconcessionsincidentallyviolatesa strictprincipleofequaltreatmentonthegroundofsex,theprincipleofsocial inclusionprovidesa reasonfordispensingwithanequaltreatmentruleinthiscase, becauseequaltreatmentprovidesaninaccurateoroff-targetguidetothegoalof achievingbettersocialinclusion.Socialinclusionperinitsunequaltreatmentifthat measurefavoursan excludedgroup,andtheexcludedgroupcanbedefinedby referencetothepatternofsocialexclusion-personsofstatepensionableage.In short,theruleisnotanunjustifiedrulefromtheperspectiveofsocialinclusionand thereforetheCouncilshouldprobablynotbeheldtobeinbreachofthelegal obligation.A majorityoftheJudicialCommittee,however,upheldMrJames claimofsexdiscrimination,becausetheargumentbasedonequaltreatmentwas compelling.Thetemptationtointroducea qualificationtotheequaltreatment principleforbenignmotiveswasresisted,nodoubtinpartbecauseitaffordedno criterionofwhatshouldcountasa benignmotive,andinpartbecausethehistory ofdiscriminationagainstwomenhasbeenrepletewithmenwhoactedwithwhat theyregardedas benign,chivalrous,andconsideratemotives. Positiveaction Ourearlierreviewofequalityjustificationsforanti-discriminationlawsnotedthe tensionbetweenanykindofdifferenttreatmentbaseduponthecharacteristicsof protectedgroupsandtheequaltreatmentprinciple.Thistensionhasnotentirely precludedsomeformsofpositiveaction,butanymeasureshavebeensubjectto 'strictscrutiny'ora stringenttestof'proportionality'.In theUnitedKingdom, withthepossibleexceptionofNorthernIreland,66positiveactionwithrespectto theallocationofjobs byquotasorthelikehasbeenregardedas toogreata violationoftheequaltreatmentprinciple.67Ourearliertheoreticaldiscussion suggestedthat,inordertooverridetheequaltreatmentprincipleandtojustify differenttreatment,whatis requiredis a compellingdistributivejustification. Whatkindof positiveactiondoes thedistributivegoal of socialinclusion mandate? 66 UnderTheFairEmploymentandTreatment(NorthernIreland)Order1998SI 1998No 3162(NI 21), theEqualityCommissionin NorthernIrelandis requiredto promote'affirmativeaction' (article7), whichis definedas actiondesignedto securefairparticipationin employmentby membersoftheProtestantandRomanCatholicCommunity(article4). However,themandatory ordersthattheCommissionmaydirecttowardsemployersare limitedto measuresto revise practicesforthepurposeof promotingequalityof opportunity(Article14). A. McColgan, DiscriminationLaw: Text,CasesandMaterials(Oxford:Hart,2000)517-518,142-145. 67 TheintricaciesandperhapsinconsistenciesoftheUS positionarebeyondthescopeofthisessay thoughthereisa similarpatternofa highlyrestrictiveapproachtoaffirmativeaction.Apartfrom court-orderedaffirmativeactionprogramsas a remedyforpast directdiscrimination,strict scrutinytypicallyrulesoutaffirmativeaction(CityofRichmondv JACrosonCo 488 US 469 (1989),AdarandConstructorsIncvPena115S Ct2097(1995)),thoughitmaypermit'targets'but not 'quotas' in voluntaryplans designedto redresspatternsof disadvantage(Johnsonv TransportationAgencyofSantaClaraCounty,CA 480 US 616(1987)). 36 g The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January20033 Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion Positivediscriminationforthepurposeof socialinclusionrequiresthat employersshouldbesensitivetodifferenceandmakereasonableadjustments,in ordertoenablemembersofexcludedgroupstoovercomeobstructionstotheir obtainingworksuitablefortheirskillsand capability.This dutyrequires employerstoconsideramongstmanythingshowtheworkplaceisorganised,how jobsarestructured,andhowtheskillsandcapabilitiesoftheworkerscouldbe improved,witha viewtothereductionofbarrierstoemploymentforexcluded groups.We havealreadyconsideredan exampleof sucha dutyofpositive discriminationin thedutyto makereasonableaccommodationsunderthe DisabilityDiscriminationAct1995.68 Socialinclusiondoesnot,however,requiretheemployertoadoptquotasto eliminatestatisticaldiscrimination,asmightberequiredundera strongegalitarian approach.Thesequotasareunsatisfactoryfromthepointofviewof social inclusion,bothbecausetheyignorethequestionwhethertheindividualworker canachieve'well-being'fromthejob,andbecausetheydonotaddressthecauses ofsocialexclusion.69Ifthecauseofsocialexclusionis thatapplicantsfroma particularexcludedgrouplackthetrainingtoperformthejob,thesolutionlies eitherin theprovisionoftrainingor thereorganisationofworkso thatless trainingisrequiredforsomepositions.Ifthecauseofsocialexclusionisthatthe hoursofworkrenderitdifficultfortheexcludedgrouptoconform,thesolution liesina considerationofwhetherflexibilityinhourscouldbeintroduced.This dutytomakereasonableadjustmentsinhoursofworkmightapplytoourearlier exampleofjob-sharingthepositionoflibrarian,70ortothecaseofa religious minorityforwhomworkat a particulartimeis incompatiblewithrequired religiousobservances.7l Althoughat firstsightthisrequirementforpositiveactionmandatedbythe socialinclusionprincipleappearstobeatoddswithcurrentdiscriminationlaw thatingeneralforbidsdifferenttreatment,a closerinspectionoftheoperationof thelawofindirectdiscriminationrevealsthatitcanapproximatetothemodel suggestedbytheaimofsocialinclusion.In a claimforindirectdiscrimination, oncetheindirectdiscriminatoryeffectofa hiringruleis revealedbystatistical evidence,theemployermustjustifytheruleon businessgroundsto avoida successfulclaimofdiscrimination.Thejustificationstandardcurrentlyusedin casesofindirectsexdiscriminationisunderEC lawa testofproportionality,72 whichissimilartothe'businessnecessity'testusedintheUnitedStates.Under otherUK anti-discriminationlaws,thetestis perhapsslightlyweaker:a requirementtobalanceobjectivelythediscriminatoryeffectoftheruleagainst 68 DisabilityDiscriminationAct 1995s 6(7) forbidsmorefavourabletreatmentexceptinso faras differenttreatmentis requiredunderthedutyof reasonableadjustment.See also Canadian EmploymentEquityAct1995s2,whichinsiststhat'equity'requiresmorethantreatingpersonsin thesamewaybut'requiresspecialmeasuresandtheaccommodationofdifferences.'Thisformula canjustifyquotasinordertobreachsocialconventionsthatcreatebarrierstoemployment:Action TravaildesFemmesv CanadianNationalRailwayCo [1987]1 SCR 1114,40 DLR (4th)193(S Ct Canada). 69 Thereare also reasonsto be scepticalabouttheeffectivenessof mandatedaffirmativeaction programmesin thelightof thelack of complianceby employerswiththe3% quota in the Disabled Persons(Employment)Act 1944;see B. Doyle, New DirectionsTowardsDisabled Workers'Rights(London:InstituteofEmploymentRights,1994)1S11. 70 Clymov WandsworthBoroughCouncil[1989]IRLR 241EAT. 71 Ahmadv InnerLondonEducationAuthority[1978]QB 36CA; Ahmadv UK (1982)4 EHRR 126, EComHR. SeealsotheAmencandutyofreasonableaccommodationofan employee'sreligious observanceorpracticeinCivilRightsAct1964TitleVII s 701(j)42 USC s 2000e(j). 72 Bilka-KaufhausGmbHv WebervonHartzC-170/84[1986]ECR 1607ECJ;EC Directive2000/78, Art2(2)(b);2002/73,newArt2(2). 37t TheModernLawReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol.66 thereasonableneedsofthepartyimposingthecondition.73Thisjustification defencerequirestheemployerto discoverand revealthepotentialcostsof eliminatingthehiringrulein thesamewaythatthedutyofaccommodation functionsas an 'inforination-forcingrule'.74Thenthecourtmustbalancethose coststotheemployeragainsttheexclusionaryimpactoftherule. AsJollsarguesintheUS context,75thisprocessiscloselyanalogoustotheduty tomakereasonableadjustment,providedthatthecourtsdonotperinita trivial costtotheemployertocountasa sufficientjustification.Ifthecourtsacceptboth thatanemployermayhavetoincursomecoststoaccommodateexcludedgroups andthatthosemeasuresmightinvolvereorganisingtheworkplace,alteringjob content,andimprovingtrainingopportunities,a justificationdefencetoindirect discriminationpresentsa similarenquirytothatposedbythedutyofreasonable adjustment.76Forexample,in LondonUndergroundLtdv Edwards(No 2),77 whereanemployerintroduceda newshiftsystemthatcompelleda singleparent eventuallytoresign,thecourtfoundthattheshiftsystem,thoughservingthe employer'sbusinessneeds,didnotpreventtheemployerfromaccommodatingthe needsofsingleparents.As MorrisonJobservedin theEmploymentAppeal Tribunal,'[T]herewasgoodevidencethatLondonUndergroundcouldhavemade arrangementswhichwouldnothavebeendamagingtotheirbusinessplansbut whichwouldhaveaccommodatedthereasonabledemandsoftheiremployees.' Thesesimilaritiesbetweenajustificationofindirectdiscriminationandthedutyof reasonableadjustmentappearmoretransparentlyunderthe EC testof proportionality.The keyquestionunderthetestofproportionalityis often whethertheemployer'sruleisnecessaryinthesensenootherrulewithlessadverse impactontheexcludedgroupwouldsatisfythebusinessneedsoftheemployer.78 Argumentsaboutjustificationinindirectdiscriminationclaimsamounttomore thananindividualisedclaimforadjustment,becausetheemployerisrequiredto justifytheadverseimpactoftheruleon an excludedclass,notmerelyon a particularjob applicant.Theoutcomeofthislegalprocessisineffecttorequire theemployertoconsiderthepossibilityofaffirmativeactionfora group,notin thesenseofadoptingquotas,butinthesenseofadjustmentstothebusinessto enablemembersoftheexcludedgrouptoobtainemployment. Althoughtheseexamplesrevealthecloseparallelinreasoningbetweenthekind ofpositiveactionrequiredbytheprincipleofsocialinclusionandtheoperationof theemployer'sjustificationdefencetoclaimofindirectdiscrimination,thematch betweenthecurrentlawandtheimplicationsoftheaimofsocialinclusionisnot exact.Thecentraldifferenceconcernsthepotentialwidthofjustificationsfor indirectlydiscriminatoryrules.Underthesocialinclusionprinciple,itshouldbe 73 HampsonvDepartmentofEducationandScience[1989]ICR 179CA. Thistestwasapprovedand describedas anapplicationoftheEC testofproportionalitybyLordNichollsinBarryv Midland Bankplc[199]ICR 859,HL 870,andbySedleyLJinAllonbyvAccringtonandRossendaleCollege [2001]ICR 1189CA 1200,thoughthereseemstobea cleardifferencebetweena testofnecessity anda merebalancingofinterests. 74 P. S. KarlenandG. Rutherglen,'Disabilities,Discrimination,andReasonableAccommodation' (1996)46 DukeLaw J 1,32. 75 C. Jolls,'AntidiscriminationandAccommodation'(2001)115HarvL Rev642. 76 S. Fredman,aboven 10,316-318. 77 [1997]IRLR 157 EAT; (affirmed[1999]ICR 494 CA); J. Conaghan,'The Family-Friendly WorkplaceinLabourLaw Discourse:SomeReflectionsonLondonUndergroundLtdv Edwards' inH. Collins,P. Davies,R. Rideout(eds),LegalRegulationoftheEmploymentRelation(London: Kluwer,2000)161. 78 ThistestofproportionalityisalsobeingappliedundertheHumanRightsAct1998,eg Wilsonv FirstCountyTrustLtdfNo2) [2001]EWCA Civ633,[2001]3 WLR 42 CA. 38 t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion possibletojustifya rulewithindirectdiscriminatoryeffectsiftherulehelpsto reducesocialexclusion.Thusthejustificationdefenceisnotconfinedtobusiness considerationssuchas cost,butcan includethebroadersocialobjectiveof reducingsocialexclusion.Forexample,inNorthernIreland,whereoneeffect of practicesof religiousdiscriminationhas beena disproportionatelevelof unemploymentamongthe Catholiccommunity,the legislationprovidesa justificationdefenceforhiringrulesthatgivepreferencetounemployedpersons, eventhoughsuchrulesalmostcertainlydiscriminateindirectlyagainstthe Protestantcommunity.79Thisspecialprovisionis requiredbecauseunderthe currentanti-discriminationlaws the employercan onlyjustifyindirectly discriminatoryrulesbyreferencetobusinessconsiderationsratherthanbroader socialobjectives. Asthislastexamplereveals,noteverylegalexpressionofthedutyofreasonable adjustmentconfersa broaddiscretionon thecourts.In someinstancesthe requirementsofreasonableadjustmenthavebeencloselystipulatedbyParliament. For instance,maternityand parentalleaverights,whichimposea coston employerstoadjusttotheneedsofnewparents,havecloselydefinedparameters andentitlements.80Thefurtherdutytoaccommodateparents'needfortimeoff worktodealwithfamilyemergenciesis morelooselydefinedbya standardof reasonableness.81These 'family-friendly'measurescan be regardedas a deterininationoftherequirementofreasonableadjustmentforparents,with theirunderlyinggoalbeinginpartthereductionofsocialexclusion. Prioritynotequality Theprecedingsketchofthearchitectureofanti-discriminationlawsbasedona goalofsocialinclusionhasemphasisedfourfeatures.First,theprimarytargetof socialinclusionis the allocationof jobs to groupsthatsufferpersistent disadvantageinthelabourmarket.Thesegroupscanbeidentifiedbyreference to one or morecriteria,noneofwhichneedreferto unalterableor 'status' characteristics.Secondly,proofofdiscriminationshoulddependuponevidenceof disadvantagecombinedwithmembershipofoneoftheprotectedgroups,without thefurtherneedtoprovecomparativegreaterdisadvantagethanothergroups. Thirdly,anti-discriminationlawsthatpursuethegoalofsocialinclusionshould, however,permita broadjustificationdefenceto bothdirectand indirect discrimination,thoughthejustificationmusteitherrestupontheneedtocombat socialexclusionora claimthatthediscriminatoryruleonlyexcludesthosepeople whocouldnottakeadvantageoftheemploymentopportunity.Finally,thegoalof socialinclusionmandatesa formofpositiveactionthatcanbedescribedasa duty ofreasonableadjustment. My briefsketchof thefeaturesof anti-discriminationlawsbasedupona principleofsocialinclusionhasnotaddressedmanyfeaturesofthecurrentlaws 79 Fair Employmentand Treatment(NorthernIreland)Order1998art 75, (SI 1998No 3162 (NI 21)). A similarprovisionin art73 providesa justificationdefenceto rulesthatindirectly discriminateinselectionforredundancy. 80 EmploymentRightsAct 1996,PartVIII (as amendedbyEmploymentRelationsAct 1999s7). Detailsare fixedby Maternityand ParentalLeave,etc.Regulations1999SI 1999/3312.The currentEmploymentBill2002 adds a tightlycircumscribedrightto paid paternityleaveand improvematernityrights. 81 EmploymentRightsAct1996,s 57A(as amendedbyEmploymentRelationsActl999s 8). 39g The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol.66 and proposalsto amendthem.The discussioncouldbe extendedin many directionswithsuggestiveresults.Forinstance,themostrecentinnovationsin discriminationlaws,whichhavebeendescribedas 'fourthgenerationduties'82 imposepositivedutiesonpublicsectorbodiestotakestepstoimproveequality.83 Theofficialjustificationforthesepositivedutiesisframedintermsofsomenotion ofequality,suchasfairequalityofopportunityormoreequalresults.AsFredman argues,however,'animportantdimensionoffourthgenerationequalitylawsis theirpotentialtoencourageparticipatedgroupsinthedecision-makingprocess itself'.84Therearemanypossibleexplanationsforthisemphasisuponparticipa- tionbydisadvantagedgroupsindeterminingthecontentofpositiveduties.A participatoryprocessmaycontributetodemocraticgovernance,a pointstressed inEuropeanUnionmeasures,85oritmayhelpminoritiestoexpresshowtheir 'difference'shouldberespected.86Butideasofequalitydo notseemtorequire suchan emphasison participationofminoritiesin theformulationofpublic policy.Incontrast,thegoalofsocialinclusiondoesemphasisethecontributionof participationinpubliclifeasa contributionto'well-being',sothiselementinthe strategyofthedevelopmentofpositivedutiesfitsintoa socialinclusionprinciple. Duringthecourseofthisanalysis,wehavecomparedtheequalityjustifications forcurrentanti-discriminationlawswiththeimplicationsofthejustificationbased uponsocialinclusion.Insomerespects,butbynomeansall,I havearguedthat thesocialinclusionjustificationprovidesa morecoherentexplanationofthelegal framework.Myargumentis notthata socialinclusionjustificationprovidesa completeinterpretationofthecurrentlaws.Sucha claimisimplausiblegiventhe influentialrolethatthenotionofequalityhasplayedintheconstructionofthe legislation.Wherethepotentialinfluenceofsocialinclusioncanbe detectedis ratherinaccountsofwhenthelawpermitsorrequiresdifferenttreatmentrather thanequalorthesametreatment.Inshort,socialinclusionprovidesa goalforthe legislationthatsuppliesa justificationinparticularinstancesfordeparturesfrom thegeneralruleofequaltreatment. Returningtoourinitialformulationoftheproblemofidentifyingtheaimsof anti-discriminationlaws,socialinclusionoffersa distributivegoalthatanswersthe questionwhenisitfairtorequireequaltreatmentandwhenisitfairtorequire differenttreatment.The answeris thatdeviationsfromequaltreatmentare requiredinorderto achievethedistributiveaimofsocialinclusion.Thisaim requirespreferenceorprioritytobegiventomembersofa particulargroup,ifthe groupcanbeclassifiedassociallyexcluded.Thepreferentialmeasuresrequiredare thosethatwillcontributetothereductionofsocialexclusion. Thedistributiveaimofsocialinclusionavoidsanydirectconnectionwitha distributivegoalframedintermsofequality.Itneitherseeksequalityofwelfare norequalityof opportunity,thoughof coursea successfulpolicyof social inclusionwouldmakea societymoreequalinbothrespects.Theaimofsocial inclusionisrathertoconstructa conceptionofunfairnessinresults,andtosuggest 82 B. Hepple,M. CousseyandT. Choudhury,aboven 1,para 1.6. 83 NorthernIrelandAct 1998,s 75 and Schedule9, Fair Employmentand Treatment(Northern Ireland)Order1998,SI 1998No 3162(NI 21); Race Relations(Amendment)Act2000. 84 S. Fredman,aboven 1,164.A glimpseintotheproposedmethodsofparticipationforthepublic sectoris providedby theDepartmentof Trade and Industry,EqualityScheme:Section75 NorthernIrelandAct1998(January2002),whichenvisagesextensiveconsultationwithlargeand smallorganisations,togetherwitha rangeofmeasuresdesignedtoencourageparticipation. 85 CommissionWhitePaper,EuropeanGovernance,25.7.2001,Com(2001)428final. 86 I. M. Young,aboven 25, 184;A. Phillips,ThePoliticsofPresence(Oxford:ClarendonPress, 1995);S. Fredman,aboven 1,153-156. 40 g The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusionJanuary2003] appropriateremedialstrategiesthatinvolvegivingpriorityor preferenceto excludedgroups.Butdoesthisconcernwithpriorityratherthanequalityentailan abandonmentoftheequaltreatmentprinciple? Itiscertainlycompatiblewiththeaimofsocialinclusiontoarguethatequal treatmentshouldapplyas thenormalrule.Socialexclusionisoftentheresultof unequaltreatment,so thata requirementofequaltreatmentoftenservesto addresstheproblem.In thelightofourearlierdiscussion,however,doesthis explanationofusingequaltreatmentasa ruleofthumbattributesufficientweight to theprinciplein viewof theforceattachedto it in anti-discrimination legislation?I doubtthatthisexplanationoftheroleoftheequaltreatment principlecouldsucceed,thoughmyargumenthasneverrequiredthatitshould. Thereasonforintroducingtheaimofsocialinclusionintotheaccountofthe aimsofanti-discriminationlegislationwastofinda solutiontothepuzzleofwhy differenttreatmentwassometimesrequiredorpermitted.Myargumentwasthata notionofdistributivejusticewasneededforsuchan account.Socialinclusion providessucha theoryofdistributivejustice,onewhichisnotsoambitiousasto castdoubtonmaintainingequaltreatmentas thenormalrule,butwhichalso explainswhenandwhydeviationsfromthenormalruleshouldberequiredor permitted.Thecontinuingimportanceoftheprincipleofequaltreatmentas an aimofthelawisnotabandonedas a resultofrecognisinga distributiveaimof socialinclusion.Evenso,westillrequireanexplanationofwhysomuchweight seemstobeattachedtotheequaltreatmentprinciple,suchthatanydeviationhas tobecarefullyjustifiedundertestsofproportionalityandthelike. Mysurmiseisthatequaltreatmenthasbeenaccordedsuchimportanceinantidiscriminationlawsfortworeasons.First,equaltreatmentis thenormalrule requiredbytheseparateprincipleofrespectforindividualdignityorequalworth. Weobservedearlierthatequalworthsometimesrequiresrespectfordifference, butweshouldnotignorehowitalsosupportsinmostinstancesa requirementof equaltreatment.Thisprincipleofequalrespectisexpressedbyarticle14ofthe EuropeanConventionfortheProtectionofHumanRightsandFundamental Freedoms:'TheenjoymentoftherightsandfreedomssetforthinthisConvention shallbesecuredwithoutdiscriminationonanygroundsuchas sex,race,colour, language,religion,politicalorotheropinion,nationalorsocialorigin,association witha nationalminority,property,birthorotherstatus.'Theindependentvalue ofrespectforindividualdignitythusstrengthenstheweighttobeattachedtothe valueofequaltreatment. A secondreasonwhyequaltreatmenthasbeengivensucha prominentrolein thelegislationis thattheprinciplehas provideda dominantconstitutional principlewithinWesternlegalsystems.A legalsystem,whichhas achieved autonomyfromthepoliticalandeconomicsystems,hasitsindependentdemands offairprocess,ofevidenceandproof,ofremedialdevices,oflegaljustification and,ingeneral,ofpreservationoftheintegrityofitssystem.87Themaximsof 87 Thisdistinctionbetweenpoliticalgoalandtheoperationalrequirementsofthelegalsystemuses theanalyticalframeworkof systemstheory,as in G. Teubner,Law as an AutopofeticSystem (Oxford:Blackwell,1993),thougha similardistinctionbetweengeneraljustifyingaim and conditionsoflegalresponsibilitycan-beexpressedthroughpoliticalphilosophy,as inH. L. A. Hart,Punishmentand Responsibility(Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress,1968)Chapter1. The terminologyof'integrity'derives,ofcourse,fromR. Dworkin,aboven26.Mydiscussionfocuses onthedemandofintegrityforequalrespect,butthelegalsystemimposesmanyotheroperational requirementsonanti-discriminationlaws,suchas proofof'detriment'as a conditionfora claim anda tendencytorequirethesatisfactionofsomecriterionof'fault'beforecompensationcanbe awarded. 41t) The Modem Law ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions TheModernLaw Review [Vol.66 'equalprotectionofthelaws'or 'treatlikecasesalike'representfundamental operationalprinciplesof theselegalsystems.The significanceof thislegal frameworkis thatwheneverpoliticalgoalshaveto be incorporatedintolaw, thelegalsystemmustaccommodatethemwithinitsownoperationalprinciples. Thepoliticalgoalbehindanti-discriminationlegislationbecomestranslatedinthe operationsofthelegalsystemas a rulethatlikecasesshouldbetreatedalike.In otherwords,thelegalsystemhasitsownindependentvaluesorcommunication system,whichplaceconstraintsonhowpoliticalgoalscanbepursuedthroughits mechanisms.Whateverthepoliticalaimbehindanti-discriminationlegislation, whetherit comprisesequalityof results,equalityof opportunity,or social inclusion,thataimhasto be modifiedto complywiththeprincipleofequal treatmentin orderforit to be accommodatedwithintegritywithinthelegal system. Acombinationofthesetworeasonsprobablyexplainssufficientlywhytheantidiscriminationlegislationattachessuchgreatweightto theprincipleofequal treatment.Thesignificanceattachedtoequaltreatmentbytheprincipleofequal respectandtheintegrityofthelegalsystemcanprovideanexplanationforwhy theanti-discriminationlawsdepartfromthearchitecturesuggestedby the distributivegoalofsocialinclusion.Forinstance,itwasnotedearlierthataimof socialinclusiondoesnotexplainwhywhitemalesshouldreceivelegalprotection againstdiscrimination,assumingthattheyarenotan excludedgroup.Wecan appreciate,however,thatthesymmetricalpatternofmanydiscriminationlaws respondstotherequirementsoftheprincipleofequalworthandthedemandsof integrityofthelegalsystem. Returning,finally,tothequestionposedattheoutset- whataretheaimsof anti-discriminationlaws?- myargumentsuggeststhatas wellas upholdingthe idealofrespectforthedignityofindividualsorequalworth,thelegislationalso mustbe understoodas pursuinga distributiveaimin orderto accountfor deviationsfromtheequaltreatmentprinciple.I haveargued,thoughcertainlynot conclusively,thatthisdistributiveaimorcriterionoffairnessmaybediscoveredin theaimofsocialinclusion.Althoughthecurrentlawdoesnotfitpreciselywiththe principlessuggestedbytheaimofsocialinclusion,thematchiscloserthanmight beinitiallysupposed,andinseveralrespectstheaimofsocialinclusionexplains featuresofthelawthatseemhardtoaccountforbyreferencetootherpossible distributiveaimssuchas equalityofopportunity.Inparticular,theaimofsocial inclusionsuggestsa moredeterminatestandardforthelegitimacyofpositive actionthanthetestsof'proportionality'or 'strictscrutiny'.It suggeststhat deviationsfromequaltreatmerstshouldbe permittedwherethediscriminatory measureis necessarytoachievetheresultofsocialinclusionformembersofa groupthatarepresentlylargelyexcluded. Moreover,anappreciationoftheaimofsocialinclusionmayprovideaninsight intothereasonswhywemayhavereservationsaboutsomeaspectsofthecurrent law. For instance,rememberJamesv EastleighBoroughCouncil,thecase concerningfreeentrytoa swimmingpool.AlthoughthemajorityoftheHouseof Lordsregardedtheproblemasa simplecaseofdirectdiscrimination,because'but for'hissexMrJameswouldhavehada freeswim,theminorityweresurelycorrect todoubtwhethertheaimofthelawincludedpreventingthelocalauthorityfrom increasingaccesstoitsfacilitiesforthosewhomightotherwisebeexcluded.Wedo notknowwhethertheconcessionbaseduponstatepensionableageservedthegoal of reducingtheexclusionof a groupthatwas otherwisedisproportionately excludedfromthispublicfacility.Thatquestionwasleftanswered,becausethe 42 t The ModernLaw ReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions January2003] Discrimination,EqualityandSocialInclusion majoritybelievedthatultimatelytheequal treatmentprincipleprovidedan exclusionaryrulethatpreventedanyjustificationofdirectdiscrimination.Theaim ofsocialinclusionexplainswhythatquestionshouldhavebeenrelevant,andwhy a deviationfromtheequaltreatmentrulemayhavebeenjustifiedinthisinstance. Thisexerciseinexaminingtheaimsoftheanti-discriminationlawsinthelightof theideaofsocialinclusionis notthereforemerelyan exerciseinmapping,of interpretation,orofrationalisation,butitisalsointendedasa criticalexploration oftheassumptionsandlimitationsoftheselaws. 43t TheModernLawReviewLimited2003 This content downloaded from 147.251.229.136 on Thu, 09 Apr 2015 08:50:37 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 1 Three Discourses of Social Exclusion The term social exclusion is intrinsically problematic. It represents the primary significant division in society as one between an included majority and an excluded minority. This has implications for how both included and excluded groups are understood, and for the implicit model of society itself. Attention is drawn away from the inequalities and differences among the included. Notably, the very rich are discursively absorbed into the included majority, their power and privilege slipping out of focus if not wholly out of sight. At the same time, the poverty and disadvantage of the so-called excluded are discursively placed outside society. What results is an overly homogeneous and consensual image of society ± a rosy view possible because the implicit model is one in which inequality and poverty are pathological and residual, rather than endemic. Exclusion appears as an essentially peripheral problem, existing at the boundary of society, rather than a feature of a society which characteristically delivers massive inequalities across the board and chronic deprivation for a large minority. The solution implied by a discourse of social exclusion is a minimalist one: a transition across the boundary to become an insider rather than an outsider in a society whose structural inequalities remain largely uninterrogated. In practice, however, `social exclusion' is embedded in different discourses which manifest these problems to varying extent. Three discourses are identified here: a redistributionist discourse (RED) developed in British critical social policy, whose prime concern is with poverty; a moral underclass discourse (MUD) which centres on the moral and behavioural delinquency of the excluded themselves; and a social integrationist discourse (SID) whose central focus is on paid work. They differ in how they characterize the boundary, and thus what defines people as insiders or outsiders, and how inclusion can be brought about. RED broadens out from its concern with poverty into a critique of inequality, and contrasts exclusion with a version of citizenship which calls for substantial redistribution of power and wealth. MUD is a gendered discourse with many forerunners, whose demons are criminally-inclined, unemployable young men and sexually and 7 R. Levitas, The Inclusive Society? © Ruth Levitas 2005 socially irresponsible single mothers, for whom paid work is necessary as a means of social discipline, but whose (self-) exclusion, and thus potential inclusion, is moral and cultural. SID focuses more narrowly on unemployment and economic inactivity, pursuing social integration or social cohesion primarily through inclusion in paid work. The three discourses differ quite markedly in how they present the relationship between inclusion/exclusion and inequality, a theme which is central to the overall argument of this book. The following discussion of RED, MUD, and SID also considers how the valorization of unpaid work plays through the different discourses. In October 1997 the Office of National Statistics (ONS) published the first estimates of the extent and value of unpaid work in the British economy. If a monetary value were put on such work, at 1995 values it would have been at least equivalent to £341 billion, or more than the whole UK manufacturing sector, and perhaps as much as £739 billion, 120 per cent of gross domestic product. Among the reasons for this statistical development was the insensitivity of conventional national accounts to the movement of activities between market and non-market sectors.1 Yet despite this official endorsement, the dominant public and social-scientific understanding of `work' remains paid work. Since the ONS figures confirmed that women do much more unpaid work than men, and that although men do more paid work, they also have more leisure, men's work is more acknowledged, as well as more highly rewarded, than women's work.2 Following a well-established theme in feminist arguments, Miriam Glucksmann argues that work cannot be elided with those forms which happen to take place in a market setting: work refers to all `activity necessary for the production and reproduction of economic relations and structures . . . irrespective of how and where it is carried out'. She describes the `manner by which all the labour in a particular society is divided up and allocated to different structures, institutions and activities' as the total social organization of labour, and goes on to discuss historical changes in the gendered division of labour within and between household and market ± shifts which the new satellite accounts are expressly developed to illuminate.3 Both Glucksmann's perspective and the new official data raise another question. How is the recognition of not just the social but the economic value of currently unpaid work compatible with the distribution of the social product primarily through rewards for paid work? RED, MUD and SID have different capabilities for acknowledging, and thus for potentially addressing, this question. The Inclusive Society8 RED: SOCIAL EXCLUSION AND CRITICAL SOCIAL POLICY In 1979 Peter Townsend published a major study of poverty, analysing survey data from 1968±9. His purpose was to redefine poverty as an objective condition of relative deprivation. Rather than defining poverty, as earlier studies and official policy had done, in terms of levels of income necessary for subsistence, Townsend argued that the crucial issue was whether people had sufficient resources to participate in the customary life of society and to fulfil what was expected of them as members of it: Individuals, families and groups can be said to be in poverty when they lack the resources to obtain the types of diet, participate in the activities and have the living conditions and amenities which are customary, or at least are widely encouraged and approved, in the societies to which they belong. Their resources are so seriously below those commanded by the average individual or family that they are, in effect, excluded from ordinary living patterns, customs and activities.4 Expectations across society might differ in many respects, but Townsend claimed there was neverthless `a loosely defined set of customs, material goods and social pleasures at any point in a nation's history which can be said to represent general amenities, or to which all or most people in that society are agreed to be entitled. Those who have few of these amenities can be said to be deprived'. Inequality might affect the style in which people participated in some social practices ± the lavishness of holidays, or celebrations of birthdays and religious festivals. Poverty and deprivation went beyond this. There was a level of resources below which, rather than just a reduction in the scale of participation, there was a sudden withdrawal from the community's style of living: people `drop out or are excluded'.5 Townsend was not the first to argue that poverty was a multi-faceted process rather than simply a matter of low income. But his was a sustained argument which widened the perspective from income to resources, and from consumption to participation. The analysis embraced housing, health and environmental pollution. It revealed disability as a particular factor in producing exclusion. It addressed deprivation at work, including hours of work, job security, and the working environment, and looked at the relationship between work, welfare and fringe benefits. The solution proposed was explicitly and broadly redistributive. Townsend recommended a decreased reliance Three Discourses of Social Exclusion 9 on means-tested benefits, which he saw as a mechanism of social control as well as a rationing device: benefits should be paid as of right. He acknowledged a conflict between this approach and the principles and requirements of a capitalist market. Nevertheless, he argued that: National action to remedy poverty ± through incomes policy, full employment, less specialization of work roles, higher social security benefits, new forms of allowances and rate support grants and a more redistributive tax structure ± is implied.6 Poverty in the United Kingdom also included a chapter on one-parent families. This was a relatively new category in social thought. Townsend noted that there was no such term before 1964, when `fatherless families' were collectively identified, and no national collation of statistics until 1967; `motherless families' were incorporated later. Consistent with later trends in social science towards deconstructing rather than constructing categories, Duncan and Edwards have argued that lone-parent families should not be treated as a single group.7 But Townsend was concerned about unmarried and separated mothers being pressed into employment despite their entitlement to benefit, and also concerned that lone fathers would continue to be subjected to improper pressure. Fathers only acquired the right to claim benefits as lone parents in 1975. This was one of a number of changes ± including linking pension upratings to the higher of earnings or prices ± brought in by the Wilson government, with Barbara Castle as Minister for Health and Social Security. Townsend attributed the poverty of oneparent families to a number of factors: the low earning-power of women; the absence of public child care; the practical restrictions that caring for children places on lone parents; attitudes to unmarried parents; the social expectation that women should be the primary carers; and the lack of income rights for women caring for children within marriage or outside it. The restructuring of the benefit system should incorporate larger maintenance allowances for children, allowances for the care of children, and an allowance for the upkeep of the family home in recognition of the unpaid work involved ± all paid as of right, rather than means-tested.8 These recommendations went some way towards recognizing the unpaid work of parenting. The whole thrust of Townsend's argument was that poverty resulted in exclusion from social participation, but he did not use the term `social exclusion'. Reflecting on this in 1997, he said that he had resisted the term for some time because he saw discrimination and exclusion as `effects rather than causes', as `by-products of . . . market The Inclusive Society10 manufactured class'; too much emphasis on social exclusion diverted attention from deprivation. However, he said `I was wrong. . . . ``social exclusion'' directs attention to the marginalised and excluded and to the potential instruments of their exclusion'.9 He argued once again for a redistributive strategy, not just through the tax and benefit systems and public services, but through the reduction of earnings differentials, a minimum wage, a minimum income for those unable to work, and financial recognition of unpaid work through at least a conditional participation income, if not an unconditional citizen's income. The eighteen years between these statements were also the eighteen years of Conservative government, marked by dramatic increases in inequality, in unemployment, and in the numbers living in poverty, as well as more restrictive conditions for less generous social security benefits. The Tories had a redistributive strategy ± but it was redistribution to the rich. Over this period, `social exclusion' gained currency in critical social policy, especially in the discourse of the research and campaigning organization, Child Poverty Action Group (CPAG). CPAG marked the 1997 election with the publication of Britain Divided: The growth of social exclusion in the 1980s and 1990s.10 Its three sections were subtitled `creating poverty and social exclusion'; `dimensions of poverty and social exclusion'; and `combating poverty and social exclusion' ± a formula which leaves open the relationship between the two terms. Walker, however, defined poverty in similar terms to Townsend: it is `a lack of the material resources, especially income, necessary to participate in British society'. Social exclusion has a broader, more comprehensive, meaning: it `refers to the dynamic process of being shut out, fully or partially, from any of the social, economic, political and cultural systems which determine the social integration of a person in society'.11 Contributors to the book were variously successful in maintaining this distinction. They emphasized that poverty does not necessarily lead to exclusion ± a point made by Townsend in 1979, who noted that although poverty constituted a serious barrier to social participation, nevertheless stability of personal circumstances, length of residence, good health and frequent social contacts mitigated the effects of low material resources. The CPAG volume argued that social exclusion may be a cause, rather than just a result, of poverty. Homelessness, health, unemployment, food, utility disconnections were discussed, as well as (and in relation to) gender, ethnicity, the social security system and the overall distribution of income and wealth. The agenda was one Three Discourses of Social Exclusion 11 of radical redistribution ± although Townsend was one of a minority, together with Lisa Harker, who mentioned unpaid work. Harker, both here and elsewhere, called for universal child benefit, plus a benefit supporting child rearing.12 This would be payable in addition to social insurance benefits, and calculated on an individual rather than household basis ± thus reducing the personal economic dependency of women on men. A concept of exclusion which refers to being shut out fully or partially is thereby extended to incorporate inequality, and its converse necessarily implies much greater equality. Britain Divided concluded on a cautiously optimistic note about the prospects for a redistributive agenda under Labour, citing Gordon Brown's John Smith Memorial Lecture where he argued that equality must be restored to its proper place in the trinity of socialist values, alongside liberty and community, and insisted that Labour would tackle poverty and inequality. Given Brown's later redefinition of equality as equality of opportunity (see Chapter 7 below), the caution may have been more appropriate than the optimism. But in the years of Thatcherite domination, direct defence of equality was difficult. It was assaulted as an immoral, even totalitarian, imposition of uniformity, and a brake on economic growth. Increasingly, the idea of citizenship was deployed in defence of welfare rights and welfare provision. Thus Walker argued that `social exclusion may . . . be seen as the denial (or non-realisation) of the civil, political and social rights of citizenship'.13 Peter Golding argued that poverty led to a reduction in participation tantamount to partial citizenship, as low income families were excluded from new information technologies, entertainment and leisure pursuits, as well as from financial institutions and from political life.14 Ruth Lister's The Exclusive Society was subtitled `citizenship and the poor', and traced the development of the broadening view of social exclusion as the antithesis of citizenship.15 Citizenship is, of course, another word which can embrace many meanings, and whose inflection to the individual or the social may vary considerably. Goodin argues that citizenship is a more egalitarian concept than inclusion.16 Whereas inclusion focuses on the division between insiders and outsiders, and does not address the relationship between boundary and centre, citizenship focuses on the characteristics which are shared. However, models of citizenship differ in their scope, and thus in what respect citizens are to be deemed equal. The version used as an antonym to social exclusion drew heavily on T. H. Marshall's model, set out in 1950, which incorporated civil, political The Inclusive Society12 and social rights. Marshall too saw citizenship as implicitly egalitarian in relation to the rights and duties attaching to any particular definition. But he also argued that the twentieth century was characterized by the progressive extension of social rights: `the whole range from the right to a modicum of economic welfare and security to the right to share to the full in the social heritage and to live the life of a civilised being according to the standards prevailing in the society'.17 It was this emphasis on social citizenship rights, and the right to share to the full in the social heritage, which made this a useful language for egalitarians for it implied, as Marshall said, greater economic equality. On the other hand, he also observed that the move towards greater equality would be limited by the tension between the principle of social justice and the operation of the market. Moreover, citizenship could operate to legitimate inequalities, provided that they did not transgress equality of opportunity, did not cut too deep, and occurred `within a population united in a single civilisation'.18 Marshall's framework was not adopted uncritically. He had addressed inequalities of class, but not those consequent on ethnicity and gender. Some argued that the concept of citizenship needed radical overhaul to avoid the problem of assimilating women to an essentially male model of the citizen.19 Nevertheless, it formed the basis of an egalitarian, redistributive, broad understanding of social exclusion, inclusion and citizenship. Although social exclusion was, at the extreme, the product of poverty, citizenship was fundamentally affected by inequality. Lister's statement sums up the standpoint: It is not possible to divorce the rights and responsibilities which are supposed to unite citizens from the inequalities of power and resources that divide them. These inequalities ± particularly of class, race and gender ± run like fault-lines through our society and shape the contours of citizenship in the civil, political and social spheres. Poverty spells exclusion from the full rights of citizenship in each of these spheres and undermines people's ability to fulfil the private and public obligations of citizenship.20 Between 1979 and 1997, the social-democratic redistributive agenda was recast in this new language of exclusion and citizenship. Social exclusion was more clearly understood as a dynamic process, and a multi-faceted one, than poverty had generally been, and questions of gender and ethnicity had much higher profile; not only poverty, but the whole gamut of social inequalities were brought into the frame. Used in this discourse, RED, social exclusion mobilizes more than the Three Discourses of Social Exclusion 13 concern with outcast poverty from which it started. It addresses the exclusionary processes in all areas of society which result in inequality itself. The characteristics of RED can be summarized as follows: . It emphasizes poverty as a prime cause of social exclusion. . It implies a reduction of poverty through increases in benefit levels. . It is potentially able to valorize unpaid work. . In positing citizenship as the obverse of exclusion, it goes beyond a minimalist model of inclusion. . In addressing social, political and cultural, as well as economic, citizenship, it broadens out into a critique of inequality, which includes, but is not limited to, material inequality. . It focuses on the processes which produce that inequality. . It implies a radical reduction of inequalities, and a redistribution of resources and of power. If Labour's understanding of social exclusion were consistent with RED, it would imply moving towards a more radically redistributive programme than that set out in the 1997 manifesto. However, other discourses, with different implications, are available. MUD: THE UNDERCLASS AND THE CULTURE OF DEPENDENCY The evolution of RED took place in a political context where social citizenship rights were under continued attack from the New Right. Unemployment and the numbers in poverty soared in the early 1980s to levels unprecedented in the post-war years, and social security spending rose with them. The government's response was to tighten eligibility for benefits and reduce their value, deny the existence of poverty, suppress and abolish some of the key indicators of its extent, and blame the poor for their own situation. References to the `underclass' and to a `culture of dependency' became embedded in a discourse concerned with social order and moral integration. The New Right of the 1980s is now widely misunderstood as an exclusively neo-liberal project, aimed at the deregulation of the market and the reduction of state intervention. It was, however, made up of two apparently contradictory, but actually symbiotic, strands of neoliberalism and neo-conservatism. Neo-liberal economics underpinned widespread privatization, and justified growing inequalities in the The Inclusive Society14 name of incentives. But neo-conservatism, which developed alongside neo-liberalism, was concerned with order rather than freedom, with family, nation and morality ± and held no brief for a minimal state. This was not the last gasp of old conservatism struggling to survive. The `free' economy needed a strong state to impose and uphold the conditions of its operations, especially in the restrictions on trade union resistance. The state also had to police the effects ± most notably in the 1984±5 miners' strike, protests over the poll tax, and urban unrest, but also on a more routine basis. The strong state in turn relied on the market ± and especially the ever-present threat of unemployment ± as a potent source of social discipline.21 This dual character of the New Right is important to understanding the political realignments of the 1990s. It is also fundamental to understanding the discourses about poverty which RED was intended to rebut. Those reliant on benefit were always separated into the deserving and the undeserving poor ± those who really needed help and those who were scroungers exploiting an overgenerous and insufficiently-policed system. At least for the deserving poor, benefits were generally seen as good for the individual recipients, if expensive for society as a whole. Echoing arguments from the United States, this changed. Economic dependence on `welfare' was construed as `dependency', a pathological moral and psychological condition created by the benefit system itself ± and fostered by the libertarianism of the 1960s ± in which the state was seen as a universal provider, sapping personal initiative, independence and self-respect. Benefits were bad for, rather than good for, their recipients. If this was true of individuals, it was even more true of the poor collectively: welfare spending gave rise to a `culture of dependency'. This discourse inexorably took over the public domain. In a television documentary about poverty and unemployment, the political commentator John Cole described the `giro culture' as `an endemic culture of no work and reliance on benefits', characterized by a `downward spiral of idleness, crime and erosion of the work ethic'.22 The focus had shifted from the structural basis of poverty to the moral and cultural character of the poor themselves. The idea of an `underclass' was central to this shift. Townsend had himself used the term without any critical connotation to refer to different groups of the excluded poor: the elderly, disabled, chronically sick, long-term unemployed and one-parent families. A large, and proportionately increasing, section of the population are neither part of the paid workforce nor members of the households Three Discourses of Social Exclusion 15 of that workforce . . . The ways in which they have been denied access to paid employment, conceded incomes equivalent in value to bare subsistence, attracted specially defined low status as minority groups, and accommodated, as a result, within the social structure as a kind of modern `underclass', need to be traced.23 This was a statement about the place of the poor in ± and notably not outside ± the overall social structure. It was free from claims about the lifestyles of the poor, and free from moral condemnation, except for the social processes which generated poverty. In 1990, Frank Field's Losing Out: The Emergence of Britain's Underclass argued that the extension of citizenship rights heralded by Marshall had been reversed by the effects of Thatcherism, particularly by exclusion from work and increased reliance on means-tested benefits. Exclusion from citizenship was the mark of the underclass, which would not disappear without `the implementation of a series of policies aimed at re-establishing full citizenship'.24 He was critical of the growing tendency both to describe and to explain poverty in cultural terms and thus effectively blame the poor for their circumstances. He used an article by Ralf Dahrendorf as an example. Dahrendorf, like Field, had written about the underclass in terms of exclusion from citizenship: `The existence of an underclass casts doubt on the social contract itself. It means that citizenship has become an exclusive rather than an inclusive status. Some are full citizens, some are not'.25 But he also argued that the underclass was characterized by low educational attainment or functional illiteracy, that incomplete families were the norm rather than the exception, and that it was culturally distinct from the rest of society: It includes a lifestyle of laid-back sloppiness, association in changing groups and gangs, congregation around discos or the like, hostility to middle-class society, particular habits of dress, hairstyle, often drugs or at least alcohol ± a style, in other words which has little in common with the values of the work society around.26 Field was at pains to emphasize the structural, rather than cultural, factors leading to the growth of an underclass. Unlike Dahrendorf, he insisted that the underclass remained committed to work, this being the `cornerstone value of the whole system'; it was `important not to lose sight of the fact that the main aim of this . . . group is to win a place back in society by gaining a job'.27 But he did not deny that they were The Inclusive Society16 behaviourally distinct and a problem for the majority: `the existence of an underclass tends to make our society a less civilised one in which to live', and `it should come as little surprise that some of those who feel they have no stake in `official' society should react in a way that demonstrates their exclusion'.28 However, in discussing the characteristics of a system which tended to trap the poor on benefits, he did express concern about the moral consequences of benefit dependency and the erosion of initiative, and referred to the `personal pathologies of many of the underclass, and the culture induced by poverty'.29 Over the following years, Field moved to a much clearer view that state provision created dependency and eroded incentives to work and to save.30 The characterization of the underclass in cultural terms was consolidated by the intervention of the American commentator, Charles Murray. Murray's tract, The Emerging British Underclass was published both in the Sunday Times, which financed his visit to Britain in 1989, and by the right-wing think-tank, the Institute of Economic Affairs (IEA). He argued that an underclass had long existed in the United States, and was now developing in Britain. He described himself as `a visitor from a plague area come to see if the disease is spreading'. He asked `how contagious is the disease?'; `is it going to spread indefinitely or is it self-containing?'. The `disease' was cultural, spread by `people . . . whose values are contaminating the life of entire neighbourhoods' ± by rejecting both the work ethic and the family ethic which are central to the dominant culture.31 Not all the poor were part of an underclass. Its existence could be diagnosed by three symptoms: `illegitimacy, crime and drop-out from the labour force': and `if illegitimate births are the leading indicator of an underclass and violent crime is a proxy measure of its development, the definitive proof that an underclass has arrived is that large numbers of young, healthy, lowincome males choose not to take jobs'.32 These three factors, Murray argued, interact to produce pathological communities in which the socialization of children ± especially boys ± is inadequate: `communities need families. Communities need fathers'.33 Fathers are necessary as role models to civilize the young; but marriage and family responsibilities are necessary to civilize men, who are, without these constraints, driven to prove their masculinity in destructive ways. The benefit system feeds the growth of the underclass, by making it too easy for lone mothers to rear children, and removing the pressure on single mothers to marry. In a later account, Murray's emphasis shifted even further towards demonizing lone Three Discourses of Social Exclusion 17 parenthood, and he proposed decreasing economic support for lone mothers and their children, while increasing the stigma attaching to them.34 The policy implications were not the extension of citizenship rights, but their greater conditionality, reduction or removal. This is, of course, exactly what happened in the United States. The Personal Responsibility and Work Opportunity Reconciliation Act of August 1996 abolished Aid to Families with Dependent Children (AFDC), replacing it with Temporary Assistance to Needy Families (TANF), in which there was no entitlement to benefits. It devolved welfare provision to individual states, but within a highly prescriptive framework underpinned by replacing federal matching funds with cash-limited block grants. Levels of grant would be cut if states failed to get people off welfare and into work: 25 per cent of all claimants should be in work by October 1997, and 50 per cent by 2002; for twoparent families, the targets were 75 per cent by 1997 and 90 per cent by 1999. For the first time since Roosevelt's New Deal, eligible claimants could be refused benefits if the cash ran out. A limit of five years was imposed on the total length of time a family could receive federal TANF funds. State plans were required to include a provision that if a family received benefit for more than two years, at least one adult in the family would have to participate in workfare-type activity. Discretion to waive this rule was permissible only where there were children under the age of one. States were required to refuse benefits to those refusing work or workfare programmes, and were to be penalized for not meeting target participation rates in work-related activities by TANF claimants. Teenage mothers would be ineligible for TANF unless attending school and living with their parents or guardians ± thus seeking `to discourage single parenthood and illegitimate births by denying entitlement to huge swathes of the US welfare system'.35 Wisconsin was among the states which had pioneered experiments in workfare before the 1996 Act, under waiver of the federal rules. Over the ten years from 1987 to 1997, the number of claimants dropped by 60 per cent. In 1997, the Wisconsin Works or W±2 programme went state-wide. All claimants were now required to work ± in unsubsidized or subsidized employment or in `community service' jobs at below the minimum wage. Lone mothers were required to return to work when their youngest child was twelve weeks old. The Governor of Wisconsin, Tommy Thompson, who pioneered the reforms was questioned as to the morality and Christianity of a policy which separated very young babies from their mothers and led to an increased reliance on soup kitchens and emergency shelters. He replied that paying people not to The Inclusive Society18 work, not to get married and to have more children was unchristian, and encouraged irresponsible behaviour.36 Murray's description of the underclass cast it in cultural and moral terms. In the United States, the so-called underclass is largely black, so the discourse has an additional racial element. This is not so immediately present in Britain, where commentators are often at pains to point out that the victim-villains are poorly qualified white working class young people. But like earlier accounts of dangerous classes lurking at the margins of society,37 including Marx's lumpenproletariat, it is a very clearly gendered picture. The delinquency of young men is directly criminal and anti-social, accompanied by wilful idleness and drug abuse. Young women's delinquency manifests itself in their sexual and reproductive behaviour, the imputed irresponsibility of lone parenthood. The two are connected through the assumption that lone parenting is inadequate parenting, with both forms of delinquency attributed to a failure of socialization, especially into the work ethic and a belief in marriage. By 1992, when John Westergaard took the underclass as the subject of his presidential address to the British Sociological Association, it was clear that there were three different meanings attaching to the term: outcast poverty; the moral turpitude of the poor; and a less specific, rhetorical usage which had become common in the media. Westergaard argued, as Stuart Hall had done five years earlier,38 that the term underclass implied a dichotomous view of society, and served to obscure inequalities among the majority: What the three have in common is, to start with, a postulate of the recent emergence of a significant minority of the population who are trapped, outside and below `society at large' either by cultural depravity or economic deprivation, and an inference, whether expressed or implied, that the divide between this underclass and the great majority is increasingly the most salient and challenging line of division for the future, by contrast with the older divisions of class now said to be in eclipse.39 Westergaard went on to argue that this was exactly why the concept had such appeal. It allowed the recognition of the increasingly obvious persistence of poverty to co-exist with arguments or assumptions about the attrition of class divisions in society as a whole. Critical social policy was more concerned to defend structural interpretations of poverty against cultural accounts which blamed the poor. The term `underclass' became very unpopular because of its Three Discourses of Social Exclusion 19 association with Murray's rhetoric of moral inferiority and social contagion. Despite its capacity to capture the ways in which aspects of poverty compound one another, it was rejected on three grounds: its imprecision; the lack of empirical evidence supporting its cultural claims; and its punitive rather than supportive policy implications.40 Its ambiguity meant that those who used it as a description of the monstrously divisive consequences for the poor of Thatcherite policies unwittingly opened the door to a quite different discourse about the potential consequences of the poor for the comfortable majority, where redistribution gave way to retribution. The idea of the dependency culture, for whose existence there was little evidence,41 also facilitated this switch from structural to cultural interpretations. Its central tenet was that groups of people excluded from society as a whole, and especially when dependent on benefit, would develop a distinctive set of morally undesirable attitudes and behaviours, characterized by various forms of parasitism, crime and immorality. Lister argued that `those who invoke the development of an `underclass' to make the case for the restoration of full citizenship rights to the poor are playing with fire'.42 The contested meaning of the underclass gave way to a strong preference for talking about social exclusion instead: thus in RED, social exclusion is used to actively refuse the moral agenda of the underclass debate. This has had little impact on the popular usage of the term `underclass', especially in the media, where it continues to carry both structural and cultural meanings. Adonis and Pollard defend its use. It `captures the essence of the class predicament for many at the bottom: a complete absence of ladders, whether basic skills, role models, education or a culture of work'.43 It is characterized by `unemployment and unemployability' as well as single motherhood and educational failure. The cultural interpretation wins out: `there is no question that upbringing plays a big and probably growing role in transferring poverty and social inadequacy from one generation to the next'.44 But as social exclusion entered public political discourse, it did so in conjunction with references to the underclass ± with Blair himself repeatedly referring to an underclass excluded from the mainstream. Social exclusion is also an ambiguous term, capable of carrying both structural and cultural meanings. Thus Duffy defines social exclusion as `a broader concept than poverty, encompassing not only low material means but the inability to participate effectively in economic, social, political and cultural life, and in some characterisations, alienation and distance from the mainstream society'.45 Where it is The Inclusive Society20 used in conjunction with the underclass, social exclusion is at risk of co-option into a highly problematic discourse, MUD, whose main characteristics are these: . It presents the underclass or socially excluded as culturally distinct from the `mainstream'. . It focuses on the behaviour of the poor rather than the structure of the whole society. . It implies that benefits are bad, rather than good, for their recipients, and encourage `dependency'. . Inequalities among the rest of society are ignored. . It is a gendered discourse, about idle, criminal young men and single mothers. . Unpaid work is not acknowledged. . Although dependency on the state is regarded as a problem, personal economic dependency ± especially of women and children on men ± is not. Indeed, it is seen as a civilizing influence on men. SID: SOCIAL EXCLUSION, SOCIAL INTEGRATION AND EUROPE The increasing public reference in Britain to social exclusion was not only the result of resistance to the underclass discourse, but the growing importance of the European Union. The origins of the European-wide emphasis on social exclusion lay in France, where the opposite of exclusion was insertion. Silver argues that social exclusion has a specific meaning in the French republican tradition, within a paradigm rooted in both Durkheimian sociology and Catholicism, and concerned with moral integration.46 Exclusion is understood as the breakdown of the structural, cultural and moral ties which bind the individual to society, and family instability is a key concern. French discourses of exclusion, themselves contested, broadened out to a consideration of groups marginalized economically, socially, culturally and, in the case of outer suburbs, spatially; and to the fields of education, employment, housing and health. Although insertion, as the obverse of exclusion, acquired a similarly wide brief, a key measure was the introduction in 1988 of a residual benefit, the RMI (Revenu Minimum d'Insertion), stressing the reciprocal nature of solidarity. Recipients of RMI were required to sign a `contrat d'insertion' ± in many cases focused on employment, but in some involving other forms Three Discourses of Social Exclusion 21 of social participation negotiated with social workers, and addressing aspects of `daily living, behaviour, and family relationships'.47 Silver sees moral integration as the distinctive characteristic of what she calls the `solidarity' paradigm. Her reading of Durkheim, however, understates the extent to which he saw social integration as based in work (see Chapter 9). It also understates how far the moral integration of `solidarity' is focused on work ± with work itself perceived as having social as well as moral and economic functions. Conversely, she neglects the moral element in liberal underclass discourse (her `specialization'), seeing the main source of integration as based in exchange. Spicker argues that although the language surrounding the RMI is more communitarian, the effect is similar to US workfare programmes ± and similarly individualizes the problem of unemployment.48 As a result of its origins within French social policy, the concept of social exclusion at European level became, as Room put it, a curious amalgam of a liberal, Anglo-Saxon concern with poverty and a more conservative, continental concern with moral integration and social order.49 But to suggest that there is a single discourse of social exclusion in Europe would be misleading. The multi-lingual character of the Union necessarily implies a variety of discourses, which will not map precisely on to each other, even when translated from the same documents. However, the differences run deeper than this, leading to a series of overlapping national discourses of exclusion, rather than a pan-European consensus.50 Discursive variation is accompanied by national policy differences, as discourses of exclusion are deployed within distinct political settings ± although these national policies are increasingly oriented to and implicated in contested interpretations of a European framework. This book is not a comparative study of discourses of exclusion or of social policy across Europe, but an examination of a single national case. Its focus is the different discourses around exclusion available to New Labour, and the uses made of them. However, among those resources are the concepts of exclusion embedded in the documents and policy instruments of the European Union itself. The discourse of key European policy papers ± in their English versions ± reveals a much narrower understanding of exclusion than that implied by Silver's `solidarity' model. This can be typified as a social integrationist discourse, SID, which stresses the integrative function of paid work. SID had a wider currency in British political discourse, and by using European documents as illustrative of it, I am not implying that this was the main source of the discourse, as will be clear from Chapters 3 and 4. The Inclusive Society22 SID can be illustrated by the two European Commission White Papers on social and economic policy issued in 1994 ± European Social Policy and Growth, Competitiveness, Employment 51 ± which are widely supposed to epitomize the social, rather than purely economic, concerns of the Union. Despite the language of solidarity, these policy documents emphasize exclusion as exclusion from paid work rather than a broader view of exclusion from social participation, and prescribe integration through paid work. The terms cohesion, solidarity, integration and exclusion recur. The core concerns of both documents are economic efficiency and social cohesion: `we are faced with the immense responsibility . . . of finding a new synthesis of the aims pursued by society (work as a factor of social integration, equality of opportunity) and the requirements of the economy (competitiveness and job creation)'.52 The economic discussion is couched in terms of efficiency, deregulation, and the need for economic growth, while the `social' discourse counterposes solidarity, integration and cohesion to unemployment, poverty and social exclusion. Sometimes exclusion is identified with poverty: `with more than 52 million people in the Union living below the poverty line, social exclusion is an endemic phenomenon';53 while the need for economic and social cohesion calls for `solidarity . . . in the fight against social exclusion', to combat the `poverty . . . which splits society in two'.54 The processes of exclusion are described as `dynamic and multi-dimensional', and linked `not only to unemployment and/or low incomes, but also to housing conditions, levels of education and opportunities, health, discrimination, citizenship and integration in the local community'.55 Yet although this list might appear to echo the factors identified in RED, it is notable that the terms social exclusion and exclusion from paid work are used virtually interchangeably, while a similar elision occurs between `people' and `workers'. A section headed `the free movement of persons' goes on to discuss only the `free movement of workers'. `Promoting the Social Integration of Disabled People' discusses only training and assistance to enter the labour market. On the `key issue of improved access to means of transport and public buildings', the Commission will `press for the adoption of the proposed Directive on the travel conditions of workers with motor disabilities' (emphasis added).56 Since Growth, Competitiveness, Employment starts from a concern with unemployment, its focus on paid work is unsurprising. Few, in any case, would dispute that unemployment is a contributory factor to social exclusion, and work a factor in social integration. This, however, is not the same as treating them as synonymous ± a slippage which Three Discourses of Social Exclusion 23 makes difficult the exploration of their empirical connection. The assumption that social integration and participation in paid work are coterminous is particularly clear in a discussion of education and skills: `The basic skills which are essential for integration into society and working life include a mastery of basic knowledge (linguistic, scientific and other knowledge), and skills of a highly technical and social nature, that is the ability to develop and act in a complex and highly technological environment, characterized, in particular, by the importance of information technologies' (emphasis added).57 The emphasis on the importance of information technology skills is probably exaggerated even in terms of the skills needed for employment, but as a description of the skills needed for integration into society, it is an odd list. Growth, Competitiveness, Employment treats the absence of these skills as the cause of social exclusion ± or what European Social Policy calls exclusion `from the cycle of opportunities': `The failure of education . . . is an increasingly important and increasingly widespread factor of marginalisation and economic and social exclusion. In the Community, 25 to 30% of young people . . . leave the education system without the preparation they need to become properly integrated into working life'.58 Working life means paid employment. Unpaid work makes only a brief appearance in these documents, and then with a view to bringing it into the market sector to create more jobs. In ruling out ab initio the possibility of `a generalized reduction in working hours and job sharing' as economically inefficient, the economic White Paper says we need to `think up new individual or collective needs which would provide new job opportunities'.59 It proposes meeting old needs in new ways. `Women's full integration in the labour market is expected to create jobs in the provision of services and goods not yet integrated into the market and currently being provided by either women's unpaid labour or paid informal women's labour'. Improving existing career opportunities for women will itself generate additional demand for child care. Where jobs are not created spontaneously, member states are exhorted to `encourage growth in the employment intensive area of the care sector and of the provision of household services', and thus to `enhance the perceived value, and therefore encourage increased skills in such sectors'.60 The assumptions about skill and value embedded here include the view that unpaid work is unskilled. Greater recognition of unpaid work other than through market mechanisms is ruled out. The extent of unpaid work, its necessity to the maintenance of social life and human relationships, and the limits The Inclusive Society24 to potential marketization are underestimated, and the problems of low pay and gender segregation in the labour market ignored.61 In these documents, markets are not seen as benign. Markets have failings, produce unacceptable inequalities and embody short-termism, and thus require regulation, or at least management: `only a properly managed interdependence can guarantee a positive outcome for everybody', and `collective solidarity mechanisms' are essential to counter adverse effects.62 This could be a prescription for a redistributive welfare state, which might therefore acknowledge and reward unpaid work, but it is not. The cost of welfare provision is seen as excessive: `current levels of public expenditure, particularly in the social field, have become unsustainable and have used up resources which could have been channelled into productive investment'.63 `Solidarity' is a device for reducing the costs of social provision, not for redistribution. The forms of solidarity invoked are manifold: between those who have jobs and those who do not; between generations; between regions; between `those who earn their income from work and those who earn their income from investments'; and between men and women, `making it easier to reconcile family life and working life'. Notably, solidarity is not just a policy issue for member states, but a matter for individuals: it is `the business of each citizen to practice ``neighbourly solidarity'' '.64 Hutton described Growth, Competitiveness, Employment as the last gasp of social Europe before it was suffocated by the monetarist criteria agreed as the foundation of monetary union. But the tension between `monetarist' and `social' Europe, and the dominance of the former, are already apparent in the document itself. Further movement in that direction followed, as austerity measures were brought in by governments across Europe anxious to qualify for entry into the single currency ± in many states provoking social unrest in response to cuts in welfare rights. The emphasis on paid work is endemic in the financial and legal framework of the Union. As the term social exclusion gained currency in Europe, currency, in the form of European funding, attached to projects to combat it. But the rules governing the use of the Community's Structural Funds reinforce the understanding of social participation as labour market activity. The Social Fund, the main source of cash to combat exclusion, may only properly be used to fund measures directly related to the labour market, either through integration of marginal groups into it or through the promotion of equal opportunities. In practice, since funding goes to projects proposed by member states on the basis of additionality, many projects concerned with the Three Discourses of Social Exclusion 25 welfare of marginal groups which are ostensibly directed to improving their labour market integration appear to have a wider brief. The legal definition of citizenship within Europe is also biased towards paid work. Louise Ackers argues that the general emphasis on `workers' rather than `people' in European law produces a stratified system of citizenship in Europe.65 Although the Maastricht Treaty declares nationals of all member states to be European citizens with the right to move and reside freely within the Union, this right does not confer equal access to social rights and benefits in the country of residence. Whereas paid workers, self-employed people and those exercizing their right to remain after ending paid employment have full social rights in their country of residence, members of their families have only derivative rights. This applies, of course, to women engaged in unpaid caring ± for children or adults ± who therefore do not have the same rights as paid workers. If family members and dependants can acquire social citizenship rights by proxy, non-employed persons not attached to a worker ± students, disabled adults, retired people, for example ± do not acquire them at all. Their right to move and reside freely within the Union is limited by the condition that they do not become a charge on the public purse of the host country. The essential point is that the emphasis on paid work as the primary means of social integration and the privileging of paid work over unpaid work has significant and gendered repercussions for citizenship status itself. A discourse about social exclusion which focuses on integration through paid work tends to reduce the social to the economic, and simultaneously limits understanding of economic activity to market activity. If inclusion tends to shift the agenda away from equality, the focus on inclusion through paid work exacerbates this. SID thus has a number of features which distinguish it from RED and MUD: . It narrows the definition of social exclusion/inclusion to participation in paid work. . It squeezes out the question of why people who are not employed are consigned to poverty. Consequently, it does not, like RED, imply a reduction of poverty by an increase in benefit levels. . It obscures the inequalities between paid workers. . Since women are paid significantly less than men, and are far more likely to be in low-paid jobs, it obscures gender, as well as class, inequalities in the labour market. . It erases from view the inequality between those owning the bulk of productive property and the working population. The Inclusive Society26 . It is unable to address adequately the question of unpaid work in society. . Because it ignores unpaid work and its gendered distribution, it implies an increase in women's total workload. . It undermines the legitimacy of non-participation in paid work. RED, SID and MUD are presented here as distinct discourses. They are, of course, ideal types. All of them posit paid work as a major factor in social integration; and all of them have a moral content. But they differ in what the excluded are seen as lacking. To oversimplify, in RED they have no money, in SID they have no work, in MUD they have no morals. In terms of Walker's broad definition of social exclusion as exclusion from social, economic, political or cultural systems, the discourses emphasize different elements ± and posit different causal relationships between them. Thus both SID and MUD are narrower than RED, with SID reducing the social to the economic and substantially ignoring the political and cultural. MUD, on the other hand, emphasizes the cultural, with the economic deriving from this, while the social and political are sidelined. In reality, although there are examples which conform very closely to a particular model, much public discourse slides between them. That, indeed, is one of the reasons why a concept like social exclusion is so powerful. Not only does the multiplicity of meanings which attach to it give it wide acceptance, but it operates as a shifter between the different discourses. Like the `underclass', `social exclusion' can, almost unnoticed, mobilize a redistributive argument behind a cultural or integrationist one ± or represent cultural or integrationist arguments as redistributive. But there are also major differences between the discourses in their capacity to recognize, let alone valorize, unpaid work. Part of the point of Glucksmann's model of the total social organization of labour is that work, or economic activity, occurs not only within the market in the conventionally-defined economic sphere, but also outside it. To understand the shifting forms of work and the relationships within which they are embedded, the analysis cannot begin from a standpoint which privileges one particular form or site of work. Many of the problems with which politicians and policy makers now grapple can be seen in terms of the breakdown of a historical organization of labour in which men had primary responsibility for paid work and women primary responsibility for unpaid domestic work, albeit often combining this with some paid employment. SID barely acknowledges non-market work at all, or treats it as a residual form. The unpaid Three Discourses of Social Exclusion 27 work of child care, for example, is either to be drawn into the market, or squeezed into the spaces around paid employment. Unpaid work is addressed solely from the standpoint of the market. This is slightly less true of MUD, which, while deploying the idea of `dependency' in its refusal to valorize unpaid work, simultaneously complains of the consequences of inadequate parenting. Yet this contradiction is itself masked by the fact that parenting is not understood as work. In general, the emphasis on paid work as a vehicle of inclusion, and the construction of exclusion as non-employment, inherently privileges market activity: it does not address either work, or social integration, in terms of the total social organization of labour. In the following chapters, I shall argue that the developing discourse of New Labour shifted it significantly away from RED towards an inconsistent combination of SID and MUD. The impossibility of adequately acknowledging unpaid labour from this standpoint produces deep contradictions between different elements of policy, most especially between the rediscovery of community and the attempt to draw everyone into paid work through the New Deal or welfare to work programmes. This contradiction can be resolved only by a rightward shift to a reformulation of the Thatcherite free economy-strong state dyad in terms of community, or by a leftward shift towards a RED agenda. A central political question for Labour's first term in office will be how it negotiates between the different available discourses of social exclusion, and how, especially through the Social Exclusion Unit, it translates them into policy. Their performance will be judged not only on whether they deliver `social inclusion', but what kind of inclusion they deliver, for whom, and on what terms. The following chapters outline the emergence of the new political discourse, and their implications for delivering inclusion. The Inclusive Society28 8 Delivering Social Inclusion How far will Labour succeed in delivering social inclusion? Blair would prefer this question deferred for ten years, but at least a provisional assessment will be needed before the election in 2001 or 2002. As the policies are put in place, it is possible to ask what kind of inclusion Labour seeks to deliver, what the criteria of success would be, and how likely it is that the policies will achieve this. None of the discourses has a well-developed set of indicators of social exclusion, partly because the centrality of the term in British politics is so new ± and partly because to clarify the definition would undermine the very flexibility of the concept which makes it politically useful. Because the meaning and imputed causes of exclusion differ in RED, SID and MUD, so too will some of the indicators of success in producing greater inclusion. The prospects for inclusion depend on which discourse you are situated in. Both provisional and later assessments can be made in Labour's own terms, and against other understandings of social exclusion and other criteria. Success in combating exclusion will be as contested as the concept itself. The most obvious critical yardsticks are those implied by RED, and the main part of this chapter considers the prospects for welfare to work and the Social Exclusion Unit from the different standpoints of RED, SID and MUD. Questions are also raised about the nature of the `social' in social inclusion, and about unpaid work, transport, participation in common institutions and political inclusion ± and the contradictions and tensions between aspects of inclusion. WELFARE TO WORK: THE VIEW FROM SID There are aspects of both welfare to work and the remit of the Social Exclusion Unit which are consistent with RED, SID and MUD. The welfare to work programme has widespread support. For RED, involuntary unemployment is one important cause of poverty; for SID, work in itself delivers inclusion; for MUD, work is a moral necessity to counter dependence. In the broadest sense, all would interpret the programme as successful if it: reduces the number of people dependent on benefit; moves the people concerned into socially useful paid employment which delivers self-esteem, social relationships and a 159 R. Levitas, The Inclusive Society? © Ruth Levitas 2005 reasonable standard of living; provides high quality, affordable care for their children; reduces poverty; reduces social security spending, thus releasing more money to be spent on health and education; and does so without coercion. Pigs might fly. The difference between the discourses lies in the priority given to these various aims. From the perspective of SID, the most important indicators of success would be a rise in labour force participation rates, especially for the target groups of young people, lone parents and people with disabilities; and a drop in the number of workless households among those of working age. Falling registered unemployment is not an adequate measure of the success of the New Deal, since it excludes those forced off the register and a range of people deemed economically inactive. In 1997, the unemployment figures fell sharply, and there were no longer 250 000 young people eligible for the New Deal, but roughly half that number. This was partly due to the effect on the count of the Jobseeker's Allowance, but also to a real drop in youth unemployment. A rise in unemployment was forecast for 1998 as the New Deal came into effect. The test of rising participation rates avoids the measurement problems associated with unemployment, but it is complicated by how far any change can be attributed to the welfare to work programme itself. Evaluating changes against a background of changing economic conditions is not so easy. There is a further complication to relying on unemployment rates as an indicator of exclusion. Unemployment rates are higher in France and Germany, and Labour, like the Conservatives, attributes Britain's lower recorded unemployment ± and that in the USA ± to the greater flexibility of the economy. But the USA has a much higher proportion of its male population in prison. If incarceration rates and unemployment rates are taken together, the difference between Europe and the United States lies principally in the proportion of young (predominantly black) men in jail.1 While levels of imprisonment in Britain are not comparable with those in the US, they are high by European Standards. This has implications for benefit budgets. The proportion of GDP spent on social security in the UK, as in the USA, is relatively low compared to France and Germany, but the costs of social security payments for the unemployed must be balanced against the greater costs of incarceration. While unemployment is the key form of social exclusion for SID, the greater social exclusion of imprisonment is neglected. Rising participation rates are more important to SID than the numbers passing through the programmes who find some form of The Inclusive Society160 work. Before the pilot schemes for lone parents and their evaluation were completed, Harman vaunted their success in terms of the percentage of participants moving into employment. These early figures were disputed because they related to those taking up the offer of an interview, not those approached or eligible. It was also suggested that these were the very women who would have taken employment without help. Some of those moving into work under the New Deal would do so anyway. Simply looking at outcomes for participants in welfare to work ignores two further problems: substitution and churning. Participants may be given a competitive advantage, so that they get jobs at the expense of others in the labour market, for example privileging the young unemployed at the expense of older workers. This substitution effect is a particular problem with subsidised employment. As Hutton said, the programmes may also result in only temporary and short-term work placements, and a churning in and out of employment. Increased labour force participation rates indicate the success of the programmes over and above substitution, churning, or existing levels of movement into work. The likely success of welfare to work in SID's terms is ± and will remain ± disputable. Its supply-side assumptions may undermine it. There is no consensus about how far unemployment is a problem of employability, and how far it is caused by a lack of demand for labour. Although the lead indicator for SID is labour market attachment, and this has priority over the quality and pay of jobs, SID differs from MUD on the issue of compulsion. The emphasis on the positive utility of work means compulsion should not be necessary; the emphasis on work as a route to self-esteem makes compulsion, especially in the shape of thinly-disguised workfare schemes, counter-productive. It is therefore important whether the New Deal results in people moving into real jobs, rather than being forced into make-work schemes for benefit, or even `benefit plus'. The quality of the scheme, and therefore of the work, is not irrelevant. Without investment to provide real jobs, improved training and skills may simply equip individuals for a competitive struggle for employment in which some must lose. The initial response of the private sector to pleas to provide opportunities for young people under the New Deal was disappointing, even with the subsidies offered. This is partly because employers do not want unwilling conscripts as workers, but it does not bode well for the expansion of jobs when the subsidies run out. One suggestion has been that local authorities might compensate for this shortfall. In a roundabout way, the local state Delivering Social Inclusion 161 would thus become the employer of last resort, in a return to limited Keynesian demand management ± a solution compatible with SID, but one which will cost money. But SID emphasizes carrots, not sticks. Within SID, the prime concern is not saving money: increased expenditure on in-work benefits, on child care, on training, and even on job creation might be wholly legitimate in promoting inclusion through work. WELFARE TO WORK: THE VIEW FROM MUD From within MUD, the central criterion of success is the reduction in the numbers of people of working age wholly dependent on benefit. A drop in the number of workless households is important. Since the central element in MUD is the moral necessity of work, neither the level of pay nor the quality of the work is important. Coercion is legitimate ± even justified as tough love. MUD may appear to be directed primarily at reducing public spending, but the discourse and the policies are ambiguous in this respect. Labour's welfare to work policies as originally floated in the Borrie report owed much to the Australian Working Nation programme,2 and especially to the JET (Jobs, Education, Training) scheme for lone mothers. Both the rhetoric, in the use of the term welfare and the phrase New Deal, and the substantive policies, moved closer to an American model. In office, Labour showed increasing interest in Wisconsin Works or W±2, and in September 1997 Jean Rogers, the W±2 administrator, attended the post-election conference at the London School of Economics on `How Labour can Deliver'. Experience in both Australia and Wisconsin showed that the provision of child care to enable lone parents to work is expensive. This is so even before posing serious questions about the quality of child care, whether parents or children suffer as a result, or the pay and conditions of the carers. MUD has other features. Work is also a prophylactic against crime. For the young unemployed, it is a means of social discipline ± or, as Labour put it, `our policy against crime is jobs'. It is important both for workers and for their children, who need to be set an example, and to learn the work ethic ± not at their parent's knee, but through separation from it. Those same children, especially in lone-parent families, are seen as in need of parental supervision to curb their criminal tendencies. This points either to an irresolvable contradiction between The Inclusive Society162 welfare to work and the agenda of social order ± or to Murray's agenda, of attempting to make lone parenthood as difficult as possible to enforce moral conformity. Success, for MUD, would mean not just a decrease in benefit dependency, but a decrease in crime and in lone parenthood, all perceived as indissolubly linked. WELFARE TO WORK: THE VIEW FROM RED For RED, the most pressing question is the effect on the lives of the excluded. The central indicator of success or failure in tackling social exclusion is the prevalence of poverty, and whether there is both absolute and relative improvement in the living standards of the poor. The availability of information to monitor these changes was undermined by changes to the statistical base during the Thatcher years; restoration and improvement is needed.3 The question will not just be whether more people are in paid work, but whether those in and out of employment, above and below working age, are better or worse off. The reduction of involuntary unemployment is one element in this. As for SID, the emphasis is on the benefits of paid work, financial and otherwise. The quality of work matters. Coercion is generally rejected because benefit penalties may be unjustly applied, and themselves cause greater poverty and exclusion ± as well as potentially undermining the New Deal by turning it effectively into a workfare programme. Compulsion is viewed as unnecessary in almost all cases if there is reasonable, reasonably paid work available, and pointless or worse if there is not. RED, like SID, sees exclusion from paid work as a form of and a factor in social exclusion. But increased rates of labour market participation will be an indicator of success only if they result in a reduction in poverty. The level of the minimum wage is crucial to RED. And whatever the success of welfare to work, it will not improve the situation of those who remain dependent on benefits or state pensions. Moreover, because RED recognizes parenting as unpaid work, lone parents dependent on benefit are not viewed as not working. The implication is an increase in benefits to relieve poverty, rather than an across the board cut or the introduction of coercion into the New Deal to force them into paid employment. For RED, welfare to work can be at best a partial solution to the problem of social exclu- sion. Delivering Social Inclusion 163 DELIVERING SOCIAL INCLUSION: THE SOCIAL EXCLUSION UNIT One of the first tasks set for the Unit in its first six months was the development of indicators of exclusion. In one sense, this will make assessment of the success of the Unit in the Government's own terms relatively straightforward. But as in the case of welfare to work, different indicators will be preferred or prioritized from the standpoint of the different discourses. Perri 6, writing for Demos, says social exclusion `can best be measured by looking at how many people are cut off from work, learning and other forms of social participation' ± the priorities of SID ± and goes on to suggest as indicators measures of both the causal processes and the condition of social exclusion. The former include `mobility, promotion and redundancy, social stratification and limited social mobility, educational failure or family breakdown'; the latter `worklessness and unemployment, homelessness, lack of membership of voluntary organisations, denial of services, isolation or lack of effective social contacts, lack of a car or a telephone'.4 It is notable that poverty does not appear as an indicator of either the cause or condition of exclusion. For RED, income data is a proxy indicator, though not a measure, of the wider multi-faceted process of exclusion. Although poverty is a prime cause of social exclusion, the two are not synonymous. Improving the material living standards of the poor is a necessary but insufficient condition for combating exclusion. The Social Exclusion Unit also sees exclusion as a complex and multi-dimensional problem. Its concern with multiple deprivation, homelessness, joblessness, and the concentration of these in areas which also suffer from high levels of crime is not immediately different from RED, and the pursuit of a co-ordinated approach to these is wholly consistent with it. To some extent, the indicators will overlap. But whether the perceived causes and thus proposed solutions coincide is another matter. In MUD, if exclusion is the result of poverty, poverty itself is largely attributed to a failure of employability ± which, given the responsibility of individuals for their own employability, is in large part a moral problem. If MUD says `the poor are different from us', RED says `yes; they have less money'. The obvious difference is that RED implies improved levels of benefits, while MUD does not. Government policy rules out additional expenditure in this form, so that for RED, as Lister said, the Social Exclusion Unit tackles exclusion with one hand tied behind its back. The Inclusive Society164 In some instances, the relationship between the two approaches is as straightforward as Lister suggests. For example, the Unit is concerned about the exclusion of sectors of society from financial services. Residents in some areas may be unable to open bank accounts, obtain credit cards, or obtain credit because of their postcode. Poorer people pay more for credit ± especially from loan sharks. Competitive strategies in the privatized utilities discriminate against poorer customers. Potential future work for the Unit includes looking at `options for improving access to services, public and private, for low income individuals or areas'. These issues may be addressed through pressure on utilities and financial institutions to alter their practice, and through encouraging credit unions ± non profit-making self-help groups which foster saving and provide small loans. There is nothing here that would conflict with a RED agenda; Child Poverty Action Group has long documented the fact that the poor pay more for most goods and services. There is, simply, a gap: one aspect of financial exclusion is that the poor have less money, and inadequate income is an important factor in debt. In other respects, the RED approach and that of the Social Exclusion Unit differ rather more. The range of goals may largely coincide, but the priority given to them is different; and since the perceived causes of exclusion are different, so too are the means of reaching those goals. If RED emphasizes social and economic inclusion, and understands poverty in material and structural terms, MUD emphasizes moral inclusion, and understands poverty as primarily cultural in origin. Explanations of poverty as a cultural problem lead all too easily into policies to control the poor. The more the thinking behind the Unit is consistent with MUD, the more the policies for achieving inclusion are likely to be ambiguous from the standpoint of RED. The most obvious example of this is the focus on social order. In terms of its initial priorities, the reduction in crime and disorder particularly on the targeted estates would be a key indicator of the Social Exclusion Unit's success ± although the measurement of crime is fraught with difficulty, and the measurement of disorder even more so. When Jack Straw was asked by Jonathan Dimbleby on 28 September 1997 what changes would take place during Labour's first term of office, he replied that communities would be safer ± but that the Government also aimed to change the norms and values of a generation, and to establish that parenting is not a purely private matter in which next door neighbours have no say. Some of the policies for delivering these outcomes rely not only on repression, but forms of repression Delivering Social Inclusion 165 which are themselves directly exclusionary ± an increased use of exclusion orders against individuals, curfews which exclude young people from public spaces, and eviction orders. As the Social Exclusion Unit started work, it was reported that there were `nearly 10 000 people . . . on the council's exclusions list for anti-social behaviour' in Manchester alone.5 A general increase in the use of eviction orders is anticipated. It may even be necessary ± but it is important to recognize that the inclusion of some is predicated on the further exclusion of others. If the control of crime and disorder leads to more prison sentences, this too represents an increase in social exclusion. The 1997 Crime and Disorder Bill makes provision for `anti-social behaviour orders' which may be sought by local councils or by the police for any person aged ten or over who has acted `in a manner that caused or was likely to cause harassment, alarm or distress to two or more persons not of the same household as himself'. The orders may contain those prohibitions `necessary for protecting persons in the local government area from further anti-social acts by the defendant'. Breaches of the order carry penalties of up to five years imprisonment. The problem lies in the catch-all formula, which does not rest on any specific offence being committed ± and does not even require that alarm and distress be reasonable responses to the behaviour in question. The early priority given to tackling truancy is again ambiguous. Although the remit of the Social Exclusion Unit referred also to exclusions from school, it was truancy which Blair stressed at the Unit's launch. In a police report to the Unit, children aged between 10 and 16 were said to be responsible for 40 per cent of all street robberies, 33 per cent of car thefts and 30 per cent of house break-ins in London, mostly during school hours. The link between truancy and crime seemed clear ± although it does not follow that most children illicitly absent from school or even most persistent truants are engaged in crime, or that they should be publicly regarded as actual or potential offenders. Other research presented to the Unit referred to the low educational achievement of young offenders, and suggested that persistent truanting was the result of poor educational attainment (mainly by boys) rather than its primary cause. Again, an improvement in educational achievement, a reduction in persistent truanting, and a reduction in crime would all be regarded as good outcomes by RED, SID and MUD. But the connections posited between them, and the policies for addressing them differ. The link long made by RED between unemployment and crime, a social and structural problem, becomes in MUD a link between unemployability and crime, a problem The Inclusive Society166 of individual behaviour. In MUD, `tough on crime, tough on the causes of crime' points to truancy and poor parental supervision as the `causes'; in RED, the emphasis is on poverty and its role in educational underachievement. The danger is not just that one hand is tied behind the Unit's back, but that repression will substitute for inclusion. The attraction for MUD of focusing on truancy is that parental responsibility can be invoked as a solution. The Crime and Disorder Bill, consistent with pre-election policy, provides for the use of parenting orders. These would apply to the parents of convicted young offenders, and to the parents of children or young people subject to child safety orders, antisocial behaviour orders, or who do not regularly attend school. They may require parents to attend weekly counselling sessions for up to three months, and to comply with other specified requirements for up to a year. Jack Straw elaborated likely requirements as being home at specified times to supervise their child and accompanying that child to school. Breaches of the order will be punishable by a substantial fine. It is not clear whether the orders will be made against the parents severally or jointly, and who will be liable for the fine, especially where parents are not married and are thus not legally liable for each other's debts. The potential conflict between meeting the requirements of a parenting order and earning a living is implicit in the suggestion that the stipulations should `as far as practicable' not interfere with times when the parent normally works. Where truanting is the problem, the children who cause most concern are those of secondary school age ± the age group where there is growing pressure within New Labour that lone parents should be compelled to seek paid employment. A suggestion that the Foyer movement be extended to single mothers is also ambiguous. Pioneered in France and developed in Britain since 1992, Foyers provide hostel accommodation for homeless young people, with help and advice to enable them to move into more permanent accommodation and training or work. They are entirely voluntary, although residents are required to keep house rules. Their encouragement by the Social Exclusion Unit would be appropriate from RED, SID and MUD ± in RED's case, especially if supported by additional funds, and a benefit system which facilitated a move on from Foyer life. But the suggestion that `young mothers would be encouraged to move into . . . hostels with their babies, and would get advice on training, access to creches and support workers, including health care visitors to monitor their children' does not seem quite in the Foyer spirit.6 There may be some young women for whom such Delivering Social Inclusion 167 facilities would be welcome and wholly appropriate, offering practical and social support not available elsewhere; some units already exist. As a policy for inclusion, it is double edged. Encouraging young single mothers into institutions ± having reduced the benefits available to them ± marks them out as a group, and is potentially exclusionary. And it rests on a presumption of moral exclusion. MUD sees single parenthood as a form of delinquency, and as a `parenting danger zone' in need of early intervention. The provision of suitable services, including housing, in a non-institutional manner is not only more expensive, but offers less possibility of social control. `SOCIAL' INCLUSION The wide brief of the Social Exclusion Unit makes its success more difficult to define than that of the welfare to work scheme. More, the potential breadth of the idea of social exclusion itself means that a very wide range of policies may bear on the delivery of inclusion. In RED, the question of social participation, not just participation in work, is central. Exclusion is exclusion from participation ± in economic, political, social or cultural systems. However the understanding of the `social' in social inclusion is under-developed. Demos addresses this in terms of networks and social capital. Social capital refers to `the quality of contacts people have and networks they plug into, and the norms of trust, reciprocity and goodwill, sense of shared life across the classes, and capacities to organise that these ties afford'; or more simply to `those relationships which provide people with a sense of trust and community'.7 The potential fruitfulness of this is undermined by the treatment of social networks as means to ends ± either of work or of social control. Thus for individuals, network poverty means lack of access to the kinds of contacts helpful in finding employment.8 For society, networks are important because `an organized citizenry can alleviate many social problems and ease the implementation of various kinds of public policy, for instance by using neighbourhood watch groups to minimise crime. As a result, nations as a whole lose a resource when the ties between individuals erode'.9 Discussions of social exclusion in contemporary political discourses do not collapse the social into the economic, although economic inclusion is paramount. There is recurrent reference in stakeholding and communitarian literature to the importance of intermediate The Inclusive Society168 institutions and to civil society ± those places where people live their lives beyond the workplace. But there is a disturbing tendency for civil society and the community to be reduced to an arena of unpaid work, a means of mopping up problems created by the market or a mediator of social discipline. Social inclusion, social networks, and sociability as ends in themselves scarcely figure: the meaning of the social needs clarification and elaboration. The presumption shared by RED, SID and MUD is that inclusion in paid work leads to greater social inclusion ± in the case of RED, provided that it also reduces poverty. There is little attention paid to the ways in which paid work may impede inclusion. Although Hutton indirectly acknowledges this where people work very long hours, and the problem of `juggling' is a constant issue in relation to women's employment, the downside of paid work is not thought of in terms of social exclusion. Yet not being able to collect young children from school affects participation in the social networks that develop around the school and in the neighbourhood as well as the relationship between parent and child. Paid work leaves less time for many other activities. The same may be true of unpaid work. UNPAID WORK The contradiction between welfare to work and parenting in Labour's policies can hardly be overstressed. It arises from thinking about parenting as a responsibility, rather than something which involves work which is currently unpaid. The unpaid work of parenting includes domestic labour as well as direct engagement with the child ± engagement which takes place through daily practicalities and which can also be describe as emotional labour. Even if welfare to work for lone parents is a success, and they move voluntarily into employment, their children are adequately cared for, and they are materially better off, there is a hidden cost. It is a cost to women of a major increase in their total workload, not a cost to society of inadequate parenting. Looking at social production from the point of view of the total social organization of labour and acknowledging the prevalence of unpaid work calls into question how we understand the meaning of work itself and the justice of using the wage relation as a means of distributing the social product, as well as the reliance on paid work as a mechanism of social inclusion. Solutions to this are not obvious, and are limited by the structural dominance of the market. Delivering Social Inclusion 169 One approach is to bring as much unpaid work as is possible into the market sector. This is the direction in which current policies point. However, even if all adults of working age are expected to be in paid work, and all children in collective day care, a great deal of unpaid work remains to be done ± and is done chiefly by women. Its implication is an increase in women's overall workload. A second approach would be to reward unpaid work directly, in proportion to its value. This, on the ONS figures, would imply a huge shift of resources from the market to the non-market sector. One common objection is the difficulty of evaluating how well unpaid work is carried out. While one can imagine that attempting to do this might be an attractive idea to Jack Straw, it is not necessary; most jobs in the market sector are not rewarded on the basis of performance related pay. A more intractable difficulty is the danger of ghettoizing women in domestic labour, the criticism levelled at the Wages for Housework Campaign in the 1970s. And a principled objection might be that distribution in relation to unpaid work, like distribution through the wage relation, rests on a redefinition of what constitutes a social contribution, not on a shift to distribution on the basis of need; it is in this sense less radical and less egalitarian that RED. It would also meet the same limits as RED. The redistribution of resources from market to non-market sector would, as Townsend said of radical redistribution through the benefits system, run up against the limits of what is possible in a system which depends fundamentally on distribution through the wage relation. A third possibility would be a major redistribution of both paid and unpaid work. This would mean breaking down the gender inequalities in both forms of work. It would also require limitations on paid working time more draconian than anything likely to be contemplated by the European Union, but affording an acceptable standard of living on the basis of much shorter hours. Movements in this direction are possible, and favoured by the French. But significant changes which do not increase poverty and inequality would be possible only on the basis of a large reduction in wage differentials, and limited by the requirements of a capitalist economy. GETTING THERE Participation in social life, whether that be paid work, voluntary work, family life, or the ragbag category leisure, depends on being able to get The Inclusive Society170 to the sites of these activities. It requires mobility; it requires transport. The promised development of an integrated transport system is fundamental to the development of social inclusion. This is an issue for SID as well as RED, for transport problems affect employment prospects. For RED, it is a wider question: the social life of those without cars can be very limited. This is particularly true in rural areas, where in many cases public transport is almost or wholly non-existent. Such a system needs to be affordable ± although affordability depends on income, so increasing the incomes of the poorest might be a useful contributory factor. It also needs to be accessible to disabled people, whose social exclusion is caused not only by lack of money, but by lack of transport and the general inaccessibility of public spaces. The response of the green pressure group SERA's response to the transport White Paper argues that an inclusive transport system would mean `a rail system that is adequately staffed, affordable and fully accessible to all disabled people' and that `all buses running on the streets of Britain are fully accessible to all the nation's citizens'.10 The promotion of an integrated transport system has a number of motivations. Reducing traffic congestion is partly about managing capitalism more efficiently; traffic jams cost firms money. It is partly environmentally driven, both in terms of the global need to reduce greenhouse emissions, and the local need to reduce asthma-inducing air pollution. Reducing car use, once a fringe concern, is now Government policy and has wide support. But this is not a straightforward matter. First, the projected need for new homes is likely to be met by increased building in rural areas. Many people want to move out of cities. The land available for building in cities is limited ± although it could be substantially increased by reducing the amount of land used for parking. Some brownfield sites are heavily polluted, and decontamination makes them more expensive to develop than greenfield sites. Increased rural development means more car use, not less. Secondly, the exhortation to individuals to use their cars less must not be a way of subordinating their needs to industry's preference for a clear run. Switching freight to rail is part of the plan, and success in this is essential to an inclusive system. This is particularly important because most of the discussions of reduced car use focus on switching short journeys to walking or cycling, on the supposition that these are most amenable to modal change. But many short journeys are made to ferry children around or carry shopping. SERA concedes that `the car can bring people into the mainstream of life who might otherwise feel excluded', notes its importance to `mothers who have a thousand and Delivering Social Inclusion 171 one things to do with . . . children', and says that the challenge is to make sure the right sort of journeys are made by car, `for they add to, and don't detract from, social inclusion'.11 This implicitly recognizes the third potential bar to and negative effect of changing public behaviour. Walking to and from a school a mile away with young children involves four miles and the best part of two hours a day. If the distances are greater, so is the time involved; if the children are at different schools, the logistics may be impossible ± and certainly impossible to combine with getting to work. Many mothers already juggle with these difficulties. Reducing car use may mean an increase in women's unpaid work. COMMON INSTITUTIONS Hutton's focus on the rich as well as the poor suggests that inclusion requires that people use the same services and institutions. Transport is one example. Others are health and education, where Hutton's concern was with the divide between public and private provision. There is a body of opinion that the combination of medical advances leading to new treatments, an ageing population and rising demands make some form of rationing in the National Health Service inevitable. Without greatly increased funding, the likely outcome of this is an increase in private health provision among those who can afford it. In both health and education there is talk of `partnership' ± the NHS buying treatments in private hospitals, private schools opening up their sports facilities to state school pupils. This will not address the fundamental inequality of provision. Short of making private health and education illegal, the only ways of radically reducing the possibility of a large and influential minority deserting collective provision are to provide public services which match those privately available, or to radically reduce the inequalities which make this desertion possible. The first route is enormously expensive, and New Labour has no intention of promoting inclusion by the second means. In both school and university sectors of education, newly divisive policies are being pursued. The introduction of fees and the abolition of maintenance grants for higher education is likely to narrow rather than broaden access. The education action zones promised in the Education Bill in late 1997 pose a different kind of problem. The purpose of the zones, described by Government officials as `the centrepiece of our modernisation agenda' is to improve educational The Inclusive Society172 standards in the designated areas. Their connection to addressing social exclusion is clear. But schools in these zones will be able to employ `innovative methods'; they will be not be bound by the requirements of the national curriculum, but be allowed to concentrate on core skills. They will also be exempt from national agreements on teachers' pay and conditions, and be able to extend their working week, extending the school day and opening schools at weekends (compare Etzioni, Chapter 5). Management of the zones will be put out to tender, and while most are expected to be run by `partnerships' of local authorities, community groups and businesses, zones may be imposed against local authority wishes and may be run solely by private businesses. This potentially places large parts of the education system in private hands, where the curriculum can be increasingly bent to the needs of industry rather than the wider needs of pupils. It also removes democratic accountability, and further undermines the role of local education authorities and local government ± continuing, rather than reversing the trends of the last twenty years. The question of democratic accountability raises the issue of political inclusion. POLITICAL INCLUSION One important wider aspect of inclusion is the question of political inclusion or inclusiveness. This addresses the structures and processes of political decision making, how these are conducted, and who is involved in them; social inclusion and exclusion more often refer to the experiences of citizens whose participation in normal social life, however this is understood, is facilitated or prevented. Social and political inclusion are doubly connected: political inclusiveness may be expected to deliver greater social inclusion; and among the aspects of social life in which participation is sought is the political process itself. From the perspective of RED, political inclusion is an aspect of social inclusion. In one sense, the whole agenda of political reform, including policies for Scottish, Welsh and regional devolution could be presented as an attempt to bring government closer to the people. Whether they could or will deliver greater political inclusion is a large and important question, beyond the scope of this book. Inclusion would mean greater participation in processes broadly defined as political ± and with the outcome of giving people greater real power over decisions affecting their lives. The reconstruction of local government would be an Delivering Social Inclusion 173 important part of this. Some of the problems about the idea and reality of political inclusion can be illustrated by looking at the early stages of the Blair Government itself. On election, Blair promised to govern inclusively. Most of Labour's references in the pre-election and immediate post-election period were to political inclusiveness; they were about consultation and `dialogue', about political rather than social or economic inclusion, about process rather than outcome. Government should be democratic, open, accountable and responsive and should eschew sectarian exclusion, hierarchical exclusivity and adversarial style. Wider consultation and public involvement, as well as the devolution of decisions according to the principle of subsidiarity, should supplement elections. Such processes might include community forums, citizens' juries, public hearings, as well as referendums. The inclusion of those groups in society hitherto excluded from or under-represented in the political process should be increased in both formal and informal processes. The most frequently stated concern was the under-representation of women; less frequent, but regular, mention was also made of ethnic minorities and disabled people. The inclusive society would be one where everyone ± or every significant group ± has a voice, and where these voices are heard either through representation on the basis of identity ± women speak for women, black people for black people ± or indirectly through advocacy groups or voluntary associations. Inclusive government was signalled by the presence of women MPs and ministers, as well as those disabled, openly lesbian or gay, or from ethnic minorities. Some of the problems deriving from constructing identities rather than collectivities as the proper basis of representation can be seen by looking at Labour's best case, women ± which also illustrates that political inclusion may be necessary, but it is scarcely sufficient. There were more women elected to the 1997 Parliament, and more women in Blair's first Government, than ever before in Britain. This resulted from a policy of having all women short-lists for a proportion of parliamentary candidates ± a policy dropped after it was challenged as illegal by two male party members. It may thus prove to be a fragile achievement. Blair's honouring of the long-standing promise of a Minister for Women with cabinet status did not inspire confidence. The job was given to Harriet Harman as an afterthought, in addition to the potentially conflicting brief of Secretary of State for Social Security. Then, in an attempt to patch up the damage, Joan Ruddock was asked to take on ministerial responsibility at a more junior level. The Inclusive Society174 However, by this time, all the salaried ministerial positions had been distributed (including Mandelson's post of Minister without Portfolio) ± so she acquired the work, the status, but not the pay. A Women's Unit was set up, part of its brief being to assess the impact on women of all policy proposals. It was given no spending budget, and some argued that to be effective, it would need to be based in the Treasury, with gender impact statements central to Treasury policy. Fears were expressed that the inclusion of women in the Blair Government meant a feminization of politics rather than an advance for feminism and the interests of women. Skjeie argues from the Norwegian experience that the political inclusion of women does not necessarily transform substantive outcomes.12 Increased representation does give a higher profile to some issues ± notably, and importantly, child care ± but responses to these issues are routinely subordinated to conventional party political agendas. This is exactly what happened in the dispute over benefit cuts for lone parents ± a dispute which also illustrated how the inclusion of women meant not only their co-option to, but their active role in legitimizing, policies damaging to women's interests. Processes of informal inclusion and consultation are at least as significant as formal presence. Blair greatly increased the number of political advisers at Downing Street, many recruited from thinktanks like the IPPR and Demos; these advisers were unelected, unaccountable and overwhelmingly male. Appointments to the large number of task forces and review bodies set up after the election continued the co-option of unelected individuals to the policy-making process, particularly those from the business sector or `community'. Political inclusion crossed party boundaries. David Mellor, a Conservative minister forced to resign after a sexual scandal, was asked to chair the Football Task Force. Alan Howarth, who defected to Labour from the Tories in 1996, was rewarded with a ministerial post at the Department for Education and Employment. Pre-election collaboration with the Liberal Democrats over plans for constitutional reform continued after the election with a cross-party Cabinet Committee ± although in the week of the 1997 Liberal Democrat Conference, both Peter Mandelson and Alistair Darling warned that if the Liberal Democrats wanted co-operation between the parties to continue, they should stop criticizing the Government's economic policies. Daniel argues that outside groups did gain greater access to ministers and civil servants ± consistent with the new Clause IV commitment to working with voluntary organizations, consumer groups and Delivering Social Inclusion 175 other representative bodies.13 However, she said, this inclusion was `not about participatory democracy so much as about participation in the delivery of policy', and that `those who confuse the two things are in for a disappointment'. Nowhere was this more apposite than in relation to the trade unions, who were repeatedly warned to expect no special treatment ± `fairness not favours'. Unions constituted a sectional interest, while the business community, apparently, was not. They were not altogether excluded from participation in the task forces, but their representation was meagre. Trade union representatives were invited to Downing Street in the late summer of 1997 to discuss the manifesto commitment to union recognition, but not involved in wider policy questions. Blair spoke at the 1997 TUC Congress, which met under the slogan `Partners for Progress', and made it clear that any political inclusion of the unions was conditional upon their conforming to the new `responsible' unionism epitomized by John Monks, which would not challenge either the policies of government or the consensual image of the new Britain it sought to promote. Blair said he would `watch very carefully to see how the culture of modern trade unionism' developed. He told the unions that there were more important battles than those over `labour law', and that they should be concentrating on issues of skills, training, welfare to work, pensions and the reform of the National Health Service. He ordered them to modernize: `Modernise your political structures as we have done in the Labour Party. Influence with this government and with me is not determined by anything other than the persuasiveness of your arguments. The old ways ± resolutionitis, the committee rooms, the fixing, the small groups trying to run the show have no future. New trade unionism ± that is your aim. Partners for Progress. That is your slogan'. But there was no doubt who was the senior, and who the junior, partner. Appropriate behaviour for trade unions was to be defined by Blairite fiat, not by trade unionists themselves, and their inclusion dependent upon this effective co-option. And it is notable that the constituencies of legitimate identity eligible for inclusion did not include class: for this would be to import `old' categories of conflict into the new era of partnership. The central question is who, and whose interests, are represented at any level of government ± and whose interests prevail. The general problem about the contemporary emphasis on dialogue and on `having a voice', which in political and social theory is based on the ideas of Jurgen Habermas, is that it gives too little recognition to the structures of power within which that discussion takes place. Emergent decisions The Inclusive Society176 take on the appearance of consensus, and political inclusion risks becoming political co-option. Moreover because there are presumed to be only differences of opinion, not conflicts of interest, dissenting voices outside the consensus are marginalized as trouble makers. Genuine political inclusiveness may be necessary to overcoming social exclusion, though it is certainly not sufficient. Rhetoric about inclusiveness, and even actual inclusion, in the processes of policy formation must be distinguished from the outcomes of these policies. The dirigiste management of Blair’s Government is easily understandable as repressing conflicts which might otherwise divide the Party within and beyond Parliament. What is less immediately obvious is that the underpinning model of society on which the third way is based is one in which conflicts of interest are suppressed. It is this which leads to the instability of the third way and its tendency to fall into authoritarianism. This model, with its consequences and limits, is the subject of the next chapter. Delivering Social Inclusion 177 Notes NOTES TO INTRODUCTION 1. Andersen, Paul and Mann, Nyta (1997) Safety First: The Making of New Labour, London: Granta Books; Davies, A.J. (1996) To Build a new Jerusalem: The British Labour Party from Kier Hardy to Tony Blair, London: Abacus; Jones, Tudor (1996) Remaking the Labour Party: From Gaitskell to Blair, London: Routledge; Panitch, Leo and Leys, Colin (1997) The End of Parliamentary Socialism: From New Left to New Labour, London: Verso; Shaw, Eric (1994) The Labour Party Since 1979, London: Routledge. 2. Layard, Richard (1997) What Labour Can Do, London: Warner Books. 3. Silver, Hilary (1994) ‘Social exclusion and social solidarity: three paradigms’ International Labour Review Vol. 133, Nos. 5–6, pp. 531–78. NOTES TO CHAPTER 1 1. Murgatroyd, Linda and Neuburger, Henry (1997) ‘A Household Satellite Account for the UK’ Economic Trends No. 527, October: 63–71; Waring, Marilyn (1988) If Women Counted, London: Macmillan. 2. These gender differences are almost certainly understated. The methodology does not allow people to record themselves as doing more than one thing at once. Respondents are expressly instructed that doing housework while caring for children should be recorded as housework rather than care of children. If this is extended to activities such as eating and leisure (which are not counted as unpaid work), the child care responsibilities of women will be seriously undercounted, and the differences between men and women reduced. 3. Glucksmann, Miriam (1995) ‘Why ‘‘Work’’? Gender and the ‘‘Total Social Organisation of Labour’’ ’ Gender, Work and Organisation Vol. 2, No. 2, p. 69, 67. 4. Townsend, Peter (1979) Poverty in the United Kingdom, Harmondsworth: Penguin p. 32. 5. Ibid., pp. 399, 249. 6. Ibid., p. 564. 7. Duncan, Simon and Edwards, Rosalind (1997) Single Mothers in an International Context: Mothers or Workers? London: UCL Press. 8. Townsend’s (1979) attitude to unpaid work, and to the position of women more generally, was not wholly consistent. In talking about levels of unemployment, he argued that the numbers would be far higher if the ‘under-utilized productive capacity of non-employed women with or without dependants’, together with other economically inactive groups were to be included. On the other hand, he was concerned that the shift from manufacturing to service industries would ‘create a major new 237 source of inequality and poverty in society’ as older men were displaced from the labour market in favour of women. He predicted that ‘a larger number of physically active middle-aged males will be pensioned off to facilitate occupational opportunity for women’ p. 682. 9. Townsend, Peter (1997) ‘Redistribution: The Strategic Alternative to Privatisation’, in Alan Walker and Carol Walker, Britain Divided: The growth of social exclusion in the 1980s and 1990s, London: CPAG, p. 269. 10. Walker, Alan and Walker, Carol, (eds) (1997) Britain Divided: The growth of social exclusion in the 1980s and 1990s, London: CPAG. 11. Ibid: 8. 12. Harker, Lisa (1996) A Secure Future? Social security and the family in a changing world, London: CPAG; Harker, Lisa (1997) ‘New Paths for Social Security’ in Alan Walker and Carol Walker, Britain Divided: The growth of social exclusion in the 1980s and 1990s, London: CPAG. 13. Walker, op cit., p. 8. 14. Golding, Peter (1986) Excluding the Poor, London: CPAG. 15. Lister, Ruth (1990) The Exclusive Society: Citizenship and the Poor, London: CPAG. 16. Goodin, Robert E. (1996) ‘Inclusion and Exclusion’, European Journal of Sociology Vol. 37, No. 2, pp. 343–71. 17. Marshall, T.H. (1950) ‘Citizenship and Social Class’ in T.H. Marshall and Tom Bottomore, Citizenship and Social Class, London: Pluto Press 1992, p. 8. 18. Ibid., p. 44. 19. Pateman, Carole (1988) The Sexual Contract, Cambridge: Polity Press; Walby, Sylvia (1994) ‘Is Citizenship Gendered?’ Sociology Vol. 28, No. 2, pp. 379–95. 20. Lister, op cit., p. 68. 21. Hall, Stuart and Jacques, Martin (1983) The Politics of Thatcherism, London: Lawrence and Wishart; Levitas, Ruth (1986) (ed.) The Ideology of the New Right, Cambridge: Polity; Gamble, Andrew (1988) The Free Economy and The Strong State, Basingstoke: Macmillan. 22. Cole on the Dole, 19 February 1993. 23. Townsend (1979) op cit., p. 920. 24. Field, Frank (1990) Losing Out: The Emergence of Britain’s Underclass, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, p. 101. 25. Dahrendorf, Ralf (1987) ‘The erosion of citizenship and its consequences for us all’ New Statesman, 12 June, p. 13. 26. Ibid. 27. Field, op cit., pp. 7, 107. 28. Ibid., pp. 155, 107. 29. Ibid., p. 8. 30. Field, Frank (1995) Making Welfare Work: Reconstructing Welfare for the Millennium, London: Institute of Community Studies. 31. Murray, Charles (1990) The Emerging British Underclass, London: IEA, p. 23. 32. Ibid., pp. 4, 17. 33. Ibid., p. 7. 34. Murray, Charles (1994) Underclass: The Crisis Deepens, London: IEA. Notes238 35. Bewick, Tom (1997) ‘The poverty of US welfare reform: lessons from California’, Working Brief 87, August/September, pp. 21–7. 36. Panorama, 29 September 1997; Rogers, J. Jean (1997) ‘Making welfare work’, New Statesman 29 August, pp. 17–18. 37. Macnicol, John (1987) ‘In pursuit of the Underclass’, Journal of Social Policy, Vol. 16, pp. 293–318; Mann, Kirk (1992) The Making of an English Underclass, Milton Keynes: Open University Press; Morris, Lydia (1994) Dangerous Classes: The Underclass and Social Citizenship, London: Routledge. 38. Thinking Aloud, 12 November 1987, ‘Is There a New Underclass in British Society?’ Channel 4. 39. Westergaard, John (1992) ‘About and Beyond the ‘‘Underclass’’ ’, Sociology Vol. 26, No. 4, pp. 575–87. 40. Oppenheim, Carey (1993) Poverty: The Facts, London: CPAG. 41. Dean, Hartley and Taylor-Gooby, Peter (1992) Dependency Culture: the explosion of a myth, New York: Harvester-Wheatsheaf. 42. Lister op cit., p. 26. 43. Adonis, Andrew and Pollard, Stephen (1997) A Class Act: The Myth of Classless Society, London: Hamish Hamilton, p. 16. 44. Ibid., p. 13. 45. Duffy, K. (1995) Social Exclusion and Human Dignity in Europe, Council of Europe. 46. Silver op cit. 47. Spicker, Paul (1997) ‘Exclusion’, Journal of Common Market Studies 35(1): 133–143; Evans, Martin, Paugam, Serge and Prelis, Joseph A. (1995) Chunnel Vision: Poverty, social exclusion and the debate on social welfare in France and Britain, STICERD working paper WSP/115, London: London School of Economics. 48. Spicker op cit. 49. Room, Graham (1995) (ed.) Beyond the Threshold, Bristol: Policy Press. 50. Sostris (1997) Social Strategies in Risk Societies: Social Exclusion in Comparative Perspective, Sostris Working Paper 1, London: University of East London. 51. EC (1994b) European Social Policy: a way forward for the Union, Brussels: European Commission; EC (1994a) Growth, competitiveness, employment: the challenges and ways forward into the 21st century, Brussels: European Commission. 52. EC (1994a) op cit., p. 3. 53. EC (1994b) op cit., p. 49. 54. EC (1994a) op cit., pp. 15–16. 55. EC (1994b) op cit., p. 49. 56. Ibid., pp. 35–6, 51–2. 57. EC (1994a) p. 136. 58. EC (1994b) op cit., p. 49; EC (1994a) op cit., p. 134. 59. EC (1994a) op cit., pp. 9,11. 60. Ibid., pp. 148–9. 61. Maier, Friederike (1994) Equal Opportunities for Women and Men: Wage and Non-wage Labour Costs, Social Security and Public Funds to Combat Unemployment, Brussels: European Commission; Rees, Teresa (1994) Notes 239 Equal Opportunities for Women and Men: Equality into Education and Training Policies, Brussels: European Commission. 62. EC (1994a) op cit., pp. 12, 15. 63. Ibid., p. 54. 64. Ibid., pp. 15–16, 139. 65. Ackers, Louise (1998) Shifting Spaces: Women, Citizenship and migration within the European Union, Bristol: Policy Press. NOTES TO CHAPTER 2 1. Thompson and du Gay (1997) ‘Future imperfect’ Nexus, Winter/Spring, pp. 8–9. 2. Twigg, Stephen Fabian Review Vol. 109, No. 2, p. 23. 3. Cohen, Nick (1997) ‘Totally Wonkers’, Observer, 9 March, p. 20. 4. New Statesman 15 January 1993, p. 5. 5. The membership of the Commission on Social Justice was: Sir Gordon Borrie, QC; Professor A.B. Atkinson, Oxford; Anita Bhalla, Asian Resource Centre, Birmingham; Professor John Gennard, Strathclyde University; The Very Reverend John Gladwin, Provost of Sheffield and Bishop-Elect of Guildford; Christopher Haskins, Chairman, Northern Foods plc; Patricia Hewitt; Dr Penelope Leach, Fellow, British Psychological Society; Professor Ruth Lister, Loughborough University; Professor David Marquand, University of Sheffield; Bert Massie, Director, Royal Association for Disability and Rehabilitation; Emma MacLennan, Vice-Chair, Low Pay Unit; Dr Eithne McLaughlin, Queens University, Belfast; Stephen Webb, Institute for Fiscal Studies; Margaret Wheeler, UNISON; Professor Bernard Williams, Oxford. 6. Beresford, Peter and Turner, Michael (1997) It’s Our Welfare, Report of the Citizens’ Commission on the future of the Welfare State, London: National Institute for Social Work. 7. Commission on Social Justice (CSJ) (1994) Social Justice: Strategies for Social Renewal, London: Vintage, p. 96 (emphasis added). 8. Townsend, Peter (1995) ‘Persuasion and Conformity: An assessment of the Borrie report on Social Justice’, New Left Review Vol. 213, pp. 137–50. 9. Milne, Kirsty (1995) ‘Welfare Statement’, New Statesman and Society, 27 January, p. 21. 10. CSJ op cit., p. 95. 11. Ibid. 12. Andersen and Mann op cit. 13. This was part of the Australian ‘Working Nation’ initiative, which, like New Labour’s New Deal, was introduced by a right-wing Labour administration. See Finn, Dan (1997) Working Nation: Welfare Reform and the Australian Job Compact for the long term unemployed, London: Unemployment Unit. 14. Showstack Sassoon, Anne (1996) ‘Beyond pessimism of the intellect: Agendas for Social Justice and Change’ in Mark Perryman (ed.) The Blair Agenda, London: Lawrence and Wishart, p. 159. Notes240 50. Mulgan (1997a) op cit., p. 202. 51. Ibid., p. 137. 52. Ibid., p. 185. 53. Guy, Will (1996) ‘Health for All’ in Ruth Levitas and Will Guy (eds) Interpreting Official Statistics London: Routledge; Wilkinson, Richard (1997) Unhealthy Societies: From Inequality to Wellbeing, London: Rout- ledge. 54. Blair, 2 June 1997, op cit. 55. Ibid. 56. Blair, 24 January 1997, ‘The 21st Century Welfare State’ Social and Economic Policy Conference, Rijksmuseum, Amsterdam. 57. Blair, 2 June 1997, op cit. 58. Mandelson, Observer 17 August 1997. 59. Blair, 29 January 1996, op cit. 60. Harman, 13 November 1997, op cit. 61. Brown, 11 September 1997, op cit. 62. Mandelson, 14 August 1997, ‘Labour’s Next Steps: Tackling Social Exclusion’, Fabian Society lecture. 63. Harman, 13 November 1997, op cit. 64. Plant, Raymond (1997b) ‘The Labour Market, Citizenship and Social Exclusion’, CASE Seminar, London School of Economics, 10 December. 65. Campbell, Bea (1993) Goliath: Britain’s Dangerous Places, London: Methuen. NOTES TO CHAPTER 8 1. Downes, David, Guardian 25 November 1997, ‘Prison does wonders for the jobless figures’; Western, Bruce and Beckett, Katherine (1997) ‘How unregulated in the U.S. Labour Market? The Penal System as a Labor Market Institution’, paper presented to the American Sociological Association, Toronto. 2. Finn, Dan (1997) Working Nation: Welfare Reform and the Australian Job Compact for the Long Term Unemployed, London: Unemployment Unit. 3. Townsend, Peter (1996) ‘The Struggle for Independent Statistics on Poverty’ in Ruth Levitas and Will Guy (eds) Interpreting Official Statistics, London: Routledge. 4. Perri 6 (1997b) ‘Social exclusion: time to be optimistic’ in The Wealth and Poverty of Networks: Tackling Social Exclusion, Demos Collection 12, London: Demos, p. 3. 5. Observer 7 December 1997. 6. Guardian 30 December 1997. 7. Perri 6 (1997b) op cit., p. 6; Schneider, Jo Anne (1997) ‘Welfare-tonetwork’ in The Wealth and Poverty of Networks: Tackling Social Exclusion, Demos Collection 12, London: Demos, p. 30. 8. Perri 6 (1997) Escaping Poverty, London: Demos. 9. Hall, Peter A. (1997) ‘Social capital: a fragile asset’ in The Wealth and Poverty of Networks: Tackling Social Exclusion, Demos Collection 12, London: Demos, p. 35. Notes 253 10. Stewart, John (1997/8) ‘And the SERA response’, New Ground 53, p. 13. 11. Ibid. 12. Skjeie, Hege (1991) ‘The Rhetoric of Difference: On Women’s Inclusion into Political Elites’, Politics and Society Vol. 19, No. 2, pp. 133–63. 13. Daniel, Caroline (1997) ‘May the taskforce be with you’, New Statesman 1 August, p. 29. NOTES TO CHAPTER 9 1. Durkheim, E. (1964 [1893]) The Division of Labour in Society, New York: Free Press. 2. Gray (1997) op cit., pp. 19–20. 3. Watts Miller, Willie (1996) Durkheim, Morals and Modernity, London: UCL Press, p. 246. 4. Soros, George Guardian 18 January 1997. 5. Durkheim, op cit., p. 211. 6. Levitas, Ruth (1998) ‘Will Hutton: Closet Durkheimian’ in Paul Bagguley and Jeff Hearn (eds) Transforming Politics: Power and Resistance, London: Macmillan. 7. Watts Miller op cit., p. 4. 8. Ibid., p. 90. 9. Durkheim, cited in Giddens, Anthony (1986) (ed.) Durkheim on Politics and the State, Cambridge: Polity Press, p. 8. 10. Stanley, John L. (ed.) (1976) From Georges Sorel: Essays in Socialism and Philosophy, Oxford University Press. 11. Durkheim, op cit., p. 17. 12. Ibid., p. 16. 13. Durkheim, cited in Giddens, op cit., p. 21. 14. Durkheim, op cit., p. 242. 15. Ibid., p. 2. 16. Pahl, R.E. (1991), ‘The Search for Social Cohesion: from Durkheim to the European Commission’, European Journal of Sociology, Vol. 32, No. 2, p. 348. 17. Lehmann, Jennifer (1994) Durkheim and Women, Nebraska: University of Nebraska Press. 18. Gilman, Charlotte Perkins (1966 [1898]) Women and Economics, New York: Harper Torchbooks. 19. Durkheim, cited in Watts Miller, op cit., pp. 75–6. 20. Durkheim, Emile (1952 [1897]) Suicide, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. 21. Durkheim, cited in Giddens op cit., p. 31. 22. Ibid., p. 238. 23. Durkheim (1964) op cit., pp. 377–8. 24. Durkheim, cited in Watts-Miller op cit p. 254. 25. Fenton, Steve (1984) Durkheim and Modern Sociology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Giddens (1971) Capitalism and Modern Social Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press; Giddens (1978) Notes254 Select Bibliography Acheson, Donald (1998) Independent Inquiry into Inequalities in Health, London, The Stationery Office. Aldridge, Stephen (2001) Social mobility: a discussion paper, London: Performance and Innovation Unit. Aldridge, Stephen (2004) Life Chances and Social Mobility: An overview of the evidence, London: Prime Minister’s Strategy Unit. Andersen, Paul and Mann, Nyta (1997) Safety First: The Making of New Labour, London: Granta Books. Barratt Brown, Michael and Coates, Ken (1996) The Blair Revelation: Deliverance for Whom? London: Spokesman. Beresford, Peter and Turner, Michael (1997) It’s Our Welfare, Report of the Citizens’ Commission on the future of the Welfare State, London: National Institute for Social Work. Blair, Tony (1994b) Socialism, Fabian Pamphlet 565, London: Fabian Society. Bradshaw, Jonathan and Peter Kemp, Sally Baldwin and Abigail Rowe (2004) The Drivers of Social Exclusion: A Review of the Literature, London: SEU/ Office of the Deputy Prime Minister. Campbell, Bea (1993) Goliath: Britian’s Dangerous Places, London: Methuen. Commission on Public Policy and British Business (CPPBB) (1997) Promoting Prosperity: A Business Agenda for Britain, London: Vintage. Commission on Social Justice (CSJ) (1994) Social Justice: Strategies for Social Renewal, London: Vintage. Commission on Taxation and Citizenship (2000) Paying for Progress: A New Politics of Tax for Public Spending, London: Fabian Society. Dahrendorf, Ralf et al. (1995) Report on Wealth Creation and Social Cohesion in a Free Society, London: Commission on Wealth Creation and Social Cohesion. Davies, A. J. (1996) To Build a New Jerusalem: The British Labour Party from Kier Hardie to Tony Blair, London: Abacus. Dean, Hartley and Taylor-Gooby, Peter (1992) Dependency Culture: the explosion of a myth, New York: Harvester-Wheatsheaf. Demos (1997) The Wealth and Poverty of Networks: tackling social exclusion, Demos Collection 12, London: Demos. Department of Health (1999) Caring About Carers: a national strategy for carers, London: The Stationery Office. Department of Social Security (1999) Opportunity For All: Tackling Poverty and Social Exclusion (OFA 1999), Cm 4445, London: The Stationery Office. Department of Social Security (2000) Opportunity For All. One Year On: Making a Difference (OFA 2000), Cm 4865 London: The Stationery Office. Department of Work and Pensions (2001) Opportunity For All: Making a Difference. Third Annual Report (OFA 2003) Cm 5260, London: The Stationery Office. Department of Work and Pensions (2002) Opportunity For All: Fourth Annual Report (OFA 2002) Cm 5598, London: The Stationery Office. 261 Department of Work and Pensions (2003) Opportunity For All: Fifth Annual Report (OFA 2003) Cm 5956, London: The Stationery Office. Department of Work and Pensions (2004) Opportunity For All: Sixth Annual Report (OFA 2004) Cm 6234 London: The Stationery Office. Duncan, Simon and Edwards, Rosalind (1997) Single Mothers in an International Context: Mothers or Workers? London: UCL Press. Durkheim, Emile (1952 [1897]) Suicide, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Durkheim, Emile (1964 [1893]) The Division of Labour in Society, New York: Free Press. Etzioni, Amitai (1994) The Parenting Deficit, London: Demos. Etzioni, Amitai (1995 [1993]) The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities and the Communitarian Agenda, London: Fontana. Etzioni, Amitai (1997 [1996]) The New Golden Rule: Community and Morality in a Democratic Society, London: Profile Books. Fairclough, Norman (2000) New Labour, New Language, London: Routledge. Fenton, Steve (1984) Durkheim and Modern Sociology, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Field, Frank (1990) Losing Out: The Emergence of Britain’s Underclass, Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Field, Frank (1995) Making Welfare Work: Reconstructing Welfare for the Millennium, London: Institute of Community Studies. Finlayson, Alan (2003) Making Sense of New Labour, London: Lawrence and Wishart. Finn, Dan (1997) Working Nation: Welfare Reform and the Australian Job Compact for the long term unemployed, London: Unemployment Unit. Gamble, Andrew (1988) The Free Economy and The Strong State, Basingstoke: Macmillan. Gane, Mike (1992) ‘Durkheim: Woman as Outsider’ in M. Gane (ed.) The Radical Sociology of Durkheim and Mauss, London: Routledge, pp. 85–134. Giddens, Anthony (1971) Capitalism and Modern Social Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Giddens, Anthony (1978) Emile Durkheim, London: Fontana. Giddens, Anthony (ed.) (1986) Durkheim on Politics and the State, Cambridge: Polity Press. Gilman, Charlotte Perkins (1966 [1898]) Women and Economics, New York: Harper Torchbooks. Glucksmann, Miriam (1995) ‘Why ‘‘Work’’? Gender and the ‘‘Total Social Organization of Labour’’ ’, Gender, Work and Organization, Vol. 2, No. 2, pp. 63–75. Golding, Peter (1986) Excluding the Poor, London: CPAG. Goodin, Robert E. (1996) ‘Inclusion and Exclusion’, European Journal of Sociology, Vol. 37, No. 2, pp. 343–71. Goodman, Alissa and Zoe Oldfoeld, (2004) Permanent Differences? Income and Expenditure Inequality, London: Institute of Fiscal Studies. Gordon, David, Laura Adelman, Karl Ashworth, Jonathan Bradshaw, Ruth Levitas, Sue Middleton, Christina Pantazis, Demi Patsios, Sarah Payne, Peter Townsend and Julie Williams (2000) Poverty and Social Exclusion in Britain, York: Joseph Rowntree Foundation. Select Bibliography262 Gray, John (1989) Liberalisms: Essays in Political Philosophy, London: Routledge. Gray, John (1992) The Moral Foundations of Market Institutions, London: IEA Health and Welfare Unit. Gray, John (1993a) Beyond the New Right: Markets, government and the common environment, London: Routledge. Gray, John (1993b) Post-Liberalism: Studies in Political Thought, New York: Routledge. Gray, John (1996) After Social Democracy, London: Demos. Gray, John (1997) Endgames: Questions in Late Modern Political Thought, Cambridge: Polity Press. Gray, John (1995) Enlightenment’s Wake: Politics and culture at the close of the modern age, London: Routledge. Green Party (1993) Manifesto for a Sustainable Society, London: Green Party. Gregg, Paul and Wadsworth, Jonathan (1996) ‘Feeling Insecure?’, Employment Audit, 2, Autumn, pp. 17–26. GUMG (Glasgow University Media Group) (1976) Bad News, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Gutmann, Amy (1988) Democracy and the Welfare State, Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. Hall, Peter A. (1997) ‘Social capital: a fragile asset’ in The wealth and poverty of networks: tackling social exclusion, Demos Collection 12, London: Demos, pp. 35–7. Hall, Stuart (2003) ‘New Labour’s double-shuffle’, Soundings 24. Hall, Stuart and Jacques, Martin (1983) The Politics of Thatcherism, London: Lawrence and Wishart. Halpern, David, Clive Bates, Geoff Mulgan, Stephen Aldridge, Greg Beales and Adam Heathfield (2004) Personal Responsibility and Changing Behaviour: the state of knowledge and its implications for public policy, London: Cabinet Office. Halsey, A. H. and Young, Michael (1995) Family and Community Socialism, London: IPPR. Harker, Lisa (1996) A Secure Future? Social security and the family in a changing world, London: CPAG. Harker, Lisa (1997) ‘New Paths for Social Security’ in Alan Walker and Carol Walker, Britain Divided: The growth of social exclusion in the 1980s and 1990s, London: CPAG. Hills, John, Julian Le Grand and David Piachaud (eds) (2001) Understanding Social Exclusion, Oxford University Press. Howarth, Catherine, Peter Kenway, Guy Palmer and Cathy Street (1998) Monitoring Poverty and Social Exclusion: Labour’s Inheritance, York: New Policy Institute/Joseph Rowntree Foundation. Hutton, Will (1995a) ‘High Risk Strategy’, The Guardian, 30 October, pp. 2–3. Hutton, Will (1995b) The State We’re In, London: Jonathan Cape. Hutton, Will (1996a) The State We’re In, London: Vintage. Hutton, Will (1996b) ‘The Stakeholder Society’ in Marquand and Seldon (1996) pp. 290–308. Hutton, Will (1996c) ‘Left with no illusions’, Prospect, March, pp. 46–50. Hutton, Will (1997a) ‘Our Stake in Society’, The Observer, 20 April, p. 29. Select Bibliography 263 Hutton, Will (1997b) ‘An Overview of Stakeholding’ in Kelly et al. (1997) pp. 3–9. Hutton, Will (1997c) The State to Come, London: Vintage. Jones, Nicholas (1997) Campaign 1997, London: Indigo. Jones, Tudor (1996) Remaking the Labour Party: From Gaitskell to Blair, London: Routledge. Kay, John (1993) The Foundations of Corporate Success, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kay, John (1996a) ‘The Good Market’, Prospect, May, pp. 39–43. Kay, John (1996b) The Business of Economics, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Kelly, Gavin, Kelly, Dominic and Gamble, Andrew, (1997) (eds) Stakeholder Capitalism, London: Macmillan. Labour Party (LP) (1992) It’s Time To Get Britain Working Again (Election Manifesto). Labour Party (LP) (1995a) Renewing Democracy, Rebuilding Communities. Labour Party (LP) (1995b) Safer Communities, safer Britain. Labour Party (LP) (1995c) A Quiet Life: Tough Action on Criminal Neighbours. Labour Party (LP) (1995d) Excellence for Everyone: Labour’s crusade to raise standards. Labour Party (LP) (1995e) A New Economic Future for Britain: Economic and employment opportunities for all. Labour Party (LP) (1996a) Tackling Youth Crime: Reforming Youth Justice. Labour Party (LP) (1996b) Parenting. Labour Party (LP) (1996c) Lifelong Learning. Labour Party (LP) (1996d) Learn as You Earn: Labour’s plans for a skills revolution. Labour Party (LP) (1996e) Aiming Higher. Labour Party (LP) (1996f) Labour and the Voluntary sector: Setting the Agenda for partnership in government. Labour Party (LP) (1996g) Strategy for Women. Labour Party (LP) (1996h) A Fresh Start for Britain: Labour’s strategy for Britain in the modern world. Labour Party (LP) (1996i) Getting Welfare to Work: Opportunities for Lone Mothers. Labour Party (LP) (1996j) Building Prosperity: Flexibility, efficiency and fairness at work. Labour Party (LP) (1996k) Labour’s New Deal for a Lost Generation. Labour Party (LP) (1996m) Protecting Our Communities: Labour’s plans for tackling criminal, anti-social behaviour in neighbourhoods. Labour Party (LP) (1996n) New Labour, New Life for Britain (draft manifesto). Labour Party (LP) (1997a) Labour’s Business Manifesto: Equipping Britain for the Future. Labour Party (LP) (1997b) Because Britain Deserves Better (1997 Election manifesto). Labour Party (LP) (2001) Ambitions for Britain (2001 Election manifesto). Layard, Richard (1997) What Labour Can Do, London: Warner Books. Lehmann, Jennifer (1994) Durkheim and Women, Nebraska: University of Nebraska Press. Select Bibliography264 Levitas, Ruth (1986) (ed.) The Ideology of the New Right, Cambridge: Polity. Levitas, Ruth (1996a) ‘Fiddling while Britain Burns: The ‘measurement’ of unemployment’ in Ruth Levitas and Will Guy (eds) Interpreting Official Statistics, London: Routledge, pp. 45–65. Levitas, Ruth (1996b) ‘The concept of social exclusion and the new Durkheimian hegemony’, Critical Social Policy 46, Vol. 16, pp. 5–20. Levitas, Ruth (1998) ‘Will Hutton: Closet Durkheimian’ in Paul Bagguley and Jeff Hearn (eds) Transforming Politics: Power and Resistance, London: Macmillan. Levitas, Ruth (2004) ‘Shuffling back to Equality?’, Soundings 26 pp. 59–72. Levitas, Ruth (2004) ‘The Concept and Measurement of Social Exclusion’ in Christina Pantazis, David Gordon and Ruth Levitas (eds) Poverty and Social Exclusion: The Millennium Survey, Bristol: Policy Press. Lister, Ruth (1990) The Exclusive Society: Citizenship and the Poor, London: CPAG. Lloyd, John (1997a) ‘A plan to abolish the underclass’, New Statesman, 29 August, pp. 14–16. Lloyd, John (1997b) ‘Interview: Clive Hollick’, New Statesman, 24 January, pp. 18–19. Lockwood, David (1964) ‘Social Integration and System Integration’ in George K. Zollschan and W. Hirsch (eds), Explorations in Social Change, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Lockwood, David (1992) Solidarity and Schism, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Lukes, Stephen (1973) Emile Durkheim: His Life and Work, London: Allen Lane. Macmurray, John (1931) Learning to Live, London: BBC. Macmurray, John (1932) Freedom in the Modern World, London: Faber and Faber. Macmurray, John (1935a) Reason and Emotion, London: Faber and Faber. Macmurray, John (1935b) Creative Society: A Study of the Relation of Christianity to Communism, London: SCM Press. Macmurray, John (1957) The Self as Agent, London: Faber and Faber. Macmurray, John (1961) Persons in Relation, London: Faber and Faber. Macnicol, John (1987) ‘In pursuit of the Underclass’, Journal of Social Policy, Vol. 16, pp. 293–318. Mandelson, Peter and Liddle, Roger (1996) The Blair Revolution: Can New Labour Deliver? London: Faber and Faber. Mann, Kirk (1992) The Making of an English Underclass, Milton Keynes: Open University Press. Marquand, David and Seldon, Anthony (1996) The Ideas that Shaped PostWar Britain, London: New Statesman/Fontana. Marshall, T. H. (1950) ‘Citizenship and Social Class’ in T. H. Marshall and Tom Bottomore, (1992) Citizenship and Social Class, London: Pluto Press. Maxwell, Dominic (2004) Fair Dues: Towards a more progressive inheritance tax, London: IPPR. Mitchell, R., Mary Shaw and Daniel Dorling (2000) Inequalities in life and death: What if Britain were more equal?, Bristol: Policy Press. Morris, Lydia (1994) Dangerous Classes: The Underclass and Social Citizenship, London: Routledge. Select Bibliography 265 Mulgan, Geoff (1997a) Connexity: How to Live in a Connected World, London: Chatto and Windus. Mulgan, Geoff (1997b) (ed. ) Life After Politics: New Thinking for the Twentyfirst Century, London: Fontana Press. Mulgan, Geoff (1997c) ‘Think well-being, not welfare’, New Statesman, 17 January, pp. 28–9. Mulhall, Stephen and Swift, Adam (1992) Liberals and Communitarians, Oxford: Blackwell. Murray, Charles (1990) The Emerging British Underclass, London: IEA. Murray, Charles (1994) Underclass: The Crisis Deepens, London: IEA. Oppenheim, Carey (1993) Poverty: The Facts, London: CPAG. Pahl, R. E. (1991), ‘The search for social cohesion: from Durkheim to the European Commission’, European Journal of Sociology, Vol. 32, No. 2, pp. 345–60. Panitch, Leo and Leys, Colin (1997) The End of Parliamentary Socialism: From New Left to New Labour, London: Verso. Pantazis, Christina, David Gordon and Ruth Levitas (eds) (2005) Poverty and Social Exclusion: The Millennium Survey, Bristol: Policy Press. Pateman, Carole (1988) The Sexual Contract, Cambridge: Polity Press. Paxton, Will and Dixon, Mike (2004) The State of the Nation: An Audit of Injustice in the UK, London: IPPR. Pearce, Frank (1989) The Radical Durkheim, London: Unwin Hyman. Plender, John (1997) A Stake in the Future: The Stakeholding Solution, London: Nicholas Brealey. Room, Graham (1995) (ed.) Beyond the Threshold, Bristol: Policy Press. Rowntree (1995) Joseph Rowntree Foundation Inquiry into Income and Wealth, 2 vols, York: Joseph Rowntree Foundation. Shaw, Eric (1994) The Labour Party Since 1979, London: Routledge. Shaw, Mary, Daniel Dorling, David Gordon and George Davey Smith (1999) The widening gap: Health inequalities and policy in Britain, Bristol: Policy Press. Showstack Sassoon, Anne (1996) ‘Beyond pessimism of the intellect: Agendas for social Justice and Change’ in Mark Perryman (ed.) The Blair Agenda, London: Lawrence and Wishart. Silver, Hilary (1994) ‘Social exclusion and social solidarity: three paradigms’ International Labour Review Vol. 133(5–6), pp. 531–78. Skjeie, Hege (1991) ‘The Rhetoric of Difference: On Women’s Inclusion into Political Elites’, Politics and Society Vol. 19, No. 2, pp. 133–63. Social Exclusion Unit (1998) Rough Sleeping, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (1998) Truancy and Social Exclusion, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (1998) Bringing Britain Together: a national strategy for neighbourhood renewal, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (1999) Teenage Pregnancy, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (1999) Bridging the Gap; new opportunities for 16–18 year olds not in education, employment or training, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (1999) Review of the Social Exclusion Unit, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2000) Minority ethnic issues in social exclusion and neighbourhood renewal, London: SEU. Select Bibliography266 Social Exclusion Unit (2001) A new commitment to neighbourhood renewal – national strategy action plan, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2001) National strategy for neighbourhood renewal – Policy Action Team audit, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2001) Preventing social exclusion, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2002) Making the connections: transport and social exclusion interim findings, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2002) Reducing re-offending by ex-prisoners, London: Social Exclusion Unit (2002) Young runaways, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2003) Making the connections: transport and social exclusion, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2003) A better education for children in care, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2004) Tackling Social Exclusion: Taking stock and looking to the future – emerging findings, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2004) Action on Debt: why it matters and what you can do, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2004) Mental Health and Social Exclusion, London: SEU. Social Exclusion Unit (2004) Breaking the Cycle: Taking stock of progress and priorities for the future, London: SEU. Sostris (1997) Social Strategies in Risk Societies: Social Exclusion in Comparative Perspective, Sostris Working Paper 1, London: University of East London. Spicker, Paul (1997) ‘Exclusion’, Journal of Common Market Studies Vol. 35, No. 1, pp. 133–43. Tony Atkinson, Bea Cantillon, Eric Marlier, and Brian Nolan (2002) Social Indicators: The EU and Social Inclusion, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Townsend, Peter (1979) Poverty in the United Kingdom, Harmondsworth: Penguin. Townsend, Peter (1995) ‘Persuasion and Conformity: An assessment of the Borrie report on Social Justice’, New Left Review Vol. 213, pp. 137–50. Townsend, Peter (1996) ‘The Struggle for Independent Statistics on Poverty’ in Ruth Levitas and Will Guy (eds) Interpreting Official Statistics, London: Routledge. Toynbee, Polly (2003) Hard Work: Life in Low Pay Britain, London: Bloomsbury. Trades Union Congress (TUC) (1996) Your Stake at Work: TUC Proposals for a Stakeholding Economy, London: Trades Union Congress. UK National Plan on Social Inclusion 2001–3 (NAP 2001). UK National Plan on Social Inclusion 2003–5 (NAP 2003). Walker, Alan and Walker, Carol (1997) (ed.) Britain Divided: The growth of social exclusion in the 1980s and 1990s, London: CPAG. Waring, Marilyn (1988) If Women Counted, London: Macmillan. Watts Miller, Willie (1996) Durkheim, Morals and Modernity, London: UCL Press. Westergaard, John (1992) ‘About and Beyond the ‘‘Underclass’’’, Sociology Vol. 26, No. 4, pp. 575–87. Select Bibliography 267 Willetts, David (1996) Blair’s gurus. London: Centre for Policy Studies. Willetts, David (1997) Why Vote Conservative? Harmondsworth: Penguin. Wright, Tony (1997) Why Vote Labour? Harmondsworth: Penguin. Young, Michael (2001) ‘Down with Meritocracy’, The Guardian, 29 June. Young, Michael (1958) The Rise of the Meritocracy 1870–2033, London: Thames and Hudson. Select Bibliography268 2 Social Innovations as a Practical Inclusive Tool 2 1. European Union. 2014. "Social innovation, a new path." Pp. 11-56 in Social Innovation: a Decade of Changes. Luxembourg: Publications Office of the European Union. Social Innovation A Decade of Changes A BEPA report August 2014 Acknowledgements This report owes much to the personal commitment, knowledge and thoughts of Agnès Hubert, Maria da Graça Carvalho and Pierre Goudin of the Bureau of European Policy Advisers, with the support and input of Baudouin Regout, under the supervision of JeanClaude Thébault and Maria Angeles Benitez Salas. A number of European Commission officials from various policy departments also contributed to this report, in particular all the members of the interservice group on social innovation. BEPA would like to thank all the participating services for their very useful work and comments, especially reflected in part II of the report, namely DG AGRI, COMM, CONNECT, EAC, ECHO, EMPL, ENER, ENTR, HR, MARKT, MOVE, REGIO, RTD, SANCO and TAXUD. Extracts from reports produced or commissioned by the European Commission have also been used in various chapters or sections of the report and are typically acknowledged in footnotes mentioning the relevant references and internet links. BEPA would also like to thank Sid-Ahmed Talbi and Carmen Tresguerres for their help. Finally, we are very grateful to Aurélie Therace for her graphical and publishing support in producing the report. Disclaimer The analysis contained in this report does not necessarily reflect the views of the European Commission. Table of contents Acknowledgements...........................................................................................................................2 Introduction...........................................................................................................................................8 PART I Social innovation, a new path..................................................................................................11 1. Social innovation as a driver for change..........................................................13 1.1. An evolving context.......................................................................................................14 1.2. The social market economy concept .................................................................17 1.2.1. The origins of the concept........................................................................................17 1.2.2. The social market economy in the European arena...................................18 1.2.3. A new strategy for the Single Market ...............................................................18 1.3. Ecosystems for social innovation..........................................................................20 1.3.1. An approach to the concept of ecosystem......................................................20 1.3.2. Main components of an ecosystem for social innovation......................21 1.3.3. Examples of ecosystems for social innovation.............................................22 1.4. Measurement of social impact...............................................................................23 1.4.1. Evidence-based policies.............................................................................................25 1.4.2. Funding/financing social innovation....................................................................26 1.4.3. Indicators for a socially innovative society.....................................................28 2. Leading by example: how public sector innovation supports social innovation............................................................................................................31 2.1. The Commission’s commitment to supporting public sector innovation............................................................................................................31 2.2. Powering European public sector innovation: towards a new architecture.......................................................................................................................32 3. Achievements and lessons learned.....................................................................35 3.1. Deepening our understanding and knowledge of social innovation .........................................................................................................................36 3.1.1. The Mapping study........................................................................................................36 3.1.2. Social innovation research in the European Union.....................................37 3.2. Instruments to improve the ecosystem............................................................37 3.2.1. The social economy......................................................................................................37 3.2.2. Microfinance......................................................................................................................39 3.2.3. Incubation..........................................................................................................................41 4 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S 3.2.4. Workplace innovation..................................................................................................41 3.2.5. Changes in governance..............................................................................................42 3.3. Specific examples of actions from the field...................................................42 3.3.1. Social inclusion................................................................................................................43 3.3.2. Migration............................................................................................................................43 3.3.3. Urban regeneration.......................................................................................................44 3.3.4. Health and ageing.........................................................................................................45 3.3.5. Social innovation and the environment.............................................................46 3.3.6. Regional strategies.......................................................................................................47 3.3.7. Lessons learned from social innovation achievements...........................48 3.4. Social entrepreneurship to revive the social economy.............................49 4. Conclusion: scanning the future to shape the future................................51 Europe’s Societal Challenges...................................................................................52 So what future for Europe and which solutions? .........................................53 What will social enterprise look like in Europe by 2020?.........................54 The way forward.............................................................................................................55 Improve governance in relation to social innovation..................................55 Focus on knowledge.....................................................................................................56 Support, encourage and improve the business environment.................56 PART II Main developments in EU policies.........................................................................................57 Executive summary.......................................................................................................................58 1. The Dominant Policy Framework 2010-20: smart, sustainable and inclusive Growth...................................................................................................59 1.1. Europe 2020 flagship initiatives............................................................................60 1.1.1. A resource-efficient Europe......................................................................................61 1.1.2. An industrial policy for the globalisation era.................................................61 1.1.3. Digital Agenda for Europe .......................................................................................62 1.1.4. Innovation Union............................................................................................................63 1.1.5. Youth on the Move........................................................................................................64 1.1.6. The agenda for new skills and jobs.....................................................................65 1.1.7. The European Platform against Poverty and Social Exclusion.............66 1.2. Consolidating the Single Market: Single Market Acts and the Social Business Initiative .......................................................................67 5T A B L E O F C O N T E N T S 1.3. The environment and resource efficiency.........................................................69 a. Making energy an integral part of governance and management...................................................................................................69 b. Empowering the consumer................................................................................70 c. The emergence of the energy-literate prosumer..................................71 d. Social lessons from Energy technology demonstration....................71 1.4. A new approach to social policy: the Social Investment Package (SIP)....................................................................................................................71 2. Main programmes, action plans and supporting schemes.....................75 2.1. European Structural and Investment Funds (ESIF).....................................76 2.1.1. European Social Fund..................................................................................................77 2.1.2. European Regional Development Fund (ERDF).............................................78 2.1.3. The European Agricultural Fund for Rural Development (EAFRD)......79 2.2. Horizon 2020: coupling research to innovation............................................81 2.3. The Programme for Employment and Social Innovation EaSI (2014-20) to follow the PROGRESS programme.........................................82 a. Social innovation and social policy experimentation supported through the PROGRESS programme.....................................82 b. Targeted support to social policy innovation projects through direct funding through the EaSI programme...........................................83 c. The Programme for Employment and Social Innovation (EaSI)......................................................................................................84 2.4. Other programmes and action plans ................................................................85 2.4.1 The COSME programme: the competitiveness of SMEs............................85 2.4.2. Erasmus for Young Entrepreneurs programme ...........................................85 2.4.3. The Erasmus+ programme for education, training, youth and sport (2014-20)..................................................................86 2.4.4. The new Creative Europe Programme (2014-20) .....................................87 2.4.5. Innovation for a Sustainable Future – The Eco-innovation Action Plan (EcoAP)......................................................................................................87 3. Initiatives and instruments.......................................................................................89 3.1. Governance and coordination.................................................................................89 3.1.1. Social innovation debate with policymakers..................................................90 3.1.2. Powering public sector innovation........................................................................92 3.1.3. Policy guidance on social innovation..................................................................93 3.1.4. New practices for making policy...........................................................................94 3.1.4.1. Expert groups and networks....................................................................................95 6 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S 3.1.4.2. European Innovation Partnerships.......................................................................96 a. The European Innovation Partnership on Active and Healthy Ageing (EIP-AHA).....................................................................................................96 b. The European Innovation Partnership on Agricultural Productivity and Sustainability (EIP-AGRI)................................................97 c. The European Innovation Partnership on Water.....................................97 d. The European Innovation Partnership on Raw Materials .................98 e. The European Innovation Partnership on Smart Cities.......................98 3.1.4.3. The Open Innovation Strategy and Policy Group.........................................98 3.1.4.4. Living Labs........................................................................................................................99 3.1.4.5. Futurium.............................................................................................................................99 3.1.4.6. Participatory leadership in the European Commission ........................100 3.1.5. Create an optimised regulatory environment.............................................100 3.1.5.1. Simplification of the European Cooperative Regulation.......................100 3.1.5.2. Proposal for a European Foundation...............................................................101 3.1.5.3. Study on the situation of Mutual Societies and their cross-border activities.............................................................................................102 3.1.5.4. European Statute for other forms of social enterprises such as non-profit enterprises............................................................................102 3.1.5.5. Reform of public procurement: enhancement of quality in the award process......................................................................................................103 3.1.5.6. Increasing and including new aid categories in the revision of the General Block Exemption Regulation for state aid....................104 3.1.5.7. Employee financial participation........................................................................104 3.2. Financing capacities and facilities.....................................................................105 3.2.1. The EaSI programme for social innovation..................................................105 3.2.2. Access to venture capital – The European Venture Capital Funds............................................................................................................... 105 3.2.3. The European regulatory framework for social investment funds: the European Union Social Entrepreneurship Funds (EuSEF)............ 105 3.2.4. The development of microcredit/microfinance...........................................106 a. European Progress Microfinance Facility.................................................106 b. European Code of Good Conduct for Microcredit Provision...........107 3.2.5. Crowdfunding for social entrepreneurs..........................................................108 3.2.6. The EIF impact investing scheme .....................................................................109 3.2.7. Dormant funds.............................................................................................................109 3.2.8. Best practice sharing between Member States regarding the use of capital accumulated in social enterprises and in particular asset locks................................................................................ 109 7T A B L E O F C O N T E N T S 3.3. Capacity building and recognition.....................................................................110 3.3.1. Recognising social innovators..............................................................................110 3.3.1.1. Mapping of the social enterprises sector, business models, economic weight, tax regimes, identification of best practices........110 3.3.1.2. Database of labels and certifications of social enterprises...............110 3.3.1.3. Social innovation prizes..........................................................................................111 3.3.2. Networks..........................................................................................................................113 3.3.2.1. Networks of Incubators for Social Innovation............................................113 3.3.2.2. Social Innovation Europe (SIE)............................................................................113 3.3.2.3. The Collective Awareness Platforms initiative (CAPS)...........................115 3.3.2.4. Digital Social Platforms..........................................................................................117 3.3.2.5. Workplace Innovation Network...........................................................................118 3.3.2.6. Multi-stakeholder platform for corporate social responsibility........118 3.3.2.7. Policy innovation design.........................................................................................119 3.3.3. Empowering people...................................................................................................119 3.3.3.1. Skills, training and education...............................................................................120 3.3.3.2. Europe for Citizens Programme.........................................................................122 3.3.3.3. Network of twinned towns ...................................................................................123 3.3.3.4. Contribute to change - Young Women in Political Careers.................123 3.3.3.5. Citizens’ dialogues.....................................................................................................124 3.3.3.6 Other activities..............................................................................................................125 3.4. Research..........................................................................................................................125 3.4.1. ‘Social Sciences and Humanities’ and ‘Science with and for Society’........................................................................................................... 126 3.4.2. Social innovation in other thematic areas of research ........................128 3.4.3. Digital social innovation..........................................................................................128 3.4.4. Pilot projects in the areas of e-Inclusion, e-Health, e-Government, e-Learning and mobility....................................................... 129 3.4.5. Research on behaviour ...........................................................................................131 ANNEX I Examples of participatory projects convened by the European Commission�����������������������������������������������������������������������������135 ANNEX II A ‘checklist’ for citizens’ deliberations�����������������������������������������������������������139 8 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S Introduction In recent years, many initiatives and events have been carried out to develop pragmatic and participatory solutions to social and environmental problems that have been made more pressing by the crisis and have been addressed inadequately or not at all by either the market or the state. Converging analyses indicate that we are (or should be) on course for economic renewal and institutional change. A response based on another way to produce value, with less focus on financial profit and more on real demands or needs is indeed an attractive premise for reconsidering production and redistribution systems. In this context, social innovations, which are emerging all over the world, are still small in scale, but they are being echoed by changes in thinking and are delivering more and more effective and relevant solutions. The notion has gained ground that social innovation is not only about responding to pressing social needs and addressing the societal challenges of climate change, ageing or poverty, but is also a mechanism for achieving systemic change. It is seen as a way of tackling the underlying causes of social problems rather than just alleviating the symptoms. Some recent international reports have analysed and explained the emerging role of social innovation vis-à-vis economic and societal challenges from different angles: yy two successive OECD reports1 have largely linked its emergence to rising inequalities. Furthermore, they argue that the crisis has revealed the weakness of the current economic system of redistribution; yy the 2013 International Labour Organisation report2 notes that, in advanced economies, the challenge is to stimulate job creation while addressing macroeconomic imbalances; and yy taking a longer term perspective, the Oxford Martin Commission for Future Generations has published a report3 on successes and failures in addressing global challenges over recent decades. The report calls for a radical shake-up in politics and business to embed long-term thinking and provides practical recommendations for action in order to create a more resilient, inclusive and sustainable future. The European Union itself has reacted promptly to this evolution. A number of policy measures, such as pilot programmes funded by the Structural Funds, have been initiated to empower various actors to address collaboratively the needs of their community.4 1 Growing unequal?, 2008; http://www.oecd.org/social/soc/growingunequalincomedistributionandpovertyinoecdcountries.htm and Divided we stand, 2011; http://www.oecd.org/els/soc/dividedwestandwhyinequalitykeepsrising.htm. 2 Repairing the economic and social fabric (ILO, World of work report 2013). 3 Now for the Long Term, 2013; http://www.oxfordmartin.ox.ac.uk/downloads/commission/Oxford_Martin_Now_for_the_Long_Term.pdf. 4 Local Employment Initiatives, EQUAL, LEADER, URBAN, …; see in this respect the 25 year anniversary of AIEDL; http://www.aeidl.eu/en.html. 9P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H In 2009, the Bureau of European Policy Advisers (BEPA) organised a workshop5 with experts, civil society organisations, policymakers and social innovators. Following this workshop, President Barroso asked BEPA to investigate the definition and raison d’être of social innovation, document the Commission’s involvement in this field, identify the barriers to its development and suggest avenues for improvement. At that time, research on this topic had been mainly empirical and the first BEPA report, published in 2010, leveraged examples from the field in order to illustrate the emergence of the social innovation movement and contribute a light conceptual framework with a broad definition of social innovations, which underlined its collaborative process and outcome-oriented nature.6 Within a few years, policy support for social innovation has moved towards the centre of the political agenda. Inside the European Commission, the number of services involved has grown and a ‘social innovation’ culture has spread in support of the Europe 2020 Strategy and its implementation. Some of these services have developed strong legal and institutional mechanisms aimed primarily at supporting social innovation. This is the case for the internal market services, where the Social Business Initiative (SBI) is supported by a permanent stakeholders group (GECES) and a list of 11 actions to be followed up. This initiative has given birth to many projects and achievements, among which the ‘Strasbourg event’ of January 2014 (cf. Part I, § 3.4) was a hallmark. In other policy areas, some services upgraded the policy relevance of social innovation: yy Transport and mobility are now viewed as areas of potential for innovation with a strong social impact. Indeed, these areas use new working methods (such as public taxis for people with disabilities, driven by pensioners) combined with technology (safety sensors in cars and smartphone-based urban transport planners) and social innovation to support the uptake of new services (shared electric vehicle fleets and development of new logistics services); yy At present, innovation in the humanitarian aid sector is almost exclusively focused on technological innovations. However, when looking at long-term risk and the development of prevention and risk reduction, the human factor in social innovation could be a strong lever. The European Commission’s contribution to the World Humanitarian Summit in 2016 will concentrate more on social innovation; and yy The improvement of knowledge on social innovation through research, platforms, hubs and networks of researchers and transformative tools to open policy perspectives is increasingly supported in various policy areas such as education and culture, health and consumption, communication or technology. The services that have been most involved in this matter from the beginning (Employment and Social Affairs, Enterprise, Regional Policy, Agriculture, and Research and Innovation) have substantially increased their contributions. Finally, even internally, the European Commission increasingly uses participatory training courses and events for human resources in a more socially innovative way. 5 http://ec.europa.eu/dgs/policy_advisers/activities/conferences_workshops/socinnov_jan-2009_en.htm. 6 http://ec.europa.eu/bepa/pdf/publications_pdf/social_innovation.pdf. 10 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S All these developments – changes in the economic and social context, policy developments, particularly in the EU, in the social field, the development of new analytical frameworks – have led BEPA to update the initial report it produced in 2010 with the active participation of all Commission services, reflecting their increasing involvement in supporting social innovation. The first part of the report discusses the general context in which these policies and programmes have emerged and the developments which they relied upon to grow. It focuses on relevant changes that have occurred – and are still ongoing – since the publication of the first BEPA report. The first part starts by presenting social innovation as a driver for change, before listing some main achievements and lessons learned from a variety of examples from the field. Finally, it suggests some recommendations for future policymakers. The second part of the report presents factually, and as comprehensively as possible, the leading 2010-20 policy framework, the main programmes and supporting schemes and the initiatives and instruments established by the Commission to support social innovation, based on the contributions of participating services. PART I Social innovation, a new path 12 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S In 2009, when for the first time the European Commission organised a workshop on social innovation, it was an attempt to capture a subject that was becoming increasingly topical. Since then, although most of the contextual elements contained in the first BEPA report have been retained and even expanded, some elements of the landscape have changed significantly. This part of the report intends to point out these changes. It first presents social innovation as a driver for change before focusing on the growing role of the public sector in overcoming the barriers to social innovation, developing some of the achievements made and lessons learned in recent years and concluding with some recommendations to pave the way forward. 1. Social innovation as a driver for change The recent dynamic combination of interests, institutions and ideas for the promotion of social innovation has been embedded in wider political, technological and economic changes which have affected and will continue to affect the development of social innovation in the current decade. A significant change in the policy background has been the closer political attention paid to redefining the relationship between the social and the economic spheres.7 The economic concepts of capital and investment have become social policy instruments and corporate social responsibility is shifting from being a matter of charity to one of inclusion. This change has been conceptually supported in particular by the revival at EU level of the concept of the social market economy, which has shaped the recent exercise to deepen the Single Market and, in so doing, has secured a place for social innovation at the core of EU policies. The second change that we have identified as significant for the future is linked to the production of social innovations. Mobilising people and resources around a novel idea has never been easy (cf. Henri Dunant creating the Red Cross). This is only the first step of many.8 Each step entails a process of co-creation which initiates the next one. Together with the search for a favourable economic, legal, social ‘milieu’ to generate co-creation, the concept of ecosystems has been borrowed from biology through management science to describe the environments where social innovations emerge, grow and thrive. We will explore how this concept can help to defragment mental ‘silos’, work across boundaries and facilitate the sharing of information and knowledge, and identify the role and interest of public authorities in enabling social innovation ecosystems. The third change is related to measurement issues, which have become increasingly important as social innovation initiatives have mushroomed. Measuring social innovation should indeed help to achieve some crucial objectives, such as proving that it is an effective and sustainable way to respond to societal needs or showing that social and environmental value creation is central to the human and ecological sustainability of societies. 7 Social innovations, Institutional Change and Economic Performance, edited by T. J. Hamalainen and R. Heiskala, © Sitra, 2007. 8 See the six different stages for the production of social innovation identified in the first BEPA report, p. 54, or Ten Practical Steps to Implement Social Innovation in the Guide to Social Innovation. 14 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S 1.1. An evolving context ‘We are at the dawn of something new’ – emphatic rhetoric or a description of what was filling the room? This remark from the podium during the ‘Social entrepreneurs have your say’ event in January 2014 in Strasbourg illustrates the state of mind of the hundreds of ‘core actors’ from all over Europe who attended the meeting. They were not only describing their perceptions but expressing a wish to be part of this ‘something new’. From the stakeholders’ workshop held in 2009 with the President of the Commission, developments in policymaking circles – inside and outside the European Commission – are palpable. As already explained in the first BEPA social innovation report, the growing interest in social innovation has come from the continuous and increased need of public authorities, civil society organisations, private corporations and individuals to respond to the new social risks with new and more effective approaches and shrinking budgets. The crisis has enhanced that process. The new participation and sharing ethos of the social networks generation, as well as the renewed necessity for Europe to develop its innovation capabilities and the mounting interest in quality of life, are boosting factors. Since the beginning of the decade, three major developments have emerged. yy the players have evolved: social players have overcome their first negative reaction of seeing social innovation only as a partial privatisation of welfare, which is the state’s responsibility. They have now become active participants in the development of social innovations at local, national and European levels.9 In all Member States, representatives of the national and local authorities, social entrepreneurs and social economy organisations, the banking and finance sector and the academic and university sector play an active part in the consultative multi-stakeholders group set up by the Commission in 201210 and large groups of citizens all over the world are joining what has been called ‘a social innovation movement’.11 Traditional economic players have also radically changed their vision as the idea that social innovation is about bringing solutions to some of the complex problems of today is seen as nec- essary.12 The financial world at large is also taking a strong interest in the sector by developing ethical investment products, including ‘social and environmental impact financing’; yy the institutions are also changing: public authorities, in particular in the social, health and education fields, are committed both to being innovative inside and promoting new forms of financing, partnerships and alliances outside in order to improve their services to users and involve stakeholders; and yy last but not least, ideas, the third corner of the action triangle, have also developed and spread. The amount of research, projects, experiments, debates, documents, books, events produced on social innovation since the beginning of the decade is impressive. A body of literature now exists to frame the various terminology sets in the social innovation galaxy, and new research continues to explore definitions but also 9 See social platform position paper on social innovation http://www.socialplatform.org/wp-content/ uploads/2014/02/20131203_SocialPlatform_PositionPaper_social_innovation.pdf. 10 GECES http://ec.europa.eu/internal_market/social_business/expert-group/index_en.htm. 11 Unger Mangabeiro, Harvard Law School; https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=b9c3PppXk1w. 12 The Solution Revolution: How business, government and social enterprises are teaming up to solve society’s toughest problems, William D. Eggers and Paul Macmillan (Harvard Business review press, 2013). 15P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H investment models, development and evaluation methodologies from an empirical as well as a conceptual perspective and the underpinnings of social innovation. EU funded research has played a crucial role in this field by funding comparative research on a large scale, encouraging both academic excellence and the practical application of results. We undoubtedly know more now about this ‘volatile’ or ‘quasi’ concept13 of social innovation, the governance structures and the role of public authorities, the capacity building, the financing capacities needed to allow social innovations to emerge, grow, scale up and spread. We know more about how social innovations are useful to local welfare systems and services and how they contribute to poverty reduction, combating inequalities and changing lifestyles. We also know more about their conditions for sustainability and the views of stakeholders. Empirical research has helped to identify where change is happening and needs to be encouraged. Conceptual research has achieved milestones in defining and framing what is really at stake. As argued by Geoff Mulgan,14 ‘[s]ocial innovation is an asset to discover the future through action rather than believing it can be discovered solely through analysis’. Furthermore, the picture would not be complete if at this point we did not address the emergence of a phenomenon that significantly affects social innovation: the rise of a hyperconnected society. The rise of the collaborative economy – from AirBnB (the social networking service for bed and breakfast) to car sharing or ‘Code4share’ to ‘Wikipedia’ – is indeed a characteristic of the recent period which goes beyond just inventing new business models. Digital social innovation is a new kind of innovation enabled by the network effect of the internet, which is leading to new models of collaborative production and content sharing which radically change the competition and supply and demand equations of traditional business models. On this issue, a study conducted by a consortium of partners15 is currently building a map of digital social innovation actors and networks. In this context, there are some challenges for the EU. yy First, in the reconfiguration of the economy which is currently taking place under the influence of network giants, how is Europe to take advantage of open and collaborative possibilities to tackle societal challenges? How is it to leverage the power of the large number of social networks of active citizens and communities who often operate under the radar?16 The potential of using digital technologies to enable better and more social innovation to engage stakeholders, citizens, geeks and civil society communities in the innovation process cannot be neglected. Considering the distributed nature of digital social innovation and its openness to new players, research based on a bottom-up approach reveals new forms of social innovation and 13 This term was coined by Jane Jenson in Social innovation. Gadget, Concept or Mobilising Idea?; www.cccg. umontreal.ca. It is defined as ‘a hybrid, making use of empirical analysis and thereby deploying scientific methods, but simultaneously having an indeterminate quality, making it adaptable to a variety of situations and flexible enough to follow the twists and turns of policy’. ‘It is more than a buzzword, it has a reputable intellectual basis but may be vulnerable to criticism on theoretical, analytical and empirical grounds’. 14 Quoted in The world in 2025, contributions of an expert group, January 2009, p.69. 15 Study on innovation in the Digital Agenda conducted by Nesta, Waag Society, ESADE, IRI and Future Everything; http://digitalsocial.eu. 16 See study by IPTS; http://ipts.jrc.ec.europa.eu/publications/pub.cfm?id=4339. 16 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S new organisational forms that can be encouraged, scaled up and incorporated into institutional frameworks; and yy secondly, how to set up the best institutional framework for harnessing the networked collective intelligence of people to tackle major social issues and produce recognised value for Europe in terms of community wellbeing, ecological footprint, and democratic legitimacy?17 17 For examples of the impact on democracy, see the 2013 World Forum Rewiring democracy – connecting institutions and citizens in the digital age. Further information is available at: http://www.epsiplatform.eu/ content/world-forum-democracy#sthash.iqvUpOPH.dpuf. A public private partnership on decentralised, open, privacy-aware architectures for the social good (including open data and public federated identity management) The internet ecosystem currently faces two major and urgent problems: In 2011 the Commission launched an initiative to pool a range of European funds to promote evidence-based social innovation, initially concentrating on social assistance schemes. the Commission’s initiative includes: • a handful of non-European companies continue to consolidate their leading positions in data aggregation and capture collective intelligence via lock-ins, monopolistic behaviour and aggressive IP litigation. Most users have accepted their exploitative business models in exchange for free services. This deal not only undermines privacy and weakens data protection, but also commodifies knowledge, identity, and personal data. Unfortunately, most European ICT research is developed to fit into this centralised model, which only aggravates the situation; and • the European Commission has been funding excellent basic research on the Internet of Things (IoT) and the Future Internet area. However, there is no strategic vision guiding EU research. Projects do not give rise to an alternative playing field since they promote the kind of short-term incremental developments that only reinforce the dominant positions mentioned above. While Europe has an unrivalled density of infrastructure and research potential, the lack of overall coherence in its vision contributes to the consolidation of non-European companies. An alternative framework is needed to provide an open architecture for the integrated management of online identity, security, data, and collective governance, based on democratic and participatory processes. The only practical response is the development of distributed and decentralised solutions for future critical infrastructures in the three main areas set out below: 1. Distributed architectures: this includes the need for open data distributed repositories, distributed cloud, distributed search and distributed social networking. It can also include the development of new mobile platforms able to ensure some basic services at European level, on top of which a whole new open ecosystem of services and applications could flourish in a participatory innovation model based on open source and open hardware development; 2. Public federated identity management for the entire EU: weave identity management into the EU Digital Infrastructure by applying a federated model to the entire Union. The agency that public or private providers have controls which platforms it talks to and the platform determines which services, products or spin-offs are supported. The aim should be to turn the current passport into an open source mesh-networked device; and 3. New governance modalities for big data (main question around collective ownership of data, data portability and data as knowledge commons): the question is how to ensure user control over personal information in an ocean of commercially valuable big data. Citizens should be aware that technical solutions do not work by themselves, therefore legal and commercial solutions have to be based on technology and integrated with the appropriate policy framework. Defining sensible governance modalities for big data will require substantial collaboration between the public and private sectors, based on a multi-stakeholder model, in order to define the minimum level of sensible regulation allowing fair competition in the emerging areas of big data. 17P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H To stimulate thought on this issue, Francesca Bria18 has described how the EU could take advantage of the shift from closed innovation to collaborative, open innovation. Her contribution is summarised below. 1.2. The social market economy concept 1.2.1. The origins of the concept The term ‘social market economy’ emerged in the post-World War II period, when Germany was looking for a new economic, political and social start. It is strongly associated with what has been coined the post-war ‘German economic miracle’. At the time, the idea was to find a renewed impetus for a laissez-faire market-based economy, rejecting the centrally planned and state-directed system of the previous period while ensuring a social and political consensus. Men like Ludwig Erhard, Alfred Müller-Armack and some of their collaborators coined the term ‘social market economy’ as a new and comprehensive understanding of a free market and socially-orientated economic order. It became the hallmark of their political and social aspirations. It entailed two ideas: first, that a market economy was a better way to improve living standards; secondly, that the market order can serve the aims of social security and protection, as long as it is flanked by the right economic and social policies. In other words, market economics and social security do not exclude each other, but which comes first? Two different schools of thought gave a different meaning to this concept. On the one hand, the Ordoliberalism of Eucken, Rüstow and Böhm (also known as the Freiburg School, to which Hayek could be added) acknowledged that protection against poverty, unemployment, illness and old age are important as long as they ‘are not pursued in conflict with the rules of the market’. On the other hand, Müller-Armack (later secretary-of-state to Ludwig Erhard) and Wilhelm Röpke had stronger views on the primacy of social aims since they rooted this concept in Christian Democratic ethics. For historic reasons, most people in Germany strongly supported the concept (and its somewhat contradictory interpretations) provided it was efficient. The social market economy was the conceptual framework for the ‘German economic miracle’ and deemed critical for ensuring economic ‘prosperity for all’ and social justice. As a result of growing inequalities and the perceived unfairness of the social protection system, however, some people started to question the efficiency of the iconic model. In 2008, for example, only 31 % of all Germans said they had a ‘good opinion’ of the social market economy, a figure that had risen to 38 % by the beginning of 2010. While it remains a rallying political concept, the social market economy and the best ways to balance in the future the ideals of freedom, social justice and economic growth are now being revisited.19 This short history of the term gives some idea of its heuristic but ambiguous meanings from its origins to the present. Today the term which ‘blended market capitalism, strong labour protection and union influence, and a generous welfare state’ does not 18 Senior Project Lead, Innovation Lab, EU Project Coordinator D-CENT - DSI. 19 cf. for instance: http://www.bertelsmann-stiftung.de/cps/rde/xchg/bst_engl/hs.xsl/269.htm. 18 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S fit the current reforms of the welfare state but, as pointed out by The Economist,20 the ‘social market economy’ broadly refers to the study of the different social institutions underpinning every market economy and it has been used to describe attempts to make capitalism more caring and to the use of market mechanisms to increase the efficiency of the social functions of the state. 1.2.2. The social market economy in the European arena The four freedoms (free circulation of goods, services, capital and people) at the heart of the EU’s Single Market are commonly seen as economic instruments to favour increased competition, specialisation and economies of scale, improve the efficiency of the allocation of resources and drive economic integration within the EU. The question is: should this driver be geared solely to economic growth or should it serve the goals of social as well as economic cohesion? On this issue, the debates of the European Convention for the Future of Europe (2003-05) were heated. The idea of a powerful Single Market underpinning international competitiveness and the creation of growth and jobs as the ultimate end of the European Union was rather dominant. After the crisis, the European social model and its aim of producing wellbeing for all is more often seen as an important goal of European integration. In contrast with the distinction which appears more obvious today, the term ‘social market economy’ in the text of the Constitution suited everyone and was embedded in the Treaty21 as it seemed to opportunely reflect the views of liberals, Christian Democrats and Social Democrats.22 1.2.3. A new strategy for the Single Market ‘The crisis has induced some critical reconsideration of the functioning of markets. It has also enhanced concerns about the social dimension. The Treaty of Lisbon, soon to enter into force, makes it explicit for the first time …that ‘the Union [...] shall work [...] for a highly competitive social market economy. All this calls for a fresh look at how the market and the social dimensions of an integrated European economy can be mutually strengthened.’ This excerpt from the mission letter from the President of the European Commission, José Manuel Barroso, inviting former Competition Commissioner, Mario Monti, to prepare a report setting out recommendations for an initiative to relaunch the Single Market clearly sets the new tone. The existing tensions between market integration and social objectives are more vividly exposed now that the Lisbon Treaty has formally introduced the objective of achieving a ‘highly competitive social market economy’. ‘If the market and the social components do not find an appropriate reconciliation, something has to give in. Following the crisis, with the declining appetite for the market and the increasing concern about inequalities, it is by no means clear that it would be the market, i.e. the 20 http://www.economist.com/economics-a-to-z/s#node-21529660. 21 Article 3 of the Treaty on European Union states: ‘The Union shall establish an internal market. It shall work for the sustainable development of Europe based on balanced economic growth and price stability, a highly competitive social market economy, aiming at full employment and social progress, and a high level of protection and improvement of the quality of the environment’. 22 At the time, it was interpreted as a symbolic ideological gain for the European socialists (The European Convention: bargaining in the Shadow of Rhetoric, Paul Magnette and Kalypso Nicolaidis – published in: West European Politics, April 2004). 19P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H Single Market, to prevail.’ In his report,23 Professor Monti clearly identified public services (or services of general economic interest) as being at the centre of social concerns. This was a window of opportunity to enable bottom-up creativity, particularly in the way services are delivered and matching the needs of users. The Monti Report raised the need to reinforce the Single Market through a series of concrete measures. This was done in a two-stage approach in April 2011 and October 2012.24 It is interesting to note that, whereas the initial impulse to reinforce the social content of the Single Market had come from a top-down initiative, the idea of developing ‘new emerging business models in which social, ethical or environmental objectives are pursued alongside financial profit’, submitted for consultation as part of a list of 12 possible initiatives to strengthen neglected aspects of the Single Market, was strongly supported by the public in the answers to this consultation. This unanimity should not hide underlying ambiguities in overcoming corporatist approaches and acquired interests in the sphere of the social economy, and different understandings in Europe of what constitutes a social enterprise or business. As acknowledged in an OECD report on social entrepreneurship25 ‘[e]ven if social entrepreneurship as an activity is developing quickly around the world and social innovations are appearing everywhere, these are both relatively recent fields of research and practice and the notions are still ill-defined. A term like social entrepreneurship tends to overlap with terms such as social economy, third sector, non-profit sector, social enterprise and social entrepreneur, some of which are also ill‑defined and overlapping. Moreover, definitions are context‑sensitive, in the sense that the geographical and cultural contexts matter’. For instance, traditions within Europe vary: the German approach differs from the Italian or British early development of cooperatives or from the successful concept in France of économie sociale et solidaire, to name just a few of the contexts where social entrepreneurship linked to social innovations is developing. Conceptual clarity is needed but cannot be imposed in a top-down approach. It has to be worked out progressively by actors, who are now speaking to each other, taking the best from each tradition, while adapting to a new common post-crisis reality. Following long discussions on definitions during the preparation of the text of the Social Business Initiative, it was finally agreed that rather than reduce a still‑developing idea to an overly narrow definition, social entrepreneurship should be defined on the basis of three main characteristics: yy the social objective was the reason for developing innovative activities; yy profits were mainly invested in achieving this social objective; and yy the organisation and ownership used participatory principles aiming at social justice. The actual development and content of the SBI are described in detail in the second part of this document. What must be stressed at this stage is that: yy social entrepreneurship should be placed in the main ‘engine room’ of European integration: the Single Market raised social innovation to a new level of recognition, 23 http://ec.europa.eu/bepa/pdf/monti_report_final_10_05_2010_en.pdf. 24 http://ec.europa.eu/internal_market/smact/index_en.htm. 25 SMEs, Entrepreneurship and Innovation, contribution of Antonella Noya (OECD, 2010). 20 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S allowing major instruments such as public procurement directives or competition policy to engage with the development of this ‘emerging’ sector; and yy the way it has been developed has been participatory26 and all‑encompassing,27 i.e. through a systemic change in approach rather than through incremental changes in the institutional infrastructure of the business world. 1.3. Ecosystems for social innovation 1.3.1. An approach to the concept of ecosystem For some time now, management scholars have recognised the parallels between biological and economic systems. The concept of an ecosystem – which in biology refers to an environment where different, sometimes competing, species can complement each other – has been used in particular by Michael Porter,28 who underlined that the traditional framework of industries made up of competitors, suppliers and customers does not pay enough attention to the many other actors and environments in an industry: the organisations making complementary products, the infrastructure on which the organisation depends, and the various institutions, people, and interest groups that affect the entire industry, including the end users or consumers. An ecosystem’s framework, in contrast, incorporates the broader environment within which organisations operate. It captures the elements of Porter’s economic analysis, adds other potentially important actors, and incorporates the non-market forces. This framework is particularly appropriate for the production of social innovation, as their promoters (social entrepreneurs, intrapreneurs, etc.) must leverage complex systems of interacting players in rapidly evolving political, economic, physical and cultural environments. Moreover, the more innovative the initiative, the more likely it is to come up against the aversion to change of those who have stakes in the system as it is. Today, ecosystems for social innovation are seen as the way to create an innovation-friendly environment where social innovations can grow and to address not only the apparent cause but also the underlying problems. The shift from social innovation as a charitable solution to a problem that has an immediate but unsustainable impact (e.g. give food to the hungry) to the transformative ambition to create long-lasting changes to solve societal problems (e.g. homelessness, food disorders) that are engrained in behaviours and institutional and cultural context (laws, policies, social norms) has also been a reason to look for a ‘friendly milieu’ to organise interactions and respond to the needs of social innovations at every stage of their development. Thus, the term ‘ecosystem’ has spread within the social innovation community as a response to the different 26 It started with a wide consultation and was shaped by three European Commissioners, i.e. the Commissioners responsible for the Single Market (M. Barnier), Employment and Social Affairs (L. Andor) and Enterprise (A. Tajani). 27 The Social Business Initiative was launched with a Communication on corporate social responsibility and a revision of the Transparency Directive as a package to increase trust: ‘Social business is a good example of an approach to business that is both responsible and contributes to growth and jobs. But we need to ensure all companies, not just social businesses, take their impact on wider society seriously: that's why I also want big multinationals [….] to be more open about what they are paying to governments across the world’ (Michel Barnier). 28 The Competitive Advantage of Nations, 1990. 21P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H needs to structure, experiment, nurture, network, support, scale up and transfer social innovations at the different stages of their development. 1.3.2. Main components of an ecosystem for social innovation Supportive policies, adequate governance, innovative finance, a variety of capacity building and recognition tools such as incubators, hubs, forums, prizes and research in methodologies, benchmarking and impact measurement are the main components which, together, create the ‘natural environment’ for social innovation to flourish. While the movement and creative energy in the ecosystem comes from the actors and their connections, the administrative, economic and legal environment has to be enabling. Where the priority objective is to solve a problem of a social or societal nature, people (in whatever capacity they act) have to pool their resources and work together. Often, a dominant administrative culture or conflicting objectives prevent this. The key to supportive governance is to identify those obstacles and create spaces for cooperation and for thinking outside the box. Promoting a culture of trust and learning from failures is also part of supportive governance. Governments have to set up enabling processes and institutions to encourage the creation of ecosystems which mobilise collective energy and initiative to develop, mostly small-scale but effective solutions to improve quality of life. Social entrepreneurship (or intrapreneurship), the main vector to channel action in this field is often small, can also be larger29 and usually has a transformative agenda. The use of digital tools to reach their goals is already quite widespread amongst social innovators (e.g. Websourd30 uses a call centre to translate job interviews, etc.). Increasingly, however, digital tools are also used as a core element to mobilise collective intelligence for the co-creation of public goods (e.g. Code for America,31 Nudge,32 etc.). This gives a radically new dimension to social innovations and the ecosystems which can allow them to grow. Communication technologies create very large and open spaces for the self-organisation and mobilisation of society which enlarge the scope of civil society mobilisation and generate new issues of control and trust (see the Digital Social Innovation project33 and the Onlife Initiative for rethinking public spaces in the digital transition34 ). Access to resources and/or funding is another crucial component, which has to be available in different forms at the right time. From access to public procurement or small experimental grants to investments in large projects likely to bring substantial social benefits in the medium to long term (e.g. investment in the social integration of prisoners to eventually reduce crime). As illustrated in the Malmö example mentioned below, this can even include regrouping investments to achieve the same social objective and involving stakeholders and end users can often double or treble the impact of budgets and or investments. 29 cf. for example SOS (http://www.groupe-sos.org). 30 http://www.websourd.org/; http://www.websourd-entreprise.fr/. 31 http://codeforamerica.org/. 32 R. Thaler & C. Sunstein, Yale University Press, 2009. 33 https://webgate.ec.europa.eu/socialinnovationeurope/directory/switzerland/event/digital-social-innovation- workshop. 34 http://ec.europa.eu/digital-agenda/en/onlife-initiative. 22 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S Any collective endeavour where the mobilisation of energies is the main resource needs catalysing places and instruments where collective work is valued and recognised (or at least not penalised). Incubators to generate the birth and growth as well as tools to exchange, compare and value are other essential components of the social innovation ecosystem. The fourth ingredient to create a fertile environment for initiating innovative practices of a disruptive nature is to develop evidence of a different nature that is likely to work and yield measurable results, but also to develop methodologies from empirical and theoretical observations to develop or scale up successful experiments. Thus, research is an essential component of the ecosystem. A striking example of the development above is the study entitled A map of social enterprises and their ecosystems in Europe.35 The European Commission called for this study in April 2013 to establish for the first time an overview of national policies, schemes and actions aimed at promoting social enterprises and supporting the development of a conducive ecosystem where it exists as well as the current state and dynamics of social investments markets. This was only done for 11 Member States.36 It studies the following issues for these countries: the political and legal recognition of the concept of social enterprise; public support schemes; whether marks and labelling schemes are in use, the social investment markets. Finally, it assesses the opportunities and barriers for each country. This first exercise shows wide differences amongst Member States regarding the degree of maturity of the ecosystem. In countries with a long tradition of social economy like Italy and France, a variety of well-established tools have been developed while in newcomers like Latvia or Romania, the recognition and the private and public support systems for social business is still in its infancy but in great demand. In itself, this study is a resource for policymakers, social entrepreneurs and stakeholders in social business in general as it provides timely information on when, where and how social entrepreneurs can find an understanding and friendly environment to initiate, develop and scale up social enterprises. 1.3.3. Examples of ecosystems for social innovation As mentioned above, the growing importance of social enterprises in the EU social innovation policy framework emphasises the importance of developing an enabling environment made of specific instruments, a more understanding environment and to develop innovative tools (e.g. European Partnerships) to stimulate interaction between actors in fertile ground. A large number of public or private actors at national and local level can take advantage of this new policy focus. Two very different case studies can be mentioned to illustrate these issues: yy firstly, Oksigen37 is a dynamic Belgian consortium established on the private initiative of likeminded individuals. It covers every stage of a social innovation’s develop- 35 http://ec.europa.eu/internal_market/social_business/docs/expert-group/20131128-sbi-sector-mapping-study_ en.pdf. 36 Denmark, Finland, France, Hungary, Romania, Latvia, Poland, Italy, Spain, Ireland and Belgium. 37 For more information, please refer to: http://www.oksigen.eu/ and http://www.i-propeller.com/. 23P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H ment, including tutoring and mentoring, the search for diverse sources of financing, upscaling and transfer and integrates applied research. It offers a springboard for leveraging the effects of public and private programmes and funds aimed at developing effective solutions to new or unaddressed social or societal needs; yy secondly, a multicultural city like Malmö,38 which is strategically putting in place an ambitious plan of ‘ecosystems’, is a good example of what can be done in this area. Local authorities together with welfare services and local economic actors have a vested interest in identifying more efficient solutions to address concrete social problems and improve the quality of life in their community. The idea is to fundamentally reassess all the direct and indirect social ‘costs’ and reallocate them in a dynamic and interactive process to benefit people in the community with a longterm impact. This cannot be done unless you create an ecosystem where administrations working in silos, economic actors willing to serve their community as well as their business interest and those citizens most concerned, are given a common framework where they can interact, design and implement. 1.4. Measurement of social impact There are at least four reasons for tackling the challenge of measuring social innovation. First, there is a need to prove that social innovation is an effective and sustainable way to respond to societal needs (from this perspective, the belief that after the crisis, social innovation can play a pivotal role in serving as a competitive future advantage for European economies and societies has been underlined in many EU documents.39 The Guide to Social Innovation, published in 2013, states in particular ‘Europe is ideally placed to take a lead and capture first-mover benefits when it comes to implementing social innovations by proactively and effectively trying to fully (and fairly) realise both economic and societal benefits’). Second, justifying the allocation of public money as well as attracting other sources of public and private financing requires a shared understanding of what the ‘positive and measurable social effects’40 of social innovations are. Third, evidence-based policies require ex ante evidence of the expected impact of the actions involved. Finally, social innovations (seen as drivers in the current transition41 ) could open the way to developing a new competitive advantage for European economies, showing that social and environmental value creation is central to the human and ecological sustainability of societies. The reasons why social innovations are difficult to measure are of course proportional to their scope (i.e. the smaller the objective, the easier the measurement). This difficulty is also explained by the fact that their success relies on factors which, by their nature, are difficult to quantify, at least in the short to medium term. Indeed, their success relies on how they have been able to act as drivers of social change,42 to break with established 38 www.malmo.se/kommission. 39 The Innovation Union flagship initiative introduced social innovation as a driver of a European innovation strategy and this idea has since guided developments in research and innovation policy, enterprise and industry in particular. 40 This is the terminology used by EU institutions (Commission, Parliament, Economic and Social Committee) to frame the notion of social impact in the EuSEF (European Social Entrepreneurship Funds) and EaSI (European Programme for Employment and Social Innovation). 41 See The EU's Fifth Project - Transitional Governance in the Service of Sustainable Societies http://www.uclouvain.be/461789.html. 42 Social innovations as drivers of social change, J. Howaldt, R. Kopp & M. Schwarz, 2013. 24 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S approaches43 and to engage a process of changing behaviours, ‘basic routines, resource and authority flows, or beliefs of the social system’ in which they occur.44 The benefits of overcoming the challenge of measuring social innovation will allow further developments in different aspects of social innovation at a crucial moment for the post-crisis economy. Both micro-level measurement (how successfully a social enterprise is contributing to this goal) and macro-level measurement (social enterprises grow in an ecosystem composed of a favourable governance framework, capacity-building tools and learning processes) have become necessary. Measures of the success/impact of social innovation is the increasingly shared idea that ‘economic outcomes have for a long time been the main indicator to measure the development of organisations and countries, but a more holistic perspective considering social, environmental and economic consequences must come to the fore to build a sustainable world’.45 Awareness of this has increased in recent years since climate change and inequalities are on the rise. Even before widespread political attention was drawn to this agenda by the Report on the Measurement of Economic and Social Progress46 (known as the Stiglitz-Sen-Fitoussi report), the Commission had already held a large forum on Beyond GDP47 in 2007. This was followed by a Communication on GDP and Beyond – Measuring progress in a changing world,48 highlighting the need for new instruments to monitor and measure environmental and social development and establishing a roadmap. A review of progress on GDP and beyond actions was published in 2013.49 In addition, other actors have also taken steps to introduce new instruments, e.g. the OECD with its Better Life Index.50 Many analysts around the world believe that it is necessary to measure wellbeing or quality of life in order to better respond to the needs of this century. As far as social innovation is concerned, this is likely to kick-start the systemic change mentioned inter alia in the first BEPA report, by bringing to the fore the value of non-tradeable goods and services that contribute to wellbeing. Against this background, we examine below the need for social impact measurement and guidance on how it should be carried out in the specific context of: yy evidence-based policies; and yy funding/financing social innovation; and to yy follow progress so far in the area of indicators and social impact measurement. 43 Social Innovation: Blurring Boundaries to Reconfigure Markets, A. Nicholls & A. Murdock; Palgrave Macmillan, 2011. 44 Making a Difference - Strategies for Scaling Social Innovation for Greater Impact, Frances Westley and Nino Antadze (presented at the Social Frontiers social innovation research conference, November 2013). 45 EESC report on social impact measurement. 46 http://www.stiglitz-sen-fitoussi.fr/documents/rapport_anglais.pdf. 47 http://ec.europa.eu/environment/beyond_gdp/index_en.html. 48 COM(2009) 433 final. 49 http://ec.europa.eu/environment/enveco/pdf/SWD_2013_303.pdf. 50 www.betterlifeindex.org. . 25P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H 1.4.1. Evidence-based policies Public policy development increasingly requires accountability as well as efficiency to ensure the best use of resources. While coarse assessments can in some cases be the way to approximate a cost benefit analysis due to urgent circumstances, scientifically based methods are increasingly used to compare (ex ante) the benefits that a community would derive from a specific measure or scheme to a comparable community which did not have this measure or scheme. The principle of social experimentation to test a policy intervention on a small population so as to evaluate its efficacy before deciding whether it should be scaled up is on the agenda of many policymakers wishing to design a potentially policy-relevant intervention as well as measure its actual efficacy. Existing methods for assessing a project’s chances of success and their different costs are detailed in a methodological guide for policymakers,51 published by the Commission in September 2011 in order to assist policymakers in designing socially innovative projects. This guide sets out basic principles to follow in order to design a potentially policy-relevant intervention. It describes six commonly used methods of evaluation, which are compared from the point of view of the reliability of the results they deliver; and considers the costs associated with each method, and the complexity of implementing them in practice. The ‘gold standard’ for these methods goes to randomised experiments. They draw from the principle of randomised controlled trial used in scientific experiment, and in particular clinical trials to test the efficacy or effectiveness of various types of medical interventions in a patient population. The use of randomised trials to test solutions was pioneered by Esther Duflo, professor at MIT and Director of the Abdul Latif Jameel Poverty Action Lab,52 which has now grown into a global network of professors who use randomised evaluations to answer critical policy questions in the fight against poverty. This network has conducted over 500 randomised evaluations in 57 countries. Some of the policy lessons have led to the scaling up of programmes which have improved the lives of millions of individuals. These include school-based deworming programmes as one of the most effective methods for improving school participation in developing countries or providing free access to chlorine dispensers at water sources to reduce the death of children under five.53 Nevertheless, randomised evaluations of social programmes take time and can be complex to implement. Many authors in the open literature have discussed the benefits and limitations of randomised social experimentation as a tool for evaluating social programmes.54 Other techniques also commonly used are referred to as non-experimental or quasi-experimental methods. They are usually less complex to implement than randomised evaluations, but the results they deliver are also less reliable. It appears that random assignment to the treatment and comparison groups is the best way to ensure that the comparison group is similar in every respect to the treatment group. Non-experimental 51 Written by J-Pal Europe at the request of
the European Commission's Directorate-General for Employment, Social Affairs and Inclusion. 52 http://www.povertyactionlab.org/. 53 http://www.povertyactionlab.org/scale-ups/chlorine-dispensers-safe-water. 54 See for example Randomization and Social Policy Evaluation, James Heckman, NBER Technical Working Paper No 107, July 1991. 26 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S methods must rely on an assumption to justify the claim that the comparison group they use is similar to the treatment group. In order to test measures aimed at the development of new social practices and/or the reorganisation of existing ones in EU Member States, the PROGRESS programme (2008-12) allocated EUR 10 million to developing social policy experiments. Thirty-six projects focusing on the social and professional inclusion of vulnerable groups were financed. Hope in stations: HOmeless PEople in train stations was one of these projects. In the new programme for employment and social innovation, technical assistance for conducting randomised evaluations is made available to administrations undertaking social policy reforms. Thus, the rapid development of this subject has proven its intrinsic interest. It is to be expected that the wide range of research projects and scientific publications on this topic will lead to enhanced cooperation on the quantification and measurement of social impact and on designing and assessing social policies. 1.4.2. Funding/financing social innovation A sound technique for measuring the impact of the social innovation is a prerequisite for funding/financing social innovation. The recent period has been characterised by the emergence of a wider diversity of funding sources for innovative ventures with a social objective from the public and private sectors. This proliferation of funding/financing mechanisms has led to the urgent need to further develop methods for measuring the social and economic benefits. Public bodies at every level have worked to increase the offer, from dedicated microfinance funds to public procurement,55 but the financial and banking sector are taking a growing interest in ‘impact finance’ and the public at large responds, where legislation permits, to calls to ‘crowdfund’ social ventures. This is good news as one of the major barriers to the development of social innovation identified in the first BEPA report was access to finance, but also overdependence on grants from charities, foundations and public support, in particular when growth capital is needed to engage in long-term ventures. This aspect has raised considerable attention, in particular at EU level, since the launch of the Social Business Initiative. The Commission’s Communication on the Single Market Act II56 highlighted the need to develop methods for measuring the social and economic benefits generated by social enterprises in the implementation of the EuSEF57 and the programme for Employment and Social Innovation (EaSI).58 In response, a subgroup of the Commission’s consultative multi-stakeholder group on social enterprise (GECES) 55 As illustrated in part 2 of this document. 56 http://ec.europa.eu/internal_market/smact/docs/single-market-act2_en.pdf. 57 The Regulation on European social entrepreneurship funds (EuSEFs) was published in the Official Journal on 25 April 2013. Together with the Regulation on European venture capital funds (EuVECA) and the Alternative Investment Fund Managers Directive (AIFMD), this Regulation aims to make it easier for AIFMD-exempt venture capitalists and social entrepreneurs to raise funds across Europe without the requirement to comply with the full AIFMD regime.  The key elements of the Regulation provide for an EU brand for EuSEFs and the introduction of a European marketing passport.  The range of eligible financing tools/investments under the EuSEF Regulation is wider than those available for venture capital funds under the EVCF Regulation. 58 The third axis of this programme focuses on microfinance and social entrepreneurship with a fund of EUR 86 million over seven years to provide grants, investments and guarantees to social enterprises which can demonstrate that they have a ‘measurable social impact’. 27P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H was tasked with providing the Commission with guidelines on how social enterprise can measure their social impact on the community. The report adopted by the GECES in June 2014 makes a set of recommendations and defines areas where follow-up is required. It underlines the benefit that a standard for social impact measurement, ideally agreed worldwide, would have. However, it recognises that no single set of indicators can be devised in a ‘top-down fashion’ to measure social impact in all cases. In order to meet the needs of social enterprises, funders and policymakers to achieve comparability in reporting and monitoring, to limit the costs of the assessment to the size and scope of the venture and to allow an approach that respects the diversity of social enterprises as well as the need to cope with change and improvement, the GECES advocates a process for social impact measurement. This process involves five stages: 1) identify objectives; 2) identify stakeholders; 3) set relevant measurement; 4) measure, validate and value; 5) report, learn and improve. All stages should involve active stakeholder engagement. In particular, the number and range of indicators should be agreed between the social enterprise, beneficiaries or service users as well as investors, allowing for lighter and cheaper processes for small ventures. The dynamics of involving all stakeholders (from investors to service users) is designed to maintain the balance between the overriding need to deliver measurable social impact and the need for a profitable operation that can meet investor expecta- tions. The report also includes guidance on reporting standards for social impact measurement and indicators, and examples of case studies illustrating how measurement techniques are used. It represents a very rigorous, participatory and useful exercise to respond to the European Commission’s request. Its conclusions stress the need for further action, in particular in raising awareness and facilitating stakeholder engagement. This idea is reinforced by the opinion on social impact measurement of the European Economic and Social Committee (EESC).59 According to the GECES subgroup, the areas where follow-up is required are: yy guidance to assist social enterprises, funders, fund managers and investors in all EU Member States in complying with the standards proposed; yy the establishment of a knowledge centre on social impact measurement for guidance, exchange of practice and monitoring; yy the development and consolidation of measurement frameworks with stakeholder participation; yy the development of reporting formats; and yy the development of a network or group of experts to act as a reference point for dissemination and development with respect to social impact measurement, integrating EuSEF and EaSI experience. 59 http://www.eesc.europa.eu/?i=portal.en.int-opinions.29291. 28 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S 1.4.3. Indicators for a socially innovative society In the wake of demands from stakeholders, the issue of social innovation and its economic, social (and environmental) impact and measurement have become significant priorities on the EU agenda. In EU policymaking, this has recently become apparent in initiatives like the Communication on the social dimension of the EMU,60 which proposes social indicators and actions to complement economic reporting. This line of reasoning now appears in many EU documents where the measurement and monitoring of social added value, change and impact is a prerequisite for the implementation of directives and programmes. In line with the idea that we are still in a learning process, analysis and research is being conducted on the measurement of societal (social and environmental) value creation and the development of indicators.61 On the latter issue, the 2013 report on Employment and Social Development in Europe highlights the need to adapt the way we measure economic and social progress in order to take proper account of inequalities. In this context, the issue of measurement and financing has made tremendous advances in recent years. New tools are being tested, new sources of finance are appearing (EU funding possibilities, crowdfunding, more access to public procurement, etc.) and the question of social value creation is being widely discussed. However, it is still a work in progress which will continue to require considerable attention in the coming years. This said, while there are currently no agreed macro or micro level measurement approaches that specifically focus on social innovation, the field of research is fed by indicators to measure innovation in public and private sector organisations (e.g. innovation union scoreboard, public sector innovation index, etc.) and indicators that focus on social normative or environmental dimensions which capture the social and wellbeing aspects (e.g. the European Statistical System (ESS) Sponsorship Group, the European System of Social Indicators, ESS/GESIS/Eurostat sustainable societies or the OECD Better Life Index). In practice, there are some new and encouraging elements in recent developments. yy First, while the assessment exercises are still straitjacketed in ‘one-size-fits-all’ public spending control standards, social and environmental policies in particular are increasingly adopting scientifically based methods such as social experimentation to test (and prove) the effectiveness of innovations in their sector before they can be scaled up and replicated; yy Secondly, ‘social impact measurement’ is an issue, which has stirred up a lively debate in many circles and at many levels. At micro level, impact investing has been on the agenda of large private firms (JP Morgan and the GIIN62 ) for a few years now. The press has echoed more than usual to the financing of the social economy in general but also to associated financial innovations such as social impact bonds or crowdfunding. As explained in sub-section 1.4.2, several activities have been developed at European level. For example, the Social Business Initiative has launched 60 http://ec.europa.eu/commission_2010-2014/president/news/archives/2013/10/pdf/20131002_1-emu_en.pdf. 61 EU research projects like e-Frame and BRAINPOoL are particularly relevant in this respect. The link with the role of social innovation in this agenda is made in TEPSIE and SIMPACT. 62 In November 2010, JP Morgan collaborated with the Global Impact Investing Network (GIIN) and the Rockefeller Foundation on one of the first significant (despite the small sample) pieces of research on investments intended to create a positive impact beyond financial returns. The study noted that the rigour of systems to track and manage social performance was the best guarantee against the risks to see exploitation of poor people for the sake of profit and system drifts. 29P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H the debate amongst national and local experts, civil society organisations63 and the European institutions. Lately, the Group of European Experts (GECES) has contributed to the discussion about the different approaches to social impact measurement, which is an important step towards the establishment of shared standards; and yy Lastly, the European Commission has launched Horizon 2020, the largest research and innovation programme in the world, with a budget of EUR 80 billion. The programme will run from 2014 to 2020 and has an important social innovation component. It is to be expected that progress will be achieved in the different areas of social innovation, including the development of indicators for social innovation and techniques for social impact measurement. 63 3M Jonathan Bland, Confrontations Europe. 2. Leading by example: how public sector innovation supports social innovation Social innovation is a bottom-up process with little theoretical conceptualisation and support from methodological developments for the measurement of social impacts. The public sector plays a pivotal role in promoting and facilitating social innovation by providing a common conceptual framework for social innovation activities. Nevertheless the public sector needs to innovate itself in order to meet the increase in public demand and to promote and facilitate social innovation. There is an urgent need to power innovation within the public sector itself in order to unlock radical productivity improvements and efficiency gains, foster the creation of more public value and a better response to societal challenges. Public authorities need to promote effective instruments (legislation, removal of barriers, and public procurement) linked to social innovation. This can only happen through a pervasive change of mind-set, with more experimentation, controlled risk taking, and an agile and personalised response to new constituent challenges. This will help unleash the potential of an innovative public sector that can enable social innovation to make the transition from a random, bottom-up approach to a systemic phenomenon. 2.1. The Commission’s commitment to supporting public sector innovation The European Commission has, for a long time, tried to develop new thinking to modernise European economies and their social model to meet societal expectations. Public sector innovation as a positive way to respond to budget constraints has indeed, for many years, been considered a policy lever to improve the quality and efficiency of pub- 32 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S lic services. For instance, the impact of new technologies researched and tested through large-scale pilot schemes on e-Government, e-Health, e-Inclusion, e-Participation and social experimentation schemes to improve social inclusion have been on the agenda for more than ten years. The same goes for social innovation schemes to empower people to improve the provision and delivery of services. In 2012, the Group of Innovation Commissioners spurred renewed interest in this area, following the Innovation Union flagship initiative. It translated into concrete actions, including in particular the ones set out below. yy The inventory of the Commission’s initiatives in public sector innovation is a first attempt to map the efforts made under different EU policy headings to support innovation in the public sector. It has so far resulted in a document focusing on processes and organisational changes in public sector organisations that contribute to increasing public welfare and quality of life (cf. 2.2 below). yy The Commission launched a pilot European Public Sector Innovation Scoreboard (EPSIS) with a view to improving its ability to benchmark the innovation performance of the public sector in Europe. The ultimate ambition was to capture and present public sector innovation in a similar way to the innovation performance rating of countries in the Innovation Union Scoreboard (IUS)64 and thereby encourage and facilitate innovation activity across the public sector. The 2013 pilot EPSIS65 was the first EU-wide attempt to better understand and to analyse innovation in the public sector. It was developed based on the experience of earlier national and regional projects, tested widely and discussed with a number of key experts in relevant areas. The EPSIS shows that all EU Member States consider public sector innovation to be a national requirement and a means by which to drive continuous improvement in public service design and delivery. The Scoreboard also shows that Member States may be grouped into two categories: a small number of ‘innovation leaders’ and a larger number that may be designated as ‘innovation followers’. ‘Innovation leaders’ are more concerned with finding radical new approaches to deliver public services whereas ‘innovation followers’ are still concerned with making fundamental reforms to public institutions. 2.2. Powering European public sector innovation: towards a new architecture Under the responsibility of the Commissioner for Research and Innovation, a group of twelve experts was asked to analyse the role of the public sector, barriers to innovation and the current gaps in policies focused on innovation in the public sector. Their report Powering European Public Sector Innovation: Towards a New Architecture66 suggests that public sector innovation today mostly happens through uncoordinated initiatives rather than as a result of deliberate, strategic efforts. The quest for more and better public sector innovation is hindered by several barriers, which fall into four major categories: weak 64 http://ec.europa.eu/enterprise/policies/innovation/policy/innovation-scoreboard/index_en.htm. 65 http://ec.europa.eu/enterprise/policies/innovation/files/epsis-2013_en.pdf. 66 http://ec.europa.eu/research/innovation-union/pdf/psi_eg.pdf. 33P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H enabling factors or unfavourable framework conditions; lack of innovation leadership at all levels; limited knowledge and application of innovation processes and methods; and insufficiently precise and systematic use of measurement and data. There are efforts underway to address these barriers, both in the European Union (e.g. Joinup,67 the common portal for e-Government solutions) and globally (e.g. the OECD’s Observatory of Public Sector Innovation68 ), and the expert group has reviewed an extensive amount of scientific literature and best practices. However, a paradigm shift is needed in order to embed and encourage an innovation culture within the public sector, which will also improve its absorptive capacity. A new innovation paradigm and design principles In its search for developing concrete recommendations to overcome the barriers to innovation, the expert group has recognised the following four design principles that should be at the heart of the public sector. These principles must be mainstreamed throughout the entire ecosystem of public sector actors for the greatest gains in quality, efficiency, fairness, transparency and accountability. yy Co-design and co-creation of innovative solutions (with other Member States, other parts of government, businesses, the third sector and citizens); yy Adopting new and collaborative service delivery models (across public, private and non-governmental actors, both within and across national borders); yy Embracing creative disruption from technology (the pervasive use of social media, mobility, big data, cloud computing packaged in new digital government offerings); yy Adopting an attitude of experimentation and entrepreneurship (government itself needs to become bolder and more entrepreneurial). Recommendations for new public sector innovation architecture in Europe The report identifies several actions that should be taken rapidly (either at EU level or in the Member States, depending on political and financial considerations). The recommendations may be divided into three groups. yy Leading Innovation: to establish a programme to empower and network innovative public leaders and to establish an EU Innovation Lab inside the European Commission to support and facilitate innovation in the work of the Commission Services. yy Enabling Innovation: to establish a network of Innovation Single Contact Points in all Member States; to establish an Accelerator for Digital Innovation and a Public Sector Angel Fund. yy Informing Innovation: to establish a Dynamic Innovation Toolbox targeted at public managers and to establish a European Citizens’ Scoreboard for public services. 67 https://joinup.ec.europa.eu/. 68 http://www.oecd.org/gov/public-innovation/observatory-public-sector-innovation.htm. 34 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S BEPA held a high-level meeting on public sector innovation in July 2013.69 The objective of this meeting was to discuss public sector innovation and the need for a more systemic approach in order to create a dynamic and open public sector. The major outcomes of the meeting may be grouped in the following areas: Evidence-based methodologies for efficient policymaking yy The need to test new policies and programmes: Innovative public programmes addressing important policy issues, which have a potential to be scaled up, should be ‘tested’ before they are implemented on a large scale. One should learn from the experiments, via rigorous evaluation. yy The need to use scientific methodologies to measure and quantify the social impact of policies and programmes: Learning about the impact of a policy is not straightforward. J-Pal,70 the poverty action Lab created by Esther Duflo, has developed a scientific methodology based on a randomised control trials approach, which allows meaningful comparisons. Innovation strategies in the public sector yy The need to highlight innovation pockets at different levels of public administration: copying successful innovations is often the most effective way to innovate and the best ideas are not necessarily the newest. The European Public Sector Innovation Scoreboard can help to understand who is doing better and how we can improve. yy The need for the public sector to invest in innovation: based on collaborative approaches to driving change and to governance. yy The need to foster innovation led by example: the European Commission can provide support by promoting systematic collaboration and rigorous evaluation of the policies adopted, applying the scientific method to the public sector and using sophisticated tools to analyse complex interacting systems. 69 http://ec.europa.eu/bepa/expertise/seminars/index_en.htm; http://ec.europa.eu/bepa/pdf/conferences/note-psi- reportweb.pdf. 70 http://www.povertyactionlab.org/about-j-pal. 3. Achievements and lessons learned Providing an overall evaluation of social innovations in Europe – including EU policies and their impact on societal challenges – is almost impossible considering the large amount of new and interactive initiatives, but also the broad goals of EU programmes that integrate social innovation. However, while the overall picture is sometimes difficult to capture at a glance, the drive behind social innovation has become firmer and instruments are better defined. This is no mean feat and the attention and budget allocated to promoting social innovation are higher than ever. The backdrop to this firmer drive is the need to improve knowledge of how and where social innovations emerge, scale up and duplicate, and how effective they are in addressing current societal challenges not only for, but also with citizens. A set of specific examples are taken from the Guide to Social Innovation, published by DG Regional and Urban Policy and DG Employment, Social Affairs in February 2013.71 Some of them show how support under the Structural Funds will increasingly be sought for the development of instruments to encourage a participatory approach to the resolution of social problems. Others develop thematic issues to deal with the major challenges that migration and ageing; environmental trends; IT solutions to inclusion; urban regeneration and housing; health and wellbeing; and the development of ethical goods and services pose at local level and which many cities or local communities need to address. While a number of the issues mentioned here would have found their place in other parts of this document, examples of practical developments mainly supported by the EU Structural Funds are meant to emulate new ideas and entrepreneurship. 71 http://ec.europa.eu/regional_policy/sources/docgener/presenta/social_innovation/social_innovation_2013.pdf. 36 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S 3.1. Deepening our understanding and knowledge of social innovation The two major sources of new knowledge developed during the last period are, on the one hand, a factual Europe-wide study on A Map of Social Enterprises and their Eco-systems in Europe, which was launched by the European Commission’s Directorate-General for Employment, Social Affairs and Inclusion in April 201372 and, on the other hand, the large body of research funded by the FP5, FP6 and FP7 Socio-economic Sciences and Humanities Programme on issues related to social innovation, including in the areas of theory building and conceptualisation, local welfare systems and services, poverty reduction, combating inequalities, and changing lifestyles. 3.1.1. The Mapping study It is composed of five main tasks which are briefly described as follows: Task 1: Identification of social enterprises – to develop an operational definition that can be used to identify, measure and map social enterprise across Europe and thus provide the basis for carrying out the remaining research tasks; Task 2: Measurement, characterisation and mapping of social enterprise – to collect (through primary and secondary research) and analyse data on the scale, characteristics and patterns of development of social enterprise in each country studied; Task 3: Legal and standards mapping – to map (a) legal ‘labels’ and frameworks designed exclusively for social enterprises where these exist; (b) corporate law aspects of the three legal forms most commonly used by social enterprises in each country studied; (c) legal and regulatory barriers to creation and growth of social enterprise; and (d) marks, labels and certification systems designed for social enterprises; Task 4: Mapping of public policies and social investment markets – to provide an overview of national policies, schemes and actions aimed at promoting social entrepreneurs and social enterprises and supporting the development of a conducive ecosystem (where these exist); and, the current state and dynamics of social investment markets in Europe; and Task 5: Developing recommendations for EU action – to develop recommendations for future research and policy action to support the growth of social enterprise in Europe. This is the very first time that researchers have carried out such a systematic and broad overview of existing traditions and legal, public policy and investment conditions for the development of social enterprises. 72 http://ec.europa.eu/internal_market/social_business/docs/expert-group/20131128-sbi-sector-mapping-study_ en.pdf. 37P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H 3.1.2. Social innovation research in the European Union The EU Socio-economic Sciences and Humanities Programme is the second main source of new knowledge from the last period. However, in view of increasing demand from policymakers and practitioners alike for social innovations and the emerging possibilities for new research avenues on social innovation, including in Horizon 2020, a policy review commissioned by the European Commission’s DG Research and Innovation from experts in the field73 has produced a systematic overview of research findings from 17 European projects in the area of social innovation. The review74 focuses on how these projects address social innovation in terms of theory, methodology, policy areas, actors, and level of analysis in order to bring the results to the attention of policymakers, wider groups of stakeholders and the broader public in a comprehensive way. The point that comes to the fore is that this report is a stocktaking exercise, undertaken with a view to fostering the engagement of the European research community in a continuous exchange of ideas and best practices for analysing social innovation and in the promotion of networking among researchers. The report ends by identifying five research fields that did not draw much attention in the projects reviewed and that are areas for further development (social innovation to overcome the inequalities of health and re-pattern the social determinants of health; social innovation in rural areas and societies; social innovation in the financial sector; social innovation and the private sector; and social innovation for managing diversity). 3.2. Instruments to improve the ecosystem As well established by now, research in social innovation is – by nature – mainly empirical and its primary field of development is the local level, where stakeholders can more easily be mobilised on concrete issues. In order to scan the scope of empirical developments and draw lessons on how social innovations contribute to reform local welfare systems, this part of the report addresses some patterns of innovatory social projects and networks to fight social inequalities and stimulate social cohesion at local level. 3.2.1. The social economy According to the EU Social Business Initiative, the social economy employs over 11 million people in the EU, accounting for 6 % of total employment. It covers bodies with a specific legal status (cooperatives, foundations, associations, mutual societies). The social economy can clearly play a role in regional development. For instance, the Emilia Romagna region has published a study on the importance of the social economy 73 Jane Jenson and Dennis Harrisson in Social innovation research in the European Union – Approaches, findings and future directions - Policy Review http://ec.europa.eu/research/social-sciences/pdf/social_innovation.pdf. 74 Its first results were presented and discussed at the conference Approaches to Research on Social Innovation: Learning from One Another for the Future, which was organised by the FP7 project WILCO jointly with the European Commission’s DG Research and Innovation on February 2013. 38 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S for territorial and social cohesion. Its main conclusions are that public policies are the fruit of the combined contribution of public authorities and social economy organisations in the provision of public utility services, in which the joint participation of both players is an essential requirement to ensure quality; and that public-private partnership is a tool to deliver more effective and efficient primary social services, which have so far been historically provided by the welfare state. At the same time, it helps identify and deliver services in new and additional fields. In so doing, new forms of cooperation are established with civil society and stakeholders. The European Regional Development Fund (ERDF) supports the development of social enterprises as it does for other types of businesses. Financial support can be delivered directly to individual companies, through social enterprise intermediaries, such as social enterprise or cooperative development agencies, and through financial institutions. There are increasing numbers of financial institutions that specialise in investing in social enterprises and many of the new ethical banks specialise in this type of investment. The European Social Fund (ESF) also supports social enterprises. Firstly, it can strengthen administrative capacities and support structures which promote social enterprises. This can be carried out in particular through education and training, for example, through the integration of social entrepreneurship in the curricula of specific vocations, or the provision of training improving the business skills of social entrepreneurs. Networking and the development of partnerships, as well as the setting up of business development services for social enterprises can be supported too. Secondly, the ESF can mobilise extra funds targeted at the development of the social economy and the promotion of social entrepreneurship and easily accessible for social enterprises. The social economy has different traditions in different parts and Member States of Europe. Some countries, like France, have a strong tradition of ‘économie sociale et solidaire’. They are gearing up with social innovation in its ‘newer’ meaning and initiatives are sprouting, often linked with the Structural Funds. For example, Avise75 has launched a call for proposals with the aim to accelerate social innovation in the social economy, and thus help to find new answers to unmet needs in fields like employment, housing, ageing, childcare, etc. Market access for social enterprises is still restricted (even if the provisions of the new directives on public procurement76 adopted by the European Parliament and the Council in early 2014 will noticeably improve the context). Sometimes they are unable to compete for public tenders against other small and medium-sized enterprises (SMEs) because of interpretations of national rules. Member States and Managing Authorities and other public contracting bodies can use the purchasing power of large and small ERDF projects to stimulate social innovation in employment and inclusion of marginalised groups. The example below from the City of Nantes illustrates how a procurement framework has opened a space for social enterprises to work directly with the private sector in helping disadvantaged people into employment. Similar examples exist in other parts of the EU. 75 http://www.avise.org/. 76 http://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/EN/TXT/?uri=CELEX:32014L0024; http://eur-lex.europa.eu/ legal-content/EN/TXT/HTML/?uri=CELEX:32014L0025; http://eur-lex.europa.eu/legal-content/EN/TXT/ HTML/?uri=CELEX:32014L0023. 39P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H The Nantes example illustrates how public works contracts can deliver a double benefit: the work that needs to be done, such as a road, as well as jobs for excluded people. 3.2.2. Microfinance Whereas microcredit refers specifically to one type of microfinance – the act of providing loans for business start-up and growth – microfinance is a broader concept in which a range of products are developed to increase financial inclusion. These products may include savings, financial education and literacy, personal loans and insurance. Microfinance was slow to take off in Europe. ADIE77 in France was one of the first to start up in the late 80s (it is now one of largest with around 20 000 borrowers in 2010). There are now over 100 microfinance institutions of which around 80 are members of the European Microfinance Network (EMN), which is supported with EU funds under the PROGRESS initiative. Although there are variations, in all EU Member States over 95 % of all businesses are micro businesses employing less than ten people. They form the bottom of the enterprise pyramid and are the seeds from which most SMEs and even large companies grow. Microenterprises in Europe employ around one-third of private sector employees and produce about 20 % of output. As mentioned in another part of this survey, the EU funds and instruments for supporting microfinance are: 77 http://www.adie.org/. Using public procurement in an innovative way: The City of Nantes The medium-sized city of Nantes (285 000 people) in north-west France has been known for nearly 15 years as a leading innovator in using social clauses in public procurement to provide entry level jobs for the long-term unemployed. France revised its public procurement rules in 2006 allowing the condition that part of the work must be delivered by a specific target group with a need for professional insertion. Nantes Metropole and surrounding suburban administrations awarded contracts using this clause. Work has included swimming pools, roads, bus routes, and a media centre. The types of trades comprise mason assistants, carpenters, painters, building workers, pavers, green space maintenance staff, plumbers, metal workers, plasterboard, and external cleaners. The city has also encouraged the development of support structures for individuals. The ‘Entreprise d’insertion’ trains and prepares them to get jobs that open up in the private sector. In 2008: • 183 contract operations contained a social clause; • 483 beneficiaries were able to work under an employment contract; • 345 000 hours dedicated to insertion (about 200 full-time equivalent jobs), a further 92 000 hours of work for disadvantaged people were produced benefiting266 employees; • 133 enterprises were mobilised through these works; • 75 % of beneficiaries were accompanied by a local insertion company (a type of training and employment social enterprise). 40 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S yy JASMINE, which provides technical assistance for microfinance organisations that are close to becoming banks or have high levels of financial sustainability (JASMINE is a joint initiative of the Commission, the European Investment Bank (EIB) and European Investment Fund (it is financed out of the ERDF); yy The ERDF, which provides support for setting up and growing microfinance; yy The EU PROGRESS Microfinance facility – a fund managed by the European Investment Fund with a total fund of EUR 160 million. It invests in microcredit providers, which may be banks or NGOs. It does this either by issuing guarantees, thereby sharing the providers’ potential risk of loss, or by providing funding to increase microcredit lending; yy The ESF mostly provides flanking measures for business start-up and business support. Over EUR 2 billion have been allocated to ESF business support measures in the current period. Part goes to micro-businesses – especially at the start-up stage. The German Gründer coaching programme78 is a good example of a national coaching scheme for start-ups that is co-financed by the ESF. In 2011, a European Code of Good Conduct for Microcredit Provision79 was developed in partnership with the microfinance sector. There are also many microfinance organisations in Europe and elsewhere that have developed innovative approaches to lending to specific groups. The Microcredit Foundation Horizonti80 in the former Yugoslav Republic of Macedonia, for example, has developed an innovative good practice ‘Housing Microfinance for Roma and marginalised people’. The initiative started in 2007 with the aim of providing affordable housing to the Roma community. 78 http://ec.europa.eu/europe2020/pdf/csr2014/nrp2014_germany_en.pdf. 79 http://ec.europa.eu/regional_policy/thefunds/instruments/jasmine_cgc_en.cfm. 80 http://www.microfinancefocus.com/microcredit-fdtn-horizonti-receives-2011-european-best-practices-award/. The Kiút Programme, self-employment and microcredit for Roma in Hungary Kiút aims to support Roma to work in the formal economy by starting up a business. The microcredit programme provides assistance by lending start-up money for small businesses to generate enough revenue to service the loan and to produce additional income for Roma families. The clients receive continuous administrative, financial and business advice and assistance. An explicit and important aim of the programme is to encourage the participation of women (with a set target of 50 % female members in each group). 41P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H 3.2.3. Incubation The world of social innovation has a number of incubators and centres which are crucial for testing new ideas and bringing together partnerships. 3.2.4. Workplace innovation Workplace innovation focuses on how to improve aspects of work organisation and introduce modern management techniques that involve workers. Workplaces with flatter hierarchies and the possibility for workers to contribute are more creative and ultimately more productive and open to addressing both social and technological challenges. Workplace innovation concerns not only the private sector but also large parts of the social economy such as charities and foundations as well as the public sector. Celebrated examples include Google, which allows employees to spend 20 % of their time on their own projects, and IKEA, which practises stand-up round-table meetings among other innovative practices allowing employees to tackle problems as they arise with minimum management interference. In the Netherlands and Belgium, workplace innovation is called ‘Social Innovation’ and has been supported for over a decade by the Structural Funds. The approach as such is strongest in northern Europe, especially Scandinavia. The ERDF’s business support measures can be used to finance such innovations helping both management and employees to explore more productive ways of working. A Social Innovation Park in the Basque country Denokinn brings together social enterprises, public authorities and the private sector to scale up successful innovations after they have been piloted. They have launched the first social innovation park in Europe near Bilbao. Denokinn received EUR 300 000 from the social experimentation part of the EU Progress Fund to develop a social inclusion dimension to their Hiriko electric car concept. The result was a plan to adopt a decentralised assembly in which the cars could be put together in work inclusion social enterprises by those excluded from the labour market. The Hiriko car was launched by President Barroso on 27 January 2012. He said ‘Hiriko is European social innovation at its best … Firstly, it is a successful example of how to give a new lease of life to traditional industrial sectors by contributing to address major modern societal challenges, in that specific case, urban mobility and pollution. Secondly, it is a great combination of new business types of cooperation and employment opportunities with a strong social dimension. Thirdly, it is an excellent illustration of the finest use that can be made of European social funds’. Results-based entrepreneurship in the Netherlands Results-based entrepreneurship (RBE) aims at stimulating technological and social innovation within SMEs. Advisers work with management and staff combining strategic advice with social innovation (improving communication, raising personnel involvement, etc.) and so stimulating technological innovation. The improved teamwork promotes a collective ambition for the company’s success encouraging new ideas, products and services. Business support is given through Social Innovation vouchers. Firms can use these vouchers to hire an expert to help them implement the method. The voucher covers 50 % of the cost up to a maximum of EUR 20 000. The minimum voucher is EUR 3 000 (with a grant of EUR 1 500). By buying a voucher, a company receives double the amount of support that it would obtain if it bought the same consultancy on the open market. As companies contribute to the cost, the scheme ensures their support and commitment. 42 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S 3.2.5. Changes in governance Governance is one of the key issues when it comes to social innovation. Among the many experiments in this field, the latest include the one led by Santa Casa da Misericordia (SCM),81 in Lisbon (Portugal). 3.3. Specific examples of actions from the field In this section of the report, real life examples of projects financed by the European Structural Funds are tabled, showing how local initiatives, all of which are different and almost unique, are able to rely on EU funding to develop and achieve their goals. 81 http://www.scml.pt/. The Santa Casa da Misericordia de Lisboa (SCML) and the Banco de Inovação Social (BIS) The SCML is one of the oldest and most important private charities in Portugal. It was founded in 1498 as the first coherent social care system in Lisbon. In the 18th century, the Queen granted the SCML the right to run the first lottery in Portugal. Since the state granted the concession for lotteries in Portugal to the SCML, which uses its proceeds to finance the SCML’s activities, the concession and activity is highly regulated. The BIS, which also means ‘twice’ in Portuguese, is an informal, collaborative, and open platform, not an official institution. It seeks to use social innovation as a tool to introduce systemic change in society at all levels: institutions, economy, education, culture. Portugal has to restore economic growth, employment, and make long-term structural reforms at all levels, but especially at institutional and economic levels (public sector, public services, competition, etc.). To help address this challenge, and even though its action is limited to Lisbon, the SCML opens up to the world, collects best practices and collaborates with other institutions in the country and abroad to introduce change. The SCML started its BIS programme about a year ago by inviting 26 other institutions to contribute their assets (knowledge, experience, funds, people, etc.) to the BIS project and bring social innovation to Portugal. The first institutions to be invited were the government itself, municipalities, universities, etc. to address all kinds of societal needs in Portugal. These new forms of governance (collaborative, informal platforms or programmes) are believed to be the best way to foster social innovation. By bringing people and institutions together and work collaboratively, it will show people in Portugal how to govern in a different way. To support and promote creativity, a call for ideas has been launched, where ideas can be debated. Many people have already sent ideas to address social needs. Social experimentation was also implemented (a current example is the United at Work project, an innovative way to address senior and junior unemployment through intergenerational entrepreneurship). TheBISalsopromotessocialbusinessbybringingtogetherpeoplewhohaveinterestsinsustainable business. There is also an ongoing workstream on education, in schools, and a creativity competition was held in about 250 schools. A social investment fund is being launched, which is necessary and the main current concern for the BIS. A key obstacle is the lack of Portuguese legislation in this area so far, in spite of the EU initiative. 43P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H 3.3.1. Social inclusion Large sections of the European population are excluded from the benefits of economic and social progress. The different forms of disadvantage related to educational attainment, gender, age, physical status or ethnic background have been exacerbated by the crisis. Among them, blindness is a disability subject to specific constraints, as explained in the example below. 3.3.2. Migration In recent years, population movements, especially immigration from non-European areas, have become a more sensitive issue in the EU. Beyond the economic impact this may have, the immigration that European countries have to cope with creates many social issues. Due to their complexity, the human dimension which is still theirs, and their local specificity, some of these situations have to be handled through practices that often involve social innovation. I-Cane: Mobility solutions for blind and visually impaired people for global use Today Europe counts approximately 13 million blind and visual impaired people, who rely on ‘old fashioned’ aids, e.g. the white cane and guide dogs. The traditional solutions do not offer navigation outside the memory constrained zone. This enforces the social and economic isolation of this fast growing population of which the majority is over 50 years of age. Developing high-tech solutions for a group of people with both limited financial means and also working with a user volume considerably lower than the requirements of high volume electronics manufacturers is not an easy market choice, it needed a particular approach. In 2004 the I-Cane foundation was initiated. Through this foundation funds were raised from charities and the public sector (province of Limburg NL and the EU ERDF fund) to execute a feasibility study and to deliver the proof of principle demonstration. In 2008 I-Cane succeeded in navigating a blind person on an unfamiliar route without hitting obstacles. In this demonstration invented by I-Cane, tactile human-machine interface also demonstrated its value since test persons were still able to listen to the environment parallel to receiving instructions via their fingers, a unique human-machine interface. From 2008 the social enterprise I-Cane Social Technology BV continued the work of the I-Cane foundation. A development time of 5-8 years must be expected for mobility tools for disabled people but is unattractive for those who seek a quick return on investment. Via support from the Social Economy network in the Netherlands, Belgium and Germany, the funds were raised to meet the matching requirements of EU ERDF (OP Zuid) and national grant arrangements. Today this combination of public and private funding has resulted in an Euregion based platform of SMEs, with European-wide knowledge institutes (such as the University of Delft, RWTH, Fraunhofer IPT, IMEC, TNO, ESA/Estec) and end cross-border user organisations, led by I-Cane Social Technology BV and the I-Cane Foundation. In 2012 the first large-scale tests with I-Cane systems started, followed by a market introduction in 2013. The I-Cane case demonstrates the combination of funding, close user interaction and cooperation between social enterprises and knowledge institutes can deliver world-class break-out solutions. Public sector innovation – immigration policy in Portugal Towards the end of the 20th century Portugal’s immigrant population doubled within a few years, and most of the new arrivals were not Portuguese speakers and had no historical links with this country. For the first time, public administration experienced considerable difficulty in communicating with the immigrant population and understanding their needs. At the same time, large migrant populations had to cope with the challenge of social integration in an unknown linguistic, cultural and bureaucratic setting. 44 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S 3.3.3. Urban regeneration Most cities in Europe have poor communities living in difficult environments. Over the past 20 years, the ERDF has financed integrated approaches to urban regeneration linking economic, social and environmental aspects. In the 1990s, the Community-led Economic Development priorities in the disadvantaged neighbourhoods of the UK were at the forefront. In the 2000s, Germany was a leading practitioner. This major shift catalysed the Portuguese one-stop-shop approach in immigration policy and the National Immigrant Support Centres (CNAI) were opened to the public in 2004. The centres responded to a number of challenges identified by migrant clients by providing various immigration-related services in one space, applying an identical working philosophy, and working in cooperation. Indeed, participation is the core of innovation at the CNAIs in addition to the integrated service delivery. The implementation of the one-stop-shop approach was based on the incorporation of intercultural mediators in public administration service provision, who play a central role in service provision because of cultural and linguistic proximity to the service-users and facilitate interaction between state services and the immigrant population by forming an integral part of the procedures of Office of the High Commissioner for Immigration and Intercultural Dialogue (ACIDI). Intercultural mediators usually come from immigrant communities themselves and speak fluent Portuguese as well as at least one other language. Following training and an exam, they are employed by certified immigrant associations, which receive grants from ACIDI. The certified associations participate in the definition of immigration policy, immigration regulation processes and consultative councils. ACIDI invests in the empowerment of immigrant leaders through training for immigrant association leaders, in partnership with universities. The mediators also play a fundamental role as integration outreach workers. Because they are immigrants themselves and normally reside in migrant neighbourhoods, they disseminate information about the rights and duties of immigrants in Portugal even outside the one-stop-shop building, reaching places and persons that the public administration would never reach if it never left its headquarters and operated exclusively through public servants. The State of North Rhine-Westphalia ‘Socially Integrative City’ programme: supporting neighbourhood renewal Since 1999, the government of North Rhine Westphalia has been developing integrated policies to support 80 neighbourhood regeneration programmes in cities within its State. An Integrated Local Action Plan (LAP) outlines how the development, reorganisation and upgrading of an area is to take place. The approach is decentralised with clear responsibilities for each level. • 55 Municipalities are responsible for the preparation and implementation of the LAP, applying for funding and ensuring the neighbourhood plan meets the needs of the city as a whole. • The district governments (regional administration units of the federal State level of NRW) advise the municipalities on funding matters and authorise payments. • The federal State ministry for urban development arranges and controls the programme and commissions evaluations. • The EU provides funding through the ESF and ERDF operational programmes. In addition, there are private housing and retail companies involved as well as foundations, welfare organisations and other stakeholders. The neighbourhood management offices work on a wide range of tasks which include stimulating networking; promoting a changed image of the neighbourhood; supporting bargaining processes; setting up communication structures; informing the population and administration; organising offers of cultural activities; promoting the local economy; forming a link between the neighbourhood, city and other levels of decision-making; and developing projects. A disposition fund (form of participatory budgeting) made up of 5 euro contributions per inhabitant finances smallscale projects decided by a local citizens’ body. These projects have an immediate impact such as neighbourhood parties, tree-planting in a school yard and outings for children whose parents cannot normally afford them. 45P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H 3.3.4. Health and ageing The European Commission has identified active and healthy ageing as a major societal challenge common to all European countries, and an area which presents considerable potential for Europe to lead the world in providing innovative responses to this challenge. The Innovation Union strategy addresses the health and ageing issue by aiming to enhance European competitiveness and tackle societal challenges through research and innovation. One way to achieve this is through Innovation Partnerships, fostering an integrated approach. Their unique strength is that they will address weaknesses in the European research and innovation system (notably, under-investment, conditions which are not sufficiently innovation-friendly, and fragmentation and duplication), which considerably complicate the discovery or exploitation of knowledge and, in many cases, ultimately prevent the entry of innovations into the market place. The European Innovation Partnership on Active and Healthy Ageing pursues a triple win for Europe: 1. enabling EU citizens to lead healthy, active and independent lives while ageing; 2. improving the sustainability and efficiency of social and health care systems; 3. boosting and improving the competitiveness of the markets for innovative products and services, responding to the ageing challenge at both EU and global level, thus creating new opportunities for businesses. This is to be realised in the three areas of prevention and health promotion, care and cure, and active and the independent living of elderly people. The overarching target of this partnership will be to increase the average healthy lifespan by two years by 2020. The ERDF is another answer to the challenge of active and healthy ageing, as illustrated by Finland, which has used this fund to co-finance a living lab focused on health and welfare services. The Living Lab Testing Process is a systematic and concrete tool, which contributes to the development of user-driven innovations and enhances cooperation between municipalities and business. The new cooperation Model improves business opportunities for companies and attracts new companies to the area. It enhances innovation and economic development strategies in a concrete way. The Living Lab on Wellbeing Services and Technology, a social innovation that produces user-driven innovations This Living Lab was a finalist of the RegioStars 2013 competition. It is an innovation platform that enables a new way of producing services for elderly people in a functional Public-Private-People partnership. Users participate actively in product development, service design and usability testing processes. The testing of welfare services and technologies takes place in real life contexts, in elderly people’s homes and service homes. The new collaborative structure consists of different stakeholders such as municipalities, suppliers, citizens, the third sector, universities, regional developers, specialists, financiers and regional, national and international networks. The created concept has increased trust between the actors. 46 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S 3.3.5. Social innovation and the environment Social innovation can tackle environmental challenges82 and is proving popular in this domain. There are a number of environmental drivers that are already instigating social innovations such as waste issues, transport and pollution problems, as well as declines in biodiversity and degradation of ecosystem services, for example, flood protection through wetlands. Although these drivers are environmental, they have social repercussions, such as health problems caused by air pollution, resource depletion due to inefficient waste disposal, exacerbation of flooding from damage to natural defences and food insecurity and agricultural issues exacerbated by poor soil quality or lack of pollination. In other words, societal and environmental issues are often interlinked and mutual solutions are possible. Some examples of forms of environmental social innovation include wood recycling social enterprises, organic gardening cooperatives, low-impact housing developments, farmers’ markets, car-sharing schemes, renewable energy cooperatives and community composting schemes.83 In some sectors social innovation can shape technology, as evidenced by the grassroots entrepreneurs and do-it-yourself builders of wind turbines and solar collectors in Denmark and Austria respectively.84 These socially innovative groups instigated the commercial development of these technologies and continue to influence their design as they become more mainstream. The application of local knowledge via community and social action can create adaptive and flexible solutions that are appropriate to solving environmental problems. The SPREAD Sustainable Lifestyles 2050 project85 was a European social platform that invited a range of stakeholders to participate in the development of a vision for sustainable lifestyles by 2050. In its research it identified social innovators as one of the gatekeepers that can enable the shift towards more sustainable lifestyles. It proposed that the intentional and voluntary effort of social innovations to change lifestyles is an indispensable bottom-up driver for change, as they often champion new and promising behaviour. As such, it suggested that social innovations should be given the opportunity to test small-scale initiatives, which could be scaled up into large-scale sustainable solutions and participate in planning and decision-making. The SPREAD project also highlighted the important role of social innovation and the supportive function of policy. It used scenarios and backcasting to outline a number of policy implications and recommendations on facilitating social innovation in this area. More generally the report suggested the need for an open transparent governance system with local participation to create ownership of decisions and ensure implementation. 82 cf. http://ec.europa.eu/environment/integration/research/newsalert/pdf/IR10.pdf. 83 cf. Seyfang & Smith, 2007. 84 cf. Ornetzeder & Rohracher, 2013. 85 http://www.sustainable-lifestyles.eu/publications/publications.html. Policy implications and recommendations on supporting social innovation to achieve sustainable living from the SPREAD project • Using effective policy instruments, which could include regulation, economic incentives and public participation. • Acknowledging that one size will not fit all. Instead, allowing for combinations or hybrid models and accepting provisions for dynamic structures that allow for change in order to fit the diversity of contexts across Europe. 47P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H Finally, one of the inputs of the SPREAD project was to underline that social innovation can complement technological innovation and policymaking to achieve systemic, long-lasting changes in lifestyles and society to tackle environmental issues. When citizens and communities instigate change themselves and develop the innovation, it is more likely to be successful and endure. 3.3.6. Regional strategies Regional strategies that incorporate social innovation are only beginning to emerge. Many French regions already integrate social innovation in some form in their strategies for innovation and economic development, as a recent survey from Avise and the ARF86 shows. Most of them consider social innovation to be linked to the social economy and/ or work organisation, but it also combines various forms of incubation, co-creation with citizens, initiatives in the health and care sector. 86 Association des Régions de France (http://www.arf.asso.fr/). Basque Country: Social innovation linked to the regional innovation strategy The Basque Country is a good example of how a region can use a wide range of approaches to achieve social innovation. Innobasque is a non-profit private company created in 2007 to coordinate and promote innovation across the Basque Country. It acts as a regional innovation partnership. The Board brings together 57 leading actors from the region. It includes the rectors of the three universities, the chief executive of the cooperative group Mondragon, representatives from three ministries as well as chief executives from leading enterprises in the region. Innobasque works at the policy level on many aspects of technological innovation but also brings in the general public through reflection groups and workshops such as its world café events, which focus on ways to promote societal transformations. The OECD has described Innobasque as leading work on social innovation and fostering collaborative action and joint research in the region. It is also exploring strategies to support the creation of new social firms (work integration social enterprises). Examples of the achievements of this public-private partnership include: • Lifelong learning via a participatory process with citizens. • Social contract for housing: participatory process with public and private agents defining housing policy for the next 15 years. • City XXI: Engagement on how a 21st century city could be developed, its urban planning and its values. • Ageing and new in-house services to help people to live in at home as they get older with a good quality of life and services. • Social contract for immigration involving all organisations and institutions to achieve a social contract for coexistence. • Up-scaling promising practices like Transition Towns, cycling cities, local currency systems, car sharing, and neighbourhood gardening. Providing institutional support to those initiatives, as well as to social entrepreneurs. • Facilitating breakthrough and creative thinking by establishing free thinking ‘designLabs’ which are physical and intellectual spaces that encourage and facilitate cooperation and the co-creation of meaningful and innovative solutions to complex problems. • Providing opportunities for societal actors, businesses and policymakers to leave their own ‘comfort zone’ and experiment and test new solutions in collaborative, open-sourced platforms. • Creating partnerships with other sectors, such as the health sector, to change environments into those facilitating more active and healthy lifestyles. 48 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S 3.3.7. Lessons learned from social innovation achievements The abovementioned examples illustrate how social innovation works and succeeds in various areas in different European countries. What further lessons can we draw? The answer could be summarised in an important contribution aimed at understanding how social innovations grow at local level and how they contribute to changing local welfare systems. These issues are illustrated by 77 case studies in a 400-page e-book on Social Innovations for social cohesion: Transnational patterns and approaches from 20 European cities, developed as part of the WILCO project.87 87 http://www.wilcoproject.eu. Summary of the main findings of the WILCO project Innovations in services to address users The majority of the social innovations identified in the survey as important and promising are service innovations. The main differences between the service innovations analysed in the WILCO project and services established in the post-war welfare traditions or the more recent managerial culture of public and private services are the following: • investing in capabilities rather than spotting deficits; • preference for open approaches, avoiding targeting with stigmatising effects; • service offers that connect otherwise separated forms of support and access, allowing for personalised bundles of support; • creating flexible forms of ad hoc support; • developing offers that meet newly emerging risks, beyond fixed social and participation rights and entitlements; and • working through ‘social contracts’ with individuals and groups. Innovations in modes of working and financing While this is in itself banal, it represents quite a challenge when it comes to disentangling what is ‘innovative’ about a project and development and what is just an effect of the deconstruction of or regression in existing welfare models and regulations. The kinds of arrangement for cooperation in social innovations are much more diversified than in the public or business sector, including not only various forms of casual paid cooperation but also many forms of voluntary and civic contributions, ranging from short-term activism to regular unpaid volunteering with a long-term perspective, and from ‘hands-on’ volunteer work to constant inputs by civic engagement in a board. Therefore, from what is reported on the various social innovations, one gets the impression that working fields are taking shape here that are innovative in two respects. First, they are innovative because they balance very different arrangements for networking, paid work, volunteering and civic engagement. And secondly, it is at least remarkably new to see how much the demarcation lines between those who operate inside the organisation and those that get addressed as co-producers are often blurred (e.g. innovations in housing and neighbourhood revitalisation). Innovations concerning the entity of (local) welfare systems One of the aims offset by the EU authorities for the WILCO project was to look at the possible contributions of social innovations to changes and developments in local welfare systems. Speaking about a welfare system usually means including, besides the local welfare state/the municipality, the welfare-related roles and responsibilities of the third sector, the market sector and the community and family sphere. The cases of social innovations studied bear testimony to the mutual relations that exist between all of these four components of a (local) welfare system. In conclusion, one of the central messages of these case studies on local social innovations is that they are the opposite of quick-fix solutions; using their full potential requires nothing less than a combination of ‘the deep strategies of chess masters with the quick tactics of acrobats’. The lifecycles of social innovations (processes of emergence, stabilisation and scaling up) are very conditional and are not available simply at the press of a button. 49P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H 3.4. Social entrepreneurship to revive the social economy Beyond the priority measures in its short-term action plan, the Social Business Initiative (SBI) has engendered powerful and sustained momentum for social entrepreneurship. One of the most iconic stages of this phenomenon was an unprecedented event held jointly by the European Economic and Social Committee (EESC), the European Commission and the city of Strasbourg88 on 16 and 17 January 2014. More than 2000 social entrepreneurs and supporters representing the rich diversity of the social economy came together to affirm that social enterprises must play a bigger role in the future of Europe and to identify new ways of boosting the sector. They called for new, innovative funding sources, business support, networking, and clearer EU-wide regulations. The event concluded with the Strasbourg Declaration, a milestone that covered a wide range of areas where social entrepreneurs want to see further changes: 88 http://ec.europa.eu/internal_market/conferences/2014/0116-social-entrepreneurs/index_en.htm. ‘A call to action to realise the potential of social enterprise Governments and public bodies have started to recognise the power of social entrepreneurship. Steps are being taken in many Member States and regions to encourage the growth of social enterprises.  At EU level, the SBI has made a positive start in promoting eco-systems for social enterprises but we must not lose momentum. Therefore, 1. The EU must follow through on all the actions in the SBI. It should develop a second phase of the SBI that broadens its scope, deepens its partnership with Member States, regional and local authorities, civil society organisations and key players in the ecosystem. 2. The European Economic and Social Committee, the next European Commission (with a dedicated inter-service structure) and the next European Parliament must take full ownership and deliver on the actions suggested in Strasbourg. 3. There must be a stronger engagement at EU, national, regional and local levels with the social enterprise community in the co-creation of new policies to support social enterprise, suited to the local context. 4. The Commission must ensure that its commitment to create an ecosystem for social enterprise is mainstreamed in its policies. 5. In partnership with the social enterprise sector, Member States, regional and local authorities must fully support the growth of social enterprises and help them build capacity. For example through legal frameworks, access to finance, business start-up and development support, training and education and public procurement. 6. The European institutions and Member States should reinforce the role of social enterprises in structural reforms to exit the crisis, notably where the social economy is less developed. 7. The Commission, the Member States and regions must boost cooperation between social enterprises across borders and boundaries, to share knowledge and practices. Similarly, all public authorities should cooperate better between themselves and enhance their capacity to support social enterprise growth. 8. Public and private players must develop a full range of suitable financial instruments and intermediaries that support social enterprises throughout their lifecycle. 9. Social enterprise still needs further research and national statistical collection for a better understanding, recognition and visibility of the sector, both among policymakers and the general public. 10. In this new Europe, all players need to look at growth and value creation from a wider perspective, by including social indicators and demonstrating positive social impact when reporting social and economic progress. 50 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S The EESC was committed to the organisation of the Strasbourg event and is actively involved in social entrepreneurship through a substantial number of opinions and the Social Enterprise Project. Pursuing its interest, it has launched Make it happen, a new project designed to keep the Strasbourg Declaration alive by promoting policy directions and concrete actions to be forwarded to the new Commission and Parliament in Autumn 2014. Nine EESC members are directly involved in Make it happen through actions that involve strengthened cooperation with social enterprise supporters, the participation of the project group members in European events, and the consultation and involvement of various social economy stakeholders and supporters of social enterprise. To further unlock the potential of this sector, the EESC has called for a more supportive environment for social enterprises and for their better integration into all EU policies. It believes that partnerships with regional and local authorities, as well as social entrepreneurs themselves, will play an important role. The main actions points guiding the Social Enterprise Project are therefore as follows: 1. Co-creation of new policies to support social enterprise 2. Partnership to support social enterprises 3. Development of a second phase of the SBI. Following an ongoing local strategy, the Social Enterprise Project is also taking part in local events spread around Europe to conduct fact-findings missions, collect best practices and investigate policy ideas and recommendations for the EU institutions. 4. Conclusion: scanning the future to shape the future ‘Europe has a head-start. It is ideally placed to take a lead and capture first-mover benefits when it comes to implementing social innovations by pro-actively and effectively trying to fully (and fairly) realise both economic and societal benefits. With its strong legacy in social democracy, solidarity, civic participation, justice and fairness, Europe arguably constitutes especially fertile grounds when it comes to sustainably enabling and growing social innovation.’89 Not only does the EU undoubtedly offer fertile ground for social innovation but, as a good gardener, it has taken good care of it, by nurturing it adequately. In 2010, in the first BEPA report, barriers and challenges to social innovation were identified according to the scope and level of ambition of the innovations: responding to social demands, societal challenges or engaging systemic change. Going systematically through the barriers identified then, it seems that a large number of them have either been or are being addressed effectively through EU policies. Milestones have been reached for instance with respect to the availability of funding for social entrepreneurs (e.g. EuSEF, EaSI, public procurement, crowdfunding). Progress is being made through innovative financial schemes, the interest of a large community of financial actors and a wide-ranging and active debate (within GECES, G8, etc.) on the establishment of a methodology to measure the impact of social enterprises on the creation of socio-economic benefits and their benefit for the community; the development of hubs is securing seed funding to promote and test pilot cases; networks of hubs should facilitate the building of ecosystems and the harnessing of contributions to expansion capital from a variety of sources. The Social Business Initiative has also addressed the question of the status of social enterprises (mapping) and the idea that innovations have ‘social’ roots is progressing among mainstream innovation corporations and public and private stakeholders. This was particularly clear during the annual EU Innovation Convention 2014.90 As a result, the EU landscape for social innovation is less fragmented today; it is generally more visible and the programmes, initiatives and instruments created recently have considerably contributed to setting up aspects of a European-wide ecosystem. 89 http://ec.europa.eu/regional_policy/sources/docgener/presenta/social_innovation/social_innovation_2013.pdf. 90 http://ec.europa.eu/research/innovation-union/ic2014/index_en.cfm. 52 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S Nevertheless, as underlined by the OECD, EU policy could gain in coherence: One example lies in the fact that one of the most powerful instruments to address issues related to social innovation, the ERDF and territorial and cohesion policy, makes no direct reference to it. Also, Social entrepreneurs and actors of social innovation who gathered in Strasbourg saw this event as a beginning and not an end. Michel Barnier, the Commissioner responsible for the Single Market, confirmed that this should become a regular event. Moreover, prospective studies recently published on the future of Europe in the medium term are proving to be valuable lessons on the path that lies ahead for Europe to take full advantage of its actions to promote social innovation. Europe’s Societal Challenges A major source of inspiration comes from the report prepared by RAND Europe entitled Europe’s Societal Challenges,91 and commissioned by ESPAS.92 It acknowledges the many challenges facing the EU and suggests ways to mitigate current downward trends. According to the report, the world in 2030 could be characterised by the following significant changes. 91 http://europa.eu/espas/pdf/espas-report-societal-trends.pdf. 92 European Strategy and Policy Analysis System (http://europa.eu/espas/). Regarding demographic change • The world’s population will be more urbanised: for the first time in history, more than 50 % of the population will live in urban zones. Specifically, about 80 % of European society will live in cities, which will become increasingly important actors. • We will also observe further ageing of the world’s population. This trend is already apparent in Europe and it will be the region with the highest average age globally. European population ageing will have direct consequences for the working population and social welfare systems, health services and pensions in terms of demand and expenditure. Regarding immigration patterns • Immigration patterns will change, becoming more inter-regional (south-south rather than south-north). However, Europe will continue to be a destination region for its neighbouring regions. Regarding the growing middle class and the empowerment of individuals • The growing middle class will be a structural change in the world to come. The global middle class will increase from 1.8 billion in 2009 to 5 billion in 2030. • Gender equality and the empowerment of women will improve as a result of more egalitarian access to education and the role of technology. Greater access to further education is likely to drive and be influenced by increased individual empowerment. This in turn may generate greater support for increasing gender equality and the empowerment of women. • Poverty will fall globally and so will inequalities and access to wealth among states. However, there is a risk that inequalities among citizens/individuals will increase in terms of revenue, especially in Europe and the United States. • The internet divide will persist within and between countries – in terms of access to networks and the internet. This means that technological development could potentially accelerate socio-economic inequalities between individuals/countries, since it essentially benefits the highly qualified, the connected and those in the higher income groups. 53P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H These scenarios, should they materialise, would be accompanied by an undoubted political impact, which may be presented as a complex picture of paradoxes: yy In an increasingly complex world, there is an increasing loss of confidence in the institutions and an increasing aversion to risk. This could translate into a crisis of political action linked to the lack of understanding of global complexities among citizens. yy A steady fall in confidence in public action and in political engagement ­­– be it at national or EU level – which could, once again, be exacerbated by the role of technology and access to unverified information. yy The advance of technology leads to a plethora of actors, just as much as it does to new ways of relating to each other (as groups or as citizens), individualistic tendencies (countering the formation of groups) and the radicalisation of society. yy Arguably, the pressures described above will call for substantial efforts in the field of social innovation. Yet, innovation may be slowed down by a culture of risk aversion. yy The interaction of the widening skills gap, digital divide and unequal benefits of technological innovations could lead to a vicious cycle for vulnerable groups, such as young people, the older poor, low-skilled workers, migrants and their children. So what future for Europe and which solutions? RAND Europe suggests four very interesting routes to explore: yy Preparing a new growth paradigm, focused on the wellbeing of citizens while offering opportunities for business to thrive: Europe’s economy is expected to continue its decline, and policymakers should focus on a ‘new growth paradigm’ centred on society, not growth. Instead of focusing efforts on creating wealth, European nations are advised to prioritise the health of societies. The successor of the current Europe Regarding the rise in inequality leading to vulnerability • Across the spectrum of expected problems is a surge in inequality. While inequalities between European countries are decreasing, within countries they are rising. • Earnings/gains from productivity growth tend to be heavily concentrated among high-income workers. At the same time, projections suggest a considerable surplus of low-skilled workers, which could lead to long-term and permanent joblessness among young people without secondary training and older workers who cannot retrain to meet requirements for new skills. As a consequence of this skills mismatch, income inequality is projected to expand. Regarding quick technological development • The development of new technologies will continue right through to 2030. Innovation will continue to depend on R&D investment, which should continue to increase in advanced economies and to further develop in China. In Europe, however, R&D expenses will decrease notably because of the increase in China, even if the 2020 objectives are met. • In order to stimulate innovation, more than one source of funding is needed: education, cooperation among universities, business, and financial institutions organised around innovation ecosystems will be important. • Innovation will also depend on the social and political organisation of society: democracy and open societies seem to favour innovation. There seems to be a circular relationship here, since innovation (particularly the development of technology) will also change the way citizens are organised. 54 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S 2020 Strategy should aim to invest in human capital and avoid sluggish productivity growth, achieved at the expense of social inclusion, public health, education and skills, security or freedom. This will include improving the innovative capacity of SMEs; bridging the digital divide between Member States; matching migrant skills to the labour market, as well as those of the young unemployed. yy Investing in citizens, including protecting the most vulnerable: Aside from fixing the economy, the report argues that the real challenge for European policymakers will be to break the trend of rising poverty risks, increasing income inequality and longterm unemployment without relying on economic growth as a panacea. Investing in health and education, preferably as early as possible (e.g. through early childhood education and care interventions) will help reduce costs in the long term, avoid exclusion, and equip citizens with the skills that are in demand in the labour market. There is also a need to bridge the gender gap and address inequalities in access to technology. yy Adapting public sector and government institutions to the 21st century: This includes mitigating increasing pressure on the affordability of welfare states, particularly health and pensions. yy Bringing citizens back into the European project: A serious and long-term effort is required from the EU institutions and its Member States to support the development of a European identity from the earliest age – a sense of belonging that would reinforce a sense of solidarity and loyalty to democratic ideals. Several EU policies that deal with employment, education, health and technological development could be used for this purpose. Similarly, more transparency in decision-making processes and structural/institutional reforms that recognise the emergence of new actors/ stakeholders on the scene (NGOs, civil society, business associations, etc.) and new forms of communication will be necessary. What will social enterprise look like in Europe by 2020? The second of the aforementioned studies is the British Council’s ‘think piece’,93 commissioned to contribute to the previously mentioned Strasbourg event. It provides a basis for discussing what will shape social innovation and the growth of social enterprises in the near future. How will social enterprise respond to economic conditions, social and environmental challenges, government policies, technology and investment over the next years? Social enterprises are on the rise throughout the EU, with governments and investors increasingly recognising the sector as a valid alternative to both private and public sector busi- ness. By 2020, associations and charities will be part of the ‘social enterprise spectrum’, generating most of their income through trading activities. Enterprises from the private sector will have to demonstrate their credentials, and could be better at this than traditional social enterprises. Public, private and social economy organisations will be encouraged by investors, funders, and governments to produce social value results in the long 93 cf. Mark Richardson, Richard Catherall ­– What will social enterprise look like in Europe by 2020? ­– British Council, January 2014. http://www.britishcouncil.org/sites/britishcouncil.uk2/files/what_will_social_enterprise_look_like_in_europe_ by_2020_0.pdf. 55P A R T I – S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N , A N E W P A T H term. As a consequence, social impact measurement and comparison (covering economic, environmental and social issues) will become mainstream in the social economy. From grants to investment: one of the most important drivers will be the development of the social finance sector. The traditional model of foundations will become outdated since more and more enterprises will try to maximise their social impact while delivering a financial return. Hybrid models of social investment (Social Investment Bonds, Social Impact Bonds) will emphasise new tools (‘investment readiness’, ‘impact reporting’) with two consequences: pressure on investors to consider social impact in investments and growing involvement of social enterprises on financial services delivery. But the context will also be constraining: new national and EU funding priorities could exclude innovative social investments; innovative social enterprises will have to make an international impact thanks to social franchising. Complex networks: social enterprises will be more concerned with the importance of their impact (through changing government practices and business, through developing effective solutions that work). This consciousness will result in highly networked micro-social enterprises. Social entrepreneurs will be connected with micro-social structures and work with public, charitable, academic and profit-oriented sectors. Thus, this collaborative approach (crowdsourcing, funding, etc.) will be an interesting alternative to traditional political investment. Indeed, effective social enterprises will be considered as models and will spread more rapidly than classical mechanisms (e.g., social franchising). And European funding will encourage this kind of collaboration across international boundaries. The way forward The European Union is at a decisive moment in its history in terms of the policies it intends to take tomorrow and the future it wants to design. With reference to social innovation, we are not yet in midstream. Over the past five years, we have seen how awareness has grown; how experiments have developed and how policies have begun to assist and foster this trend. With regard to the outcomes, expectations that have emerged and changes that could occur in Europe in the coming years, we need to measure the distance still to go to achieve the major challenge of social innovation and move beyond the expanding myriad of small initiatives and projects with limited results – as successful as they are – to achieve a real systemic change that puts social innovation at the heart of all processes and policies. From where we stand today, building on the gains that have already been made and in addition to the abovementioned suggestions from RAND Europe, we believe that the following three key areas for reflection, exploration and action should be prioritised and explored. Improve governance in relation to social innovation In this field, the levers for improvement and action mainly concern the following three areas: globally speaking, a wider, more permanent support for the role of the public sector (at European, national, regional and local level) in terms of innovation, especially social innovation; fostering the link between social innovation and the private sector, in particular by improving framework conditions to enable the development of enduring partnerships; making corporate social responsibility a systematic and essential element of analysis and operating mode of all businesses. 56 S O C I A L I N N O V A T I O N – A D E C A D E O F C H A N G E S Clearly, to reach these goals, the European Commission should keep improving synergies between its different services. Focus on knowledge Improvements in recent years to impact measurement and mapping have demonstrated their value. Today we should continue in this direction and further enrich knowledge in these two areas of research. Other hitherto unexplored areas deserve to be investigated, especially the interactions between social innovation and health. Research on social innovation must continue to move forward, in order to test new models, focus on best practices or favour bottom-up approaches. Finally, the growing role of information and communication technologies (ICT) in social innovation should be better incorporated in the way we understand and treat this topic. Support, encourage and improve the business environment The Single Market Act (I & II) and the Social Business Initiative have already made many improvements for European businesses that want to promote or participate in social innovation. All possibilities for going further in this direction should be explored and exploited: improve regulations in this field, mainly with regard to accessing finance; encouraging partnerships to support social innovation; using public procurements as a genuine social policy instrument; and developing a second phase of the Social Business Initiative. Ultimately, the addition of these initiatives, the effect of these policies and the gradual (possibly irreversible) evolution in the way we look at social innovation could lead to side effects of unexpected magnitude. yy What is at stake is the ongoing struggle against inequality. We see that it continues to rise and tomorrow it may be even more central to the issues that European policies will have to face and fight. yy What is also at stake is the emergence of a different conception of the economy, a shared economy that is not focused exclusively on growth. yy Finally, empowering the citizen remains at the very heart of social innovation issues. This fundamental issue cannot be ignored by European policies. 3 Inclusive Workplace 3 1. Blanchard, Kenneth H. 2010. "The power of vision." Pp. 17-30 in Leading at a Higher Level: Blanchard on How to Be a High-performing Leader. Harlow: Financial Times Prentice Hall. 2. Heinemeier Hansson, David and Jason Fried. 2010. "Chapter 1." Pp. 12-19 in ReWork: Change the Way You Work Forever. Vermilion. 3. Ligeti, George. 2012. "Chapter 1 omg!" Pp. 16-33 in OMG! Not Training Again. HumanRobot, Budapest. Chapter 2 THE POWER OF VISION Jesse Stoner, Ken Blanchard, and Drea Zigarmi When leaders who are leading at a higher level understand the role of the triple bottom line as the right target—to be the provider of choice, employer of choice, and investment of choice—they are ready to focus everyone’s energy on a compelling vision. The Importance of Vision Why is it so important for leaders to have clear vision? Because Leadership is about going somewhere. If you and your people don’t know where you are going, your leadership doesn’t matter. From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com 18 Leading at a Higher Level Alice learned this lesson in Alice in Wonderland when she was searching for a way out of Wonderland and came to a fork in the road. “Would you tell me, please, which way I ought to go from here?” she asked the Cheshire Cat. “That depends a good deal on where you want to go,” the cat responded. Alice replied that she really did not much care. The smiling cat told her in no uncertain terms: “Then it doesn’t matter which way you go.” Jesse Stoner conducted an extensive study that demonstrated the powerful impact of vision and leadership on organizational performance.1 She collected information from the team members of more than 500 leaders. The results were striking. Leaders who demonstrated strong visionary leadership had the highestperforming teams. Leaders with good management skills but without vision had average team performance. Leaders who were identified as weak in vision and management skills had poorperforming teams. The biggest impediment blocking most managers from being great leaders is the lack of a clear vision for them to serve. In fewer than 10 percent of the organizations we have visited were members clear about the vision. This lack of shared vision causes people to become inundated with multiple priorities, duplication of efforts, false starts, and wasted energy—none of which supports the triple bottom line. A vision builds trust, collaboration, interdependence, motivation, and mutual responsibility for success. Vision helps people make smart choices, because their decisions are being made with the end result in mind. As goals are accomplished, the answer to “What next?” becomes clear. Vision allows us to act from a proactive stance, moving toward what we want rather than reactively away from what we don’t want. Vision empowers and excites us to reach for what we truly desire. As the late management guru Peter Drucker said, “The best way to predict your future is to create it.” From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com 19 The Power of Vision Effective Versus Ineffective Vision Statements A lot of organizations already have vision statements, but most of them seem irrelevant when you look at the organization and where it’s going. The purpose of a vision statement is to create an aligned organization where everyone is working together toward the same desired ends. The vision provides guidance for daily decisions so that people are aiming at the right target, not working at cross-purposes. How do you know if your vision statement works? Here’s the test: Is it hidden in a forgotten file or framed on a wall solely for decoration? If so, it’s not working. Is it actively used to guide everyday decision making? If the answer is yes, your vision statement is working. Creating a Vision That Really Works Why don’t more leaders have a vision? We believe it’s a lack of knowledge. Many leaders—such as former president George H. W. Bush—say they just don’t get the “vision thing.” They acknowledge that vision is desirable, but they’re unsure how to create it. To these leaders, vision seems elusive—something that is magically bestowed only on the fortunate few. Intrigued by the possibility of making vision accessible for all leaders, Jesse Stoner teamed up with Drea Zigarmi to identify the key elements of a compelling vision—one that would inspire people and provide direction. In “From Vision to Reality,” Jesse and Drea identified three key elements of a compelling vision:2 • Significant purpose: What business are you in? • A picture of the future: What will the future look like if you are successful? From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com • Clear values: What guides your behavior and decisions on a daily basis? A vision must include all three elements to be inspiring and enduring. Let’s explore these elements with some real-world examples. Significant Purpose The first element of a compelling vision is a significant purpose. This higher purpose is your organization’s reason for existence. It answers the question “Why?” rather than just explaining what you do. It clarifies, from your customers’ viewpoint, what business you are really in. CNN is in the “hard spot news-breaking business.” Their customers are busy people who need breaking news on demand. Their business is to provide hard news as it unfolds—not to provide entertainment. According to CNN, the typical family today is too busy to sit in front of the television at 7 p.m. Dad has a second job, Mom is working late, and the kids are involved in activities. Therefore, CNN’s purpose is to provide news 24 hours a day. This helps CNN employees answer the questions “What are my priorities?” and “Where should I focus my energy?” Walt Disney started his theme parks with a clear purpose. He said, “We’re in the happiness business.” That is very different from being in the theme park business. Clear purpose drives everything the cast members (employees) do with their guests (customers). Being in the happiness business helps cast members understand their primary role in the company. A wonderful organization in Orlando, Florida, called Give Kids the World, is an implementation operation for the Make-A-Wish Foundation. Dying children who always wanted to go to Disney World, SeaWorld, or other attractions in Orlando can get a chance through Give Kids the World. Over the years, the organization has brought more than 50,000 families to Orlando for a week at no cost to them. The organization thinks having a sick child is a family issue; therefore, the whole family goes to Orlando. 20 Leading at a Higher Level From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com When you ask the employees what business they are in, they tell you they’re in the memory business—they want to create memories for these kids and their families. On a visit to Give Kids the World, one of our colleagues passed a man who was cutting the grass. Curious about how widely understood the organization’s mission was, our colleague asked the man, “What business are you in here at Give Kids the World?” The man smiled and said, “We make memories.” “How do you make memories?” our associate asked. “You just cut the grass.” The man said, “I certainly don’t make memories by continuing to cut the grass if a family comes by. You can always tell who the sick kid is, so I ask that youngster whether he or she or a brother or sister wants to help me with my chores.” Isn’t that a wonderful attitude? It keeps him focused on servicing the folks who come to Give Kids the World. Great organizations have a deep and noble sense of purpose—a significant purpose—that inspires excitement and commitment. When work is meaningful and connected to what we truly desire, we can unleash a productive and creative power we never imagined. But purpose alone is not enough, because it does not tell you where you’re going. A Picture of the Future The second element of a compelling vision is a picture of the future. This picture of the end result should not be abstract. It should be a mental image you can actually see. The power of imagery has been described by many sports psychologists, including Charles Garfield in Peak Performance: Mental Training Techniques of the World’s Greatest Athletes. Numerous studies have 21 The Power of Vision From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com demonstrated that not only does mental imagery enhance performance, but it enhances intrinsic motivation as well.3 CNN’s picture of the future is not something vague like being the premier network news station or being “number one.” It’s a picture you can actually create a mental image of: “To be viewed in every nation on the planet in English and in the language of that region.” Walt Disney’s picture of the future was expressed in the charge he gave every cast member: “Keep the same smile on people’s faces when they leave the park as when they entered.” Disney didn’t care whether a guest was in the park two hours or ten hours. He just wanted to keep them smiling. After all, they were in the happiness business. Your picture should focus on the end result, not the process of getting there. At Give Kids the World, their picture of the future is that in the last week of the lives of youngsters who have been there, they will still be laughing and talking to their families about their time in Orlando. Some people mistakenly use the Apollo Moon Project as an example of a vision. It is a wonderful example of the power of creating a picture of the future, but it’s not an example of a vision. In 1961, when President John F. Kennedy articulated a picture of the future—to place a man on the moon by the end of the 1960s and bring him home safely—the United States had not even invented the technology to accomplish it. To achieve that goal, NASA overcame seemingly insurmountable obstacles, demonstrating the power of articulating a picture of the future. However, once the goal was achieved, NASA never re-created its spectacular achievement, because it was not linked to a significant purpose. There was nothing to answer the question “Why?” Was the purpose to “beat the Russians” or to “begin the Space Defense Initiative” or—in the spirit of Star Trek—“to boldly go where no one has gone before”? Because there was no clear purpose, there was no way to guide decision making going forward 22 Leading at a Higher Level From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com and answer the question “What next?” The second element—a picture of the future—is powerful, but it alone does not create an enduring vision. Clear Values The third element of a compelling vision is having clear values. High performing organizations have clear values. Values define leadership and how employees act on a day-to-day basis while doing their work. Values provide guidelines for how you should proceed as you pursue your purpose and picture of the future. They answer the questions “What do I want to live by?” and “How?” They need to be clearly described so that you know exactly what behaviors demonstrate that the value is being lived. Values need to be consistently acted on, or they are only good intentions. They need to resonate with the personal values of the members of the organization so that people truly choose to live by them. The values need to support the organization’s purpose. Because CNN is in the journalism business, not the entertainment business, its values are “to provide accurate, responsible journalism and to be responsive to the news needs of people around the world.” These values help reporters and producers make on-the-spot decisions about news coverage and would be quite different if CNN were in the entertainment business. Robert Johnson founded Johnson & Johnson for the purpose of alleviating pain and disease. The company’s purpose and values, reflected in its credo, continue to guide the company. Using its values to guide its decision making, Johnson & Johnson quickly recalled all Tylenol capsules throughout the United States during a 1982 tampering incident that was localized in the Chicago area. The immediate cost was substantial, but not knowing the extent of the tampering, the company didn’t want to risk anyone’s safety. In the end, Johnson & Johnson’s triple bottom line was served, demonstrated by the company’s long-term gains in reputation and profitability. 23 The Power of Vision From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com Most organizations that do have values either have too many values or have not rank-ordered them.4 Research done by Ken Blanchard and Michael O’Connor shows that people can’t focus on more than three or four values that really impact behavior. They also found that values must be rank-ordered to be effective. Why? Because life is about value conflicts. When these conflicts arise, people need to know which value they should focus on. The Disney theme parks have four rank-ordered values: safety, courtesy, the show, and efficiency. Why is safety the highest-ranked value? Walt Disney knew that if guests were carried out of one of his parks on a stretcher, they would not have the same smiles on their faces leaving the park as they had when they entered. The second-ranked value, courtesy, is all about the friendly attitude you expect at a Disney park. Why is it important to know that it’s the number-two value? Suppose one of the Disney cast members is answering a guest question in a friendly, courteous manner, and he hears a scream that’s not coming from a roller coaster. If that cast member wants to act according to the park’s rank-ordered values, he will excuse himself as quickly and politely as possible and race toward the scream. Why? Because the number-one value just called. If the values were not rank-ordered and the cast member was enjoying the interaction with the guest, he might say, “They’re always yelling in the park,” and not move in the direction of the scream. Later somebody could come to that cast member and say, “You were the closest to the scream. Why didn’t you move?” The response could be, “I was dealing with our courtesy value.” Life is a series of value conflicts. There will be times when you can’t act on two values at the same time. For a vision to endure, you need all three elements—a significant purpose, a picture of the future, and clear values—to guide behavior on a day-by-day basis. Martin Luther King, Jr. outlined his vision in his “I Have a Dream” speech. By describing a world where his children “will not be judged by the color of their skin but by the content of their character,” he created powerful and specific images arising from the values of brotherhood, respect, 24 Leading at a Higher Level From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com and freedom for all—values that resonate with the founding values of the United States. King’s vision continues to mobilize and guide people beyond his lifetime because it illuminates a significant purpose, provides a picture of the future, and describes values that resonate with people’s hopes and dreams. A Compelling Vision Creates a Culture of Greatness A compelling vision creates a strong culture in which the energy of everyone in the organization is aligned. This results in trust, customer satisfaction, an energized and committed workforce, and profitability. Conversely, when an organization does not live up to its stated values, employee and customer trust and commitment erode, negatively impacting all aspects of the bottom line. For example, Ford lost credibility and market share when its stated value—“Quality Is Job One”—was tested by its hesitation to take responsibility in the recall of the defective Firestone tires on its Explorer sport utility vehicle in 2000.5 Vision Is the Place to Start Research clearly demonstrates the extraordinary impact of a shared vision, or core ideology, on long-term financial performance. The cumulative stock returns of the HPOs researched by Collins and Porras were six times greater than the “successful” companies they examined and 15 times greater than the general market over a 50-year period of time!6 For this reason, vision is the place to start if you want to improve your organization’s HPO SCORES and hit the target. Research has demonstrated time and again that an essential characteristic of great leaders is their ability to mobilize people around a shared vision.7 If it’s not in service of a shared vision, leadership can become self-serving. Leaders begin to think their people are there to serve them, instead of the customer. Organizations can become 25 The Power of Vision From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com 26 Leading at a Higher Level self-serving bureaucracies where leaders focus their energies on recognition, power, and status, rather than the organization’s larger purpose and goals.The results of this type of behavior have been all too evident recently at Enron, WorldCom, and others. Once the leader has clarified and shared the vision, he can focus on serving and being responsive to the needs of the people, understanding that the role of leadership is to remove barriers and help people achieve the vision. The greatest leaders mobilize others by coalescing people around a shared vision. Sometimes leaders don’t get it at first, but the great ones eventually do. Louis Gerstner, Jr. is a perfect example. When Gerstner took the helm of IBM in 1993—amidst turmoil and instability as the company’s annual net losses reached a record $8 billion—he was quoted as saying, “The last thing IBM needs is a vision.” A lot of people asked us what we thought about that statement. Our reply was, “It depends on how he defines vision. If he means a ‘pie-in-the-sky’ dream, he’s absolutely right.The ship is sinking. But if all he’s doing is plugging the holes, the ship isn’t going anywhere.” We were amused to read an article in The NewYork Times8 two years later. In that article, Gerstner conceded that IBM had lost the war for the desktop operating system, acknowledging that the acquisition of Lotus signified that the company had failed to plan properly for its future. He admitted that he and his management team now “spent a lot of time thinking ahead.” Once Gerstner understood the importance of vision, an incredible turnaround occurred. It became clear that the company’s source of strength would be in integrated solutions and resisted pressures to split the company. In 1995, delivering the keynote address at the computer industry trade show, Gerstner articulated IBM’s new vision—that network computing would drive the next phase of industry growth and would be the company’s overarching strategy. That year, IBM began a series of acquisitions that positioned services to become the company’s fastest-growing segment, with growth at more than 20 percent per year. This extraordinary turnaround demonstrated that the most important thing IBM needed was a vision—a shared vision. From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com If an organization’s vision is compelling, the triple bottom line is served. Success goes way beyond mere financial rewards. Vision generates tremendous energy, excitement, and passion, because people feel they are making a difference. They know what they are doing and why. There is a strong sense of trust and respect. Managers don’t try to control, but rather let others assume responsibility, because people know they are part of an aligned whole. People assume responsibility for their own actions. They take charge of their future, rather than passively waiting for it to happen. There is room for creativity and risk taking. People can make their contributions in their own way, and those differences are respected, because people know they are in the same boat— all part of a larger whole going “full steam ahead!” Vision Can Exist Anywhere in an Organization You don’t have to wait for an organizational vision to begin. Vision is the responsibility of every leader at every level of the organization. It’s possible for leaders of departments or teams to create shared visions for their departments even when the rest of the organization doesn’t have one. Consider our work helping a tax department in a Fortune 500 company. The leader of the department stated: “We began to understand our own and each others’ hopes and dreams and discovered how close they were. We found ways to work together more effectively and began to enjoy work a lot more. We discovered what business we were really in: ‘Providing financial information to help leaders make good business decisions.’ As a result, we began to partner more effectively with business leaders. Our department gained more credibility in the company, and other departments began asking us what we had done to make such a turnaround. They became interested in creating a vision for their own department. It was contagious.” Too often, leaders complain that they can’t have a vision because the larger organization doesn’t have one. Again, it’s not 27 The Power of Vision From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com necessary to wait. The power of vision will work for you and your team, regardless of your level in the organization. Make Your Vision a Reality In their book Full Steam Ahead! Unleash the Power of Vision in Your Company andYour Life, Ken Blanchard and Jesse Stoner define vision as “knowing who you are, where you’re going, and what will guide your journey.”9 Knowing who you are means having a significant purpose. Where you’re going means having a picture of the future. What will guide your journey are clear values. However, vision alone is not enough. For a leader to ensure that the vision becomes a reality—a shared vision that mobilizes people—Ken and Jesse identify three important guidelines that people must follow: How the vision is created, how it’s communicated, and how it’s lived. How It’s Created The process of creating the vision is as important as what the vision says. Instead of simply taking the top management to a retreat to put the vision together and then announcing it to others, encourage dialogue about the vision. While the initial responsibility for drafting an organizational vision rests with the top management, the organization needs to put in place mechanisms to give others an opportunity to help shape the vision—to put their thumbprint on it. For a departmental or team vision, it’s possible to craft the vision as a team. Although the leader must have a sense of where he’s going, it’s important that he trusts and utilizes the knowledge and skills of the people on the team to get the best vision. Regardless of how you initially draft the vision, it’s important that you get input from those it affects before you finalize it. Ask people these questions: “Would you like to work for an organization that has this vision? Can you see where you fit in the vision? Does it help you set priorities? Does it provide guidelines for making decisions? Is it exciting and motivating? Have we left anything 28 Leading at a Higher Level From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com 29 The Power of Vision out? Should we delete anything?” Involving people will deepen their understanding and commitment and create a better vision. How It’s Communicated Creating a vision—for your organization or department, for your work, and for your life—is a journey, not a one-time activity. In some organizations, a vision statement may be found framed on the wall, but it provides no guidance or, worse, has nothing to do with the reality of how things actually are. This turns people off. Visioning is an ongoing process; you need to keep it alive. It’s important to keep talking about the vision and referring to it as much as possible. Max DePree, the legendary former chairman of Herman Miller and author of Leadership Is an Art, said that in his visionary role, he had to be like a third-grade teacher. He had to keep on saying it over and over and over until people got it right, right, right!The more you focus on your vision, the clearer it will become, and the more deeply you will understand it. In fact, aspects of what you thought was the vision may change over time, but its essence will remain. How It’s Lived The moment you identify your vision, you need to behave as if it were happening right now.Your actions need to be congruent with your vision. As others see you living the vision, they will believe you are serious, and this will help deepen their understanding and commitment.Two strategies will support your efforts to live your vision: • Always focus on your vision. Your vision should be the foundation for your organization. If an obstacle or unforeseen event throws you off-course, you may have to change your short-term goals, but your vision should be long-lasting. Change is bound to happen. Unforeseen events are bound to occur. Find a way to reframe what is happening as a challenge or opportunity on the road to living your vision. From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com 30 Leading at a Higher Level • Show the courage of commitment. True commitment begins when you take action. There will be fears; feel them and move ahead. It takes courage to create a vision, and it takes courage to act on it. In the words of Goethe, “Whatever you can do, or dream you can, begin it. Boldness has genius, power, and magic in it.” Vision and Leadership Vision always comes back to leadership. People look to their formal leaders for vision and direction. While leaders should involve people in shaping direction, the ultimate responsibility for ensuring and maintaining a vision remains with the leaders and cannot be delegated to others. Creating a vision is not an activity that can be checked off a list. It’s one of the most critical ongoing roles of a successful leader. It means the difference between high and average performance, whether it’s an entire organization, a department, or a team. Once a vision is agreed upon, it is up to the leader to ensure that people respond to the vision. The leader’s job is to support people in accomplishing the vision by removing barriers; by ensuring that policies, practices, and systems make it easier for them to act on the vision; and by holding themselves, their peers, and their people accountable for acting consistently with the vision. This way people serve the vision, not the leader. Vision calls an organization to be truly great, not merely to beat the competition and get big numbers. A magnificent vision articulates people’s hopes and dreams, touches their hearts and spirits, and helps them see how they can contribute. It aims everyone in the right direction. COMPANION ONLINE RESOURCE Visit www.LeadingAtAHigherLevel.com to access the free virtual conference titled Set Your Sights on the Right Target and Vision. Use the password “Target” for your FREE access. From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com 310 Leading at a Higher Level Chapter 2 1 Jesse Stoner, Visionary Leadership, Management, and High Performing Work Units (doctoral dissertation, University of Massachusetts, 1988). 2 Jesse Stoner and Drea Zigarmi, “From Vision to Reality” (Escondido, CA: The Ken Blanchard Companies, 1993). The elements of a compelling vision were also described by Stoner in “Realizing Your Vision” (Provo, UT: Executive Excellence, 1990) 3 Charles Garfield and Hal Bennett, Peak Performance: Mental Training Techniques of the World’s Greatest Athletes (New York: Warner Books, 1989). 4 Ken Blanchard and Michael O’Connor, Managing by Values (San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler, 1997). 5 Ford Motor Company documents indicate that company officials had data that Firestone tires installed on Explorer sport-utility vehicles had little or no margin for safety in top-speed driving at the tire pressures that Ford recommended. The papers were part of a collection of documents that Congressional investigators released before the third round of Congressional hearings investigating Ford’s and Bridgestone/Firestone Inc.’s handling of tire failures. 6 Jim Collins and Jerry Porras, Built to Last: Successful Habits of Visionary Companies (New York: HarperCollins, 1994). 7 Research studies described in Leaders: The Strategies for Taking Charge by Warren Bennis, 1985, and The Leadership Challenge by Kouzes and Posner, among others. 8 New York Times, August 2, 1995. 9 Ken Blanchard and Jesse Stoner, Full Steam Ahead: Unleash the Power of Vision in Your Company and Your Life (San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler, 2003). From the Library of Lee Bogdanoff Download at WoweBook.Com CHAPTER TAKEDOWNS Ignore the real world “That would never work in the real world.” You hear it all the time when you tell people about a fresh idea. This real world sounds like an awfully depressing place to live. It’s a place where new ideas, unfamiliar approaches, and foreign concepts always lose. The only things that win are what people already know and do, even if those things are flawed and inefficient. Scratch the surface and you’ll find these “real world” inhabitants are filled with pessimism and despair. They expect fresh concepts to fail. They assume society isn’t ready for or capable of change. Even worse, they want to drag others down into their tomb. If you’re hopeful and ambitious, they’ll try to convince you your ideas are impossible. They’ll say you’re wasting your time. Don’t believe them. That world may be real for them, but it doesn’t mean you have to live in it. We know because our company fails the real-world test in all kinds of ways. In the real world, you can’t have more than a dozen employees spread out in eight different cities on two continents. In the real world, you can’t attract millions of customers without any salespeople or advertising. In the real world, you can’t reveal your formula for success to the rest of the world. But we’ve done all those things and prospered. The real world isn’t a place, it’s an excuse. It’s a justification for not trying. It has nothing to do with you. Learning from mistakes is overrated In the business world, failure has become an expected rite of passage. You hear all the time how nine out of ten new businesses fail. You hear that your business’s chances are slim to none. You hear that failure builds character. People advise, “Fail early and fail often.” With so much failure in the air, you can’t help but breathe it in. Don’t inhale. Don’t get fooled by the stats. Other people’s failures are just that: other people’s failures. If other people can’t market their product, it has nothing to do with you. If other people can’t build a team, it has nothing to do with you. If other people can’t price their services properly, it has nothing to do with you. If other people can’t earn more than they spend … well, you get it. Another common misconception: You need to learn from your mistakes. What do you really learn from mistakes? You might learn what not to do again, but how valuable is that? You still don’t know what you should do next. Contrast that with learning from your successes. Success gives you real ammunition. When something succeeds, you know what worked—and you can do it again. And the next time, you’ll probably do it even better. Failure is not a prerequisite for success. A Harvard Business School study found alreadysuccessful entrepreneurs are far more likely to succeed again (the success rate for their future companies is 34 percent). But entrepreneurs whose companies failed the first time had almost the same follow-on success rate as people starting a company for the first time: just 23 percent. People who failed before have the same amount of success as people who have never tried at all.* Success is the experience that actually counts. That shouldn’t be a surprise: It’s exactly how nature works. Evolution doesn’t linger on past failures, it’s always building upon what worked. So should you. Planning is guessing Unless you’re a fortune-teller, long-term business planning is a fantasy. There are just too many factors that are out of your hands: market conditions, competitors, customers, the economy, etc. Writing a plan makes you feel in control of things you can’t actually control. Why don’t we just call plans what they really are: guesses. Start referring to your business plans as business guesses, your financial plans as financial guesses, and your strategic plans as strategic guesses. Now you can stop worrying about them as much. They just aren’t worth the stress. When you turn guesses into plans, you enter a danger zone. Plans let the past drive the future. They put blinders on you. “This is where we’re going because, well, that’s where we said we were going.” And that’s the problem: Plans are inconsistent with improvisation. And you have to be able to improvise. You have to be able to pick up opportunities that come along. Sometimes you need to say, “We’re going in a new direction because that’s what makes sense today.” The timing of long-range plans is screwed up too. You have the most information when you’re doing something, not before you’ve done it. Yet when do you write a plan? Usually it’s before you’ve even begun. That’s the worst time to make a big decision. Now this isn’t to say you shouldn’t think about the future or contemplate how you might attack upcoming obstacles. That’s a worthwhile exercise. Just don’t feel you need to write it down or obsess about it. If you write a big plan, you’ll most likely never look at it anyway. Plans more than a few pages long just wind up as fossils in your file cabinet. Give up on the guesswork. Decide what you’re going to do this week, not this year. Figure out the next most important thing and do that. Make decisions right before you do something, not far in advance. It’s OK to wing it. Just get on the plane and go. You can pick up a nicer shirt, shaving cream, and a toothbrush once you get there. Working without a plan may seem scary. But blindly following a plan that has no relationship with reality is even scarier. Why grow? People ask, “How big is your company?” It’s small talk, but they’re not looking for a small answer. The bigger the number, the more impressive, professional, and powerful you sound. “Wow, nice!” they’ll say if you have a hundred-plus employees. If you’re small, you’ll get an “Oh … that’s nice.” The former is meant as a compliment; the latter is said just to be polite. Why is that? What is it about growth and business? Why is expansion always the goal? What’s the attraction of big besides ego? (You’ll need a better answer than “economies of scale.”) What’s wrong with finding the right size and staying there? Do we look at Harvard or Oxford and say, “If they’d only expand and branch out and hire thousands more professors and go global and open other campuses all over the world … then they’d be great schools.” Of course not. That’s not how we measure the value of these institutions. So why is it the way we measure businesses? Maybe the right size for your company is five people. Maybe it’s forty. Maybe it’s two hundred. Or maybe it’s just you and a laptop. Don’t make assumptions about how big you should be ahead of time. Grow slow and see what feels right—premature hiring is the death of many companies. And avoid huge growth spurts too—they can cause you to skip right over your appropriate size. Small is not just a stepping-stone. Small is a great destination in itself. Have you ever noticed that while small businesses wish they were bigger, big businesses dream about being more agile and flexible? And remember, once you get big, it’s really hard to shrink without firing people, damaging morale, and changing the entire way you do business. Ramping up doesn’t have to be your goal. And we’re not talking just about the number of employees you have either. It’s also true for expenses, rent, IT infrastructure, furniture, etc. These things don’t just happen to you. You decide whether or not to take them on. And if you do take them on, you’ll be taking on new headaches, too. Lock in lots of expenses and you force yourself into building a complex businesss—one that’s a lot more difficult and stressful to run. Don’t be insecure about aiming to be a small business. Anyone who runs a business that’s sustainable and profitable, whether it’s big or small, should be proud. Workaholism Our culture celebrates the idea of the workaholic. We hear about people burning the midnight oil. They pull all-nighters and sleep at the office. It’s considered a badge of honor to kill yourself over a project. No amount of work is too much work. Not only is this workaholism unnecessary, it’s stupid. Working more doesn’t mean you care more or get more done. It just means you work more. Workaholics wind up creating more problems than they solve. First off, working like that just isn’t sustainable over time. When the burnout crash comes—and it will—it’ll hit that much harder. Workaholics miss the point, too. They try to fix problems by throwing sheer hours at them. They try to make up for intellectual laziness with brute force. This results in inelegant solutions. They even create crises. They don’t look for ways to be more efficient because they actually like working overtime. They enjoy feeling like heroes. They create problems (often unwittingly) just so they can get off on working more. Workaholics make the people who don’t stay late feel inadequate for “merely” working reasonable hours. That leads to guilt and poor morale all around. Plus, it leads to an ass-inseat mentality—people stay late out of obligation, even if they aren’t really being productive. If all you do is work, you’re unlikely to have sound judgments. Your values and decision making wind up skewed. You stop being able to decide what’s worth extra effort and what’s not. And you wind up just plain tired. No one makes sharp decisions when tired. In the end, workaholics don’t actually accomplish more than nonworkaholics. They may claim to be perfectionists, but that just means they’re wasting time fixating on inconsequential details instead of moving on to the next task. Workaholics aren’t heroes. They don’t save the day, they just use it up. The real hero is already home because she figured out a faster way to get things done. Enough with “entrepreneurs” Let’s retire the term entrepreneur. It’s outdated and loaded with baggage. It smells like a members-only club. Everyone should be encouraged to start his own business, not just some rare breed that self-identifies as entrepreneurs. There’s a new group of people out there starting businesses. They’re turning profits yet never think of themselves as entrepreneurs. A lot of them don’t even think of themselves as business owners. They are just doing what they love on their own terms and getting paid for it. So let’s replace the fancy-sounding word with something a bit more down-to-earth. Instead of entrepreneurs, let’s just call them starters. Anyone who creates a new business is a starter. You don’t need an MBA, a certificate, a fancy suit, a briefcase, or an aboveaverage tolerance for risk. You just need an idea, a touch of confidence, and a push to get started. *Leslie Berlin, “Try, Try Again, or Maybe Not,” New York Times, Mar. 21, 2009. 16 chapter 1 omg! Team: brrrr! Why is the word "team" being used so often in the corporate world, or in the world of work at all? Teams compete in sports and in games. Companies, local government departments, or NGOs have rather built little communities and teams do not exist in civilian life at all. Well, to be precise they do, but only in our heads. This is what makes playing in "teams" reality and this is the line along which people will identify with either the blue or red team (telecommunications company, TV channel, food chainstore). This is the phenomenon the business world has learned to exploit so well. If, let's say, we consider ourselves part of the Monkey Informatics team, then we will get into battle against Donkey Software with much greater vehemence and determination on the battlefield of business. Once we have established team consciousness among the 17 team members, then they can work 18 instead of 8 hours a day, and are prepared to commit smaller or greater infringements or acts of immorality to the detriment of the other company, motivated purely by a desire to "win". To win the "competition". But what competition? Is it really a competition? Is there a start and a finish line? Is there a moment when somebody blows the whistle to signal the end of the match and we know whether it's the Monkeys or the Donkeys who have won? In reality the winners are the owners, who take their winnings home at the end of the year in the shape of dividends. They, more often then not, have a share in the Monkey and Donkey company alike. Training is often used to build a team. This is even though real team building should not be achieved at a place distant from work and not with the involvement of an outside figure, but rather during normal business hours at work. Team is not built by the training session or the trainer, but by the leader and the 18 community itself. Team is built on an average busy Thursday, or in the evening when the server suddenly breaks down, but the assignment must be completed by morning the next day the latest. And there is a leader and all the staff members are ready to join hands and without concern for themselves or for the others, they overcome the situation and tackle the problem. They do it for each other. Not out of fear of the upcoming deadline, and not for praise or money; but simply for each other. Now, that is team building. All the rest is maraschino cherry on top of the cake. If a set of people does not evolve into a real community (all right, let's call it a "team") sooner or later, it is probably due to poor organisational climate. Company culture is shaped and developed by the management. humanrobot: Is it not food for thought when advisers - for very high hourly rates - have no alternative but to advise the top management of a company of about ten thousand employees that they should - at least once a week - have lunch together with the workers in the company canteen? 19 Road to training All training must serve the improvement of the organisation. Training programmes range on a very wide scale, but if training is not part of a consciously thought-out and implemented building/development process, then training has very little to add. Where do things go astray? Some training sessions just don't work; that's happened to me, too. Also there are bad trainers. But the seed of poor training is always sown during the preliminary ordering phase. This may be a realistic threat when 1. the expectations and responsibilities of the parties are not clarified, 2. training is wanted because there's some money left at the end of the year, or when there is not enough money and the client is seeking to get a bit of a facelift rather than root-level improvement, 3. client has some hidden objective or expectation of training, 20 4. the to-be participants do not have the faintest clue of what their boss has got in store for them. When the expectations and responsibilities of the parties are not clarified: the client cannot clearly express what he wants to achieve through training; the developers – in the hope of financial and professional gains – are willing to go into any length to please the client and they do not squeeze out all the required information; the participants only spring to attention when they learn that participation is compulsory; the venue used only provides what is customary but fails in giving custom-tailored services. When training is wanted because there's some money left at the end of the year: "It doesn't matter what it is..., just do something!", goes the task description. Now, it is up to the trainer to decide if he will take on an assignment like that in exchange for pocket money or the survival of his enterprise, or - on the grounds of protecting his own or the client's business interests - tactfully refuses suggesting that they should be reconsidering 21 the proposal at the beginning of next year in view of the long-term objectives. When there is not enough money, but the client is seeking to get a bit of a facelift treatment instead of real improvement: although people ought to be paid higher or more staff is needed because of increased workload, the company is unable or unwilling to spend more. Well, why don't we just give them a slap on the shoulder? Instead of sending them off for two days to a wellness hotel, the management gets them two trainers to do something with the overworked and underpaid staff. When the client has some hidden objective or expectation of the training: there was one school principal who wanted training from me because he feared that the mayor would not make him school principal when his mandate was over unless he had his teachers' support. He thought training would be a form of reward to his staff. When the to-be participants do not have the faintest clue of what their boss has got in store for them: I have been witness to a 22 development programme - which, by the way, required many days of preparation - in which participants begged the trainer like school children not to make them do anything. What it all boils down to is that the decisionmaker (leader number one or the HR manager) decides that the organisation needs developing or, alternatively, staff members or teams need skills development or improvement in specific special areas of expertise. Or that development is needed across the entire organisation as they want to introduce an entirely new organisational culture. Of course, culture will not change overnight during training; the most a trainer can do is make people aware of the realisations that are already there lurking inside people's heads. 23 Most of the time, this is not recognised by the participants. Only felt or sensed. humanrobot: "Hi there, we've got a little money left over in our budget, which we must either pay the government in taxes or alternatively, we can buy a research project. Could you not do some management programme on the pretext of research for us? You know, the bosses go down to the country each year. Now, this we could link this to a management training programme, a little bit of wine tasting and mini golf at the end", goes the typical rhetoric of the company HR. 24 What is training definitely not about? Training - and I must stress this again - is a means of organisation development. If it is wanted by a small market enterprise, the final and sole objective might just be to improve profitability. Nothing else. After all, the company was originally set up to make profit. What else? Of course, the other question is the price the company is paying to achieve the expected return. Training is not a form of reward. Going sailing or spending one week in Barcelona (often coined incentive training) by the top management is more like a company holiday rather than organisation development. It may well be that the participants will have a good time and can unwind, they may also inevitable get to know each other better; even more so, loyalty to the generous boss will increase, after all, this great guy/girl is paying for the bill. Yet I insist that this has nothing to contribute to company development. Training is not a form of punishment. "I am here because they put my name on the list, 25 just now when I have a deadline to meet tomorrow." Too many of my training sessions start out like this. In a better scenario, participants and I reward the sincerity of the comment with roaring laughter. Things are not going right? Well, just enrol them in some effectiveness-booster training. That'll make a difference. Is the staff overconfident? We'll send them off to an overnight survival course. But why? Training is not the place for the trainer to hold theatrical shows. The trainer is a facilitator who is tasked with eliciting the thoughts and feelings that are already there inside the participants. The trainer is there to encourage people to say certain things, look at various life situations from different angles, express different problems and find the solutions if solutions can in fact be identified. During all this, it is not the task of nor the time for the trainer to make himself popular or likeable. Of course, there are times during training when the trainer is acting, as may be the case with short theoretical type presentations. There are moments when theatrical skills are called for, when the trainer 26 is driven by empathy. Nonetheless, all these moments must be used to serve the purpose of development and not the acceptance of the trainer, or the satisfaction of the trainer's personal desire to be in the centre of attention. Training is not designed to pave the way for an unpleasant discussion. "People will feel better and it will be easier for them to take the pill", said one potential client; eventually, I declined the offer. The act of announcing any unpleasant news is an organisation development tool itself: having an open and clear approach, the honest exploration of the troubles and their causes, the ability to identify with the people concerned by the management is the best possible developmental tool that cannot be matched by even the best of trainers. 27 humanrobot: "Unfortunately, as it turned out, I could not attend the event; I had a foreign delegation to meet", says one director as he invites me for coffee behind the imitation leather padded door of his office. "Nevertheless, I would love you to tell me a few words about the people, who was the best of them all, perhaps the most cooperative and who impeded progress most. You know, I need this info to deal with these people in my everyday work." You would have to be a real tacky diplomat to get out of a tight situation like this one. After all, the client is your client even if he had failed to turn up at the training. He will issue you with your performance certificate, he will pay you, and it is up to him whether you will use this as a reference work, or quietly conceal that you have ever been near the place. 28 The selling phase It is always difficult to sell. Especially if you are selling a service, which most people believe they have some understanding of. Now organisation development is just such a service. I tend to feel I am really screwed when I find that my client has some vague knowledge of the subject and they keep wanting to convert the little they know into loose change. (This kind of work presents a real challenge because on the one hand I can utilise the eagerness of my partner but at the same time use a bit of tactfulness and diplomacy to keep my fingers on the steering wheel. Let's call this group of people sciolists. They will show off their patchwork knowledge already during initial consultation. A typical example for this when they want to show off before their superiors or employees. Or they may want to get a training product from you that they may have heard of before and have grown to like it for some reason, and are most certainly not willing to hear the sad news from 29 you that this is exactly what they do not actually need. There is, however, a group of clients that are either highly educated or totally ignorant on the subject. This latter group, recognising their ignorance, are excellent partners hence I put them in the same category with the educated ones. These clients 1. do not see their roles in a relationship of subordination / domination, but focus on identifying shared goals, 2. are ready and willing to learn and understand the entire training process, and 3. are happy to share information - which we, service providers, can also learn a lot from and can offer them custom-tailored programmes, 4. do not disguise problematic organisational components or shun their own responsibility. Many service providers are irritated if the client wants to be part of the process in a creative way. However this is normally for the better since the client 30 1. will identify with the project if personally involved, 2. will find participation rewarding and realise their own responsibilities, 3. will be of assistance to you since they will most certainly know more about their organisation than you. All you have to realise and consequently indicate to them is the border line between their and your responsibility. humanrobot: We were holding a training session for the teaching staff of a vocational school in a small town. The programme was a great success mostly because the weaving and wood-carving teachers were open to the development methodologies we applied, which - by the way - were very detached from their everyday reality. They were able to laugh at themselves and could even tell us what they believed in, and the things they would not like to make changes to because they were convinced they had been doing well. When we finished, there was an Angel of Silence. Then suddenly, appearing seemingly from nowehere, the school principal asked a young lady teacher to hand out photocopies of a story and asked the teachers to read it and "nod one by one if you think you have understood it". 31 Boxing and whitewater rafting An organisation developer company was launching a new business branch and ran boxing training for the managers. According to the concept underlying the programme, world one has to learn to give and take punches in the business. Does it not occur to you that such a programme might , in fact, be organised for the sole reason to make the organisation developer stand out from the rest. At all costs? The question is: why is any knowledge of boxing required to sell an IT system, build a residential estate, or introduce a new brand of swimming suits? Many think that the business world is like a boxing ring into which one only steps if armed from head to toe. Whitewater rafting Some like it. And some loathe it. Our likes and dislikes and the way we relate to extreme sports vary, and rightly so. What may seem extreme sport to one person may be daily routine for he other. Some of the feelings experienced in training courses, the thoughts and arguments of others, 32 and the mutually worked out solutions may be carried over into the realm of everyday reality. This is the real meaning and purpose of training. There is, however, a limit beyond which scaring or frightening people is expressly hazardous. And also unethical. Just because someone, having a helmet on his head, detests getting into an incessantly swaying rubber dinghy with three other people from the controlling department, it does not mean that they cannot be excellent payroll accountants who never make a mistake in thirty years, especially not at the cost of the company. It is not freezing to death in the icy waters and rolling over rocks that grinds you into a team - this is so even if the water, the boat and progress are fantastic metaphors in the various areas of business. 33 humanrobot: I've often had participants shyly eyeing the noses of their shoes and coming up to me directly before the training was about to begin to ask me about the type of activities they will be expected to perform. After a significant number of similar cases that showed the same pattern, I came to the realisation that people were worried that they would be subjected to humiliating exercises. In these cases it transpired that the manager responsible for organising the training failed to inform the participants on what they were to expect. In one development programme, an excessively obese lady came up to me, her neck badly covered with moles, and she asked me on a soft tone full of concern what type of activities we would be playing during the day. She told me how much she feared to make any physical contact with anyone because she had the belief that no-one would feel comfortable touching her under any circumstance. She also shared with me some of her former bad experiences. It transpired that a few years before the lady had looked perfectly average; she was a mother and a wife, but recently she had been diagnosed with a tumour, which produced the above symptoms. There were no activities on the cards that involved the touching of each other on this training session. 4 Dynamics of Social Inclusion/Exclusion in Public Space 4 1. Kennett, Patricia. 1999. "Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion." Pp. 37 – 60 in Homelessness: exploring the new terrain, edited by Patricia Kennett and Alex Marsh, Bristol: The Policy Press. 2. Mathieson, Jane, Jennie Popay, Etheline Enoch, Sarah Escorel, Mario Hernandez, Heidi Johnston, and Laetitia Rispel. 2008. "The meanings of social exclusion." Pp. 11-38 in Social Exclusion. Meaning, measurement and experience and links to health inequalities. A review of literature. WHO Social Exclusion Knowledge Network Background Paper 1. (Available on-line at: http://www.who.int/social_determinants/media/sekn_meaning_measuremen t_experience_2008.pdf.pdf). 37 THREE Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion Patricia Kennett This chapter considers the relationship between homelessness and the concepts of citizenship and social exclusion. The connections are complex and numerous while at the same time nebulous and changing. The meanings of the concepts themselves represent ‘contested terrain’. This chapter will argue, however, that this conceptual framework contributes to an understanding of the multiple connections between the ensembles of social rights, institutional and policy arrangements within and through which homelessness has been understood and through which the boundaries of citizenship and social exclusion have been drawn. The discussion will be located in the context of the contemporary ‘entrepreneurial’ city. This chapter will begin with a brief discussion of the concepts of citizenship and social exclusion (for fuller discussions see Turner, 1993; Room, 1995; Bulmer and Rees, 1996; Jordan, 1996; Levitas, 1998; Lister, 1998). Developments in the post-war period will then be explored to establish the institutional,ideological and discursive context through which homelessness was constructed and the boundaries of citizenship and inclusionary and exclusionary criteria were established. The chapter will then consider the emergence of the new homelessness within an alternative policy discourse. Particularly from the early 1980s, this discourse was accompanied by the renegotiation of the content and meaning of citizenship rights. The chapter will argue that the current model of social integration and citizenship seems to be one in which there has been a re-evaluation of the notion of civil rights and an increasing emphasis on the‘privatised’ citizen (Lister, 1990), active in the workfare state of the stakeholder society. 38 Homelessness Citizenship and social exclusion The concept of citizenship has a long history but is most commonly associated with the work of T.H. Marshall (1950) for whom citizenship is based upon rights and entitlements. His central theme was that the rights of citizenship involve national constitutional rights such as civil and political rights,as well as embracing social rights,each of which is closely associated with social and political institutions. The hallmark of advanced industrial democracies is the eventual institutionalisation of all three types of rights and, in particular, social citizenship. For Marshall, the citizenship rights that accrue to members of a political community integrate previously unintegrated segments of the population and serve to mitigate some of the inequalities of class, thus altering the pattern of social inequality. Marshall discusses‘class fusion’which he refers to as the“general enrichment of the concrete substance of civilised life, a general reduction of risk and insecurity,and equalisation between the more or less fortunate at all levels” (Marshall,1950,p 6). This leads“...towards a fuller measure of equality,an enrichment of the stuff of which the status is made and an increase in the number of those on whom the status is bestowed”(p 29). Marshall’s thesis has been criticised for its evolutionary and Anglocentric nature (Giddens, 1982; Mann, 1987), as well as its emphasis on class. As Marsh (1998) points out,general accounts of citizenship often render other social divisions in society,such as gender and ethnicity,invisible. Marshall (1950) also fails to recognise the contingency, flexibility and fragility of the social contract between the state and the individual and that the attainment of citizenship rights and the opportunity to exercise such rights is a process of constant struggle and negotiation. The progression from civil to political and social rights is not the smooth, inevitable process Marshall suggests, but has always been dependent on political struggles between social movements, groups and classes. Retrogression and the erosion of the rights of particular groups are an ever-present possibility. Byrne (1997) describes the term social exclusion as “currently the most fashionable term” (p 28) for describing social divisions in European capitalist societies. It has been the catalyst for extensive debate regarding the nature of social differentiation (for example, Rodgers, et al, 1995; Room, 1995; Jordan, 1996) and is now widely utilised both in national and international policy arenas (for example,European Commission,1994; Social Exclusion Unit, 1998). Saraceno (1997) argues that the reconstruction of debates from poverty to social exclusion has involved “an actual conceptual shift, and a change in perspective; from a static to 39 a dynamic approach, as well as from a distributional to a relational focus” (p 177). Lee and Murie (1997) point out that the term social exclusion is more explicitly concerned with the social rights of citizenship and the ability to exercise such rights, particularly in relation to accessing services such as housing, employment and healthcare. And, according to Abrahamson (1997) “the element that distinguishes social exclusion from poverty and makes it, perhaps, more potent, is ... the affiliation with the issue of citizenship rights” (p 148). So while Room (1991) had defined social exclusion in relation to social rights and the inability of ‘citizens’ to secure these social rights, for Tricard social exclusion refers to: ... processes and situations by which persons or groups tend to be separated or held at a distance from ordinary social exchange or positions which promote or allow integration or ‘insertion’ – that is,from participation in institutions or from access to rights, services or resources which imply full membership of society. (Tricard, 1991, p 2) The relational dynamics between housing and social exclusion have recently been explored by Lee and Murie (1997) who seek to show “the way in which the housing system forms part of the process through which poverty and deprivation arises and is experienced”(p 4). Somerville (1998), in applying the theory of social exclusion to housing processes, explores the themes of housing production, housing tenure, residential segregation, mobility and processes associated with homelessness and leaving home. He seeks to show “how housing processes cut across the different social levels (labour process, social reproduction and ideology), how they reflect prevailing patterns of social exclusion,and how they can mitigate or reinforce those patterns” (p 761). Anderson (1999), however, argues that debates linking housing and social exclusion have tended to “neglect a significant group of people who have no accommodation, or have shelter which is much less secure than council housing – single homeless people” (p 157). Yet, Pleace (1998) argues that the concept of social exclusion offers the opportunity to reconceptualise single homelessness and rough sleeping. He states that “‘homelessness’ does not actually exist as a discrete social problem” (p 50). Single homelessness is best seen as an outcome of processes of social exclusion, particularly “the inability of a section of the socially excluded population to get access to welfare services and social housing” (p 50). He sees the recent policy initiatives around resettlement and inclusion for single homeless people Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 40 Homelessness (for example, the Rough Sleepers Initiative) as a “development of the relationship between the understanding of single homelessness and the concept of ‘social exclusion’” (p 51). This chapter will argue, however, that while recent policy initiatives have indeed brought the issues of rough sleeping and single homelessness back onto the agenda it has been in the context of the promotion of a ‘productivist’rather than a redistributive social policy agenda,emphasising the active rather than the passive citizen, with labour market insertion the key to inclusion (Levitas, 1998). These themes are encapsulated in the 1994 White Paper of the European Union, European social policy – A way forward for the Union: ... it is clear that there needs to be a move away from more passive income maintenance measures towards active labour market measures designed to ensure the economic and social integration of all people. This means giving a top priority to employment,securing new links between employment and social policies by developing a ‘trampoline’ safety net, and recognising that those who are not in the labour market also have a useful role to play in society.... (European Commission, 1994, p 34-5) As Esping-Andersen (1996) argues,“the idea is to redirect social policy from its current bias in favour of passive income maintenance towards active labour market programmes that ‘put people back to work’, help households harmonise work and family obligations, and train the population in the kinds of skills that post-industrial society demands” (p 3). The promotion of the active citizen is now said to be an essential element of the enterprise culture and the entrepreneurial, competitive city. It signifies the emergence of an alternative mode of integration to that maintained and supported through the post-war era of Keynesian welfare capitalism. The dimensions of citizenship, social exclusion and homelessness during this period will now be explored to highlight the contingent and temporally specific nature of citizenship, social rights and integration. Homelessness: a thing of the past A mode of integration in any phase of capitalist development emerges through the relationship between the state, the family, the individual and the institutional framework. Its sustainability depends on its resonance 41 with broader public and ontological narratives, that is, narratives which are attached to cultural and institutional formations larger than the single individual,and“personal narratives rooted in experience”(Sommers,1994, p 619). The narratives encapsulated within the institutions of the postwar welfare state provide an insight into the nature of the webs of relationality within a mode of inclusion and their cultural and temporal specificity. The economic and political context was the promotion of Keynesian welfare capitalism organised around mass production and mass consumption of capital goods, within a largely national context. The welfare consensus emphasised an explicit commitment to state intervention through universal access to direct public provision of welfare benefits. It accepted an extended role for the state in economic and social policy and implicitly guaranteed social rights of citizenship for the whole population as a right. The discourse was that the state would ensure all citizens enjoyed a certain minimum standard of life and economic security as a matter of right. The mass consuming, mass producing, wage-earning society of the Fordist era was supported by a mode of integration encompassing a commitment to Keynesian capitalism,universal citizenship and collectively minimised individual risk, in that the state was seen as the primary guarantor against the vagaries and uncertainties of everyday life. Radical class struggle faded from political discourse and, according to Bowles and Gintis,“the language of liberal democracy, the lexicon of rights,was ...installed as the nearly universal means of political discourse” (Bowles and Gintis,1982,p 64). The boundaries of social rights,however, were constructed within a specific narrative and that narrative reflected the privileged status of the white, male working class and the “partial citizenship”of women and black men (Kennett,1998). While the Fordist welfare state linked the interests of capital and labour in a programme of full employment and social welfare it also involved the interplay of forms of social power other than class, such as racism and patriarchy (Williams, 1994). Thus the welfare settlement of the post-war period was a product of the “interrelation between capitalism, patriarchy and imperialism” (Williams, 1994, p 61). In Britain the ethos of egalitarianism prevailed and the trends were towards decreasing social inequality and the gradual inclusion of previously excluded or marginal populations. On the new housing estates the move was to a more fragmented, home-centred culture as rising working-class living standards started to establish themselves. This was a period in which growing middle-class affluence enabled the further development of home-owning suburbia, while the ‘estate’ provided mass housing for Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 42 Homelessness the‘respectable’working class. The Fordist regime could be characterised in terms of housing as a social right, universalism of subsidies and tax breaks and as an era of mass suburbanisation and direct state housing provision (Florida and Feldman, 1988). Personal disposable incomes rose,the rate of inflation was modest,the scale of unemployment was low and the majority of the population were well-housed. However, for the poor to be incorporated into the home ideal they had to meet certain criteria relating to personal decency and the acceptance of established behavioural norms. Issues relating to class, race, gender and sexuality were major considerations in how home was defined and who was able to gain access. Women and people from ethnic minorities were unlikely to have equal access to the capital through which the suburban home ideal could be achieved, and were likely to be denied access to local authority waiting lists (Rex and Moore, 1967; Castles and Kosack, 1973; Rex and Tomlinson, 1979; Henderson and Karn, 1987; Smith, 1989). Nevertheless, the provision of state housing served to justify the institutions of the Keynesian welfare state and support the hegemony of the post-war settlement at the micro level. In Britain in 1960 7.5 million people were living in poverty (Coates and Silburn, 1970) and there were 2,558 households (10,270 by 1976) in temporary accommodation (Burke, 1981). Yet for the majority of individuals the ideological commitment to equality and welfarism was compatible with the ‘lived’ experience at the micro level. As Byrne points out: ... in the Fordist era, good council housing was the locale in space of an employed working class and movement into it from poor council housing and out of it to the cheaper end of the owner-occupied system was simply an incremental matter. (Byrne, 1997, p 33) The prevailing ideology was one in which income and housing need had been met and poverty and homelessness involved a small number of people on the margins of society. The homeless population, under the 1948 National Assistance Act, was to be the object of welfare services rather than housing departments. This served to construct and maintain the undeserving status of the homeless and reinforce the individual, pathological model of homelessness. The way in which the homelessness problem was constructed, “which stressed the deviant characteristics of homeless individuals rather than issues such as housing shortage” (Neale, 1997, p 37), contributed to a policy agenda which served to render the 43 homeless population ‘invisible’ and perpetuate the logic of the public narrative that this was an era in which poverty and homelessness were a thing of the past. Redrawing the boundaries of citizenship: risk, insecurity and the active citizen The last 25 years have been a period of substantial flux and change during which the landscape of capitalism has been reshaped: economic, political, social and cultural activities are said to have created a new set of conditions from the past. According to Jessop selective narratives of past events generate distinctive accounts of current economic, social and political problems, from which emerge “a limited but widely accepted set of diagnoses and prescriptions for the economic and political difficulties now confronting nations,regions,and cities and their populations”(Jessop, 1996,p 3). The redrawing of the boundaries of citizenship can be seen in this context. Allen argues that “discourses of citizenship are shaped not only by the material and political realities which they (selectively) reflect, but also by the way they seek to provide justificatory explanations for, and principles to guide, the social activities which organise that reality” (1998). As economic conditions deteriorated during the mid-1970s, the postwar consensus began to crumble. The institutional arrangements of the post-war period which had supported specific configurations of citizenship were increasingly perceived as barriers and impediments to the deploying of new methods of production and consumption. In Britain, the erosion of the post-war consensus occurred in the context of rampant inflation in the wake of the oil crisis, and involved the acceptance by the 1976 Labour government of the International Monetary Fund’s prescription of income restraint, cuts in social expenditure and, ultimately, the abandonment of Keynesian policy. By the 1980s a major structural reform of the welfare state was underway linked to an alternative economic doctrine, philosophical tradition and an anti-collectivist orthodoxy. Economic individualism and supply-side economics, as advocated by Hayek and Friedman,provided the framework for the policy formulations of monetarism, and the rhetoric for the devaluation of the welfare state portraying it as a barrier to economic recovery and the road to ‘serfdom’ and economic ruin. Writers such as Nozick (1974) influenced the notions of the minimal state and the atomistic individualism. The critique and devaluation of state intervention incorporated all three elements as Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 44 Homelessness governments sought to reintroduce market processes into the welfare state and public sector. Connotations of a bloated, self-interested and inefficient bureaucracy were introduced and supported by‘public choice’ theorists (Niskanen,1971,1973) with recommendations for the reduction in the size and power of government agencies and the introduction of competition and market forces into welfare provision. By the end of the 1980s there was an explicit policy emphasis on market-based approaches to the delivery of services, the role of local authorities became more focused on that of enabler rather than provider, and the ‘desirability’ and increased role for voluntary and private agencies in social policy was enhanced. As Dean argues,“the burden of welfare provision was shifted from the state to the informal, voluntary and commercial sectors and the character of welfare transactions became, if not literally private, more akin to contractual relations in the marketplace” (Dean, 1999, p 218). These developments were accompanied by the erosion of the relative predictability and certainty of the mass producing,mass consuming Fordist era of welfare capitalism, and a change in the balance of class relations reflecting the changing relative status of different groups and their relationship with the state.The Fordist industrial order of stability in which the life cycle of the “working-class [male] masses was predictable and, mobility wise, generally flat” (Esping-Andersen, 1993, p 227) has come to an end. The decline of Fordism has been accompanied by the rise in both professional and lower-end service occupations, changes in class composition and a recrystallisation of class forces, resulting in a declining overall standard of living for large sections of the population and a reduction in the number and quality of employment opportunities. As discussed in the last chapter, the stable, predictable patterns of the conventional Fordist life cycle, underpinned by the institutions of the welfare state, have given way to greater variety and less predictability. Thus,in contrast to the postwar period, there seems to be increasing insecurity not only in the labour market but in many aspects of day-to-day life. Changes in the structure of employment combined with the reorientation of the welfare state are said to have created an arena of risk,insecurity and uncertainty for the majority of the population,not just the poor (Forrest and Kennett,1997),in contrast to the previous mode of inclusion. According to Beck (1992) insecurity has emerged in the context of the increasing individualisation and autonomisation of contemporary society,and Giddens (1991,1992,1994) argues that in this era of reflexive modernity “the concept of risk becomes fundamental to the way both lay actors and technical specialists organise the social world” (Giddens, 45 1991, p 3). Within this risk culture individuals are constantly required to assess their risk status and make decisions regarding potential risk“through contact with expert knowledge ...”(Giddens,1991,p 5). Life-style choice, life-planning and the reflexivity of the self are central to the construction of an individual’s identity in this risk environment and,in turn,are linked to the notion of ontological (or emotional) security (Giddens, 1991). Increasingly,the social relations of everyday life have come to be associated with complexity and uncertainty, independence and individualism. The ‘collective management’ of uncertainty during the post-war period has given way to what Marris refers to as “the competitive management of uncertainty” (Marris, 1996, p 14) where strategies for containing uncertainty and risks must be developed individually. Thus, there has been a transfer of risk from the state and the employer to the family and the individual and a redrawing of the boundaries of citizenship (Kennett, 1998). This reorientation is an indication that the nature and significance of the social relations of welfare change over time as does the relationship between the individual and the state. This relationship is encapsulated in the institutions and ideology of the welfare state through which the inclusionary/exclusionary boundaries of citizenship are articulated and perpetuated. This restructuring of relations between state and civil society and the establishment of new forms of intervention were most evident during the Conservative era in Britain when there was the most profound shift towards‘welfare pluralism’(Dean,1999). However,following their election in May 1997,the Blair government has pursued similar strategies indicating according to Marquand (1998) that New Labour “has turned its back on Keynes and Beveridge” (quoted in Dean, 1999, p 221). According to Dean (1999) “New Labour has combined the economic liberalism of the Thatcher/Reagan orthodoxy, with something approaching socially conservative Christian democracy” (p 221). Key policies of New Labour have been Welfare-to-Work and the New Deal. Initially introduced to overcome the problem of unemployment among young people the scope of the New Deal has been extended to include, for example, lone parents and those over 25. According to King and Wickham-Jones: The policy recast in fundamental fashion Labour’s strategy to tackle poverty: previously, Labour administrations and social democrative thinkers had placed much weight on amelioration of general destitution through State-directed public spending programmes. New Labour, by contrast, emphasised paid work, Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 46 Homelessness seemingly to the exclusion of other approaches. (King and Wickham-Jones, 1999, p 271) They go on to point out that in contrast to the commitment to universal and unconditional social rights which was central to Marshall’s conception of citizenship and to the Labour Party’s welfare agenda between 1945 and 1992, conditionality, compulsion and coercion appear to be the hallmarks of the policies of the Blair administration. Sanctions and penalties, such as loss of benefit, will fall on those who either refuse to participate or who are unable to finish the New Deal programmes. The implications of this move towards conditional citizenship are as yet unclear. King andWickham-Jones (1999) point out the uncertainty in calculating the numbers denied benefit because ofWelfare-to-Work. The most recent figure they cite is that of “1,352 individuals who had lost benefit because of their failure to participate” (p 279). Dean (1999) argues that in the context of conditional citizenship one outcome might be that “more citizens will defect from their contract with the State, in the sense that they will ‘disappear’ into the shadowy world of the informal economy. If welfare reform does not work with the grain of everyday survival strategies the result may be more not less social exclusion” (p 232). And similarly, the emphasis on labour market insertion as the means to social inclusion fails to take account of the nature and content of employment and the fact that low pay and casualisation characterise large sectors of the labour market today. Drawing on the work of Jessop (1994) Dean argues that “the space between the individual and the State is itself ‘hollowed out’ as it is subordinated to economic forces and made increasingly conditional on the citizen’s individual ‘stake’ in the economy as a paid worker” (p 225). While recognising the importance of the political and cultural dimensions to inclusion and exclusion Madanipour argues that: ... the main form of inclusion is access to resources, which is normally secured through employment.... Marginalization and long-term exclusion from the labour market lead to an absence of opportunity for production and consumption, which can in turn lead to acute forms of social exclusion. (Madanipour,1998, p 77) However,participation in the labour market does not necessarily guarantee inclusion, particularly because of inadequate access to resources and the 47 nature of employment available. For example, a recent study on the distribution of poor households within the countries of the European Union indicated that 35% of poor households were classified as working poor (EAPN, 1997). As Levitas (1998) argues, labour market insertion as the key to inclusion serves only to obscure the differential access to resources which exists within the working population not just between those within the labour market and those outside. This approach obscures the complex interplay of processes which structure opportunities particularly in relation to gender and ethnicity (issues discussed further in Chapters Five and Six of this volume) and which enable people to access and maintain a reasonable standard of life. Evidence suggests that the restructuring of capitalism combined with a renegotiation of the context of citizenship rights has been accompanied by a shift towards increasing inequality,social exclusion and homelessness,particularly among young people, women and people from ethnic minorities who are increasingly likely to enter into the sphere of the state and be reliant on more basic and coercive forms of social assistance. Homelessness and the entrepreneurial city Homelessness is not a new or transient phenomenon, but recently has emerged as a problem affecting different kinds of areas from inner cities to rural areas, and has involved a widening spectrum of the population. A recent Survey of English Housing (1995/96) reported on people’s experiences of homelessness. Six per cent of respondents reported that they had some experience of homelessness in the last 10 years. Of those aged 16-24 20% said that they had been homeless during the same time period and among lone parents with dependent children the figure was 29% (Green et al, 1997). Although the number of statutory homeless has continued to drop from its peak of 178,867 households in 1991, in 1996 it still represented 131,139 households in Great Britain, higher than any year before 1989 (Wilcox, 1997). Nor is homelessness among single women the ‘hidden’ homelessness of the past. More women can be seen sleeping rough and, particularly among younger women, there is likely to be greater use made of night shelters, with a rise of 70% in 1995 of women under 21 years old using winter shelters. Hopper (1991) recognises novel elements of the phenomenon in terms of the scale, the heterogeneity of the homeless population in terms of gender, race and age, and the episodic nature of homelessness. While for Marcuse contemporary homelessness is distinguishable as: Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 48 Homelessness ... large-scale, permanent and independent of the short-term business cycle,a combination never before existing in an advanced industrial society. It represents the inability of the market and the unwillingness of the state to care for the most basic needs of a significant segment of the population ... and their consequent complete exclusion from or suppression in the spatial fabric of a technologically and economically advanced city. It may thus fairly be called ‘advanced homelessness’. (Marcuse, 1993, p 359) As alternative narratives have converged and combined in the contemporary city, so “economic, political and cultural spaces have been opened up, resulting in a restructuring of relations of inclusion and exclusion, of centrality and marginality” (Mommas, 1996, p 196). For Jessop the “intersection of these diverse economic, political and sociocultural narratives” (Jessop, 1996, p 4) has crystallised in the context of the‘entrepreneurial’city where the processes through which homelessness occurs and the policy context in which it is maintained are most stark. The rhetoric of competitiveness,partnership and cohesion has dominated the discourse at both national and European Union levels. According to Oatley (1998) urban policy in Britain“has shifted from a welfare approach dominated by social expenditure to support deprived groups in depressed areas (1969–1979) to entrepreneurialism aimed at generating wealth and stimulating economic development” (p 203). Oatley lists a range of initiatives introduced during the 1990s, from City Challenge in 1991 to the Single Regeneration Budget which has become the central plank in the government’s regeneration policy,which he claims marked“a paradigm shift”. According to Oatley “These initiatives radically altered the way in which policies aimed at tackling problems or urban decline and social disadvantage were formulated,funded and administered”(1998,p x). While there is nothing new about characterising the city as the site of entrepreneurialism, what has been radically altered is the intensification of competition between urban regions for resources, jobs and capital and the policy agenda which has accompanied this intensification. With the growing importance of international competition in the global marketplace, which had played a fairly minor role in the Fordist 1950s and 1960s,major cities act as centres of economic,social,cultural and structural change as the arena is created in which cities promote innovation and entrepreneurialism in order to secure competitive advantage. The ‘managerialism’ of the 1960s has given way to what Harvey (1989) refers to as ‘entrepreneurial’ urban governance, thus facilitating the 49 transformation from the rigidity of Fordist production systems supported by Keynesian state welfarism,to a more geographically diverse and flexible form of accumulation. For Harvey, the basis of this new urban entrepreneurialism: ...rests ...on a public private partnership focussing on investment and economic development with the speculative construction of place rather than the amelioration of conditions within a particular territory as its immediate (though by no means exclusive) political and economic goal. (Harvey, 1989, p 16) In both social and urban policy the emphasis is on reducing public services and stressing the role of agencies alternative to local government, and the need for a mix of private, not-for-profit and voluntary inputs. As larger cities endeavour to become transnationally important financial and control centres, urban initiatives concentrate on establishing special corporations for economic promotion in close cooperation with the private sector, thus incorporating elements of deregulation, privatisation and public– private partnership (Fainstein,1991;Krätke and Schmoll,1991). So while in the 1960s urban problems of poverty and inner-city decay were met by welfare initiatives and redevelopment, more recently the emphasis has been on growth based on market-oriented solutions and‘wealth creation,’ with the consequences that: ... the inner city ... becomes a microcosm for growth strategies based on financial services and property development, on deregulation and on polarised labour markets characterised by divergent skills and growing social inequality. (Hill, 1994, p 166) The affluent consumer and powerful corporations have become the object of urban policy and have, according to Harvey (1989), been subsidised at the expense of local collective consumption for the working class and the poor. The‘public interest’has become subsumed under private interests (Marcuse, 1993), increasing social division as well as reinforcing spatial divisions of consumption. The refurbishment of urban space and emphasis on cultural renewal facilitates gentrification processes and the promotion of consumption palaces, festivals and other leisure and cultural facilities as civic boosterism and place identity have become the“favoured remedies for ailing urban economies” (Harvey, 1989, p 28). As Griffiths (1998) argues “Entrepreneurialism is founded on speculation and risk-taking; Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 50 Homelessness competition by its very nature, throws up winners and losers” (p 43). For the displaced and the poor the ‘image of affluence’ is likely to offer, at best,the opportunity of low paid, insecure employment and, at worst, the prospect of locating a pitch from which to panhandle for a few hours (seeWinchester andWhite, 1988) before returning to the excluded space of the “multiply divided city” (Marcuse, 1993). Zero tolerance and coercion have become the response to destitution and poverty. Prestigious office locations install deterrents such as sprinkler systems to prevent the homeless from sleeping in their doorways, at the same time as major companies enter into a range of partnerships with voluntary organisations in the spirit of“new philanthropy”(Housing,1991) for the young homeless. Carlen argues that“at the end of the twentieth century in England the management of homelessness is not merely about housing scarcity but has also become a site of struggle over social change” (Carlen, 1996, p 10). Agencies seeking to work with the homeless have themselves become embedded in the entrepreneurialism of the city. With the emphasis on civic boosterism,according to Ruddick (1996),through their involvement with local growth coalitions in the spirit of public–private partnerships, service providers have, to some extent, become the intermediary in the production of a new social urban space in that they “manage the tensions between the visible impoverishment and global cities” (Ruddick, 1996, p 185). Hopper (1991), Marcuse (1993) and Carlen (1996) have all pointed to the changing role of government and the nature of the homelessness industry who construct and manage the problem within the narratives of the entrepreneurial city. For Carlen “agency-maintained homelessness” occurs through: ...the bureaucratic or professional procedures for the governance of homelessness which deter people from defining themselves as homeless; deny that homelessness claims are justifiable under the legislation; or discipline the officially-defined homeless into rapidly withdrawing their claims to homeless status. (Carlen, 1996, p 59) As well as the practices engaged in by local authorities, she highlights the “quality assurance” and “exclusionary categorisation and referral procedures”(p 59) utilised by hostel staff in the selection and management of hostel populations. Hopper (1991) argues that agencies providing services are in fact powerful interest groups in themselves and they 51 manipulate definitions of the problem and change their policies in ways that are most consistent with their continued existence. In Britain, as the providing state has become the enabling state, so attempts have been made to introduce market-based approaches to the delivery of local services. Thus local authorities have developed a strategic role to facilitate services and provision for the homeless through housing associations and non-profit organisations by distributing funds for which organisations have to compete. As service providers“they are the intermediaries through which flow the resources of relief to the homeless, and the people who outline how we should respond to this social phenomena” (Robertson, 1991,p 142). The‘professional’providers,through the bureaucratic process of fund-getting, supply information that appeals to the funding source, encouraging the development of specialised programmes which catalogue the homeless according to a range of individual vulnerabilities. The ‘homeless problem’thus becomes defined not in terms of structural causes, but as merely an aggregate of social ‘characteristics’ symptomatic of underlying causes. The homeless population is thus reclassified as provision fragments and funding focuses on the pathological and individual characteristics of the homeless (that is, alcoholic, mentally ill) to which specialised professional skills are matched to specialised populations. It is the perceived need which becomes the social problem to which specialised caretakers can respond. Not only do these developments influence the labelling and stigma attached to being homeless, but also affect how the homeless person perceives themselves. In order to negotiate the burgeoning networks of agencies the homeless person must (re)classify her/himself into an appropriate category of perceived need. These processes are particularly apparent in one major government initiative to combat homelessness which has been the Rough Sleepers Initiative (RSI). First initiated in London it is credited with reducing the numbers of central London rough sleepers from 1,000-2,000 in 1990 to around 270 in May 1995. (DoE, 1995). This was accompanied by the Department of Health’s Homeless Mentally Ill Initiative (HMII). The government committed £96m for the first phase of the RSI (1990-93) to organise direct access accommodation, advice, outreach work and some permanent housing association lettings. However,the 1995 Consultation Paper reported that: ...people continue to sleep out at several main sites,for example, the Strand and the Bullring at Waterloo. Their evident plight is distressing not only for them but also for those who live, work Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 52 Homelessness and visit the centre of the capital, and it is frustrating for those who seek to promote London as a world-class centre for business and tourism. (DoE, 1995, p 4) The initiative was extended for a further period and a greater emphasis was placed on“those sleeping rough or with a clear history of sleeping rough” (DoE, 1995, p 7; emphasis original). By March 1996 £182m had been spent on the initiative. In 1995 the RSI model was extended outside London and local authorities were required to “quantify the extent of rough sleeping in their area,and if it existed,to examine its causes”(DoE,1996,p 21). Only Bristol was able to ‘prove’ and document to the satisfaction of the DoE that rough sleeping was a significant problem and they were awarded £7.5m in 1996. More recently the RSI has been extended to Brighton, following their successful bid for capital and revenue funding. It could be argued that the distribution of funds has been based on a local authority’s expertise in formulating a bid rather than real need. In addition, this major focus on RSI has contributed to the perception of homelessness as rooflessness and funding has not been directed towards those people living in insecure and inappropriate condition. The emphasis on‘rough sleepers’ has been perpetuated by the Social Exclusion Unit, and the Unit has set itself the target of reducing rough sleepers by two thirds by 2002 (Social Exclusion Unit, 1998). However, according to the Homeless Network: ...it is our contention that without either a continuing supply of new accommodation, or a significant reduction in the flow of newly homeless people into London, we are likely to see the numbers of street homeless people increase sharply over the next 18 months. (quoted in Social Exclusion Unit, 1998, p 12) A recent report has indicated that while for many homeless people (636 or 13%) the resettlement process had had ‘positive outcomes’ in that the individuals involved were in non-RSI housing (Dane, 1998), for others (787 or 16%) the tenancy was considered to have been unsuccessful with the vast majority ending in abandonment. As one ex-tenant states“When I left I’d just had enough. It was just a big relief to walk out that door”. For another: “... it was like living a shell hermit-like existence. I was lonely, didn’t have the money to travel into the East End I knew,couldn’t 53 live on my benefits. My referral agency stopped visiting me after six months and my housing association wasn’t interested. I knew after six weeks that there was no future in that place for me”. (quoted in Dane, 1998, p 15) Clearly, there could be a number of explanations for these developments. They could be seen as the result of ineffective allocation, management and monitoring strategies adopted by the agencies involved. They could be seen as an example of the contradictions between the images and aspirations of the homeless themselves, and the political and policy narratives instituted by governments, for example, the assertion that “a place in a hostel has to be the start of a process that leads back to the things most of us take for granted” (Social Exclusion Unit, 1998, p 2). They could also be seen as an example of a policy agenda in which the diverse needs, expectations and aspirations of homeless people are subordinated to or subsumed within a strategy of stimulating wealth creation and enhancing competition. Conclusion In the context of growing inequality and insecurity, labour market participation has become the panacea for an inclusive society. While the rhetoric of social exclusion has permeated the policy discourse it is not the comprehensive and dynamic approach offered by Berghman (1995), which looks beyond the experiences of work and income which has been adopted. It is a more narrowly applied definition which is encapsulated in the emerging model of citizenship and welfare. There has been a changing balance between rights and responsibilities and between the state and civil society. Work appears to be replacing welfare while social rights focus on contractual relations and coercion. The policy responses to increasingly visible destitution and homelessness in British cities are an indication of the changes mentioned above. The Social Exclusion Unit has shown little concern with tackling the multifarious processes through which people find themselves homeless. Instead, as cities seek to compete in the international arena, the image of people sleeping in the streets contradicts and undermines the strategies of competitiveness, partnership and cohesion. Thus, it is those sleeping rough who have become the object of a narrowly defined set of policy solutions aimed mainly at restoring legitimacy in the entrepreneurial city. The definition of inclusion perpetuated by the government combined Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 54 Homelessness with the reformulation of welfare and citizenship rights will do little to stem the flow of homeless people, nor to support and maintain those attempting to reconstruct a life off the street. This unidimensional construction of social rights and emphasis on entrepreneuralism and competitiveness may benefit some. However,it is unlikely to be a context for developing a policy and institutional framework through which homeless people can achieve forms of social inclusion which are both appropriate and sustainable. As Power et al (1999) argue, factors perpetuating the homeless life-style might begin with lack of accommodation but there are other interrelated and complex factors, such as marginalisation, insecurity, identification, vulnerability, lack of choice, isolation and lack of income/employment. The narrow interpretation of social exclusion evident in current policy does not connect with the multidimensional nature of contemporary homelessness, nor utilise the existing social networks and (limited) resources which exist among the homeless themselves. Within the current mode of integration there is little likelihood of addressing the homelessness issue and it would appear that at the end of the 20th century the most extreme manifestations of social exclusion – homelessness – will continue to be a feature of British cities. References Abrahamson,P.(1997)‘Combating poverty and social exclusion in Europe’, inW. Beck, L. van der Maesen and A.Walker, The social quality of Europe, Bristol:The Policy Press, pp 145-76. Allen, J. (1998) ‘Europe of the neighbourhoods: class, citizenship and welfare regimes’, in A Madanipour, G. Gars and J. Allen (eds) Social exclusion in European cities, London: Jessica King Publishers, pp 25-51. Anderson, I. (1999) ‘Social housing or social exclusion’, in S. Hutson and D.Clapham (eds) Homelessness: Public policies and private troubles,London: Cassell, pp 153-73. Bagguley, P. (1991) ‘Post-Fordism and enterprise culture: flexibility, autonomy and changes in economic organisation’, in R. Keat and N. Abercrombie (eds) Enterprise culture, London: Routledge. Beck, U.(1992) Risk society: Towards a new modernity, London: Sage Publications. 55 Berghman, J. (1995) ‘Social exclusion in Europe: policy context and analytical framework’ in G. Room (ed) Beyond the threshold: The measurement and analysis of social exclusion, Bristol:The Policy Press, pp 10-28. Bowles,A.and Gintis,H.(1982)‘The crisis of liberal democratic capitalism: the case of the United States’, Politics and Society, vol 1, no 1, pp 51-93. Bulmer, M and Rees, A. (eds) (1996) Citizenship today:The contemporary relevance of T.H. Marshall, London: UCL Press. Burke, G. (1981) Housing and social justice, Harlow: Longman Group Ltd. Byrne,D.(1997)‘Social exclusion and capitalism’,Critical Social Policy,vol 17, no 1, pp 27-51. Callinicos,A. (1992) Against postmodernism:A Marxist critique, Cambridge: Polity Press. Carlen, P. (1996) Jigsaw: A political criminology of youth homelessness, Buckingham: Open University Press. Castles, S. and Kosack, G. (1973) Immigrant workers and class structure in Western Europe, London: Harper and Row. Coates, K. and Silburn, R. (1970) Poverty and the forgotten Englishman, Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. Dane,K.(1998) Making it last:Report into tenancy outcomes for rough sleepers, London: Housing Services Agency. Dean, H. (1999) ‘Citizenship’, in M. Powell (ed) New Labour, new welfare state?:The third way in British Social Policy, Bristol:The Policy Press, pp 213-34. DoE (Department of the Environment) (1995)‘Rough Sleepers Initiative: future plans’, Consultation Paper linked to the Housing White Paper, Our future homes, London: DoE. DoE (1996)‘Rough Sleepers Initiative:the next challenge’,Strategy Paper linked to the Consultation Paper‘Rough Sleepers Initiative:future plans’, London: DoE. Esping-Andersen (1993) Changing classes, stratification and mobility in postindustrial societies, London: Sage Publications. Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 56 Homelessness Esping-Andersen, G. (1996) Welfare states in transition: National adaptations in global economies, London: Sage Publications. EAPN (European Anti-Poverty Network) News (1997) No 49, JuneJuly, Brussels. European Commission (1994) European social policy – A way forward for the Union:AWhite Paper, European Communities, Luxembourg: Office for Official Publications available at http://www.eurotext.ulst.ac.uk/policy/ social/general/espwptoc.html #x (1:10:98@ 14:20:06) Fainstein, S. (1991) ‘Promoting economic development’, Urban Planning in the United States and Great PlanningAmerican PlanningAssociation Journal, vol 57, no 1, pp 22-33. Florida, R.L. and Feldman, M.M.A. (1988) ‘Housing in US Fordism’, Policy & Politics, vol 12, no 2, pp 187-209. Forrest, R. and Kennett, P. (1997) ‘Risk, residence and the post-Fordist city’, American Behavioural Scientist, vol 41, no 3, pp 342-59. Forrest, R. and Kennett, P. (1998) ‘Re-reading the city: deregulation and neighbourhood change’, Space and Polity, vol 2, no 1, pp 71-83. Giddens, A. (ed) (1982) Profiles and critiques in social theory, London: Macmillan. Giddens, A. (1991) Modernity and self-identity: Self and society in the late modern age, Cambridge: Polity Press. Giddens,A.(1992) The transformation of intimacy:Sexuality,love and eroticism in modern society, Cambridge: Polity Press. Giddens, A. (1994) Beyond Left and Right: The future of radical politics, Cambridge: Polity Press. Green, H., Keacon, K., Iles, N. and Down, D. (1997) Housing in England 1995/96. A report of the 1995/1996 Survey of English Housing, London: ONS. Griffiths,R.(1998)‘Making sameness:place marketing and the new urban entrepreneurialism’, in N. Oatley (ed) Cities, economic competition and urban policy, London: Paul Chapman Publishing, pp 41-57. 57 Harvey, D. (1989) ‘From managerialism to entrepreneurialism: the transformation in urban governance in late capitalism’, Paper presented to the Vega Symposium, Stockholm, July. Henderson, J. and Karn,V. (1987) Race, class and state housing: Inequality and the allocation of public housing in Britain,Aldershot: Gower. Hill, D.M. (1994) Citizens and cities, Hemel Hempstead: Harvester Wheatsheaf. Hopper, K. (1991) ‘Symptoms, survival and the redefinition of public space: a feasibility study of homeless people at a metropolitan airport’, Urban Anthropology, vol 20, no 2, pp 155-75. Housing (1991) ‘Doing business with the homeless’, May, pp 29-30. Jessop, B. (1994) ‘The transition to post-Fordism and the Schumpeterian workfare state’, in R. Burrows and B. Loader (eds) Towards a post-Fordist welfare state, London: Routledge, pp 13-37. Jessop, B. (1996) ‘The entrepreneurial city: re-imaging localities, redesigning economic governance, or re-structuring capital?’, Paper presented at Urban Change and Conflict Conference,Glasgow, January. Jordan, B. (1996) A theory of poverty and social exclusion, Cambridge: Polity Press. Kennett, P. (1994) ‘Exclusion, post-Fordism and the “new Europe”’, in P. Brown and R.Crompton (eds) The new Europe:Economic restructuring and social exclusion, London: UCL Press, pp 14-32. Kennett, P. (1998) ‘Differentiated citizenship and housing experience in Britain,Germany andAustralia’,inA.Marsh and D.Mullins (eds) Housing and public policy: Citizenship, choice and control, Buckingham: Open University Press, pp 30-56. King, D. and Wickham-Jones, M. (1999) ‘Bridging the Atlantic: the Democratic (Party) origins of Welfare to Work’, in M. Powell (ed) New Labour, new welfare state?:The ‘third way’ in british social policy, Bristol:The Policy Press, pp 257-80. Krätke, S. and Schmoll, F. (1991)‘The local state and social restructuring’, International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, vol 15, no 4, pp 542- 52. Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 58 Homelessness Lee, P. and Murie, A. (1997) Poverty, housing tenure and social exclusion, Bristol:The Policy Press. Levitas, R. (1998) The inclusive society? Social exclusion and New Labour, Basingstoke: Macmillan. Lister, R. (1990) The exclusive society: Citizenship and the poor, London: Child Poverty Action Group. Lister, R. (1998) Citizenship: Feminist perspective, Basingstoke: Macmillan Madanipour,A. (1998) ‘Social exclusion and space’, in A. Madanipur, G. Cars and J.Allen (eds) Social exclusion in European cities, London: Jessica Kingsley Publishers, pp 75-89. Mann,M.(1987)‘Ruling class strategies and citizenship’,Sociology,vol 21, no 3, pp 339-54. Marcuse, P. (1993) ‘What’s so new about divided cities?’, International Journal of Urban and Regional Studies, vol 17, no 3, pp 355-65. Marquand, D. (1998) ‘What lies at the heart of the people’s project’, The Guardian, 20 May. Marris, P. (1996) The politics of uncertainty, London: Routledge. Marsh,A. (1998) ‘Processes of change in housing and public policy’, in A. Marsh and D. Mullins (eds) Housing and public policy: Citizenship, choice and control, Buckingham: Open University Press, pp 1-29. Marshall,T.H. (1950) Citizenship and social class, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Mommas, H. (1996) ‘Modernity, postmodernity and the crisis of social modernization:a case study in urban fragmentation’,International Journal of Urban and Regional Research, vol 20, no 2, pp 196-216. Neale,J.(1997)‘Theorising homelessness:contemporary sociological and feminist perspectives’, in R. Burrows, N. Pleace and D. Quilgars (eds) Homelessness and social policy, London: Routledge, pp 35-49. Niskanen, W.A. (1971) Bureaucracy and representative government, Aldine: Atherton. Niskanen,W.A. (1973) Bureaucracy: Servant or master? Lessons from America, London: Institute of Economic Affairs. 59 Nozick, R. (1974) Anarchy, state and utopia, NewYork, NY: Basic Books. Oatley, N. (ed) (1998) Cities, economic competition and urban policy, London: Paul Chapman Publishing. Pleace, N. (1998) ‘Single homelessness as social exclusion: the unique and the extreme’, Social Policy and Administration, vol 32, no 1, pp 46-59. Power, R., French, R., Connelly, J., George, S., Hawes, D., Hinton, T., Klee, H., Robinson, D., Senior, J., Timms, P. and Warner, D. (1999) Promoting the health of homeless people, London: Health Education Authority. Rex, J. and Moore, R. (1967) Race, community and conflict, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rex, J. andTomlinson, S. (1979) Colonial immigrants in a British city:A class analysis, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Robertson, M.O. (1991) ‘Interpreting homelessness: the influence of professional and non-professional service providers’,UrbanAnthropology, vol 20, no 2, pp 141-53. Rodgers, G., Gore, C. and Figueiredo, J. (1995) Social exclusion: Rhetoric, reality, responses, Geneva: ILO. Room, G. (1991) National policies to combat social exclusion, First Annual Report of the EC Observatory on Policies to Combat Social Exclusion, Brussels: European Commission. Room, G. (ed) (1995) Beyond the threshold:The measurement and analysis of social exclusion, Bristol:The Policy Press. Ruddick,S.(1996) Young and homeless in Hollywood:Mapping social identities, NewYork, NY: Routledge. Saraceno, C. (1997) ‘The importance of the concept of social exclusion’, in W. Beck, L. van der Maesen and A.Walker (eds) The social quality of Europe, Bristol:The Policy Press, pp 177-85. Smith,S.J.(1989) The politics of‘race’and residence,Cambridge:Polity Press. Social Exclusion Unit (1998) Rough sleeping, London: Social Exclusion Unit. Somerville,P.(1998)‘Explanations of social exclusion:where does housing fit in?’, Housing Studies, vol 13, no 6, pp 761-80. Homelessness, citizenship and social exclusion 60 Homelessness Sommers,M.R.(1994)‘The narrative constitution of identity:a relational and network approach’, Theory and Ethics, vol 23, no 5, pp 605-49. Tricard, J.P. (1991) ‘Note de problematique: working papers of the Social Exclusion Observatory, EC Commission’, in D. Robbins (1992) Social exclusion 1990-1992:The United Kingdom EC Observatory on policies to combat social exclusion,European Economic Interest Group,Lille:Animationa and Research, pp 1-6. Turner, B. (ed) (1993) Citizenship and social theory, London: Sage Publications. Twine, F. (1994) Citizenship and social rights, London: Sage Publications. Wilcox,S.(1997) Housing finance review 1997/1998,York:Joseph Rowntree Foundation. Williams,F.(1994)‘Social relations,welfare and the post-Fordism debate’, in B. Loader and R. Burrows (eds) Towards a post-Fordist welfare state?, London: Routledge, pp 49-73. Winchester, H.P.M. and White, P.E. (1988) ‘The location of marginalised groups in the inner city’, Environment and Planning D, Society and Space, vol 6, no 1, pp 37-54. Social exclusion literature review September 08 11 3. The meanings of social exclusion ‘“Exclusion” is not a concept rooted in the social sciences, but an empty box given by the French state to the social sciences in the late 1980s as a subject to study… The empty box has since been filled with a huge number of pages, treatises and pictures, in varying degrees academic, popular, original and valuable’. (Murard, 2002:41) Given its origins and rapid spread across nation states and global regions, it is perhaps inevitable that the phrase ‘social exclusion’ is used in different ways at different times reflecting different institutional, political, historical and geographic contexts. In this section we describe some of the meanings attaching to the concept of social exclusion and consider the relationship between these meanings and policy and actions aimed at addressing social exclusion. 3.1 Constituent elements of the concept of social exclusion Definitions of ‘social exclusion’ variously emphasise: • The groups at risk of being excluded: for example, Lenoir (1974) quoted in Silver (1994:532) wrote: ‘the excluded made up onetenth of the French population: the mentally and the physically handicapped, suicidal people, aged invalids, abused children, drug addicts, delinquents, single parents, multi-problem households, marginal, asocial persons, and other social misfits’ • What people are excluded from: for example, Silver (1994: 541) notes that: ‘the literature says people may be excluded from: a livelihood; secure, permanent employment; earnings; property, credit or land; housing; the minimal or prevailing consumption level; education, skills and cultural capital; the benefits provided by the welfare state; citizenship and equality before the law; participation in the democratic process; public goods; the nation or the dominant race; the family and sociability; humane treatment, respect, personal fulfilment, understanding’ • The problems associated with social exclusion: for example, England’s Social Exclusion Unit (SEU’s) defined social exclusion as: ‘a shorthand for what can happen when people or areas suffer from a combination of linked problems such as unemployment, poor skills, low incomes, poor housing, high crime environments, bad health and family breakdown’(SEU, 1997) • The processes driving exclusion and the levels at which they operate: for example, Estivill (2003:19) argues that: ‘Social exclusion must … be understood as an accumulation of confluent processes with successive ruptures arising from the heart of the economy, politics and society, which gradually distances and places persons, groups, communities and territories in a position of Social exclusion literature review September 08 12 inferiority in relation to centres of power, resources and prevailing values’ • The agents and actors involved: for example, Mike Rann, Prime Minister of South Australia commented that: ‘social exclusion is created by harsh and unjust economic conditions compounded by difficult social environments and made worse by insensitive government policies and government neglect…’ (South Australian Labor Party, 2002). Importantly, the differing emphasis on one or more of these facets of ‘exclusion’ has different implications for policy/action to address exclusion. A selection of definitions of social exclusion is provided in Appendix 1. These definitions are drawn from academic literature, reports from governmental and intergovernmental agencies; and from the ILO country case studies. Whilst not exhaustive they do illustrate both recurring elements and subtle differences in the ways in which social exclusion is defined. Much of the ‘common ground’ apparent across these definitions can be attributed to Graham Room (1992, 1995), who was instrumental in establishing social exclusion as a multidimensional, dynamic and relational concept. These three constituent elements deliver insights into the nature, consequences and implications of unequal power relationships, and point to the important conceptual contribution that ‘social exclusion’ can make to understanding and addressing social and health inequalities. Multidimensional: Room’s conceptual shift from poverty, as primarily concerned with income and expenditure, to social exclusion, which he argues implies multidimensional disadvantage, has since been expanded upon in the literature. Definitions now typically refer variously to different dimensions (social, economic, cultural, political) and different levels (micro e.g. individual, household; meso e.g. neighbourhoods; and macro e.g. nation state and global regions) along which a social exclusion/inclusion continuum is seen to operate. The consensus that social exclusion is a multidimensional phenomenon is present both in the English and the Spanish literature. García Roca (1998) for example, identifies three dimensions to social exclusion: a structural or economic dimension referring to a lack of material resources associated with exclusion from the labour market; a contextual or social dimension, expressed in a lack of integration into family life and the community; and a subjective or personal dimension expressed in an erosion of self worth and increased sense of anomie. Kronauer (1998) argues that the concept of social exclusion derived from France needs to be combined with elements of the concept of the “underclass” as used in the United States of America (USA) and the UK (Murray,1990), to differentiate it from poverty. According to Kronauer, social exclusion arises when a marginal economic position and social isolation combine. In this context he argues social exclusion is a product of people’s relationships with: the labour market, consumption, institutions, social relationships, culture and geographical space. Other relevant arguments have been developed by Social exclusion literature review September 08 13 Gaviria, Laparra and Aguilar (1995), Minujin (1998), Cabrera (2000) and Velásquez (2001), based on Tezanos (1999). Dynamic: This refers to the changing and interactive nature of social exclusion along different dimensions and at different levels over time. Some, including Room (1995) and Barnes (2005), contend that persistence over time is an integral aspect of social exclusion, while others (Levitas et al., 2007) have argued that judgements about the importance of persistence are neither theoretically nor empirically based. Most definitions recognise that the experience of social exclusion is unequally distributed across socio-economic and ethnic groups and that it is not a static state experienced by the same social groups at all times in all places. The experience and consequences of stigmatising conditions such as HIV/AIDS, for example, differ profoundly between South Africa and the USA and between ethnic groups in the USA. Additionally, rapid structural transformations and in particular the impact of globalisation are altering the contours of exclusion and inclusion within and between nation states and global regions. In elaborating on the dynamics of social exclusion Castel (1997) argues that the causal relationship between poverty and disadvantage and wider inequalities must be recognised: the linkage between the experience of those at the margins of society and the fundamental working of societies. To do this, he suggests, ‘exclusion’ should be replaced by ‘disaffiliation’ because “Exclusion is immobile. It designates a state or, rather, privation states […] To speak of disaffiliation, on the other hand, is not to confirm a rupture, but to delay a journey. The concept belongs to the same semantic field as dissociation, disqualification or social invalidation. Disaffiliated, dissociated, invalidated, disqualified, with relationship to what? This is in fact the problem. [...]To look for the relationships between the situation in which one is and that from which one comes, not to autonomise the extreme situations but to link what happens in the peripheries and what arrives to the centre’ (Castel, 1997:16-17). It is apparent that Castel’s argument refers not only to the dynamism of the social exclusion concept but also to its relationality. Relational: This refers to the critical conceptual shift from the focus on distributional outcomes within a poverty discourse (i.e. the lack of resources at the disposal of individuals, households and/or wider social groups) to a focus on social relationships. However, there are two linked but importantly different strands to this argument. One focuses on the idea that social exclusion involves the rupture of relationships between people and the society in which they live. This is vividly described by Room who notes that the concept is referring to: “people who are suffering such a degree of multidimensional disadvantage, of such duration, and reinforced by such material and cultural degradation of the neighbourhoods in which they live that their relational links with the wider society are ruptured to a degree irreversible. This is the core of the concept (..) inadequate social Social exclusion literature review September 08 14 participation, lack of social protection, lack of social integration and lack of power." In his writing on social exclusion and capability deprivation Amartya Sen adopts a related perspective arguing that social exclusion focuses attention on to the disadvantages arising from being excluded from shared opportunities enjoyed by others. Looking back to classical Greece, Sen (2000:4) writes: ‘In this Aristolelian perspective, an impoverished life is one without freedom to undertake important activities that a person has reason to choose’. He draws parallels with the eighteenth century writings of Adam Smith, according to whom: “the (in)ability to appear in public without shame” is an important deprivation in itself. Indeed, for Sen, (2000:8): ‘the real importance of the idea of social exclusion lies in emphasizing the role of relational features in the deprivation of capability and thus in the experience of poverty’. A second interpretation of a relational perspective on social exclusion is that it focuses attention on inequalities as the product of social relationships that are defined historically by normative systems that assign social identities and associated power and status to different individuals, groups, classes, and even States. As in Norbert Elías’ famous study in the 1960s of the English town given the pseudonym ‘Winston Parva’, “the exclusion and the stigmatization of those excluded turned out to be powerful weapons that were used by the old-established residents to keep their identity, to reaffirm their superiority, to maintain the outsiders firmly in their place” (Elías, 1998, [1993]:86). This approach to a relational perspective on exclusion demands a group, rather than an individual, analysis, that recognizes human interdependence as its foundation. In Michael Mann's analysis (1986:2), it is to understand the place that human groups occupy in “social power networks”. The exercise of power (economic, political, ideological or military) by human groups in social networks is unequal and it is from here that hierarchies are derived (Mann, 1986: 4). From this relational perspective, social reality viewed through the lens of social exclusion is the product of an unequal balance of power between social groups, nation states and global regions which contributes to an unequal distribution of goods and services. For these writers, without the two ingredients of redistribution and recognition it is not possible to overcome exclusion (Fraser, 1997:18). For this reason, a relational perspective implies an emancipatory dimension (involving new less hierarchical social systems), a political dimension (involving new political actors) and an institutional dimension (involving new public administrations and materiality of the state) (Fleury, 1998: 13-14). There are other important differences in the way social exclusion is conceptualised. For example, it can be understood as a phenomenon operating in a continuum across society, or as affecting a segment of the population placed outside mainstream society. Similarly, it may be conceptualised as a process - a way of explaining power relationships Social exclusion literature review September 08 15 underlying and producing inequalities - or as a state, a way of describing the most disadvantaged people or social groups, who are assumed to be ‘excluded’ from social systems and relationships. In most definitions this ‘state’ is seen to be associated with (extreme) poverty. There is also a distinction between schools of thought that emphasise lack of participation of individuals in society in general and labour markets in particular and those that identify social exclusion as a lack of access to rights as a citizen and/or member of particular group, community, society or country (Curran et al., 2007). The participation approach underpins much of the European writing on exclusion/inclusion, whereas the rightsbased approach is more strongly associated with the development literature (Gore & Figueiredo, 1997). Curran et al. also suggest that the rights-based approach may be particularly relevant in the context of mental health. However, Curran et al. (2007:295) have suggested that ‘in the face of globalisation and greater international labour mobility, the rights-based and participation approaches become increasingly difficult to separate’ (2007:295). The definition offered by Levitas et al. (2007:25) illustrates how both approaches can be integrated: ‘Social exclusion is a complex and multi-dimensional process. It involves the lack or denial of resources, rights, goods and services, and the inability to participate in the normal relationships and activities, available to the majority of people in a society, whether in economic, social, cultural or political arenas. It affects both the quality of life of individuals and the equity and cohesion of society as a whole’. Burchardt et al.’s (1999) definition emphasises participation: ‘an individual is socially excluded if he or she does not participate in key activities of the society in which he or she lives’. This type of definition implies that social exclusion is relative, applicable to individuals living in a particular society. It leaves open question of who should decide which activities may be regarded as ‘key’. This is not only an empirical question, implying the existence of a measurable inclusion/exclusion threshold according to the degree of participation in a particular activity, but also a normative one, involving the choice of key activities (or dimensions of participation necessary for inclusion) at a specified time and place. The United Nations Development Programme (UNDP) is a strong advocate of a human rights-based approach to address social exclusion. At a recent virtual round table facilitated by the UNDP (UNDP, 2007a), it was argued that translating social exclusion as the UN non discrimination clause enables the concept to be grounded in international law applicable to the majority of states, and allows the necessary relationships between ‘duty bearers’ and ‘claim holders’ to be cultivated. From this perspective, social exclusion is understood to involve discrimination on the basis of social attributes and social identity. Marshall (1964) identified three stages in the development of rights: civil rights, political rights, and social rights. Since the Universal Declaration of Human Rights in 1948, a series of legally binding international treaties have established human rights standards which signatories have obligations to respect, protect and fulfil. Social exclusion literature review September 08 16 Civil rights include the rights to life, liberty and personal security; the right to equality before the law; the right to protection from arbitrary arrest; and the right to religious freedom. Political rights include free speech, expression, assembly and association, and political participation and vote. Economic and social rights include the rights to a family, to education, to health and wellbeing, to social security, to work and fair remuneration, to form trade unions, and to leisure time. Cultural rights include the right to benefits of culture, to the ownership of indigenous lands, rituals and shared practices, and the right to speak one’s language and to ‘mother tongue’ education. Todd Landman (2006), in work commissioned by the UK’s Department for International Development (DFID), argues that social exclusion is a form of rights violation if systematic disproportionality of treatment of people across social, economic and political spheres can be demonstrated. He further argues that human rights deficits can increase people’s vulnerability to exclusion. Another key conceptual issue in the literature on social exclusion is that of agency. This is usually understood as a question of “who is doing the excluding?” (Atkinson, 1998) and is highly contested in the literature with attention having been directed at the causal role of ‘agents’ ranging from globalisation, multi-nationals and international agencies such as the World Bank and IMF, through nation states and their institutions, to excluded individuals/groups themselves. There appears to have been relatively little empirical research on the potential for agency amongst groups most severely affected by exclusionary processes. However, there is a rich literature from civil society and other sources demonstrating that rather than passive victims such groups can actively mould and/or resist exclusionary processes and their social, economic and health consequences. Importantly, this literature also gives more emphasis to the role of public services in addressing social exclusion and to issues of social justice and social solidarity than is apparent in much of the academic literature (Popay et al. 2008). 3.2 Making sense of diverse definitions of social exclusion The discussion so far suggests that whilst it is possible to identify common constituent elements in the meanings attaching to the concept of social exclusion there are also important differences in emphasis and tone. Frameworks developed by Hilary Silver (1994), Ruth Levitas (1998; 2005) and Jo Beall (2002) have made important contributions to understanding the ideological and political roots of these differences and illuminating the implications for policy/action to address social exclusion. Hilary Silver’s paradigms of social exclusion Silver argues that social exclusion is ‘polysemic, i.e. it has multiple meanings and therefore requires extensive semantic definition’ (1994: 536). She identifies three paradigms in which she argues the different meanings and usages of the term social exclusion are embedded. She borrowed Kuhn’s definition of a paradigm as ‘a constellation of beliefs, Social exclusion literature review September 08 17 values, techniques and so on shared by the members of a given community’ (Kuhn, 1970:175). According to Kuhn (1970:7) such paradigms ‘specify not only what sorts of entities the universe does contain but also, by implication, those that it does not’. As Silver notes: ‘Each paradigm attributes exclusion to a different cause and is grounded in a different political philosophy: Republicanism, liberalism and social democracy. Each provides an explanation of multiple forms of social disadvantage – economic, social, political and cultural – and thus encompasses theories of citizenship and racial-ethnic inequality as well as poverty and long-term unemployment’ (Silver 1994: 539). The Solidarity paradigm is embedded in French Republican political ideology, and views exclusion as the breakdown of a social bond between the individual and society that is cultural and moral, rather than economic. It draws on Durkheimian social theory: ‘like deviance or anomie, exclusion both threatens and reinforces social cohesion’ (Silver 1994:542). More recent uses incorporate multicultural notions of how the basis of solidarity is reconfigured. The Specialization paradigm typifies Anglo-American liberal thought about exclusion. It perceives social actors primarily as individuals, who are able to move freely across boundaries of horizontal social differentiation and economic divisions of labour. This paradigm holds that exclusion is a form of discrimination. The roots of exclusion are to be found in unenforced rights and market failures. The specialization paradigm emphasises the individual and micro-sociological causes of economic exclusion; however, social liberals are also cognisant of the effects of structural change. According to Silver (1994:560): ‘The split between supply-side and demand-side theories parallels the division between classical and social liberalism… In contrast to supply-side theoreticians who attribute poverty or unemployment to individual failings, most sociologists now accept that the new poverty and long-term unemployment have demand-side or structural causes’. The Monopoly paradigm, influential on the European Left, sees exclusion as the result of the formation of group monopolies, restricting access of outsiders to resources. ‘Drawing heavily on Weber, and, to a lesser extent, Marx, it views the social order as coercive, imposed through a set of hierarchical power relations. In this social democratic or conflict theory, exclusion arises from the interplay of class, status and political power and serves the political interests of the included… Exclusion is combated through citizenship, and the extension of equal membership and full participation in the community to outsiders’ (Silver 1994: 543). In this paradigm, theories of labour market segmentation epitomise the link between social closure and economic exclusion. Importantly, the focus in Silver’s analysis is on the role of political ideology in generating different understandings of the nature and causes of social exclusion, and by implication different approaches to Social exclusion literature review September 08 18 policy/action to address social exclusion. However, there are limitations to this typology. Each of Silver’s paradigms presents exclusion as based in social relationships between two groups: the included and the excluded. Whilst drawing attention to the ‘actors’ and ‘forces’ driving exclusionary processes this dichotomous approach fails to take account of the social gradients in access to resources and power evident in all societies. The paradigms also fail to account for the differential emphasis placed in different definitions on the potential for agency by people experiencing exclusionary processes. Finally, and importantly from the perspective of this paper, Silver’s paradigms are shaped around advanced Western democracies. Their applicability in the global context remains therefore to be demonstrated, although in later writings, Silver extended the analysis to the Americas (2004, 2005). Ruth Levitas’ discourses of social exclusion Silver is primarily concerned to illuminate the political ideologies underpinning different definitions of social exclusion. Whilst she raises questions about the significance for policy of these differences she does not consider these in detail. In contrast, Ruth Levitas (2005) is primarily concerned to illuminate how ideological underpinnings for concepts of social exclusion change over time and how these are translated into different policies/action. Her focus is the UK and her work is based on an analysis of political discourse over the past two decades or more. As she notes: ‘a discourse constitutes ways of acting in the world, as well as a description of it. It both opens up and closes down possibility for action’ (Levitas: 2005:3). Levitas identifies three different social exclusion discourses in the UK. These are described briefly below. The redistributionist discourse (RED), emphasises poverty as a prime cause of social exclusion. It posits citizenship as the obverse of exclusion: ‘poverty spells exclusion from the full rights of citizenship… and undermines people’s ability to fulfil the private and public obligations of citizenship’ (Lister,1990:68). RED addresses social, political, cultural and economic citizenship, broadening out into a critique of inequality (Levitas, 2005:14). The moral underclass discourse (MUD) emphasises cultural rather than material explanations of poverty, resonating with the work of Charles Murray (1990), whereby the excluded are to blame for their fate. It focuses on the behaviour of the poor and implies welfare benefits are bad as they undermine people’s ability to be self sufficient creating dependency. It is a strongly gendered discourse. (Levitas 2005:21). The social integrationist discourse (SID) sees social inclusion and exclusion primarily in terms of labour market attachment. It obscures inequalities between paid workers, particularly gender inequalities (Levitas,2005:26). Levitas argues that RED, SID and MUD are: Social exclusion literature review September 08 19 ‘… ways of thinking about exclusion that imply different strategies for its abolition. In RED, the assumption is that the resources available in cash or kind to the poor need to be increased both relatively and absolutely, implying both improved levels of income maintenance and better access to public and private services. In SID, the solution is increased labour market participation, for paid work is claimed to deliver inclusion both directly and indirectly through the income it provides. In MUD, the emphasis is on changing behaviour through a mix of sticks and carrots – manipulation of welfare benefits, sanctions for non-compliance and intensive social work with individuals’ (Levitas,2005:x). Her analysis is strongly informed by a socialist feminist perspective. In particular she points to the contradictions inherent in policies that valorise unpaid work (e.g. promote good quality parenting as a mechanism to address anti-social behaviour) whilst at the same time linking income maintenance entitlement to formal employment. Although Levitas’s framework focuses on contemporary Britain and is particularly applicable to states with established welfare systems, it has a broader relevance highlighting key issues concerning the nature of public policy responses to multiple social disadvantages. In the context of the UK, for example, she argues that policies to address social exclusion have moved from a concern with distributional equality to focus on ways of: ‘lifting the poor over the boundary of a minimum standard – or to be more accurate, inducing those who are sufficiently sound in wind and limb to jump over it – while leaving untouched the overall pattern of inequality, especially the rich’ (Levitas, 2005:156). In a similar vein, Veit-Wilson (1998), differentiates between ‘weak and ‘strong’ political discourses of social exclusion in Europe, noting that power relationships are absent from the ‘weak’ version: ‘In the weak version of this discourse, the solutions lie in altering these excluded people’s handicapping characteristics and enhancing their integration into dominant society. Stronger forms of this discourse also emphasise the role of those who are doing the excluding and therefore aim at solutions which reduce the powers of exclusion” (Veit-Wilson, 1998: 45). Jo Beall’s approaches to social exclusion Jo Beall (2002) has identified three approaches to social exclusion which are described below. The neo-liberal approach views social exclusion as ‘an unfortunate but inevitable side effect of global economic realignment’ (Beall, 2002:43). As a consequence of the emergence of free trade and a single global market, Social exclusion literature review September 08 20 workers are now excluded from the benefits of trade barriers and social and employment protection. A second approach argues that ‘social exclusion represents little more than an unhelpful re-labelling of poverty or acts to distract attention from inequality generated by the workings of the economic system’ (Beall, 2002:44) (emphasis added). The third, transformationalist, approach focuses attention on social relations embedded in formal and informal institutions, and ‘signals the use of the social exclusion framework to analyze international processes and institutional relationships associated with rapid social and economic global change and local impacts and responses’ (Beall, 2002:44). Of these three approaches, the neo-liberal and re-labelling of poverty approaches conceptualise social exclusion as a ‘state’ whereas the transformational approach focuses attention on exclusionary processes. This latter approach is concerned with social interactions and power relationships at different levels – from global to local – and recognises the social, political and cultural, as well as the economic, dimensions of power. Social exclusion literature review September 08 21 3. 4 Key points: the meanings of social exclusion The concept of ‘social exclusion’ is contested, and has multiple meanings. These meanings are being continually redefined over time and have different policy implications. The term ‘social exclusion’ has been used to describe: groups at risk of exclusion; what people are excluded from; the states associated with exclusion; the processes involved and levels at which they operate; and the actors involved. There is some consensus that ‘social exclusion’ is: (a) multidimensional, encompassing social, political, cultural and economic dimensions, and operating at different social levels; (b) dynamic, impacting in different ways to differing degrees at different social levels over time; and (c) relational. A relational perspective has two dimensions. On the one hand, it focuses on exclusion as the rupture of relationships between people and the society resulting in a lack of social participation, social protection, social integration and power. Alternatively, a relational perspective points to exclusion as the product of unequal social relationships characterised by differential power i.e. the product of the way societies are organised. Definitions also differ in other fundamental respects. ‘Social exclusion’ has been conceptualised as a continuum across society, or as affecting a segment of the population outside mainstream social systems and relationships. Similarly, social exclusion may be defined as the processes embedded in unequal power relationships that create inequalities or as a state of multiple disadvantage. There is also a distinction between schools of thought that emphasise lack of participation of individuals in society and those that identify social exclusion as a lack of access to citizenship rights for members of particular group, community, society or country. In terms of who or what is driving exclusion, attention has been directed at the causal role of diverse ‘agents’ ranging from globalisation to excluded individuals/groups themselves. Although there has been little research on the agency of groups most affected by exclusionary forces there is ample evidence from other sources that they are rarely passive victims. Silver (1994), Levitas (1998; 2005) and Beall (2002) have made important contributions to our understanding of the ideological and political roots of different definitions and illuminated the implications for policy/action to address ‘social exclusion’. While many definitions of ‘social exclusion’ incorporate apparently contradictory connotations, the labelling approach distinguishing ‘the excluded’ from the rest of society, dominates attempts to operationalise and measure ‘social exclusion’ and policy/action to address it. Social exclusion literature review September 08 22 4. Exclusionary Processes ‘The concept [social exclusion] takes us beyond mere descriptions of deprivation, and focuses attention on social relations and the processes and institutions that underlie and are part and parcel of deprivation’ (de Haan, 2001:26). The previous section explored some of the differences - often implicit underlying definitions and descriptions of ‘social exclusion’. A key theme has been the distinction between social exclusion conceptualised as a ‘state’, a ‘process’, or both. As de Haan notes, conceptualised in relational and process terms, social exclusion can help increase understanding of the causes and consequences of deprivation and inequalities. In this section, we focus on some of these exclusionary processes. As Sen (2000) has noted a distinction can be drawn between active exclusionary processes that are the direct and intended result of policy or discriminatory action including, for example, withholding political, economic and social rights from migrant groups or deliberate discrimination on the basis of gender, caste or age; and passive exclusionary processes, which in contrast, arise indirectly, for example when fiscal or trade policies result in an economic downturn leading to increased unemployment. Whether active or passive, exclusionary processes operate at many levels – in households, villages and cities, nation states and global regions – and encompass, for example: institutionalised and informal racism, discrimination and xenophobia; deeply rooted social structures such as patriarchy; political ideologies such as neo-liberalism and the policies that flow from these; and the workings of global, national and local economies. Climate change is creating new powerful exclusionary processes and these will increase in the future whilst conflict, fuelled by competition over land and resources, by hatred and greed has long been a powerful exclusionary force and continues to be so. In a review of this nature we cannot cover the full range of exclusionary processes nor do justice to their complexity instead we have sought to illustrate the complexity, pervasiveness and scale of the processes involved. We focus on the economic, social, political and cultural domains, in particular: the exclusionary processes accompanying globalisation; the potentially exclusionary impacts of public policy; and the stigmatising and exclusionary impacts of certain cultural and symbolic processes. This section ends with a discussion of the distinctive contribution of the social exclusion relational ‘lens’. 4.1 Economic transformation and globalisation The concept of social exclusion emerged from the 1970s onwards during a period of rapid social and economic transformation at national, regional and global levels. As Silver (1994) and others have highlighted these transformations created what were perceived to be new social problems that challenged the assumptions underpinning Western welfare state provision concerning the operation of labour markets, the potential for full Social exclusion literature review September 08 23 employment, the relationship between paid and unpaid work and the nature of citizenship and entitlement1 . The economic crisis of the 1970s triggered a rise in the power and influence of neo-liberal ideologies and policies including: industrial restructuring, the opening up of labour markets, moves to reduce workers protection and the retreat of state provided welfare. Production was relocated and decentralised often moving to low wage economies, capital investment in new technologies contributed to growing unemployment in the older established industrial heartlands of Western Europe, North America and Australia, differentially affecting already disadvantaged groups and whole geographic areas. These trends were reinforced by the progressive growth of the tertiary sector of the economy from the 1960s, especially of the financial sector. As the financial sector became more global the monetary sovereignty of the nation state was undermined. These dynamics in the financial sector added to the pressure for greater labour flexibility, expressed in higher unemployment, more precarious employment and loss of the old mechanisms of social protection for many workers (Salama, 2006:64-72; Castel, 2004:75-86). The nature and impact of globalisation and employment conditions around the world are considered in detail in the final reports of two other WHO Knowledge Networks (Benach, et al.,2007; Labonte, et al.,2007), including the dramatic impacts of these changes on the distribution of income and wealth and social relationships. Organised labour organisations and informal networks of solidarity have been undermined, individuals, households and entire communities have been put under extreme social and economic pressure, working conditions have deteriorated for millions of people, poverty increased and income inequalities widened. It was in this context that ‘social exclusion’ was seen to provide greater explanatory power than the concept of poverty: not only does it move beyond the economic domain to highlight the multidimensionality of inequalities, but it also illuminates causal processes. Some commentators went further arguing that the concept of social exclusion opened up new ways of investigating and understanding global exclusionary processes. Beall (2002:50) for example, suggests that it provides: ‘a way of understanding the relational and institutional dynamics that serve to include some and keep others out in a connected but polarized global economic context. As such, it is an analytical construct compatible with the study of global economic processes and the poverty and inequality to which they increasingly give rise’. As Castells (1998:162) has noted: ‘globalization proceeds selectively, including and excluding segments of economies and societies in and out of networks of information, wealth and power that characterize the new dominant systems’. And whilst the economic and social impact of these transformational forces may have been felt initially in high income 1 Feminist writers, amongst others had, of course, challenged the assumptions underpinning western welfare states before these macro economic and social changes became prominent. Social exclusion literature review September 08 24 countries, they have been both global and local in their reach. For example, Beall (2002), using examples from the cities of Faisalabad and Johannesburg, highlights the ways in which exclusionary processes associated with globalization graft themselves onto local dynamics of social exclusion. At the same time it is not just segments of societies that are subject to exclusionary processes but whole nations and regions of the world notably for example Sub-Saharan Africa (SSA). Some writers, such as Amartya Sen, caution against a wholesale condemnation of globalisation arguing that it can be both a threat and an opportunity. For example, the positive impact on women’s lives of paid employment in the garment industry in Bangladesh despite poor working conditions is described in the final report of the SEKN (Popay, et. al. 2008). For Sen, it is not globalization and markets per se that are problematic. Indeed, in a sense Sen sees markets as value-free, representing the ‘basic arrangement through which people can interact with each other, and undertake mutually advantageous activities’ (2000: 28). Rather, Sen argues, it is the malfunctioning of markets and the lack of adequate governance of globalizing forces that are the root of the problem. The role of public policy in this regard is considered next. 4.2 Public policy and exclusionary processes For many writers, broadly positioned on the ‘democratic left’, exclusionary processes are not simply an unintended consequence of the economic restructuring that has taken place in the past 40 years: rather they are a necessary condition for it in a situation where, as David Byrne has argued (1999:128) ‘post-industrial capitalism [is] founded around a flexible labour market and … a systematic constraining of the organizational powers of workers as collective actors’. For Byrne, ‘the excluded’ are a reserve army of labour, moving in and out of employment at the bottom end of the labour market, mobilised or demobilised according to fluctuations in the economy. These writers point to the exclusionary processes associated with economic and social policies enacted by many Western states. For example, Navarro and colleagues (Navarro and Shi, 2001; Navarro et al., 2006) have analysed the relationship between political commitment to redistributive policies in high income capitalist countries and levels of income and social and health inequalities, arguing that where this commitment is weakest, in liberal democracies such as the USA, Canada and the UK, income and health inequalities are greatest. Similarly, Townsend (1997) has argued that the principle causes of increased levels of relative poverty in Britain from the 1980s onwards are deregulation; privatisation; unemployment; reduction in public spending; restructured taxes; and the centralising of political control. The dominance of the international financial sector led to economic and political pressure on many low income countries to repay the debt accumulated in the post-war period. Multilateral banks pressed for structural adjustment policies in the 1980s, which became known in the 1990s as “the Washington Consensus”. These ‘adjustments’ included opening up economies to international competition, increasing labour Social exclusion literature review September 08 25 flexibility, restricting public social expenditure and the introduction of new ‘pro-market’ forms of social protection for the poor underpinned by neoliberal theories (Stewart,1998: 38-42; Salama, 1999). These involved a shift away from the public funding and provision of essential services (e.g. healthcare) to a focus on subsidising demand for services from private sector providers (Hernández et al., 2002:323-333) and an increasing reliance on conditional cash and/or service transfers primarily to the poor (Popay et al., 2008; Hernández, 2003:352-358; Rodríguez, 2007). However, many commentators argue that these selective programmes have not had the impacts anticipated by their proponents. Instead, it is argued, they have increased social inequalities creating new forms of ‘social exclusion’. These critics maintain that social protection systems that are conditional upon people's capacity to pay rather than their citizenship status (as in universal systems) will inevitably be exclusionary as well as being expensive to administer and difficult to target effectively (Hernández, 2002; Lauthier, 2005; Le Bonniec, 2005; Rodríguez, 2005; Mkandawire, 2005; Townsend, 2007). An alternative view, from the radical left, is that the link between the right to an income and the obligation to earn or use it in ways consistent with the economic and cultural hegemony of capitalism should be broken (Bowring, 2000, in Davies, 2005:5). Bowring argued that redistributionist scholars, by emphasising participation in work, income and commodity relations, implicitly equate exclusion with normative deviation and inclusion with conformity to social convention. He also argued for the assertion of the existence of new, non-commodified, needs, which cannot be satisfied by capitalism and which prefigure a different kind of society (2000:309). Moreover, for Bowring (2000:314) ‘assuming people are ashamed of poverty is… a scandalous attribution to make’; and many people living on substandard incomes are reluctant to describe themselves as such. ) 4. 3 Discrimination, stigma and human rights The discussion so far has highlighted exclusionary processes embedded in economic, political and social relationships operating within and between nation states. However, as Estivill (2003) has argued, these processes are overlain and reinforced by cultural and symbolic processes which differentiate and stigmatise particular groups, nations and global regions. Estivill (2003:45) describes three stages in the development of these dominant social values and attitudes. Dominant institutions start by applying negative labels and attributes to define and classify those who do not conform to dominant social ‘rules’. The victorious ‘social mindset’ then uses its categorization to legitimize differences in the treatment of others. The third stage is characterised by strong repression and stigmatisation. This description resonates with Durkheim’s (1895) analysis of deviance: ‘Imagine a society of saints, a perfect cloister of exemplary individuals. Crimes (or deviance) properly so called, will there be unknown; but faults that appear venial to the layman will create Social exclusion literature review September 08 26 there the same scandal that the ordinary offence does in ordinary consciousnesses. If, then, this society has the power to judge and punish, it will define these acts as criminal (or deviant) and will treat them as such.’ Public attitudes towards the poor in Britain illustrate the exclusionary potential of these processes. For example, research by Gough and Eisenschitz (2006) suggest that these attitudes are at best indifferent, at worst, hostile, in a context of socio-spatial separation of the poor from the better off. They argued that this hostility is shaped, among others, by popular culture and political ideology propagated by the mass media, competition for jobs and other resources, and fear of poverty. A Fabian Society Report on child poverty (2006) reinforces this picture arguing that there would be little public support for a more progressive tax regime in the UK. However, a more nuanced picture emerges from the Joseph Rowntree Foundation’s 2007 report on public attitudes to income inequality, with a majority of people thinking that the gap between high and low incomes is too great although this does not translate directly or simplistically into support for more redistributive policies. Whilst Durkheim’s theories are deterministic – leaving little space for agency on the part of disadvantaged people – more recent theorists have acknowledged that people are not necessarily passive victims. For example, Estivill (2003:14) argues that in the face of powerful exclusionary processes individuals and/or groups ‘either try to find a way out through their own networks of relations or, if they so decide, they can fight against the circumstances of their exclusion and criticize society for its lack of recognition’. However, as Gough and Eisenschitz (2006:131) point out: ‘In an individualistic society, it is natural to blame social failure on oneself’ (Gough and Eisenschitz, 2006:131). They suggest that prevailing negative attitudes can increase the sense of powerlessness felt by people living in poverty and undermine their capacity for collective action. In addition to the lack of realistic opportunities for advancement, the ability of disadvantaged groups to improve their circumstances is further compromised by the social specificity of what Bourdieu (1986) has called ‘cultural capital’: a composite of social behaviours, accent, physical demeanour, cultural tastes and attitudes acquired in childhood. While higher-class cultural capital is regarded as universal, lower-class capital has limited socio-spatial recognition. Gough and Eisenschitz (2006: 111) contend that despite the mass media, the class gap in cultural capital in the UK is probably not narrowing, and that everyday behaviours still stigmatise and exclude the poor. Negative social values and attitudes towards the poor and poverty in high income countries also create downward pressure on the level of aid monies going to low income countries. For example, a household survey of public attitudes towards poverty in developing countries commissioned in 2006 by DFID in the UK echoed, at a global level, negative and paternalistic perceptions of recipients of aid (Lader, 2007). On the positive side, over four fifths of respondents were concerned about poverty in developing countries, and 53% thought the UK government’s commitment to poverty reduction in developing countries was too little. However, two Social exclusion literature review September 08 27 fifths of respondents agreed with the statement: ‘some people have said that most aid to developing (poor) countries is wasted’, generally blaming developing countries themselves for wasting aid, through corruption (76%) and inefficiency (46%). The most popular policy to help countries with corrupt governments was putting strict conditions on how the money was spent. The impact of cultural and symbolic exclusionary processes is not confined to attitudes towards the poor. Operating through formal legalised and institutionalised systems as well as informally, these processes devalue and undermine the cultures and voices of indigenous peoples around the globe. They are contributing to the displacement of millions, rendering many stateless and condemning them to live in extreme poverty and constant fear with limited if any rights (Popay et al., 2008). Economic, cultural and symbolic exclusionary processes are together fuelling an unprecedented growth in the numbers of people without citizenship. These include refugees in countries with no asylum legislation; the displaced; failures in the birth registration system; and illegal immigrants. ‘Noncitizens’ implicitly do not exist in the eyes of social institutions and are not in a position to make claims to human rights, social protection or public services. The Office of the United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees (UNHCR) reported that at the end of 2005, the number of people with ‘official’ refugee status or protected or assisted by the UNHCR because they were at risk stood at 21 million. A year later this had increased by 56% to 32.9 million (UNHCR, 2007). The International Labour Organisation (ILO) has made a major contribution to understanding the nature of exclusionary processes in both developed and less economically developed countries (LEDCs) drawing particular attention to the significance of fundamental civil and political rights (Figueiredo and Gore, 1997). In many countries of the South, particularly those still struggling to free themselves from the negative legacies of their colonial past, political exclusion remains a powerful constraint on people’s participation in formal institutions. Importantly, the contours of political exclusion are frequently mapped onto and reinforce patterns of cultural discrimination and stigmatisation. 4. 4 Social exclusion and other relational concepts Social exclusion is one of a number of relational ‘lens’ used by social scientists to make sense of patterns of social differentiation and inequalities. Notable others include gender, social class, religion, caste and ethnicity and all are complex and contested. Arguably, at the very least there are important overlaps between the social realities these concepts seek to describe; the particular contribution of social exclusion may be to focus attention on to the interaction and impact of multiple exclusionary processes. Participants at a recent Round Table on social exclusion (UNDP, 2007a), mostly drawn from the UNDP and other UN agencies, highlighted the unequal power relationships underlying poverty, and the experiences of Social exclusion literature review September 08 28 exclusion of non-citizens, migrant workers and indigenous groups (for example the Janajati in Nepal and the Roma in Eastern Europe) and of stigmatised groups (for example the Dalits in India and Burakumin in Japan). They acknowledged that the concept of ‘social inclusion’ may be double-edged for ethnic, religious or linguistic minorities and indigenous peoples, with the potential for states to adopt policies of forcible displacement or assimilation that eradicate cultural differences. Minority groups often seek recognition of equal rights, including recognition of diversity2 . Women and children were identified as being particularly vulnerable to exclusion, due to their weak economic and political power and lack of status in their communities, violence against women, increased HIV/AIDS vulnerability, and their exposure to ritual exclusion (eg women who refuse genital mutilation or rites of widowhood in the Cameroun). The UNDP round table participants identified failure on the part of states to address exclusion based on caste, ethnicity, gender and geography as one of the causes of conflict. Examples of groups resisting discrimination by violent action include the Maoist people in Nepal, conflict in Sudan, and action by militant youths in the Niger delta, where the poorest and most excluded indigenous groups have had no share in the benefits of natural resources exploited by oil companies and the state (Mathieson et al. 2008). An estimated three-quarters of the world’s conflicts have an ethnic or religious dimension, most often linked to exclusion from economic or political opportunities and/or suppression of cultural identity. The insistence by some commentators to distinguish between causal processes underpinning different axes of social differentiation is linked in part to the earlier discussion of the diverse meanings attaching to social exclusion. Beall (2002), for example, adopting a definition reflecting the European orgins of the concept, argues that experiences under apartheid in South Africa are best understood as racial oppression, exploitation and denial of citizenship rights rather than social exclusion. In contrast, she suggests, social exclusion is primarily speaking to class based divisions driven by economic processes and labour market dynamics and hence is more relevant to understanding the genesis of inequalities in postapartheid urban South Africa where: ‘… new forms of capitalist production and changes in employment in Johannesburg, associated with the rise in importance of the service sector, have begun to erode the entrenched correspondence between racial and class divisions that characterized racial economic development and employment patterns during much of the apartheid era. The new socially excluded residents of Johannesburg are not only those who are black but also white who 2 Following many years of lobbying by indigenous and non-indigenous people, on 13 September 2007, the United Nations General Assembly adopted a declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples, which although non-binding, sets out the individual and collective rights of indigenous peoples and prohibits discrimination. Social exclusion literature review September 08 29 are superfluous to the requirements of the global economy and Johannesburg’s place in it’ (2002:49). Concerns about the relationship between different dimensions of social differentiation and inequality and the relative salience of different causal processes are important. The concept of social exclusion has considerable analytical potential to enhance understanding and inform policy/action. It focuses attention simultaneously on the complex causal processes driving poverty and disadvantage and on the multidimensional nature of the experience or outcome of these processes. However, the insights provided by the social exclusion ‘lens’ cannot replace those provided by the lens of gender, ethnicity, caste, age, disability and so on. Only taken singly and in combination will the understanding provided by these concepts make the maximum contribution to achieving more equitable and cohesive societies and global systems. 4.6 Key points: the processes of exclusion A relational approach to defining social exclusion that focuses on multidimensional, dynamic, processes embedded in unequal power relationships has ‘investigative advantage’ in understanding the causes and consequences of poverty and deprivation. These processes operate and interact across economic, social, political and cultural dimensions, through social relations within and between individuals, communities, institutions, nation states and global regions. A focus on exclusionary processes can: • Highlight the impacts of economic and social transformation driven by relational and institutional power differentials; • Reveal linkages between processes associated with globalisation and local exclusionary dynamics; • Illuminate the active and passive exclusionary processes arising from public policy; • Expose the role of cultural and symbolic processes as drivers of exclusion stigmatising the poor and other population groups, restricting human, civil, political and cultural rights and constraining capacity for collective action. In theory the concept of social exclusion has considerable analytical potential. It can focus attention onto the interaction between multiple exclusionary processes operating across systems of social stratification associated with gender, ethnicity, caste, religion, social class etc. However, insights provided by the social exclusion ‘lens’ are complementary to these other relational lens rather than providing an alternative way of conceptualising these. Social exclusion literature review September 08 30 5. Alternative and parallel discourses ‘…the concept of social exclusion as it originated in Western Europe, seems to have played a role in the re-opening of old debates and discussions… under new terminology’ (Saith, 2001:10) 5.1 Which alternative discourses? As Saith highlights, debates surrounding the concept of social exclusion have echoes in and to some extent have replaced older debates. In the previous section important overlaps with debates about the nature and causes of inequalities associated with major axes of social differentiation notably gender, race/ethnicity, caste, age and ability/disability, were discussed. It was noted that the particular feature of the social exclusion lens is that it focuses attention on the role played by relationships between individuals, groups and whole nations, and particularly differential power embedded in these relationships, in the generation of poverty and inequality. In addition to overlaps with other relational concepts there are therefore important links with more proximal concepts – concepts which may have greater policy/action salience than social exclusion in some parts of the world. Poverty is clearly the most obvious alternative concept from this perspective but there are others: basic needs, sustainable development, social cohesion, social capital, etc. We have chosen to focus here on just two alternative discourses – poverty and social capital - partly because they are the most proximal to social exclusion but also because these discourses and their relationship to social exclusion are arguably the most contentious. 5.2 Poverty, vulnerability, capability and human development The concept of poverty is fast evolving, and when broadened to incorporate notions of relativity, vulnerability and capability deprivation, it tends to dovetail with thinking about social exclusion. Notwithstanding this common ground, most commentators would argue that the concepts of poverty and social exclusion are not synonymous. Poverty was long conceptualised in absolute terms typically in terms of a minimum consumption basket to meet an individual’s basic needs (Rowntree, 1901). It has more recently been redefined in relative terms, placing emphasis on the distribution of income and wealth in a society. There has been a corresponding move from defining an absolute poverty line - denoting a minimum standard of living that is similar in any country at any time - to a relative poverty line, set for example as a proportion of the national average income at a point in time. Peter Townsend’s landmark work in the UK was instrumental in this reconceptualisation of poverty, establishing a set of resources, in the form of goods and services, governing standards of living, and moving towards a multidimensional, relative, definition of poverty. He also includes social participation – another relational concept - as a resource necessary to avoid poverty and its consequences. Social exclusion literature review September 08 31 ‘Individuals… can be said to be in poverty when they lack the resources to obtain the types of diet, participate in the activities and have the living conditions and amenities which are customary, or at least widely encouraged or approved, in the societies to which they belong’ (Townsend, 1979:31). This relative concept of poverty is now prevalent in many countries in South and North America, Western Europe and Australasia. In the UK it was recently reiterated by the newspaper columnist Polly Toynbee: ‘To be poor is to fall too far behind what most ordinary people have in your own society’ (Toynbee, 2006). And it has gained credence to the right of the political spectrum in the UK: whereas in the past Conservative administrations have tended to dismiss relative poverty as reflecting no more than unavoidable, almost natural, inequalities in society (Beresford et al., 1999), in 2006 the Conservative Party leader David Cameron was quoted as saying: “Even if we are not destitute, we still experience poverty if we cannot afford things that society regards as essential” (Cameron, 2006). Measures of poverty in the UK, the EU and many other countries are consistent with this conceptualisation (for example, in the UK, poverty is assessed against low-income thresholds linked to contemporary median incomes). As noted in earlier sections whilst some Northern Hemisphere commentators have voiced a concern at the way in which the discourse of social exclusion is decentring poverty discourses, others have focused on the additional benefits of the exclusion ‘lens’. From an Anglo-Saxon poverty tradition, Matt Barnes (2005:15) has attempted to draw distinctions between poverty, deprivation and social exclusion. In his schema, and in contrast to poverty and deprivation, the concept of social exclusion ‘evokes a multi-dimensional notion of participation in society, involving a combination of physical, material, relational and societal needs, over a period of time’ (Barnes, 2005:16). This approach echoes Estivill’s suggestion (2003:21) that: ‘if poverty is a photograph, exclusion is a film’. Table 1: Comparison of poverty, deprivation and social exclusion Poverty Deprivation Social exclusion One-dimensional Multi-dimensional Multi-dimensional Physical needs Physical needs Material needs Physical needs Material needs Societal participation Distributional Distributional Distributional Relational Static Static Dynamic Individual Household Individual Household Individual Household Community Source: Barnes (2005) Social exclusion literature review September 08 32 However, whilst social exclusion has become the dominant inequality discourse in Europe and Latin America this is not necessarily the case around the globe. In other regions, notably South East Asia and SubSaharan Africa the discourse of poverty, defined in both absolute and relative terms and extending to include notions of vulnerability, basic needs, capabilities, resource enhancement and sustainable human development and have greater policy/action relevance and salience. This is discussed in other SEKN documents and the SEKN’s final report (Popay, et al. 2008; Rispel et al. 2007; Johnston et al. 2008). Not-with-standing the pioneering work of scholars such as Peter Townsend, euro-centric approaches to defining and measuring poverty and deprivation have been criticised from a development perspective for placing too much emphasis on income disadvantage. For example, Robert Chambers (1997) on the basis of participatory research with people experiencing poverty and disadvantage in Africa, Asia and Latin America, emphasises the notion of vulnerability, which he defines as exposure to risk and shocks, and defencelessness, or the lack of means to cope without damaging loss. As Chambers (1997:45) argues: ‘Deprivation as poor people perceive it has many dimensions, including not only lack of income and wealth, but also social inferiority, physical weakness, disability and sickness, vulnerability, physical and social isolation, powerlessness and humiliation … In practice, much of this wide spectrum of deprivation and ill-being is covered by the common use of the word poverty… [However] poverty is then defined as low income, or often as low consumption, which is more easily and reliably measured. Surveys are carried out and poverty lines constructed. This limits much of the analysis of poverty to the one dimension that has been measured’. Castel also focuses on the notion of ‘vulnerability’ pointing to need for a better understanding of the trajectory of groups and individuals along a ‘continuum of vulnerable situations’ (Castel, 1998: 129). In Castel’s formulation vulnerability is not understood as an individual weakness, but as a range of situations that human groups share but the resources and capabilities to avoid or escape them is unequally distributed. Minujin similarly proposes a continuum from inclusion to exclusion characterised by increasing vulnerability (Minujin, 1998: 176-187). Of particular relevance at a global level is the notion of human development: the process of enlarging people’s choice by expanding human capabilities and functioning. This understanding of the common global development challenge regardless of GDP has been promoted by the UNDP, inspired by Amartya Sen’s work on capabilities: ‘At all levels of development the three essential capabilities for human development are for people to lead long and healthy lives, to be knowledgeable and to have a decent standard of living. If these basic capabilities are not achieved, many choices are simply Social exclusion literature review September 08 33 not available and many opportunities remain inaccessible. But the realm of human development goes further: essential areas of choice, highly valued by people, range from political, economic and social opportunities for being creative and productive to enjoying self-respect, empowerment and a sense of belonging to a community’ (UNDP, 2007b). The UNDP’s first Human Development Report published in 1990 introduced the Human Development Index (HDI) which incorporates Sen’s three ‘essential’ capabilities. Since then three other indices have been developed, including a Human Poverty Index (HPI). These are described in section 6.6 below. In contrast to the UNDP’s broad conceptualisation of poverty as deprivation in elements essential for human life, the World Bank uses a reductionist monetary figure of $US 1 a day to define absolute poverty. This measure is now widely adopted by international agencies although it fails to take account of social needs and local complexity. Indeed, the first of the eight Millennium Development targets is to halve, between 1990 and 2015, the proportion of people whose income is less than $US 1 a day, using a 1993 measure of purchasing power parity (PPP) to adjust for differences in prices between countries. In developing countries, measures of poverty generally reflect an absolute approach relying on calculation of the costs of a ‘basket’ of basic needs. 5.3 Social exclusion and social capital Social capital, like social exclusion, is a contested concept which has received much attention in recent years. It has been described as a relational concept, concerned with ‘identifying the nature and extent of social relationships’ (Szreter and Woolcock, 2004:650). Whereas the conceptual literature linking social exclusion to health is limited, social capital has been widely theorised as a mediating link between socioeconomic inequality and health, building on Richard Wilkinson’s influential book, Unhealthy Societies (1996). There has also been extensive empirical research in this area, the interpretation of which is a subject of ongoing debate (see section 8 of this paper). Robert Putnam, one of the key advocates of the concept, defines social capital as: ‘features of social organisation such as networks, norms and trust’ (Putnam, 1993). Types of networks range from the informal (family, friends, neighbours) to the formal (sports clubs, civic associations); norms are ‘those unstated rules or standards that often govern actions during informal or spontaneous social relations’ (Hean et al., 2004); and trust has been defined as ‘belief in the goodwill and benign intent of others’ (Kawachi et al, 1997). Putnam (1993, 2000) sees social capital as the social infrastructure (‘wires’) that enables individuals to gain access to resources. Viewed at a relational level, social capital is thus for Putnam the property of individuals, but only by virtue of group/community membership. In Social exclusion literature review September 08 34 contrast, network scholars, notably James Coleman (1988), argue that social capital refers to the resources that flow through networks (for example, material resources, willingness of network members to offer assistance, information): i.e. the electricity rather than the wires themselves. Bourdieu (1986) a French socialist and sociologist writing from a radically different theoretical and political position to Putnam, also defines social capital in terms of networks but emphasises their role in the constitution and maintenance of hierarchical class relations and social and economic inequalities. This is part of his account of different forms of capital (economic, cultural, social and symbolic) and their interrelationships. According to Virginia Morrow (2002:11), ‘Bourdieu is primarily concerned with how economic capital underpins these other forms, how forms of capital interact with wider structures to reproduce social inequalities, and how the day-to-day activities of social actors draw upon and reproduce structural features of wider social systems’. Much of the empirical research on social capital has been underpinned by the Putnam approach to understanding the concept. In this context, the unit of analysis to which the concept can be applied is contentious. While some neo-classical economists see social capital as the property of individuals, others, including the neo-conservative Francis Fukuyama (1995) see it as a characteristic of spatially defined communities ranging from villages to entire societies. It has been suggested that communities possessing high levels of social capital may obtain benefits including faster economic development, better government and improved health. However, most commentators recognise that social capital can be associated with either good or bad outcomes: the purposes for which resources are used being analytically and practically distinct from how they are obtained. Thus high levels of social capital may be associated with criminal and ‘terrorist’ activity, corruption and nepotism and/or social control, blocking the access of ‘out-groups’ to ‘community’ resources. Conventionally, within the Putnamesque approach, two types of social capital have been identified: ‘bonding’ social capital, referring to relations between members of a group or network who share a common identity; and ‘bridging’ social capital, which transcends these divides (for example, of age, ethnicity, class), through participation in associational activity. More recently, a third dimension, ‘linking’ social capital, has been introduced, defined by Szreter and Woolcock (2004:655) as ‘norms of respect and networks of trusting relationships between people who are interacting across explicit, formal or institutionalized power or authority gradients in society’. Linking social capital, according to Szreter and Woolcock (2004:656), is: ‘particularly relevant for the effective implementation of measures to assist the ill, poor, and the ‘socially excluded’. For example, they argue that without relationships of trust and respect between those involved in delivering public services and ‘the poor’, these measures are unlikely to succeed. Szreter and Woolcook conclude that a three-dimensional conceptualisation of social capital: Social exclusion literature review September 08 35 ‘places great emphasis on both the quality and quantity of relationships between all citizens. It also places emphasis on whether or not these relationships are founded on mutual respect between people, differentiated either horizontally by their varying social identities or vertically by their access to different levels of power and authority’ (Szreter and Woolcock, 2004:663). It has been argued that much empirical research on social capital has suffered from a lack of theoretical clarity (Hean et al., 2004) and attempts at measurement reflect the conceptual debates described above. Criticisms include: a preponderance of indicators that reflect the same ‘elasticity’ with which the term ‘social capital’ is used in different disciplines and approaches; a lack of clarity about the choice of unit of analysis or level for measurement (e.g. individual, aggregate, or community); over-reliance on self-reports; a large number of potentially omitted variables; and problems with the transferability and appropriateness of survey instruments to different geographic contexts and disciplinary realms. Blaxter argues that these problems have implications for the study of the putative relationship between social capital and health because: ‘…there is a tendency to define as social capital whatever social indicators best predict health status. This becomes tautologous: social capital promotes good health, but is at the same time defined by those things known to be health promoting’ (Blaxter, 2004:15). In part because of these measurement difficulties, there are conflicting views on the relationship between social capital and health outcomes. For example, whilst Szreter and Woolcock, (2004:65) claim that the ‘specific research connecting social capital to health outcomes via a social support mechanism is vast’ , Muntaner (2004:765), argues that ‘the health effects of social capital cannot be taken for granted and in spite of some promising findings, the burden of proof is still on the ‘social capital’ hypothesis’. Morgan and Swann (2004:190), in the conclusion of their secondary analysis of surveys relating to social capital and health conclude that ‘the positive relationships that have been found are only true for some indicators of social capital and vary according to the health outcome of interest. Moreover, while some independent effects have been found, social capital has less power to predict health than other more familiar indicators of socio-economic status’. Swann and Morgan (2002:6) have also reviewed qualitative research on social capital to ‘look beneath the surface at the hard-to-measure processes and actions of people’s relationships to others, at community structures, and the ‘life’ of communities and networks’. This review identified a number of barriers to the acquisition and utilisation of ‘social capital’, including differential power and the experience of disempowerment, social identity, rights and aspects of place. Attempts have also been made to observe community relationships and norms directly. Social exclusion literature review September 08 36 At a general level, the utility of the Putnam approach to defining the concept of social capital has been criticised because of its foundation in the liberal traditions of utilitarianism and individualism (Skocpol, 1996; Hernández et al., 2001). From this perspective it is the notion of ‘capital’ available for individual roots - with its root in economics – that is the problem, notwithstanding the focus on personal relationships and voluntary association. These commentators challenge the assumption that “values” related to mutual trust and reciprocity will generate individual wealth and make for successful societies and criticise attempts to create hierarchies of societies based on the level of social capital (Inglehart, 1997). These approaches, it is argued, fail to recognise that conflict and power relationships do not necessarily lead to social failure and that voluntary relationships and the action of voluntary associations are not necessarily freely chosen but may result from potentially invisible pressure from states and institutions (Hernández et al., 2001:21-23). Recent approaches to using the concept of social capital in research and policy has also been criticised for distracting from more pressing economic and political issues. For example, Muntaner (2004:677) has argued that: ‘the political use of social capital outside public health leans towards tolerance for social inequality and against egalitarian social change’. He adds that an emphasis on the measurement of ‘social capital’, to the detriment of data reflecting political and economic processes, can lead to ‘pseudo explanations’ where: ‘Crime, isolation, drug use, broken windows, sexually transmitted diseases and other diseases are seen as the outcome of some intrinsic deficiency of the community’ (Muntaner, 2004: 678). There are then major controversies surrounding the value of social capital as a conceptual lens through which to understand the nature and consequences of social relationships at micro, meso and macro levels within societies – controversies that mirror those surrounding the concept of ‘social exclusion’. A pre-requisite for any analysis of the relationship between these two concepts is clarity of theoretical and ideological position and definition. Thus, for example, Putnam sees social capital as associated with social benefits or social problems – and hence as potentially a focus of social policy. Bourdieu on the other hand uses the concept as part of his social theory of inequality and does not develop it as a single cause of social ills or argue that policy should seek to impact on it specifically as distinct from social inequalities in general. Putnam’s neo-Durkheimian perspective on social capital aligns itself most obviously with Levitas’ SID discourse, and Silver’s ‘solidarity’ paradigm, described in section 3. Bourdieu’s analysis is closer to radical redistributionist interpretations of social exclusion, drawing on conflict theory, as exemplified by Silver’s ‘monopoly’ paradigm and Beall’s transformationalist approach. A three-dimensional conceptualisation of social capital goes some way towards exploring links between micro- and macro-sociological phenomena, but falls short of the ‘integrated analysis of institutions’ that Sen (2000) sees as essential to a relational approach to social exclusion; neither does it take full account of the dynamic structural aspects of global exclusionary processes. In summary, as Social exclusion literature review September 08 37 Levitas cautions (2006:136): ‘the conceptual background and political implications of ‘exclusion from social relations’ and ‘social capital’ are not the same’, and care should be taken to avoid defining, measuring, and interpreting them interchangeably. 5.3 Key points: alternative and parallel discourses This section has considered concepts that may act as alternatives to social exclusion as ‘lens’ through which to understand and act on social inequalities. Poverty and social capital have been selected for attention here as the most proximal concepts and arguably the most contentious. There are other concepts which might have been considered including, for example, human rights, basic needs and sustainable development. The conceptualisation and measurement of poverty and related notions of vulnerability and capability deprivation, have become increasingly sophisticated in recent decades. It is now widely accepted that poverty is relative (defined in terms of a particular spatial, cultural and temporal context) and multi-dimensional, encompassing lack of social as well as material resources. However, in contrast to the notion of ‘social exclusion’, contemporary measures of poverty tend to be restricted to distributional (rather than relational) resources, and to focus on the individual and household levels. Whilst poverty continues to dominate the policy agenda in many low income countries/regions, eurocentric conceptual approaches have been challenged, in particular through Chambers’ work on vulnerability and Sen’s work on capabilities. In response to such critiques, since 1990, the UNDP has produced the Human Development Index, a composite measure of life expectancy, educational attainment and income, and more recently, a Human Poverty Index which adopts a relative rather than absolute approach. In contrast, the World Bank promotes an absolute measure of poverty and continues to set the extreme poverty line at $US1/day Despite criticisms that this level is now out of step with increases in commodity prices/costs of living and should be increased to $2 per day at a minimum, it is still widely adopted by policy makers focused on international poverty reduction targets e.g. Millennium Development Goals. Social capital is a relational concept which, like social exclusion, has received much attention in recent years and is highly contested. Leading theories differ as to the nature, role and benefits of social capital. The operationalisation and measurement of social capital reflects these controversies including: a lack of theoretical and definitional clarity; contested choices of indicators and levels of measurement; reliance on self-reports; and limited transferability. In contrast to social exclusion, the relationship between social capital (defined in terms of relationships of trust and reciprocity) and population health/health inequalities has been widely theorised and is the subject of extensive empirical study. Research linking social capital to health outcomes is controversial whilst qualitative research has highlighted Social exclusion literature review September 08 38 barriers to the acquisition of social capital in disadvantaged communities. More generally, the concept within the Putnamesque approach is criticised as emanating from the liberal traditions of utilitarianism and individualism, and for distracting attention for the political and economic causes of inequalities. A pre-requisite for any analysis of the relationship between ‘social exclusion’ ‘poverty’ and/or ‘social capital’ is clarity of ideological and theoretical position and definition. Care should be taken to avoid defining, measuring, and interpreting these concepts interchangeably. Social exclusion literature review September 08 74 References Almeida-Filho, N. & Silvapaim, J. (1999). La crisis de la salud pública y el movimiento de la salud colectiva en Latinoamérica. Cuadernos Médico Sociales (Rosario), (75): 5-30. Appasamy, P., Guhan, S., Hema, R. et al. (1996). Social exclusion from a welfare rights perspective in India. International Institute of Labour Studies and United Nations Development Programme, Research Series 106, Geneva: ILO publications Arsenic Policy Support Unit (APSU) (2006). Social Aspects of Access to Healthcare for Arsenicosis Patients. Arsenic Policy Support Unit. Dhaka, Bangladesh. Atkinson, A.B. (1998). Social Exclusion, poverty and unemployment, in Atkinson, A.B. & Hills, J. (eds). Exclusion, Employment and Opportunity. CASE paper 4. London: London School of Economics Barnes, M. (2005). Social Exclusion in Great Britain. An empirical investigation and comparison with the EU. Aldershot: Ashgate Barry, B. (2002). Social exclusion, social isolation, and the distribution of income. In Hills, J., Le Grand, J., & Piachaud, D. (eds.) Understanding social exclusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press Beall, J. Globalization and social exclusion in cities: framing the debate with lessons from Africa and Asia (2002). Environment & Urbanization 14(1): 41-51 Benach, J., Muntaner, C., & Santana, V. (2007). Employment Conditions and Health Equity. Final Report to the WHO Commission on the Social Determinants of Health from the Employment Conditions Knowledge Network (ENCONET). Beresford, P., Green, D., Lister, R., & Woodard, K. (1999). Poverty first hand: poor people speak for themselves. London: CPAG Blane, D. (2000). The life course, the social gradient, and health. In Marmot, M. & Wilkinson, R.G. (eds.) Social determinants of health. Oxford: Oxford University Press Blaxter, M. (2004). Questions and their meanings in social capital surveys. In Morgan, A. & Swann, C. (eds.) Social capital for health: issues of definition, measurement and links to health. London: Health Development Agency Bourdieu, P. (1986). The forms of capital. In Richardson, J.G. (eds). Handbook of theory and research for the sociology of education. New York: Greenwood Press Social exclusion literature review September 08 75 Bowring, F. (2000). Social exclusion: limits of the debate. Critical Social Policy, 20, 307-30 Breihl, J. (2003). Epidemiología Crítica. Ciencia emancipadora e intercultural. Buenos Aires: Universidad Nacional de Lanas; Lugar Editorial. Brunner, E., & Marmot, M. (2000). Social organisation, stress and health. In Marmot, M. & Wilkinson, R.G. (eds.) Social determinants of health. Oxford: Oxford University Press Burchardt, T., Le Grand, J., & Piachaud, C. (1999). Social exclusion in Britain 1991-1995. Social Policy and Administration. 33/3: 227-44 Burchardt, T., Le Grand, J., & Piachaud, C. (2002). Degrees of exclusion: developing a dynamic, multidimensional measure, in Hills J, Le Grand J, Piachaud D. 2002. Understanding social exclusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press Burchardt, T., & Vizard, P. (2007). Definition of equality and framework for measurement: Final Recommendations of the Equalities Review Steering Group on Measurement. CASE paper 120. London: LSE Byrne, D. (1999) Social Exclusion. Buckingham: Open University Press Cabrera, P. (2000). Introducción: exclusión, desviación, pobreza. En: Tezanos, F., Cabrera, P. Miradas en el encuentro. Acortando distancias, construyendo realidades, Madrid: RAIS:17-21 Cameron, D. (2006). Quoted by Thompson I. in ‘Is Poly Toynbee really the new guru? The Guardian, 25/11/2006 Castel, R. (1997) [1995]. Las metamorfosis de la cuestión social. Una crónica del salariado. Buenos Aires: Paidós. Castel, R. (1998). La lógica de la exclusión. In Bustelo, E. & Minujin, A. (eds.) Todos entran. Propuesta para sociedades incluyentes. Bogotá: UNICEF, Santillana: 119-160. Castel, R. (2004). La inseguridad social. ¿Qué es estar protegido? Buenos Aires: Manantial. Castells, M. (1998). The end of the millennium. Oxford: Blackwell. Chamberlayne, P., Rustin, M., & Wengraf, T. eds. (2002). Biography and social exclusion in Europe. Experiences and life journeys. Bristol: Policy Press Chambers, R. (1997). Whose reality counts? Putting the first last. London: ITDG publishing Coleman, J. (1988). Social capital in the creation of human capital. American journal of sociology. 94:S95-S120 Social exclusion literature review September 08 76 Commission on Social Determinants of Health (CSDH) (2006). A conceptual framework for action on the social determinants of health. Discussion paper for the Commission on Social Determinants of Health. Draft. Geneva: WHO Council of Europe (1998). Fighting social exclusion and strengthening social cohesion in Europe. Recommendation 1355, Parliamentary Assembly debate on 28 January 1998 Crawhall, N. (2006). IPACC secretariat mission to Niger report. In Report on West African regional conference of indigenous peoples of the Sahara and Sahel. Agadez, Niger, 20-25 February 2006, available: www.ipacc.org.za Curran, C., Burchardt, T., Knapp, M., McDaid, D. & Bingqin, L. (2007). Challenges in multidisciplinary systematic reviewing: a study on social exclusion and mental health policy. Social policy and administration 41 (3): 289-312 Dahlgren, G. & Whitehead, M. (1993) Tackling inequalities in health: what can we learn from what has been tried? Working paper prepared for the King’s Fund International Seminar on Tackling Inequalities in Health, September 1993, Ditchley Park, Oxfordshire. London: King’s Fund Dahlgren, G. & Whitehead, M. (2006). Levelling up (part 2): a discussion paper on European strategies for tackling social inequities in health. Copenhagen: WHO regional office for Europe (Studies on social and economic determinants of population health, No.3). Davies, J.S. (2005). The social exclusion debate: strategies, controversies and dilemmas. Policy studies 26(1) 3-27 Department of Social Security (DSS) (1999). Opportunity for All: tackling poverty and social exclusion. London: The Stationery Office Department for International Development (DFID) (2005). Reducing poverty by tackling social exclusion. A policy paper. Department for Work and Pensions (DWP) (2003). United Kingdom National Action Plan on Social Inclusion 2003-05: the annexes. London: Department for Work and Pensions http://www.dwp.gov.uk/publications/dwp/2003/nap/ Dunn, S. (1999). Creating accepting communities. Report of the MIND inquiry into social exclusion and mental health problems. London: MIND publications Durkheim, E. (1895). The rules of the sociological method Elias, N. (1998) [1993]. Ensayo teórico sobre las relaciones entre establecidos y marginados. In Elias, N. La civilización de los padres y otros ensayos. Social exclusion literature review September 08 77 Compilación, presentación y traducción de Vera Weiler. Bogotá: Norma, Editorial Universidad Nacional: 79-138. Esping-Andersen, G. (2000). Fundamentos sociales de las economías postindustriales. Barcelona: Ariel. Estivill, J. (2003). Concepts and strategies for combating social exclusion: an overview. Geneva: International Labour Organisation European Council (2000). Fight against poverty and social exclusion – Definition of appropriate objectives. Brussels, 30 November 2000 http://ec.europa.eu/employment_social/social_inclusion/objectives_en.htm European Commission (2006). Portfolio of overarching indicators and streamlined social inclusion, pensions and health portfolios. Brussels Fabian Society (2006). Narrowing the gap. The final report of the Fabian Commission on life chances and child poverty. London: Fabian Society Figueroa, A., Altamirano, T., & Sulmont, D. (1996). Social exclusion and inequality in Peru. International Institute of Labour Studies and United Nations Development Programme, Research series 104, Geneva: ILO publications Fleury, S. (1998). Política social, exclusión y equidad en América Latina. Nueva Sociedad, N° 156, Julio-Agosto: 1-25 (pdf version). Fraser, N. (1997). Redistribución y reconocimiento. En: Fraser, N. Iustitia Interrupta. Reflexiones críticas desde la posición ‘postsocialista’. Bogotá: Siglo del Hombre, Universidad de los Andes: 15-54. Fraser, N. (2003). Redistribución, reconocimiento y exclusión social. In Departamento Administrativo de Bienestar Social (DABS) & Facultad de Ciencias Políticas y Relaciones Internacionales, Pontificia Universidad Javeriana (eds.) Inclusión social y nuevas ciudadanías. Condiciones para la convivencia y seguridad democráticas. Seminario Internacional. Memorias. Bogotá: DABS, PUJ: 55-69. Fukuyama, F. (1995). Trust: the social virtues and the creation of prosperity. New York: Free Press García Roca, J (1998). Exclusión social y contracultura de la solidaridad. Prácticas, discursos y narraciones. Madrid: HOAC. Gaviria, M., Laparra, M., and Aguilar, M. (1995). Aproximación teórica al concepto de exclusión. En: Álvarez-Uría, F. y otros. Desigualdad y pobreza, hoy. Madrid: Talasa: 133-200. GES (Gabinet d’Estudis Socials) (1995). Informe sobre a pobreza en Galicia. Santiago de Compostela, Xunta de Galicia Social exclusion literature review September 08 78 Gordon, D., Adelman, L., Ashworth, K., Bradshaw, J., Levitas, R., Middleton, S., Pantazis, C., Patsios, D., Payne, S., Townsend, P., & Williams, J. (2000). Poverty and Social Exclusion in Britain. York: Joseph Rowntree Foundation 2000 Gore, C. and Figueiredo, J.B. (eds.) (1997). Social exclusion and anti-poverty policy: a debate. International Institute for Labour Studies Research and United Nations Development Programme, research series 110. Geneva: International Labour Organisation publications Gough, J. & Eisenschitz A, with McCulloch A. (2006). Spaces of social exclusion. London: Routledge Graham, H. (2004). Health inequalities: concepts, frameworks and policy. Health Development Agency briefing paper. London: Health Development Agency de Haan, A. (2001). Social Exclusion: enriching the understanding of deprivation. World Development Report Forum on ‘Inclusion, Justice and Poverty Reduction’. Hassan, M.M., Atkins, P.J., & Dunn, C.E. (2005). Social implications of arsenic poisoning in Bangladesh. Soc Sci Med. 61:2201-11 Hean, S., Cowley, S., Forbes, A. & Griffiths, P. (2004). Theoretical development and social capital measurement. In Morgan, A. & Swann, C. Social capital for health: issues of definition, measurement and links to health. London: Health Development Agency Hernández, M. (2002). Reforma sanitaria, equidad y derecho a la salud en Colombia. Cadernos de Saúde Pública , 18 (4), Jul-Ago: 991-1001. Hernández, M. (2003). Neoliberalismo en salud: desarrollos, supuestos y alternativas. In Restrepo, D.I. (Ed) La falacia neoliberal. Crítica y alternativas. Bogotá: Vicerrectoría Académica y Sede Bogotá, Universidad Nacional de Colombia: 347-361 Hernández, M., Obregón, D., Miranda, N. et al. (2002). La Organización Panamericana de la Salud y el Estado colombiano: cien años de historia, 1902-2002. Bogotá: OPS/OMS. Hernández, M., Ochoa, D., & Novoa, E. (2001). Del capital social a la construcción de lo público. Trans, Revista de la Sede Bogotá, N° 1: 10-41. Hills J, Le Grand J, Piachaud D. (2002). Understanding social exclusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press Inglehart, R. (1997). Modernization and Postmodernization: Cultural, Economic and Political Change in 43 Societies. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Social exclusion literature review September 08 79 International Institute for Labour Studies (IILS) (1998). Annex I: issues for discussion. In: Figueiredo, J.B. & de Haan, A. eds. Social exclusion: an ILO perspective. International Institute for Labour Studies Research series 111. Geneva: International Labour Organisation Johnston, H. (2008). Disentangling inequities in Bangladesh: A social exclusion and health analysis. SEKN Background Paper 11, Dhaka, Bangladesh Juliano, D. (2001). Género y exclusión. In Valencia, A. (ed) Exclusión social y construcción de lo público en Colombia. Bogotá: Centro de Estudios de la Realidad Colombiana (CEREC), Facultad de Ciencias Económicas, Universidad del Valle: 27-50. Karikalan, I. (2002). Oorakali. In Basu, T. (eds) Translating caste. Stories, essays, criticism. New Delhi: Katha Kawachi, I., Kennedy, B.P., Lochner, K., & Prothrow-Smith, D. (1997). Social capital, income inequality and mortality. American Journal of Public Health. 87:1491-8 Klein, N. (2001). The Unknown Icon. The Guardian Weekend, March 3 2001 Krieger, N. (2003). Theories for social epidemiology in the twenty-first century. In Hofrichter, R. (ed.) Health and social justice. Politics, ideology, and inequity in the distribution of disease. A public health reader. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass Kronauer, M. (1998). Social exclusion and underclass – new concepts for the analysis of poverty. Pp 51-75. In Hans-Jurgen, A. (ed) Empirical poverty research in a comparative perspective. Ashgate: Aldershot Kuhn, T. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions. 2nd edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press Labonte, R., Blouin, C., Chopra, M., Lee, K., Packer, C., Rowson, M., Schrecker, T., & Woodward, D. (2007). Towards Health-Equitable Globalisation: Rights, Regulations and Redistribution. Final Report of the Globalisation Knowledge Network to the WHO Commission on Social Determinants of Health. Lader, D. (2007). Public attitudes towards development. Knowledge and attitudes concerning poverty in developing countries, 2006. A report on research using the Office for National Statistics Omnibus Survey produced by the Office for National Statistics on behalf of the Department for International Development. London: Office for National Statistics Landman, T. (2006). Human rights and social exclusion indicators: concepts, best practices, and methods for implementation. University of Essex: Department of Government Human Rights Centre Lauthier, B. (2005). Una protección social mutualista y universal: condición para la eficacia de la lucha contra la pobreza. In Salama, P., Marques-Pereira, Social exclusion literature review September 08 80 J., Lauthier, B., Le Bonniec, Y., Rodríguez, O., Giraldo, C. Sistemas de protección social: entre la volatilidad económica y la vulnerabilidad social. Colección estudios sobre protección social, tomo 1. Bogotá: Centro de Investigaciones para el Desarrollo (CID), Facultad de Ciencias Económicas, Universidad Nacional de Colombia: 95-154. Le Bonniec, Y. (2005). Colombia: una apuesta aún incierta. In Salama, P., Marques-Pereira, J., Lauthier, B., Le Bonniec, Y., Rodríguez, O., Giraldo, C. Sistemas de protección social: entre la volatilidad económica y la vulnerabilidad social. Colección estudios sobre protección social, tomo 1. Bogotá: Centro de Investigaciones para el Desarrollo (CID), Facultad de Ciencias Económicas, Universidad Nacional de Colombia: 158-176. Lenoir, R. (1974). Les exclus: un Francais sur dix. Paris: Le Seuil Levitas, R. (1998). The inclusive society? Social exclusion and new labour. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan Levitas, R. (2005). The inclusive society? Social exclusion and new labour. Second edition. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan Levitas R. (2006). The concept and measurement of social exclusion. In Pantazis C, Gordon D & Levitas R (eds.) Poverty and social exclusion in Britain. The millennium survey. Bristol: Policy Press Levitas, R., Pantazis, C., Fahmy, E., Gordon, D., Lloyd, E. & Patsios, D. (2007). The multi-dimensional analysis of social exclusion. Bristol Institute for Public Affairs, University of Bristol Lister, R. (1990). The exclusive society: citizenship and the poor. London: CPAG Mabbett, D. (2004). Learning by numbers: the role of indicators in the social inclusion process. Paper for the ESPAnet conference, Oxford, 9-11 September 2004 Madanipour, A. et al. (eds.) (1998). Social exclusion in European cities. Processes, experiences and responses. London: Jessica Kingsley Mann, M. (1986). The Sources of Social Power. Vol. I: A history of power from the beginning to A.D. 1760. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Marmot, M. & Wilkinson, R.G. (eds.) (2006). Social determinants of health. 2nd edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press Marshall, T.H. (1964). Class, citizenship and social development. New York: Doubleday. Mathieson, J. Alhacen, A (Aghirin’man, Arlit) (2007). Social exclusion in north Niger: A case study. SEKN Background Paper 5, Lancaster, UK McLean, C., Campbell, C., & Cornish, F. (2003). African-Caribbean interactions with mental health services in the UK: experiences and expectations of Social exclusion literature review September 08 81 exclusion as (re)productive of health inequalities. Soc Sci Med 56: 657- 669 Miliband, D. (2006). Social exclusion: the next steps forward. Wetherby: Office of the Deputy Prime Minister Publications. Minujin, A. (1998). Vulnerabilidad y exclusión en América Latina. En: Bustelo, E., Minujin, A. (Editores) Todos entran. Propuesta para sociedades incluyentes. Bogotá: UNICEF, Santillana: 161-205. Mkandawire, T. (2005). Targeting and Universalism in Poverty Reduction. Social Policy and Development Social Program Paper Number 23, Geneva: United Nations Research Institute for Social Development. Organización Panamericana de la Salud (OPS) (2003). Exclusión en salud en países de América Latina y el Caribe. Serie N° 1. Extensión de la Protección Social en Salud. Washington: OPS/OMS, Agencia Sueca para el Desarrollo Internacional (ASDI). Morgan, A. & Swann, S. (2004). Where next for social capital research? In Morgan, A., & Swann, C. (eds.) Social capital for health: issues of definition, measurement and links to health. London: Health Development Agency Morrow, V. (2002). Children’s experiences of ‘community’: implications of social capital discourses. In Swann, C. & Morgan, A. (eds.) Social capital for health: insights from qualitative research. London: Health Development Agency Muntaner, C. (2004). Commentary: social capital, social class and the slow progress of psychosocial epidemiology. International Journal of Epidemiology. 33:674-80 Murard, N. (2002). Guilty victims: social exclusion in contemporary France. In Chamberlayne, P., Rustin, M., & Wengraf, T. (eds.) Biography and social exclusion in Europe. Experiences and life journeys. Bristol: Policy Press Murray, C. (1990). The emerging British underclass. London: Institute of Economic Affairs Health and Welfare Unit Navarro, V. & Shi, L. (2001). The political context of social inequalities and health. Int Journal of Health Services. 31(1) 1-21 Navarro, V. (eds.) (2002) The political economy of social inequalities. Consequences for health and the quality of life. Baywood: Amityville Navarro, V., Muntaner, C., Borrell, C., et al. (2006). Politics and health outcomes. Lancet 368:1033–7 Social exclusion literature review September 08 82 Organisation for Economic Cooperation and development (OECD) (1997). Societal cohesion and a globalizing economy. Washington DC: OECD, March 1997 Palmer, G., MacInnes, T., & Kenway, P. (2006). Monitoring poverty and social exclusion in the UK 2006. York: Joseph Rowntree Foundation www.poverty.org.uk, published by the New Policy Institute on behalf of the Joseph Rowntree Foundation Pantazis, C., Gordon, D., & Levitas, R. (eds.) (2006). Poverty and social exclusion in Britain. The millennium survey. Bristol: Policy Press Parr, H., Phil, C., & Burns, N. (2004). Social geographies of rural mental health: experiencing inclusions and exclusions. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 29 (4) 401-19 Paugam, S. (1995). The spiral of precariousness: a multidimensional approach to the process of social disqualification in France. In Room, G. (ed.) Beyond the threshold. The measurement and analysis of social exclusion. Bristol: Policy Press. Payne, S. (2006). Mental health, poverty and social exclusion. In Pantazis, C., Gordon, D. & Levitas, R. (eds.) Bristol: Policy Press Pierson, J. (2002). Tackling Social Exclusion. London: Routledge Popay, J., Williams, G. Thomas, C. and Gatrell, A. (1998). Theorising inequalities in health: The place of lay knowledge, Sociology of Health and Illness 20 (5), 619–644 Popay, J., Escorel, S., Hernandez, M., Johnston, H., Mathieson, J., and Rispel, L. on behalf of the WHO Social Exclusion Knowledge Network (2008) Understanding and tackling social exclusion; Final Report of the Social Exclusion Knowledge Network of the Commission on Social Determinants of Health. Geneva with web link Prigogine, I. & Stengers, I. (1985). Order out of chaos. London: Flamingo Putnam, R. (1993). Making democracy work. Civic traditions in modern Italy. New Jersey: Princeton University Press Putnam, R. (2000). Bowling Alone. The collapse and revival of American community. New York: Simon and Schuster Rispel, L. Molomo, B. Dumela, S. (2007). South African Case Study on Social Exclusion. SEKN Background Paper 3, Johannesburg, South Africa Rodríguez, O. (2005). Avatares de la reforma del sistema de seguridad social, Ley 100 de 1993. En: Salama, P., Marques-Pereira, J., Lauthier, B., Le Bonniec, Y., Rodríguez, O., Giraldo, C. Sistemas de protección social: entre la volatilidad económica y la vulnerabilidad social. Colección estudios sobre protección social, tomo 1. Bogotá: Centro de Investigaciones para el Social exclusion literature review September 08 83 Desarrollo (CID), Facultad de Ciencias Económicas, Universidad Nacional de Colombia: 177-231. Rodríguez, O. (2007).s Las transformaciones teóricas y políticas del Banco Mundial: la antesala al Manejo Social del Riesgo. Bogotá. Documento elaborado para el grupo Colombia del Nodo Regional Conjunto para América Latina de la Red de Conocimiento sobre Exclusión Social, Comisión de Determinantes Sociales de la Salud, Organización Mundial de la Salud (inédito). Room, G. et al. (1992). Observatory on national policies to combat social exclusion. Second annual report. Brussels: Directorate General for Employment, Social Affairs and Industrial Relations, Commission of the European Communities Room, G. (1995). Poverty and social exclusion: the new European agenda for policy and research. In Room, G. (ed.) Beyond the threshold. The measurement and analysis of social exclusion. Bristol: Policy Press. Rosanvallon, P. (1995). La nueva cuestión social. Repensar el Estado providencia. Buenos Aires: Manantial. Rowntree, S. (1901). Poverty: a study of town life. London: Longmans Green Saith, R. (2001). Social exclusion; the concept and application to developing countries. Working paper number 72. Queen Elizabeth House, University of Oxford Salama, P. (1999). Riqueza y pobreza en América Latina. La fragilidad de las nuevas políticas económicas. México: Universidad de Guadalajara, Fondo de Cultura Económica. Salama, P. (2006). De la flexibilidad a la cohesión social, pasando por las finanzas. In Le Bonniec, Y., Rodríguez, O. (eds) Crecimiento, equidad y ciudadanía. Hacia un nuevo sistema de protección social. Colección Estudios sobre Protección Social, tomo 2. Bogotá: Alcaldía Mayor de Bogotá, Departamento Administrativo de Bienestar Social Schrecker, T. (2006). Personal communication Scokpol, T. (1996). Unravelling from above. The American Prospect, N° 25. En: http://www.prospect.org/cgi-bin/printable.cgi Sen, A. (2000). Social Exclusion: concept, application and scrutiny. Social Development papers 1. Asian Development Bank Seoane, J. (Comp.) (2004). Movimientos sociales y conflicto en América Latina. Buenos Aires: Agencia Sueca de Desarrollo Internacional (ASDI), Consejo Latinoamericano de Ciencias Sociales (CLACSO). Social exclusion literature review September 08 84 Shaw, M., Dorling, D., & Davey Smith, G. (2006). Poverty, social exclusion, and minorities. In Marmot, M. & Wilkinson, R.G. (eds.) Social determinants of health. 2nd edition. Oxford: Oxford University Press Silver, H. (1994). Social exclusion and social solidarity: three paradigms. International Labour Review. 133:531-78 Silver, H. (2004). European Policies to Promote the Social Inclusion of Disadvantaged Groups: Lessons for Latin America. Pp. 135-76. In Buvinic, M. & Mazza J. (eds) Social Inclusion: Latin America's Development Challenge. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, Inter-American Development Bank Silver, H. (2005). From Poverty to Social Exclusion: Lessons from Europe. Pp. 57-70. In Hartman, C. (eds.) Poverty and Race in America: The Emerging Agendas. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books Social Exclusion Unit (SEU) (1997). Social Exclusion Unit: Purpose, work priorities and working methods. London: The Stationery Office South Australian Labor Party (2002). Labor’s social inclusion initiative: Labor’s plans for government. Spano, A. (2002). Female identities in late modernity. In Chamberlayne, P., Rustin, M., & Wengraf, T. (eds.) Biography and social exclusion in Europe. Experiences and life journeys. Bristol: Policy Press Stewart, F. (1998) La insuficiencia crónica del ajuste. In Bustelo, E. & Minujin, A. (eds) Todos entran. Propuesta para sociedades incluyentes. Bogotá: UNICEF, Santillana: 25-65. Swann, C. & Morgan, A. (2002). Introduction: Social capital for health: insights from qualitative research. In Swann, C. & Morgan, A. (eds) Social capital for health: insights from qualitative research. London: Health Development Agency Szreter S and Woolcock M (2004). Health by association: social capital, social theory and the political economy of public health. International Journal of Epidemiology. 33:650-67 Tezanos, F. (1999). Tendencias de dualización y exclusión social en las sociedades tecnológicas avanzadas. Un marco para el análisis. En: Tezanos, F. (Editor) Tendencias en desigualdad y exclusión social. Madrid: Sistema. Townsend, P. (1979). Poverty in the United Kingdom. Harmondsworth: Penguin Townsend P. (1997). Redistribution: the strategic alternative to privatisation. In Walker, A. & Walker, C. (eds.) Britain divided. The growth of social exclusion in the 1980s and 1990s. London: CPAG Social exclusion literature review September 08 85 Townsend, P. (2007) The Right to Social Security and National Development: Lessons for OECD experience for low income countries; Issues in Social Protection, Discussion Paper 18, International Labour Office Toynbee, P. (2006). The Guardian, 23 November 2006 United Nations Development Programme (UNDP) (2007a). Summary of the virtual round table on social exclusion www.hdr.undp.org/docs/nhdr/consolidated_replies/161.pdf, accessed 3.10.07 United Nations Development Programme (UNDP). (2007b). Human Development Reports. Glossary of terms. Available at: http://hdr.undp.org/en/humandev/glossary/ United Nations High Commission for Refugees (UNHCR) (2007). 2006 global trends: refugees, asylum-seekers, returnees, internally displaced and stateless persons. Geneva: UNHCR Valencia, A (2001). Exclusión social y construcción de lo público en Colombia. In Valencia, A. (ed.) Exclusión social y construcción de lo público en Colombia. Bogotá: Centro de Estudios de la Realidad Colombiana (CEREC), Facultad de Ciencias Económicas, Universidad del Valle: 11-25. Veit-Wilson, J. (1998). Setting adequacy standards. Bristol: Policy Press Velásquez, F. (2001). Exclusión social y gestión urbana: a propósito de Cali. En: Valencia, A. (Editor) Exclusión social y construcción de lo público en Colombia. Bogotá: Centro de Estudios de la Realidad Colombiana (CEREC), Facultad de Ciencias Económicas, Universidad del Valle: 97-156. Watkins, K. (2006). Human Development Report 2006. Beyond scarcity: power, poverty and the global water crisis. New York: Palgrave Macmillan Available: http://hdr.undp.org/hdr2006/statistics/indicators/ Watkins, K. (2007). Human Development Report 2007/2008. Fighting climate change: human solidarity in a divided world. New York: Palgrave Macmillan Available: http://hdr.undp.org/en/reports/global/hdr2007-2008/ Wilkinson, R. (1996). Unhealthy Societies: the afflictions of Inequality. London: Routledge Wilkinson R.G., and Pickett, K.E. (2006). Income inequality and population health: a review and explanation of the evidence. Social Science and Medicine 62 1768-84 Wolfensohn, J.D. (1997). The challenge of inclusion. Annual meetings address. Hongkong, 23 September 1997 5 Inclusive Education 5 1. Clough, Peter, and Jenny. Corbett. 2000. "Routes to Inclusion: Introduction." Pp. 3-33 in Theories of Inclusive Education: A Students' Guide. London: Paul Chapman publishing. 2. European Agency for Special Needs and Inclusive Education. 2014. "Inclusive Education Benefits All." Pp. 11-15 in Five Key Messages for Inclusive Education: Putting Theory into Practice. Odense: European Agency for Special Needs and Inclusive Education.                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                   INCLUSIVE EDUCATION BENEFITS ALL Introduction There is increasing recognition across Europe, and more widely at international  level, that moving towards inclusive policy and practice in education is an  imperative. The Council conclusionson the social dimension of education and training state that: ‘Creating the conditions required for the successful inclusion of  pupils with special needs in mainstream settings benefits all learners’ (Council of the  European Union, 2010, p. 5).  The Commission of the European Communities’ Green Paper on Migration and  Mobility underlines that:  Schoolsmust play a leading role in creating an inclusive society, as they representthe main opportunity for young people of migrantand host communitiesto get to know and respecteach other … linguistic and cultural diversity may bring an invaluable resource to schools (Commission of the  European Communities, 2008, p. 1).  The United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO)  (2009) clearly indicates that inclusive education is a question of equity and is  therefore a quality issue impacting upon all learners. Three propositions regarding  inclusive education are highlighted: inclusion and quality are reciprocal; access and  quality are linked and are mutually reinforcing; and quality and equity are central to  ensuring inclusive education.  A number of Agency projects have also focussed on this issue. The report on the  Agency’s Raising Achievement for All Learners(RA4AL) conference (European  Agency, 2012c) highlights that issues surrounding the definition of inclusion have  become increasingly important, but that there appears to be growing agreement on  the need for a rights­based approach to develop greater equity and social justice  and to support the development of a non­discriminatory society. The debate about  inclusion has, therefore, broadened from one that used to focus on relocating  children described as having special educational needs into mainstream schools, to  one that seeks to provide high­quality education – and consequent benefits – for all  learners.  As more countries move to a wider definition of inclusive education, diversity is  recognised as ‘natural’ in any group of learners and inclusive education can be seen  as a means of raising achievement through the presence (access to education),  participation (quality of the learning experience) and achievement (learning  processes and outcomes) of all learners.  Putting Theory into Practice  11                                                                                                                                                                                                                                Agency work on Key Principlesfor Promoting Quality in Inclusive Education (European Agency, 2009b) reinforces the importance of learner­ centred/personalised learning approaches, teacher assessment that supports  learning, and collaborative work with parents and families – these are, however, key  to improving the quality of education for all learners.  Inclusive educationas an approach to raise achievement for all learners Wilkinson and Pickett note that ‘greater equality, as well as improving the wellbeing  of the whole population, is also the key to national standards of achievement’  (2010, p. 29). They stress that if:  a country wantshigher average levelsof educationalachievementamong its schoolchildren, it must addressthe underlying inequality which createsa steeper social gradientin educationalachievement(ibid., p. 30).  Challenging the idea that including all learners may somehow be detrimental to high  achievement, the Organisation for Economic Co­operation and Development (OECD,  2011) shows that improving the lowest performing students does not have to be at  the expense of higher performers. The findings of the UNESCO report Learning Divides (Willms, 2006) also provide evidence that strong school performance and  equity can go hand­in­hand and that countries with the highest levels of  performance tend to be those that are successfully raising the achievement of all  learners (European Agency, 2012d).  According to the Agency’s RA4AL report,  Farrelland colleagues(2007) … found a small body of research to suggest that placing learnerswith SEN in mainstream schools hasno major adverse consequencesfor allchildren’sacademic achievement, behaviour and attitudes. A systematic review of the literature commissioned by the Evidence for Policy and Practice Initiative (EPPI) (Kalambouka etal., 2005) also found that, in general, there are no adverse effects on learnerswithoutSENwhen learners with special needsare included in mainstream schools (European Agency,  2012d, p. 8).  Several studies outline the benefits of inclusion for learners without disabilities.  These benefits include:  increased appreciation and acceptance of individualdifferencesand diversity, respectfor all people, preparation foradultlife in an inclusive society and opportunitiesto master activities by practising and teaching others. Such effects are also documented in recentresearch, for example Bennettand Gallagher (2012) (European Agency, 2012d, p. 8).  Five Key Messages for Inclusive Education 12                                                                                                                                The positive impactof inclusive placementson learnerswith disabilities is noted by research such as MacArthur etal. (2005) and de Graaf etal. (2011). This includes improved social relationshipsand networks, peer role models, increased achievement, higher expectations, increased collaboration among schoolstaff and improved integration of families into the community (European Agency, 2012d, p. 8).  Further benefits may include access to wider curriculum opportunities and  recognition and accreditation of achievement.  Consideration should be given to improving the organisation of ‘spaces’ for learning and providing more opportunitiesfor learnersto discover talents in a range of areasbeyond academic learning (ibid., p. 25).  Research by Chapman et al. (2011) focussed specifically on:  leadership that promotesachievementfor learnerswith SEN/disability and suggested that the presence of a diverse student population can, under the rightorganisationalconditions, stimulate collaborative arrangementsand encourage innovative waysof teaching hard to reach groups(European Agency,  2012d, p. 21).  ‘What is good for pupils withSEN is good for all pupils’ This statement made in the Agency publication Inclusive Education and Classroom Practice (European Agency, 2003, p. 33) has, since that time, been frequently  reiterated in Agency work.  For example, the same study highlighted that:  peer tutoring or co-operative learning is effective in both cognitive and affective (social-emotional) areasof pupils’ learning and development. Pupilsthat help each other, especially within a system of flexible and well-considered pupil grouping, profitfrom learning together (ibid., p. 23).  In Agency work on inclusive practice in secondary schools in 2005, it was stressed  that:  All students – including students with SEN – demonstrate improvementsin their learning with systematic monitoring, assessment, planning and evaluation of their work (European Agency, 2005, p. 8)  and that:  All students benefitfrom co-operative learning: the studentwho explains to the other student retainsinformation better and for longer and the needs of the student who is learning are better addressed by a peer whose level of understanding isonly slightly higher than his or her own level (ibid., pp. 18–19).  Putting Theory into Practice  13                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                      The RA4AL report states that:  a system that allowslearnersto progresstowardscommon goals, butthrough differentroutes, using differentstyles of learning and assessment, should be more inclusive and raise the achievementof all learners(European Agency,  2012d, p. 25).  Agency work on Assessment in Inclusive Settings also notes the need to involve all  learners and parents/families in both the learning and the assessment process  (Watkins, 2007).  The same report points out that the process of differentiation needs careful  consideration. Although it may also be associated with individualisation and  personalisation and seen as a way to meet more specific individual or group needs,  it often remains teacher­centred rather than learner­led. Personalisation needs to  start with the needs and interests of all learners.  In the Agency’s more recent i-accessproject, it is noted that the benefits of assistive  technology or ‘enabling technology’ often prove useful for a large variety of users.  ‘Accessibility benefits users with disabilities and/or special educational needs and  may often benefit all users’ (European Agency, 2012e, p. 22).  The views of young people with and without disabilities expressed in the Young Views on Inclusive Education publication provide a clear summary of the benefits of  inclusive education for all learners. As one young learner said: ‘Inclusive education is  for all children. Normal schools should be near their homes. This experience  promotes meeting people from the neighbourhood’ (European Agency, 2012a,  p. 11). Others added: ‘Students with and without special needs can learn from each  other and exchange their knowledge’, ‘It is good for us – good for them. It is  important to recognisethe benefits to everyonein the class’ and ‘Inclusive  education helps mainstream children to become more tolerant, with more open  minds’ (ibid., p. 22).  Monitoring progress As inclusive education has broadened to consider quality education for all learners,  it is necessary to find new ways to monitor progress. It is suggested in Agency work  on indicators and the MIPIE report (2011a) that, at school level, data collection  could consider the factors that impact upon the quality of schools’ admission  strategies, such as: non­discriminatory admission rules and policies; policies and  strategies developed to support learners in disclosing their needs; the existence of a  clear policy statement against bullying; implementation of existing codes of practice  on inclusive education; staff training sessions on admission issues and on creating a  welcoming school climate; working respectfully and collaboratively with learners  Five Key Messages for Inclusive Education 14                                                                                                                                                                                            and families; strategies to help learners and families to participate actively in the  school community and classroom; and the availability of information, counselling  and advice strategies and their impact on learners.  In conclusion, the broader inclusion debate now seeks to provide high­quality  education – and benefits – for all learners. Strong school performance and equity  can go hand­in­hand.  The education system is complex and fragmented and, at present, lacks coherent  thinking about inclusiveeducation. In general, there is little support for principals  and leaders who may be trying to bring about change in isolated situations. Diversity  is increasing across the system, but the traditions of the past restrict action. Schools’  capability must be developed through context awareness, correspondence  (between legislation and policy/practice), conceptual clarity and a continuum of  support – for all stakeholders – that encourages schools to be proactive rather than  reactive. Getting to know all learners and intervening early will develop quality  support for all learners that it is seen as part of regular education.  Putting Theory into Practice  15                                                                                                                                                            BIBLIOGRAPHY Bennett, S. and Gallagher, T.L., 2012. The Delivery of Education Servicesfor Students who have an Intellectual Disability in the Province of Ontario. Toronto: Community  Living Ontario  Chapman, C., Ainscow, M., Miles, S. and West, M., 2011. Leadership thatpromotes the achievementof students with special educationalneedsand disabilities.  Nottingham: National College for School Leadership  Commission of the European Communities, 2008. Green Paper –Migration & mobility: challengesand opportunitiesfor EUeducation systems. {SEC(2008) 2173}  /* COM/2008/0423 final */ Brussels: Commission of the European Communities  Council of the European Union, 2010. Councilconclusionson the social dimension of education and training. 3013th EDUCATION, YOUTH AND CULTURE Councilmeeting Brussels, 11 May 2010. http://www.consilium.europa.eu/uedocs/cms_Data/docs/pressdata/en/educ/1143  74.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 1999. Financing of SpecialNeeds Education – A seventeen-country Study of the Relationship between Financing of SpecialNeeds Education and Inclusion. Middelfart, Denmark: European  Agency for Development in Special Needs Education  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2002a. Transition from Schoolto Employment. Key Principlesand Recommendationsfor Policy Makers.  Middelfart, Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special Needs  Education. http://www.european­ agency.org/sites/default/files/transition_transition_entext.pdf (Last accessed July  2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2002b. Transition from Schoolto Employment. Main problems, issues and options faced by students with special educationalneedsin 16 European countries. SummaryReport.  Middelfart, Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special Needs  Education. http://www.european­agency.org/sites/default/files/transition­from­ school­to­employment_Transition­en.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2003. Inclusive Education and Classroom Practice. SummaryReport. Odense, Denmark: European  Agency for Development in Special Needs Education. http://www.european­ agency.org/publications/ereports/inclusive­education­and­classroom­ practices/iecp­en.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  Five Key Messages for Inclusive Education 32                                                                                                                                                                                                European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2005. Inclusive Education and Classroom Practice in Secondary Education. SummaryReport.  Odense, Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education.  http://www.european­agency.org/publications/ereports/inclusive­education­and­ classroom­practice­in­secondary­education/iecp_secondary_en.pdf (Last accessed  July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2006. Individual Transition Plans: Supporting the Move from Schoolto Employment. Odense,  Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education.  http://www.european­agency.org/publications/ereports/individual­transition­plans­ supporting­the­move­from­school­to­employment/itp_en.pdf (Last accessed July  2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2009a. Multicultural Diversity and SpecialNeeds Education. Odense, Denmark: European Agency for  Development in Special Needs Education. http://www.european­ agency.org/publications/ereports/multicultural­diversity­and­special­needs­ education/multicultural­diversity­and­special­needs­education (Last accessed July  2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2009b. Key Principles for Promoting Quality in Inclusive Education – Recommendationsfor Policy Makers.  Odense, Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education.  http://www.european­agency.org/publications/ereports/key­principles­for­ promoting­quality­in­inclusive­education/key­principles­EN.pdf (Last accessed July  2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2010. Early Childhood Intervention –Progressand Developments2005–2010. Odense, Denmark:  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education.  http://www.european­agency.org/publications/ereports/early­childhood­ intervention­progress­and­developments/ECI­report­EN.pdf (Last accessed July  2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2011a. Mapping the Implementation of Policy for Inclusive Education: An exploration of challengesand opportunitiesfor developing indicators. Odense, Denmark: European Agency for  Development in Special Needs Education. http://www.european­ agency.org/agency­projects/mapping­the­implementation­of­policy­for­inclusive­ education (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2011b. Teacher Education for Inclusion AcrossEurope – Challengesand Opportunities. Odense,  Putting Theory into Practice  33                                                                                                                                                                                                    Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education.  http://www.european­agency.org/publications/ereports/te4i­challenges­and­ opportunities/te4i­challenges­and­opportunities (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2011c. Key Principles for Promoting Quality in Inclusive Education – Recommendationsfor Practice.  Odense, Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education.  http://www.european­agency.org/publications/ereports/key­principles­for­ promoting­quality­in­inclusive­education­1/Key­Principles­2011­EN.pdf (Last  accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2011d. Participation in Inclusive Education – A Framework for DevelopingIndicators. Odense, Denmark:  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education.  http://www.european­agency.org/publications/ereports/participation­in­inclusive­ education­a­framework­for­developing­indicators/Participation­in­Inclusive­ Education.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2012a. Young Views on Inclusive Education. Odense, Denmark: European Agency for Development in  Special Needs Education. http://www.european­ agency.org/publications/ereports/young­views­on­inclusive­education/YoungViews­ 2012EN.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2012b. Profile of Inclusive Teachers. Odense, Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special  Needs Education. http://www.european­agency.org/agency­projects/Teacher­ Education­for­Inclusion/Profile­of­Inclusive­Teachers.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2012c. Raising Achievementfor All Learners– Quality in Inclusive Education. Reporton the conference held in Odense, Denmark on 13th –15th June 2012. Odense, Denmark:  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education.  http://www.european­agency.org/sites/default/files/RA4AL­conference­report.pdf  (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2012d. Raising Achievementfor All Learners– Quality in Inclusive Education. Odense, Denmark:  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education.  http://www.european­agency.org/publications/ereports/ra4al­synthesis­ report/RA4AL­synthesis­report.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2012e. Promoting Accessible Information for Lifelong Learning: Recommendationsand findingsof the iaccess project. Odense, Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special  Five Key Messages for Inclusive Education 34                                                                                                                                                                          Needs Education. http://www.european­agency.org/publications/ereports/i­ access/i­access­report.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2012f. Vocational Education and Training: Policy and Practice in the field of SpecialNeeds Education – Literature Review. Odense, Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special  Needs Education. http://www.european­agency.org/agency­projects/vocational­ education­and­training/vet­files/VET­LiteratureReview.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2012g. Teacher Education for Inclusion: ProjectRecommendationslinked to Sourcesof Evidence.  Odense, Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education.  http://www.european­agency.org/agency­projects/Teacher­Education­for­ Inclusion/sources­of­evidence.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Development in Special Needs Education, 2013. European and InternationalPolicy Supporting ICTfor Inclusion. Odense, Denmark: European  Agency for Development in Special Needs Education. http://www.european­ agency.org/sites/default/files/european­and­international­policy­supporting­ict­for­ inclusion_policy­supporting­ict­for­inclusion.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  European Agency for Special Needs and Inclusive Education, 2014. Vocational Education and Training – Summary of CountryInformation. Odense, Denmark:  European Agency for Special Needs and InclusiveEducation. http://www.european­ agency.org/sites/default/files/VET Summary of Country information 2014.pdf (Last  accessed July 2014)  Farrell, P., Dyson, A.S., Polat, F., Hutcheson, G. and Gallannaugh, F., 2007. ‘SEN  inclusion and pupil achievement in English schools’ Journalof Research in Special EducationalNeeds, 7(3), 172–178  Frilseth, L., 2012. The Norwegian Modelfor Education for Allin Upper Secondary School. Norwegian Directorate for Education and Training. http://www.european­ agency.org/agency­projects/ra4al/ra4al­seminar­pdf/Norway­L­Frilseth.pdf (Last  accessed July 2014)  Fullan, M., 2011. Change Leader: Learning to do whatmattersmost. San Francisco:  Jossey­Bass  de Graaf, G., van Hove, G. and Haveman, M., 2011. ‘More academics in regular  schools? The effect of regular versus special school placement on academic skills in  Dutch primary school students with Down syndrome’ Journalof International Disability Research, December 2011, 57(1), 21–38. doi: 10.1111/j.1365­ 2788.2011.01512.x  Putting Theory into Practice  35                                                                                                                                                                                                            Hargreaves, A. and Shirley, D., 2009. The Fourth Way –The inspiring future for educationalchange. Joint publication with Ontario Principals’ Council and National  Staff Development Council. Thousand Oaks, CA: Corwin Press  Kalambouka, A., Farrell, P., Dyson, A. and Kaplan, I., 2005. The impactof population inclusivity in schoolson studentoutcomes. Research Evidence in Education Library.  London: EPPI­Centre, Social Science Research Unit, Instituteof Education, University  of London  Kyriazopoulou, M. and Weber, H. (editors), 2009. Developmentof a set of indicators – for inclusive education in Europe. Odense, Denmark: European Agency for  Development in Special Needs Education. http://www.european­ agency.org/publications/ereports/development­of­a­set­of­indicators­for­inclusive­ education­in­europe/Indicators­EN­with­cover.pdf (Last accessed July 2014)  MacArthur, J., 2009. Learning Better Together: Workingtowardsinclusive education in New Zealand schools. Wellington: IHC  MacArthur, J., Kelly, B., Sharp, S. & Gaffney, M., 2005. Participation or exclusion? Disabled children’sexperiencesof life at school. A paper presented at the Children’s  Issues Conference, Dunedin, New Zealand, July 2005  Menter, I., Hulme, M., Elliott, D. and Lewin, J., 2010. Literature Review on Teacher Education in the 21st Century. Scottish Government Social Research. Edinburgh:  Scottish Government  Organisation for Economic Co­operation and Development, 2011. PISA in Focus. Improving Performance: Leading from the Bottom. 2011/2 (March). Paris: OECD  Redley, M., 2009. ‘Understanding the social exclusion and stalled welfare of citizens  with learning disabilities’ Disability & Society, 24(4), 489–501  UNESCO Institute for Information Technologies in Education and European Agency  for Development in Special Needs Education, 2011. ICTsin Education for People with Disabilities: Review of innovative practice. Moscow: UNESCO Institute for  Information Technologies in Education. http://www.european­ agency.org/publications/ereports/ICTs­in­Education­for­People­With­ Disabilities/Review­of­Innovative­Practice (Last accessed July 2014)  United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization, 2009. Policy Guidelines on Inclusion in Education. Paris: UNESCO  United Nations, 2006. Convention on the Rights of Personswith Disabilities. New  York: United Nations  Watkins, A. (editor), 2007. Assessmentin Inclusive Settings: Key Issues for Policy and Practice. Odense, Denmark: European Agency for Development in Special Needs  Five Key Messages for Inclusive Education 36                                                      Education. http://www.european­agency.org/publications/ereports/assessment­in­ inclusive­settings­key­issues­for­policy­and­practice/assessment­in­inclusive­ settings­key­issues­for­policy­and­practice (Last accessed July 2014)  Wilkinson, R. and Pickett, K., 2010. The SpiritLevel: Why Equality is Better for Everyone. London: Penguin  Willms, J.D., 2006. Learning divides: Ten policy questionsaboutthe performance and equity of schoolsand schooling systems. Montreal: UNESCO Institutefor Statistics  World Health Organization/World Bank, 2011. World Reporton Disability. Geneva:  WHO Press. http://www.who.int/disabilities/world_report/2011/en/index.html  (Last accessed July 2014)  Putting Theory into Practice  37  6 Political Aspects of Social Inclusion – What Are Inclusive Policies? 6 1. Etzioni, Amitai. 2001. The Third Way to a Good Society. Center for Communitarian Policy Studies of The George Washington University, Washington, DC. 2. Bates, Peter and Fabian A. Davis. 2004. “Social Capital, Social Inclusion and Services for People with Learning Disabilities.”Disability and Society 19 (3): 195-207. THE THIRD WAY TO A GOOD SOCIETYl Amitai EtzioniW Abstract TheThird Waydebatehas,sofar, not beenvery successful.Whilegovernmentsacross theworld searchfor a newpolitical synthesis,thetheoretical debatehasofferedlittle to those interested in a newframework for progressive politics. This essaypresentsan account ofwhat the Third Wayreally means,and roots it in a communitarianvision of thegoodsociety.It arguesthatsuchsocietiesachievea dynamicbalancebetweenstate, market and community, and blends theoretical discussion with the practical implications ofsuch an approach.At the core oftheanalysisis theideathat the Third Wayis an ethical position that seeksto treat people as endsin themselves.While flexibility andpragmatism are important to thenewpolitics, theyshouldbe understood as componentsofa broaderframework, in which socialprogress is measuredby more than theaccumulation ofmaterial goods.How dowe managedevolutionsuccessfully? Whatapproach shouldgovernmenttaketoinequality? Whatis theproper relationship betweenrights andresponsibilities? Theessayilluminates theseandother issues,and callsfor a broad-ranging moral dialogue to addressthem. The GoodSociety:First Principles TheVision We need a clearer vision of where the Third Way is taking us. While debateson improvementsto public programs or legal structuresfascinate some,mostpeopleare not interested in technocraticdetails. Theyyearn for a vision of wherewe are headed, one that provides a way of assessingpastaccomplishmentsandplans for the future. Sucha vision inspiresandcompels;it lendsmeaningto ourendeavorsandsacrifices,to our lives. We aspireto a society that is not merely civil but is alsogood. A good societyis one in which people treat one another as ends in themselves and not merely as instruments; aswhole personsratherthan asfragments; asmembersof a community, bonded by ties of affection and commitment, ratherthan only as employees,traders, consumersor evenas fellow citizens. In the terms of the philosopherMartin Buber,a good society nourishes 'I-Thou' relations, although it recognizesthe inevitable and significant role of 'I-It' relations. Some core values of a good society canbe directly derived from its definition. Child abuse, spousal abuse, violent crime in general imd of course civil and international war offend thebasicprinciple of treating peopleasends.Hence,our love of peace. Furthermore,we hold that violating individual autonomy,unlessthere are strongcompelling public needs,is incompatiblewith treatingpeopleasends.This isthe ultimate foundation of our commitmentto liberty. .Amitai Etzioni is University ProfessorandDirector of the Centerfor Communitarian Policy Studiesof The GeorgeWashington University, Washington,DC. 5 Whenwe find value in creatingor appreciatingart,musicandotherexpressionsof culture, orengagein learning for its own sake,we typically are in the realmof ends.In contrast,whenwe trade in theseitemswe are in the instrumentalrealm, which is quite legitimate, aslong as it doesnot intrude on, let alone dominate,thatof ends. Whenwe bond with family, friends or community memberswe live upto thebasic principle of thegoodsociety.Thevaluesof love, loyalty, caringandcommunity allfind their roots here. In contrast,whenwe 'network' -bonding for a utilitarian purpose rather for its own sake-we abandonthis realm. The relationship of the basic principle to socialjustice is a complex one. The priority of treating peopleasendsrequiresmore than equality of opportunity but less than equality of outcomes; it denotesa rich basic minimum for all. Still othervalues arisemore indirectly, we shall see,outof moraldialogues.Theseseekto limit conflict and cultural wars and put a premium on reaching sharedunderstandings-a major attribute of good societies. The ethicaltenetthatpeopleareto betreatedaspurposesratherthanoQlyasmeans is commonly recognized. Less widely accepted is the significant sociological observationthat it is in communities,not in the realmof the statenor the market,that this tenetis bestinstitutionalized. Equally pivotal is the recognition thatonly in a societywhereno oneis excluded, and all aretreatedwith equalrespect,areall peopleaccordedthestatusof beingendsin themselvesand allowed to reach their full human potential. Furthermore,the core communitarian idea -that we have inalienable individual rights and social responsibilities for each other -is based on the samebasic principle: we are both entitled to be treated as ends in ourselves and are required to treat others and our communities in this way. The good societyis onethatbalancesthree often partially incompatible elements: the state,the market,andthe community. This is theunderlying logic of the statements above.The good societydoes not seekto obliterate thesesegmentsbut to keepthem properly nourished-and contained. Similarly, muchhasbeenmadealreadyof the fact thattheThird Way(neueMitte, centrist approach, communitarian thinking) does not view the government as the problem or asthe solution but asone partnerof the good society. Nor does it seethe marketasa sourceof all that is good or evil but asa powerful economic engine that mustbe accordedsufficient spaceto do its work while alsoguardedproperly. Different Third Way societies still struggle with finding the proper point of balance.The continentalsocietiesstill havealong wayto gotowardcurtailing thestate and allowing the market to function properly. The United States may well have overshotthe point of balance by according the market too much space.The United Kingdom andHolland might be drawing closerto the point of balance.Germanyand aboveall Franceare still reliant onthebig state.However,thethird partnerof thegood society-the community -has not beengivenits propershareof the social division of labor in all Third Way societies. The vision of agood societyis a tableauonwhich we project our aspirations,nota full checklistof all thatdeservesourdedication.And the vision is oftenreformulatedas the world aroundus changes,andaswe change.Moreover, it points to different steps that different societiesbestundertake,dependingon theirplace onthe Third Way. But the ultimate vision is oneandthe same. I; The good society is 'an ideal. While we may never quite reach it, it guides our endeavors,andwe measureourprogressby it. 2 The Third Way The Third Wayis a road that leadsus toward thegoodsociety. However, it should be acknowledged atthe outsetthatthe Third Way is indeedfuzzy atthe edges,not fully etched.As TheEconomist (1998)wrote aboutthe Third Way: 'Trying to pin down an exactmeaning is like wrestling aninflatable man.If you geta grip onone limb, all the hot air rushesto another.' ProfessorStevenTeles (n.d.) of Brandeis University has calledtheThird Way' a masterworkof ambiguity'. But this is oneof the mainvirtuesof this approach: it points to the directions that we ought to follow, but is neither doctrinaire nor an ideological rigid system. The Third Way is not American, British or the property of any other nation or region or culture. Among its numerousorigins arethe Old andthe New Testament;the teachingsof the Ancient Greeks;Asian, Muslim and Jewishconceptionsof harmony and responsibility for others thanself; Fabianthinking; Catholic socialthought; and much else? The Third Way hasoftenbeendepictedin negativeterms,in termsof thatwhich it is not. It is correctly stated as neither a road paved by statist socialism nor one underpinned by the neoliberalismof the free market. It tilts neitherto the right nor to the left. (In the US -which hashadno significant socialist tradition -the Third Way runs betweena New Deal conceptionof big state,which administerslarge-scalesocial programs and extensively regulatesthe economy, and a libertarian or laissezfaire unfettered market:) Here, an attempt is made to furnish it with a positive and normative characterization as a:public philosophy that both provides principles and points to public policy implications. Above all,we suggestchangespeoplewill haveto introduce into their own ways of conductand their institutions. Is thereoneThird Way ormultiple Third Ways?While somesocietiesdrive more in the left lane (France,Italy) andsomemore in the right (the United States),the road they all travel is fully distinct from the one charted by totalitarian and libertarian approaches.Moreover, while the various Third Way societies differ in their specific synthesisof theways of the stateandthe market,theyarepulling closerto oneanother. Much has been written aboutthe needto find a way that will allow European economiesto compete globally but not becomeAmericanized; to enhanceeconomic flexibility and productivity but not yield all to the service of mammon;to develop a new European social model. Much of what follows addressesthese questions by focusing ontwo keyissues:therole of community ontheThird Wayandtheneedto set clear limits on how far one oughtto tilt in the American direction. 7 The Rolesof the Cornrnunity 2The NeglectedPartner 2. CommunitiesdefinedCommunities arethe main socialentitiesthatnourishends-based(I-Thou) relationships,while the market is the realm of means-based(I-It) relationships. The state-citizen relationshipalsotendsto the instrumental. True,somepeoplebond at work, andsome barter in communities, but by and large without communities a deficit in ends-basedrelati is sureto bepronounced.As JohnGray(1996: 16)putit: 'The flourishing of individuals presupposes strong and deep forms of common life. ' In short, communities area major componentof good societies. The conceptof community is often saidto be vague and elusive. This chargeis alsomadeagainstotherwidely usedconceptssuchasclass,elites and evenrationality. Communities, in my understanding,are based on two foundations, both of which reinforce I-Thou relationships. First, communitiesprovide bondsof affection thatturn groups of people into social entities resembling extended families. Second, they transmit a sharedmoral culture (a setof sharedsocial meanings and values, which characterize that which the community considers virtuous versus unacceptable behavior) from generationto generation,aswell asreformulating this moral framework day by day. Thesetraits define anddifferentiate communities. While in earlier eras, and to some extent today, communities were largely residential (membershipwas geographicallydefined,as in villages), this i&now often not the case.Contemporary communities evolve amongmembers of one profession working for the sameinstitution (for example,thephysiciansof a given hospital orthe faculty of a college); membersof an ethnic or racial group evenif dispersedamong others(a Jewishcommunity oroneof Bangladeshiimmigrants in eastLondon); people who sharea sexualorientation; or intellectualsof the samepolitical or cultural feather. Somecommunities arequite large,and in part imagined; for instance,many gay men visiting anotherpart of the country know socially somepeoplewho live thereand feel closeto others they meetthere for the first time. Groups that merely sharea specific interest-to preventthe internet from being taxed orto reducethecostsof postage-are solelyan interestgrouporlobby. They lack the affective bonds and sharedculture that make communities into places that truly involve people ratherthan focusing ona narrow facetof their lives. Critics correctly point out thatcommunitiesarenot necessarilyplacesofbrotherly and sisterly love; they may be oppressive,intolerant, nasty. This is largely true of communities in earlier eras. In democratic societies,people often choose which communities to join and participate in, making communities as a rule less overpowering. While evencontemporarycommunities are far from perfect,the same obviously holds for the stateandthe market. We must stopcomparing existing social entities to somevisionary utopia and askinsteadhow they canbe improved. And we mustrecognizethat eachof the threepartnersis better(not necessarilygood) atsome tasks than the others. Communities are often overlooked as a very important social factor evenby Third Way advocates,who tendto focus onseekingthe properbalance betweenthe stateandthe market.4In a well balancedsocietyall three complementand containoneanother. 8 Therelative advantage 6fcommunities The specialcapacityof communitiesto moveustowardthegood societyis highlighted by the finding that people who live in communities live longer, healthier and more contentlives thanpeople who arebereft of suchmembership.Theyare likely to have significantly fewerpsychosomaticillnessesand mentalhealthproblemsthanthosewho live in isolation. And, with their craving for sociality well sated,community members are muchless likely to join violent gangs,religious cults or militias. The fact that social isolation is dangerousfor mental healthwas highlighted in 1955 during the first mission to establisha US base in Antarctica, where isolation provoked paranoid psychosis (Stuster 1996: 8). Since then, numerousstudies have shownthat isolation significantly increasesvarious psychologicalhealthrisks.5In their classic study of New Yorkers lonely in high-rise apartments,Mental Health in the Metropolis, Leo Srole andhis associates(1962)found that 60percentof the residents had sub-clinical psychiatric conditions and 20 percentwere judged psychologically impaired. Numerousstudieshavedemonstratedthat,afterwork-related stress,the most important socialfactor in mentalhealthis marital, familial andfriendshiprelationships (Walz 1994: 56-57). Elderly people who live alone,have no friends, or have poor relationships with their children are 60 percentmore likely to developdementiathan thosewhose social contactsaremore satisfying,accordingto a studypublished by the medicaljournal TheLancet (Fratiglioni 2000). Communities, datashows,canplaya majorrole inproviding preventiveandacute care,reducing the need for publicly funded socialservicesas divergent aschild care, grief counsellingandprofessionaldrugandalcoholabusetreatment,aswell asassisting in curtailing juvenile delinquency. The strongestevidencefor thesestatementsis found inreligious communities that meetmy definition of sharedaffective bondsanda moralculture. Practically all kinds of anti-social behavior are relatively low among Mormon communities in Utah, Orthodox Jewishcommunities in New York, and Black Muslim groups.Theyarealso lower, on average,in villages and small-town America as comparedto large cities, where communities are lessprevalent. There are scoresof studies similar to the ones summarizedhere that highlight communities' important role. Patrols of volunteers,called OrangeHats,chaseddrug dealersout of their neighborhood in Washington,DC. In the process,membersof the community alsobecamecloserto oneanother. In 1988, Wellsburg, West Virginia, had a particularly high incidence of heart disease -29 percent above the national average. By 1996, the community's cardiovascular health profile was among the best in the state,according to a study conductedbyMary Lou Hurley andLisa Schiff. The improvementreflectedcommunity organizedwalks, healthypotluck suppersandnumerousclassesinaerobicsandways to reducecholesterol,blood pressureandstress.A screeningof 182communitymembers found that they had maintained their weight loss and most of the reduction in cholesterol and blood pressure.According to the researchers,'the averagewellness score ...topped the 1988baseline by 12 percentand the averagefitness score by 42 percent' (Hurley & Shiff 1996). In the county of Tillamook, Oregon, diverse community groups, including religious and liberal ones,decidedto collaborate onthe problemof teenagepregnancy, leading to a decreasefrom twenty-four pregnancies per thousand girls age ten to seventeenin 1990to sevenperthousandin 1994(Luke & Neville 1998). 9 Theseare buta few illustrative findings. Aside from significantly reducingpublic costs,communalprovisions suchastheseare often muchmore individually tailoredth public programsand canbe made muchlessalienating than governmentaction. Ergo, next For all thesereasons,cultivating communitieswherethey exist,andhelping themform where they have been lost, is essentialfor future provision of much social good; it should be a major priority for future progressalong the Third Way. In the next yearscommunities should be increasinglyrelied uponto shouldera greatershareof those socialmissions that mustbe undertaken,because-to reiteratecommunities can do so at a much lower public costand with greaterhumanity than either the state or the market. In effect, communitiesmaywell be the most important newsource ofsocial servicesin theforeseeablefuture, asthe ability to increasetaxes topayfor social servicesis nearly exhausted;and thetotal costswill continueto rise at rates higher thaninflation.6 Seeking much greaterreliance on communities is not an attemptto replace the welfare state.Onthe contrary,byreducingthe burdenonthewelfare state,communities help sustainit. Existing public policies andproceduresshouldbereviewedregularlyto ensurethat the renewalandmaintenanceof existing communitiesis not inadvertentlyundermined (for example,bypreempting their naturalroles)andthatthesepolicies andprocedures opportune community developmentona local, regionaland societallevel. To fostercommunitiestheprime minister may call onall ministersto provide him annually with reportsonstepsto involve communitiesmore in their work; community 'audits' could further assesswherethereis room for greatercommunity involvement; and statistics oughtto be published regularly aboutprogressin the neededdirection. However, experienceshows that suchmeasuresare much more effective if they are represented,symbolically and in practice, by high profile institutions. This strongly suggests that one should create a special division within a suitable ministry (for example,the Home Office or the Departmentfor the Environment, Transportandthe Regions) or better yet, createa new ministry dedicatedto community development. While critics are likely to complain aboutcentralism,forming somekind of permanent taskforce for community development in a government departmentwould further reinforce this important mission. Much hasbeenmade in recentyears aboutthe newways through which the state might projectitself. It hasbeensaidit shouldbean'enabler' anda 'catalyst' ratherthan itself directing andfinancing socialprograms.This postrnodernmanagementis saidto be flat rather than hierarchical; based on networking rather than directive; serving public goals indirectly via the market. A good part of this is true, and needs no repeatinghere.Someof it is over-hyped;the managementstyle mostsuited for social work may not bethe samefor building a destroyerand so on. Above all, Third Way management styles must be tailored not merely to take into account various combinations of the stateandthe market but alsoto involve communities. 10 2.2 MutualityandVoluntaryAssociations A good societyrelies evenmore onmutuality than onvoluntarism. MutUalityis a form of community relationship in which people help eachotherratherthan merelyhelping thosein need.7TheNeighborhoodWatchschemeandanti-crimepatrols(by community volunteers) suchas in Balsall Heath in Birmingham, where crime wasreducedby six citizen teams regularly patrolling the streets (Leadbeater 1997), are examples of mutuality. Soareconsumerandproducercooperatives,like LocalFoodBuying Groups and mutual saving associationssuchas credit unions (Leadbeater& Martin 1998). Fostering Tenant ManagementAssociations in council estatesrather than relying mainly on governmentor profit-making managementis anothercasein point. Mutuality-based associationshave always existed and have beenon the rise in recentyears. Still, theyneedto be much expanded,encouraged,andfurbishedwith the neededresourcesin orderto carrymore of the socialburdensin the yearsto come. Mutuality is commonly and naturally practiced among family members,friends, neighbours,colleaguesand membersof voluntary associations.It canbean important sourceof child care(suchasin parentcooperatives,where parentsprovide a few hours of service each week, thereby reducing public costs and providing natural staff accountability); sick care (for instance, when people are discharged 'early' from hospitalsto behelpedby kin and othercommunity members);grief support;andmuch else. Mutual-help groups (oddly often called self-help groups)canplaya major role coping with cancer,contagiousdiseases,alcoholism, obesityandthelike (probablythe best known is the highly successfulAlcoholics Anonymous -Wuthnow 1994: 71). Theyarea vastlyunderusedresource.In the new century,public services,especiallythe National Health Service and welfare agencies, should greatly increase efforts highlighting the value of such groups, as well as help prime them and provide resources. It must, however, ensure that its role in initiating and conducting these groupsdoesnot sapthesegroups' naturalcommunalflows or stunttheirdevelopment. Mutuality is undermined when treated like an economic exchangeof services. (Undermining occurs,for example,whengovernmentspayfriendsto befriendsassome countriesdoto ensurethatsomeonevisits andinformally assiststhosedischargedfrom hospitals.) Mutuality is based on an open-ended moral commitment. In mutual relationships, people do not keep books on each other but have a generalized expectation that the other will do his or her turn if and when a need arises.Public policies and arrangementsthat attemptto organize mutuality asif it wereanexchange will tend to undermine this moral foundation. Examples of suchpolicies are 'time banks', in which hours spentbaby sitting, for example, are recordedand the same amountof hours in voluntary serviceare expectedin return, or establishingprograms like used clothing exchanges, in which the amount of clothes one contributes determinesthe amountonereceivesfrom the exchange.Much looser,more informal 'arrangements' -of the kind that prevail among people who 'exchange' gifts -are preferred. At the same time, posting on a website or other public place the time contributions various membersof a community have made,asonedoesfor financial donations,may help foster suchcontributions. To favQrmutuality is notto make light of voluntarism. Indeed,it shouldbe further encouraged.A good start in this direction are Chancellor Gordon Brown's policies encouraginga spirit of voluntarismandcivic patriotism. His measuresincludematching peoplewho wantto offer theirtime andmoneythrough voluntary work with charitable and voluntary organizationsseekingvolunteers,via a dedicatedwebsite. Theimportanceof voluntarismfor community building,civic spiritanddemocratic governmenthasbeensetout manytimes andrequiresno repetition. It shouldbe noted, however,that severalThird Way societies,especiallyonthe continent,still havealong way to go before voluntarism is properly developedand canassumeits shareof the socialbusinessthat mustbe conducted. Voluntarism is bestcarried out, wheneverpossible,in the servicelearningmode. Service learning is a form of voluntarism in which thosewho servedo not maintain they areacting purely through altruism but insteadacknowledgethat theythemselves benefit educationallyandsocially from theirexperience.It is especiallycompatiblewith the idealof treatingpeopleasends,although all forms of voluntarismarepreferableto pure means-basedrelationships. The questionoftenarises:who will beableto provide moretime for mutualityand voluntarism, given thatmoreandmore women,who usedto bea majorsourceof both, are now in paid employment? One answer may well be seniorcitizens. They are a rapidly growing class;live longerandhealthierlives than theirpredecessors;consumea growing proportion of the societalresources;andwould greatly benefit from staying involved in pro-socialroles. Without their contribution, societiesmaywell notbeable to attendto a large andgrowing portion of its socialbusiness. While eachmemberof everycommunity oughtto bebothrequiredandexpectedto make contributions to the common good above and beyond that of their own community (for instance,by paying taxesdue in full), theyshouldbe allowed,indeed encouraged,to provide 'extras' for their own community. Hence, it is crucial for communities to befree to levy someform of fees,duesortaxesabovethoselevied by the state.Parentsshouldbewelcomed whentheycontribute services,moneyandassets to their children's schools rather than be expected to put their resourcesinto an anonymouspot from which all schools may draw. Ethically, it is too heroic to expect thatpeople will be willing to do for one and all as muchas they arewilling to do for their own communities. And limiting contributions to universalpots is incompatible with a society thatviews communities as essential,constitutive socialentities. At the sametime communitiesshouldbeencouragedto careaboutthefateof other communities;for example,better-off communitiesshouldbeexpectedto helpthoseless endowed.To the extentthey assisttheir sistercommunities,the affluentonescould be celebratedandgiven taxbenefits.Specialleviescould bededicatedto specific projects, making themmore readily acceptedthan increasesin generaltaxes. Much more realistic and valuable programs are regional ones, in which communities helpone anotherwith arrangementsthatvary fromrapid transitsystemto coordinating police efforts, from building highways andbridgesto sharinganairport. These sharing arrangementsare often quite properly touted as enhancing efficiency (indeed many would not be possible without regional collaboration). However, they often -although by no means always -do serve as somewhat indirect forms of reallocation of resources,asthe better-off communities pick up a largershareof the coststhan the other ones,or the lessendowedonesreapadisproportionatepart of the benefitsgenerated. 12 2.3 Pro-communityPublicPolicies Community renewalcanbeenhancedbyproviding occasionsfor socialgatherings(for example, opening schools for community meetings; fostering neighborhood street festivals). Temporary organizerscanbeassignedto anareato initiate groupformations. And community renewalbenefitsfrom improving the physical conditions,safety,and accessibility of public spaces.(Foracompelling example,seethe discussionof schools as community hubs in Bentley 1998and Jupp 1999.) Renewalis alsofosteredbyinviting groupsof peoplesharingtheuseof a property, area or public service to participate in decision-making regarding its use. Examples include citizens settingthe hoursa park is open,who mayuse it (children and dogs?) and for what purposes(public assemblyor communing with nature?).More support mustbe given to groupsof citizenslike thosewho setparkopeningtimesandbylaws in the Phoenix Community ParknearCharingCrossRoad in centralLondon(Warpole & Greenhalgh 1997). Calling on such groups to assume some responsibility for maintaining sharedfacilities can further enhancebonds among the members.Major benefits can be achieved if peoplearehelpedto form shopping coops,mutual saving andloan associations,andotherformsof economicorganizationthatparallelandhence enforce communal bonds. For communities to flourish, public policies must take into account that often communities' boundariesdo not conform to administrative ones.Theseboundaries should be tailored to the communities' lines ratherthan attemptto makecommunities adhereto a presetadministrative geography. In addition,public policies needto betailoredto smallersocialunitsthanare often encompassedin one administrative district, becausecommunities are often smaller. This applies to policies such as the New Deal for Communities, aimed at smaller neighbourhoods of 2-5,000 people, and the National Strategy for Neighborhood Renewal. The reorganization of core social policy programs around smaller neighbourhoodunits is anongoingpriority. Increaseddevolution allows more citizens to participate in their own government,becomemore politically engaged,andincrease their civic skill andeffect. For instance,neighborhoodofficersentrustedwith patrolling local areasfor deteriorating facilities, environmentalproblemsand socialconflicts can be helpful especiallyif electedratherthan appointed,andif theirpriorities are seteither solely by the affected communities or at leastin close consultationwith them. Policy-makersshouldtakeinto accountthatcommunitiesneednotbe residentialor include members who live next to one another. Communities can form around institutions (universities, hospitals)orprofessions(longshoremen,accountants).They are often ethnically basedand canevenform in cyberspace(virtual communities).Best results are achieved when communities that already share social bonds are further reinforced by providing them with accessto a sharedonline 'wired' space. Thriving communities often need core institutions such as local schools, courthouses,postoffices and downtownshoppingareas.Undersomeconditions, such as when an area has been largely depopulated, it might make senseto yield to considerations of economic and administrative efficiency and consolidate or 'regionalize' such institutions or allow downtown shopping to be replaced by supermalls. However, sucheconomicandadministrative efficiencies should neverbe consideredthe only relevantconsiderations.To put it differently, aThird Way society gives much weight to social costs that include costs resulting from the loss of 13 community when its core institutions are shut down. Only when non-socialconsidera clearly outweigh socialonesshouldcore institutions, the mainstaysof community, be closed. 2.4 CommunitySafety Policies that seek to sustain or renew communities must take into account that communities are formed and reinforced large)y in public spacesrather than in the privacy of one's home. To the extent that these spacesare unsafe or depleted, communities are diminished. Therefore, communities should take special care to maintain public playgrounds, sidewalks,pedestrianwalkways, parks andplazas. For non-residentialcommunitiesthis might entailproviding meetingspacesin, for instance, public schools or libraries; setting aside segmentsof public parks for picnics; and providing group-based transportation, such as vans that bring senior citizens or handicappedpeopleto daycenters. Public safety and community welfare benefit from the introduction of 'thick' communitypolicing thatentails muchmorethanmerelygettingcopsoutof theircarsto walk the beat.This involves the community in settingpriorities for the police and in overseeingtheir conduct.And it requiresinvolving thepolice in conflict resolutionand in the protection of the overall quality of life.8 All future building, street,neighborhood and town planning should provide for enhancedpublic safetyandcommunitybuilding. Among thenumerouspossibilities are wider sidewalks,porchesthatabutsidewalks,gatesthatblocktraffic but notpedestrians and muchmore. (The British experiment in modem tower-block building during the 1970's which decimated communities that had existed in many working class neighborhoodsparallels similar calamitousprojects in the United States.) Currently in the UK there is no dutyto inform localresidentsaboutrepeatsexual offenders released into a community. When pedophiles, who have a very high recidivism rate,arereleasedfrom jail andmoveinto a neighbourhood,thereshouldbea dutyto inform communities. At the sametime,communitiesshouldbewarned against harassingtheseoffenders. (While sucha combination maysound utopian, it hasbeen approximated in the US stateof Washington.) Criminals who have paid their duesto society,served their sentencesand led a legitimate life without any new arrests for ten years should have their rights fully restoredand their recordssequestered.Suchrecordswould be reopenedbefore sentencingonly if they have beenreconvicted. In this way a good society can foster repentance,leading to full restoration of former criminals to membership in the community. Restorativejustice, especiallyfor non-violentfirst-time offenders,servesthesame purpose.This practice requiresoffendersto meetwith their victims in the presenceof third parties from the community. In the process,offenders learn aboutthe victims' suffering,expresstheir regrets,andmakeamends.The goalis to mix punishmentwith rehabilitation, and to keeptheseoffenders asintegratedmembersof the community (Clear & Karp 1999). 3 Moral Culture andits Institutions 3.The Powerof theMoralCultureof Communities The primary socialrole of communitiesis often seento beits fosteringof interpersonal bonding, ratherthan its provision of moral culture. However, bothhavean important role in nourishing I-Thou relationshipsand in undertaking important socialfunctions. While community bondingsatisfiesaprofound humanneed,moral culture canserveto enhancesocial order significantly while reducing the needfor state intervention in social behavior.Oneshouldnot allow legitimateambivalenceaboutthe moralvoicesof communities (which will beaddressedshortly)to overwhelmtheirtremendouspotential contributions to good forms of socialorder. There are clearly someforms of behavior thata good societyconsidersanathema and must seekto curb (suchasdamagingthe environment,domesticviolence, neglect of children, selling liquor and cigarettes to minors). The moral culture of the community helpsto define suchbehaviors.Most importantly, the community's ability to draw onsubtleand informal processesof social regulation, suchasapprobationand censure,is much more compatible with ends-basedrelations than relying on the coercive powers of the state. Extensive studies have demonstratedthat theseprocessesplaya-major role in curbing drug abuse,preventingpettycrime andviolation of the environment,andmuch else(Luke & Neville 1998).Aside from curbing anti-social behavior,the moralculture of communitiescanalso fostergood conduct,including attendingto one's childrenand elders,paying taxes,volunteeringandmanyotherpro-socialactivities (Sampson1997). While one should not exaggerate the role that community forms of social regulation play in reducing serious crime, the considerablesuccessof those already implemented shows both the value of mobilizing communities on the side of social order and one way thesereductionscan be achievedmuchmore extensivelythan has beendoneso far. Oneof the mainvirtues of drawing onthe informal regulationof communitiesto fosterpro-socialbehavioris thatfew if anypublic costsareexacted,andsuchprocesses are muchmore sensitiveto subtle individual differences than official programs.9 Third Way governments do best when they resist the rush to legislate good behavior. Whenthere is a valid needto modify behavior,the stateshouldrealize that relying on informal community-basedprocessesis preferableto relying onthe law.10 Third Way governmentsshould realize that legislation often numbs the moral conscience.When legislationis introduced in placeswhere amoralculture doesexist, the result frequently will be to diminish the moral voices of the community. For example,if the governmentwereto rule thatalcoholicsattendAA meetingsorfacejail sentences,suchmeetings would be far less effective than those in which attendees participatebecauseof their own innermotivationsandthe encouragementof thoseclose to them. We have also learned from attempts to suppress divorce, abortions and consumption of alcohol by law that such policies tend to backfire and should be avoided,whetheror notoneopposesthesebehaviors.Oneshouldhavefaith in faith; the shortestline to pro-social conduct,whateveroneconsiderssuchconductto be,entails convincing people of the merits of the moral claims we lay on them. The law best 15 follows newsharedmoralunderstandingsratherthantrying to leadthem.TheAmerican Prohibition is a telling casestudyof what happenswhenthis point is ignored. This is not to suggestthatthere is no room for legislation concerning moral and social issues.However, it is far better for informal socialprocessesto underpinprosocial behavior than for the police, courts, and inspectorsto do so. And laws that supplementand help sustainmoral cultures will be more effective and humanethan those that try to takethe lead. The differencebetween'naked' laws (not precededor backedby moral commitments)and 'well-covered' oneshas major implications for public leadersand politicians. Leadershavetwo ratherdistinctroles. One,oftenunderscored,isto prepare legislationandbuild supportfor it amongthe legislators.The otherratherdifferentand less well understood role is to build up and change the moral culture. They best combine both attributes and lead with moral persuasionbefore they call on the legislature. Suchleaderscan carry their societymuch further along the Third Way. 3.2 imiting the Powerof Communities While the moralculturesof communitiesarea majorwellspring for constructingagood society,community-basedmorality itself needsto bescrutinizedby membersaswell as outsideobservers.Onemethodis to assessthe community's moral culture by drawing onsharedsocietalvaluesasenshrinedin thebasiclaws orthe constitutionof the state. Communities mustbecontainedandbalanced,just like all the otherelementsthatmake for a good society.11 While onemaydiffer aboutspecifics,inprinciple no communitycanbefully relied upon to determine that which is right and wrong. For example, should immigrant communities be allowed to arrangemarriages evenif there is a large agedifference betweenthecoupleandconsentis doubtful? Shouldfemale circumcision orchild labor be tolerated?Theseare not questions over which communities should havethe final say,as they concernbasichumanrights. Communities in earlier ages,and evensomein contemporaryfree societies,have oppressedindividuals andminorities. It istherole of thestateto protectthe rightsof all members in all communities as well as those of outsiders present within the communities' confines. Thus,no community should be allowed to violate the right to free speech,assemblyand so on of anyone -whether they are members,visitors, passers-byorotherwise.Any notion thatcommunitiescanberelied uponasthe soleor final arbitratorof morality falls apartwith thesimple observationthata communitymay reach100percentconsensusin discriminating againstsomepeopleonthebasis.of race. This vision of contained yet thriving communities is not farfetched. Numerous communities existwithin democraticsocietiesthatabideby theirconstitutionsorbasic laws. The rules that contain communities may be further extended or curtailed as constitutionsare modified, but thebasicprinciple is the same:unfetteredcommunities are no better than unfettered markets or states. A good society achievesa balance through mutual containment of its core elements;the community is not exempted. However, the fact that communities can get out of hand should not be used as an argumentagainstcommunities perse.Like medicine,food and drink, if takenin good measurecommunities are essentialelementsof the good life; if takento excess,they can destroyit. 16 3.3 RightsandResponsibilities Somepeople championindividual andhumanrights andcivil libertiesasanunbounded principle, to which exceptionsareto be tolerated only under very specialconditions; others demand that people live up to their duties (whether prescribed by state or church), with very little concernfor their rights. At the coreof the Third Way oughttobe the recognition that a good society combines respect for individual rights and fulfillment of basic humanneedswith the expectationthat memberslive up to theirrespon to themselves,their family and friends,andto the community atlarge. Oneof the greatestachievementsof the communitarianapproachhasbeencurbingthe languageof rights thathasturned everywant and interestinto a legal entitlement, fostering unnecessarylitigiousness.12While this is largely anAmericanmalaise,in the UK compensationclaims have risen exponentially in the past ten years. In the US 'rights talk', which fosters a disregard of social responsibility, was dominant in the 1980's, in the daysof rampantindividualism. Today, it hasbeenlargelyreplaced by a wide recognition that both individual rights and social responsibilities must be respected(Giddens 1998;Etzioni 1993). What exactlyis meantby 'rights and responsibilities'? Basic individual rights are inalienable, just asone's socialobligations cannotbe denied. However, it is a grave moral error to arguethatthereare 'no rights without responsibilities' or vice versa.13 Thus, people who evadetaxes,neglect their children or fail to live upto their social responsibilities in someotherwayare still entitled to a fair trial, free speech,and other basicrights. The numberof basicrights we shouldhavemaybe debated,butthosethat are legitimate are not conditional. Hence,policies that denycriminals the right to vote while in jail (as holds in boththe UK andthe US), some evenafter they have served their term (asis the casein manystatesin the US), shouldbemodified. Following the sameprinciple, nobodyshouldbedeniedthebasicnecessitiesof life evenif theyhave not lived up to their responsibilities, such as to find work. Society can show its disapproval and punish irresponsible individuals without disenfranchising them or condemning themto abjectpoverty. As a corollary, a personwhose rights have beencurbed-perhaps a personhas beendeniedthe right to vote becauseof a registration foul-up orjail sentence,or has beensilencedthrough ameritlesslibel suit-is still not exemptfrom attendingto his or her children, not littering and other socialresponsibilities. In short,while rights andresponsibilities arecomplementaryandnecessitateone another, each has its own moral standing and is part and parcel of ends-based relationships. A good societydoesnot denypersonstheir basicrights evenif they do not live upto their responsibilities,just as it doesnot exemptfrom responsibility those whose rights have not beenfully honored. Responsibilityfrom all,for all Responsibilities from all means that a good person, a memberof a good society, contributesto the commongood.No oneis exempt,althoughof coursepeoplewill vary greatly in the contributions they can make. In considering this matter, consider aparap Ylho has lost the useof his limbs. He is permanentlyinstitutionalized. He usesa small stick in his mouthto turnpagesof a book. Shouldwe provide him with a nurse's aideto turnthepagesor expecthimto take thatmuchresponsibility for his own well-being? In order to serve both the person's dignity and the expectation that 7 everyone will do as much for the commongood as they can,we would expecthim to turn the pages himself, assuming he can do so without undue effort. If assuming responsibility to the bestof one'sabilities appliesunderthesecircumstances,surelyno one is exempt from contributing to the commongood in line with his or herability. Accordingly, high schoolstudentsshouldbeencouragedto do communityservice as part of their civic practice, perhaps as 'millennium volunteers' (Briscoe 1995). Seniorcitizens should be expectedto help eachother,membersof their families and their community. Thosewho receivewelfare andcannotfind gainful work shouldhold community jobs. People with contagiousdiseasesshould be expectedto take special pain not to spreadit to othersandso on. The referencehereis not primarily to legal commitments,enforced bycourtsand by the police, but to moral obligations.14And dischargingone's responsibility should not be considereda sacrifice or a punishmentbut an ennobling activity, somethinga good persondoes.Indeed,high schoolstudentscangaindeepsatisfactionfromworking in soupkitchens,as seniorcitizens canby voluntarily running socialcentersfor other seniors,and so on. Responsibility from all is to beparalleledby responsibilityfor all. Responsibility for all meansthat everybodyis to be treatedwith the respectdueto all humanbeings. This meansfirst of all socialinclusion. Communities canplay an especiallyimportant role in ensuring that everyoneis included andtreated with the full respectentitled to thembythemere factof their humanity,asanendinthemselves.lsAn obviousexample is that discrimination based on race, ethnicity, gender, sexual preference,religious background or disability shouldbe the focus of moral dissuasionand legally banned. Discrimination not only offends our elementarysenseof justice -it is incompatible with treating people asendsin themselves. Responsibility for all also meansensuring that everyonehasaccessto the basic necessitiesof life. Voluntary associations,extended families, friends, mutual saving associationsandreligious charitycanhelpto provide someof these,but cannottake on the final responsibility to ensurethat all will beattendedto. It is the responsibilityof the stateto ensurethat suchprovisions areavailableto all. One of the core implications of treating every humanbeing asanendmeansthat all deservea rich basicminimumstandard ofliving,irrespectiveof theirconduct.These arethings which are everyone'sdue. They deserveat leastfood, shelter,clothing and elementaryhealth care. Peoplewho act in anti-social ways or do not dischargetheir social responsibilities -whether becauseof their genes,parents,'the system', poor upbringing, or characterfailing -are notto bedeniedthe elementarylife necessitieswe provide to inmates,prisonersof war andpets. No one's basic humanity and membershipin the community shouldbedenied.It follows that no oneshouldbe completelycut offwelfare ordumpedinto thestreetseven if theyrefuseto work, attendclassesor do community service.The provisions to such idle or selfishpeople(who area minority of benefitsrecipients)maybe reducedandnot include cashbeyond some small amount,but the state's duty in a good societyis to ensurethatno onegoeshungry,homeless,unclothedor sickandunattended.Theymay well deservemuch more,and what is 'enough' -for instancein termsof healthcaremight be rather difficult to define.16 Similarly, there is considerable room for debate over what such a rich basic minimum entails (Nathanson 1998), that understanding is sure to differ with the economicconditions of the society,theageof thoseaffectedandtheir healthstatus,and 18 the community's specific moralsharedunderstanding.But thesedeliberationsoughttobe abouthowextensivethe provision of thesebasicgoodsshouldbe-not whethertheyshould be provided atall. Providing abasic minimum to peoplewill not kill the motivationto work for most,as long as work is available and they are able. Though somewill abusethe system,agood societyshould considerthis a smallprice to pay for affirming thebasichumanityof everyone.Putting mental patients,alcoholics,motherswith children or anyoneelseonto the streets,cutting off all benefitsto them,is simply not compatiblewith treating all peopleasends in themselves. During the 1990's, welfare systems,which badly neededto be reformed,wererestructu However,herewe seea clear caseof over-correction, arguablythe mostextreme of many that took place in recentyears.The reform entailedcutting off somepeople in toto -not lowering benefits but terminating them -and terminating not merely cashsupportbutalsohousing allowances,food stampsand healthinsuranceforchildren. Overthe next years,thesereforms needto be re-reformed if we areto ceasethis violation of this basic tenetof agood society.Thereis muchroom for deliberationconcern what exactly societyowes eachpersonand at what levels benefitswill cut into motivation to work and to refrain from anti-social behavior. For instance,furnishin cashwould not necessarilybe a part of such a state (or even charity)provided package.To ensurethatcommunityjobs keeppeopleabovethepovertyline ofthe kind alreadydiscussed,their income from wagespublicly provided and from otherkinds of benefits -whether in kind or in cash-should be high enoughto meetthe 'minimum' test. In many areasthere is a complex and tense relationship betweenrights andresponsi In thesesituations it is agravemistaketo presumethateitherrights orresponsi are dominant. Rights and responsibilities should be treated as two cardinal moral claims. In the bestof all worlds, both canbe fully honored.In reality,policies cannotoftenmaximize both. But no apriori assumptionshouldbemadethat priority will be given to one ratherthanthe other.I? All policies that impinge on the balance between individual rights and socialresponsi shouldbereviewed andadjustedaccordingly. The right to privacy, for example,is to be respected,but it should not take priority over protectionof life and limb. For instance,mandatorydrugtestingof schoolbusdrivers,train engineers,andairtraffic controllers is legitimate becausein thesecases,the violation of privacy is smallwhereas the dangerto thc;>sethey areentrustedwith is considerable.At the sametime,the ban onthe violation of the privacy of medicalrecordsby employers-records that concernthe mostintimate partsof our life andwhose violation yields at bestminimal social benefits-should beupheld and fully enforced. , A balanced societyapproachesthe tension betweenindividual rights and social responsibilities along theselines andadjustsitspolicies accordingly. In someareasit might enhancethe reachof rights (for instancein the protectionof personal information) while in othersthe claim of socialresponsibilities (for instance,keeping DNA profiles of all criminals), without sucha combined approachbeing inconsistent. The sameholds for increasing freedomof information, subjecting the police to race relationslaws andthe armedforcesto humanrights,asdefined by theEuropeanCourt of Human Rights onthe one hand,while alsoenablingpolice to interceptanddecode email messageson the other. Along the sameline, drug dealers in prisons should be stoppedandroutine testing of inmatesshould be introduced. 10 3.4 MoralDialogues:ChangingMoralCultures Debatesaboutour moralcultureareoftenunnecessarilypolarized.Weare notlimited to eitheradheringto traditional, conservativemores (for example,traditional two-parent families, with mothers athome)ortreating allbehaviorsasif theyhadequallegitimacy (two parents,single parents,gay marriages,sequentialmonogamies,polygamy). We can expressa preference for peermarriages (in which fathers and mothershavethe same rights and the same responsibilities) over other forms of family without condemningthe latter. There are socialand moral options betweenrigidly sticking to tradition (as parts of the religious right demand)and a cultural-moral free-for-all (as someonthe left have,in effect, advocatedin the past). While initially the moralculture of a given community or groupof communitiesis handed down from generation to generation, this culture need not be fixed or 'traditional'. On the contrary, moral culture is continually recastto reflect new social needs,demands,insights and,aboveall, moralclaims.This occursthroughaprocessof specialimportanceto thoseseekingagoodsociety:moraldialogue.Moral dialoguesare 'give and take' discussionsthat engagevalues ratherthan merely interestsor wants. Theyinvolve morethanfactsandreasons;theyengageourbeliefs. Theyarecomposed of the many hours spentover meals, in pubs,while commuting, at work and in the media discussing moral issues. Local communities,whole national societies,and eveninternationalcommunities engage in extensive dialogues about acute moral issues, such as our duty to the environment,women's rights andsexualdiscrimination,andspecific questionssuchas gay marriages,putting children on trial asadults,the deathpenalty, crueltyto animals andtesting a whole village's DNA in orderto catcha criminal. Usually only one ortwo topics arethe subjectof intensive moral dialogue at any one time. Practically anyone can try to initiate a moral dialogue, from the prime minister to a local poet, from a media personalityto a groupof protesters.However, it is ultimately the public atlarge thatdecideswhich it will engagein. Despiteclaimsto the contrary, the media -which servesasan important venue for moral dialoguescontrols neitherthe agendanorthe outcome,althoughof courseit influencesboth. This is becausethe media itself is not of one mind, and becausethe public is much less susceptibleto brainwashingthan is oftenassumed.IS Moral dialogues are largely aboutvalues. They are not dialoguesamongexperts but amongcitizens. Moral dialoguesoften draw on factualand logical arguments,but they are mainly ethical, rather than empirical, in nature. Recall, for instance,the argumentsthathavetakenplace overbombing Serbiaduring theKosovo war,releasing Pinochetor allowing gaymarriage. When a community is engagedin a moral dialogue,the discussionoften seems disorderly, meandering and endless.However, it frequently does lead to a genuine recasting of that community's voluntary moral culture, that which the community condonesor censures. Most importantly, through theprocess ofmoral dialoguepeopleoftenmodifytheir conduct,feelingsandbeliefs.For example,inthe 1950smostcommunitieshadnosense of a moral obligation toward the environment. A profound moral dialogue that developedin the 1960sand 1970sled not merelyto a sharedmoral senseof our dutyto Mother Earth(althoughcommunitiescontinueto differ onwhat exactlythatentails)but also to a fair measure of changed behavior, such as voluntary recycling and 20 conservationof energy. In short,if acommunityneedsto changeitssocialpolicies in a significant way, such changes are bestpreceded (as far as public policies are concerned)and largeley generated(asfar as changesinpersonal and social conduct are concerned)by moral dialogue. Moral dialogues can follow what sociologists call 'moral panic' but thesetwo should not be conflated. Panic alarmspeople and can leadthem to embracedubious policies. In contrast,moraldialoguesleadthemto reexaminetheir beliefs,world views and prejudices,andto recastthem. One of the great weaknessesof some of the Third Way governmentsis their tendencyto take shortcuts,oftenskirting orshort-changingtheneedfor moraldialogue. For instance,thereleaseof aThird Way framework documentin Germanyin mid-l 998 by ChancellorGerhard Schroderwas notprecededby adialogue with the membersof the SocialDemocratic Party or evenits leadership,notto mentiontheGermanpublic at large. In contrast, changing Clause IV of the Labour party platform followed 'the widest consultation exercise ever undertakenby a British political party... Tens of thousandstook part, almosthalf the party participated' (Blair 1997:51). Currently moral dialogues are badly needed on issues such as limiting the centrifugal effects of devolution, deeper involvement in the European Union, the implications of continued immigration andthe effectsof growing multiculturalism on the core values of the society. The rise of right-wing parties in Austria, Switzerland, Germany and France, and the romanticisation of Communist regimes in eastern Germany,are in part driven by lack of sufficient dialogue onthesematters. Another topic that calls for a moral dialogue is in the area of international humanitarian efforts. What are the limits and scope of foreign aid? When should economic sanctionsbe applied? When is the exerciseof force justified? When is it appropriateto cancelthe debtof developingnations?Shouldwe putpressureon other countriesto changetheir moral cultures in mattersranging from child laborto female circumcision? While there are no guaranteedways to trigger moral dialogues or ensure their development,devices suchasextensivepublic hearingsby Parliamentarycommittees andinquiries by citizen commissionsmayinitiate dialogue.The latterhaveno official standingand maybe establishedby a think tank, foundation or someothercivic body. They arecomposedof therepresentativesof major segmentsof societyaffected bythe issuesunder study,conductpublic hearingsandpublishrecommendationsbasedonthe dialogue theytrigger. Suchdevicesmustbeusedmuchmoreextensivelyif morepeople areto becomefurtherengagedbythe moralandpolitical issuesattheheartof theThird Way. Many groups that are strongly committed to specific valuestend to demandthat public leaderspushtheir agendathrough,engineeringpublic supportif it doesnotexist. The power of leadership in a democratic society is, thankfully, much more limited. Political leadershipin freesocietiesmustjudiciously chooseoccasionsonwhich major changesare sought,with newcoalitions built andpolitical capitalput atrisk, ratherthan vainly tilting with the wind. Suchwillingness to assumerisk at selectpoints was evident when Old Labour transformed into New Labour, when the old opposition betweenleft and right was leapfrogged onthe road to a Third Way. It is evident in the continuedrecastingof the welfare state, and in guiding countries from an industrial to a knowledge-based economy. It will be called upon againto face the next major challengesof the Third 21 Way: curbing inequality; balancing devolution with building a community ofcommunities; and defining the place of the national community within the European one,amongothers. Involving thepublic more in dialoguesaboutmajorpolicy change,especiallythoseconcerning moral and social issues,makes it more difficult to govern. Suchdialoguesare time-consuminganddo not necessarilyconcludeasgovernmentmaywish. But it is doubtful that it would bepossibleto achieveprofoundandlasting socialchangewithout suchdialogues.To put it more starkly: a governmentcanmake incrementalchangesyear on year without profoundly engaging the public -or it can truly lead in newdirections. This can only be done if the public hasbeenengagedand won over-oftencausing significant changesinthe direction governmentwasseekingto move.After all, democracyentails muchmore than a solid majority in the parliament. 3.5 Family:TheNeedforaDefinitiveNewLook Throughout history, in all societies, families have been entrusted with initiating character formation, introducing younger generationsto the moral culture of the community,preparing themto be good people. Before one can settle any of the numerous specific issues that arise from the transition from traditional forms of families to 'postmodern' ones,we require a more conclusive examination of the evidence aboutthe effects of highly divergent social arrangements.To proceed,the governmentshouldconvenea 'sciencecourt', aninquiry composed of expert social scientists.19The court would hold public hearings, interrogatingscientific witnessesandrepresentativesof the various bodiesof thought on the subject. The court might require additional analysis of existing data or the generationof new data,to provide a strong and sharedbody of relevantevidence.In this way it should be ableto reachsolid credible conclusionsaboutcritical issuesthat ariseconcerningour ability to replacethetwo parentfamily, andhelpmoveto settlethepublic dialogue ontheseissues.Clearly it makesa greatdealof difference for the moral cultureandforpublic policy whetherchildren suffergreatlyor actuallybenefit,assome maintain, from new forms of family arrangementsand the institutionalization of children.Thesciencecourtshouldfocus onchildrenof young age,especiallyfrom birth until five, the years in which manybelieve the foundationsof characterareformed. .The sciencecourt should investigate not merely whetherthe absenceof a second partneris harmful, but also the implications of a growing 'children deficit'. There is evidencethatthe birth ratein severaldevelopedsocietiesis falling belowthe population replacementlevel,with numerousill consequencesfor society!OTo put it more sharply, if we onceheld thatthe first socialdutyof the family is the moral educationof children, we may now wish to amend this to say that duty calls for having children at all!' Millions seechildrenasa burden,interfering with theircareersandlifestyle. This is just anotherdisconcertingreflectionof thepressuresof globalismandradicalindividualism. The introduction of severalnew family policies might bestbe delayed until the work of the sciencecourtis completed.This holds,for instance,for legal authorization of newforms of marriage(Wilkinson 1999),suchastime-limited commitments,givin§ full legalendorsementto householdpartnerships,andintroducing covenantmarriages! There are those who ask: Why do we have to rule which form of marriage we oughtto favor ratherthan let eachpersonmake herorhis ownchoices?Firstly, aslong asmarriageremainsa statesanctionedand enforced institution, we mustdecidewhat 22 amounts to a marriage.The sameis true for the questionof who is entitled to benefitsavailable. to thosewho are married. Even if all state involvement was abolished,thescience court woulg still be neededto help focus the moral debate,which reshapes voluntary moral culture. If one form or anotherof marriage and family wereto prove harmful to children,we still shouldnotnecessarilyban it, butfamilies andcommunities ought at leastto know aboutit. Somekey matters,though,requireno studyor inquiry. Thereshouldbeno return t9 'traditional' forms offamily, in which womenwere treatedassecondclasscitizens.This would violate the principle of treating all asends(Wilkinson 1999).Fathersandmothers should have the samerights and responsibilities. Fathersobviously can look after children andwomenwork outsideof thehousehold.A substantivestepinthe right direction will bemadewhenlaws that allow mothersof newborn childrento takepaid leave and have their jobs held for them for a given number of years are also fully applied to fathers. There is no one correctway to balancework and family; eachpersonandcouple must work this out. It is, however, in the interestof a good societyto encourageand enableparentsto spendmore time with their children. 3.6 SchoolsasPlacesof CharacterForn1ation Much has been written about making schools into more effective tools for the competitive information economy,and on the needto improve academicskills and knowledge of graduates. However, we have also known since Aristotle about the importanceof characterdevelopment.In our society,schoolsaretheplacesin whichthe characterof young peopleis developed.Theyarethe placewhereyoungpeople learn, or at least ought to, how to control their impulsesand develop empathy,essentialfor treating one anotherasendsratherthan only asinstruments. Theyaretheplacewhere young peopleshould learnhowto dealcivilly with one anotherandto resolveconflicts peacefully. Most importantly, in schoolsyoungpeoplelearn thattreatingothersonly as instrumentsis profoundly unethical,andthattheyhaveresponsibilities foroneanother, their family andthe community. A good societyrequiresgoodpeople; it cannotallow for charactereducationto be driven out by academics.The directexperiencesandnarrativesoffered by schoolsare more important for characterformation than lectures on ethics or civics. Community service, peer mentoring and other ways of taking responsibility, role playing and participation in mockgovernmentsare all vastly superiorforms of civic educationthan formal and abstractlectures aboutdemocraticgovernment. To ensurethatthis core educationprinciple will be heeded,an annualassessment should be made in all schoolsof the educational(as distinct from teaching)messages they impart,andof their approachto characterformation. If thesearedefective,schools. should be helped by personnelespeciallydedicatedto this issueto restructure their approach. Educational,family andwelfare policies are oftendevelopedin isolation from one anotherand,mostof all, from work practices.But if peopleareto be treatedas ends, they cannotbeviewed asfragments,asstudentsor parentsor workers. Eachindividual mustbetreatedasawhole. This, in turn,requiresa muchbetterdovetailing of different policies. For example,schooldaysendbeforemostparentsfinish work. Unsurprisingly, 23 a high level of juvenile crime occurs between3 and 6 PM. Gapslike theseml;istbe bridged with policies that treatthe many aspectsof societyas segmentsof onewhole. The OtherPartners:Stateand Market The good society is a partnershipof three sectors: government,private sector,and community. Eachone reflects and servesa distinct facet of our humanity. Only by serving all three,ratherthanfragmenting them or settingone againstthe other,canwe achievea societythatencompassesthewhole person,essentialfor theirbeingtreatedas endsin themselves. . While thesepartnersmay differ in terms of their respectiveroles,andthesemay changewith socialconditions,in agood societythethreesectorsseekto cooperatewith oneanother. Eachis partof the solution; noneis blamed asthe sourceof theproblem. Theyare complementaryratherthanantagonistic.Most importantly, eachpartnerhelps containthe others,to ensureone will not usurpthe missions bestaccomplishedbythe others.Maintaining this three-waybalanceis atthe heart of the good society. 4.The State TheThird Way approachmaintains thatsweepinganddetailed controlof the economy and societybythe stateis incompatible with agood society,asis anunfetteredmarket. It also follows thatwhile the statecan and should be slimmed down, there are many tasks thatareits legitimate domain. .The main responsibility for public safetyshould restwith the state.Therefore,to the extent that the society draws on private policing (suchashired guards)and profit-making prisons,their conductshouldbe closelyregulated.At thesametime, the state's function in this arena should be contained by the community. For instance, civil review boards can help ensure that the police do not brutalize citizens. Another form of containmentis scrutiny by a free press. .Citizens should not be armed in a good society, and police arms should be minimal. Thestateshouldensurethecontinueddisarmamentof thepopulation.To the extent that a civil militia is needed,asthe Swiss for instancehold, arms are bestdepositedin public armories.Holding a gun upto a personis aboutasfar as one canget from treating peopleasends. .A major goal for the next decadeshould be significantly increasing certitude (sometimesreferredto as 'celerity') thatthosewho violate the law will be caught, those caught will be convicted and those convicted will serve their term. An increasein certitude would allow a reduction in the length of prisontime andthe harshnessof the term (for example,less solitary confinementandlessreliance on high securityprisons)while atthesametime enhancingpublic safety.The resultis amorehumanetreatmentof criminals andgreaterpossibility of theirrehabilitation, in line with our criteria for the good society,aswell as significantly lower public costs(after a transition period):3 Punishing those who violate the law is unavoidable in an orderly and just society. Increased certitude combined with shorter sentences will ensure punishmentand curtail the inhumanand costly treatmentthat often ensueswhen people are incarcerated.Hopefully suchan approachwould also detercriminals more effectively. 24 The stateshouldberesponsiblefor public health,that is,for healthmattersthatare in the interestof the community aboveandbeyond thatof individual patients,for example: containing communicable diseases,ensuring the safety of drugs and foods, and undertaking some forms of preventive health such as mandatory vaccinations and water fluoridation. Illness andthe resulting dependencynot only exactincreasinglylargepublic costs, but are also incompatible with people achieving their full potential. Preventivecareis the bestantidote.Specificgoalsforpreventivecareshouldbe set for eachdecade,including contributions expectedfrom citizens, for instance,by increasing the amount of exercise they take. Decreasing the rate of smoking, especiallyamong teenagers,is thesingle most important preventive goalfor the next ten years. While figures differ, the importance of preventive care is highlighted by the finding that in a givenperiod in the United Stateschangesin lifestyle added 11.5 years to life expectationwhile improvements in medical servicesadded only 0.5 years. A good societyshould view the marketasakinto nuclearenergy:it canprovide an enormous and growing bounty of products and services,and help to servethe commongood,including cultureandarts,scienceandeducation,public healthand welfare. However, it mustbewatchedovercarefully. If excessivelyrestrictedthe market cannotperform well. At the sametime, a good societyassumesthatif the marketis not properly contained,it maydehumanizepeopleandwreak havoc on local communities, families and socialrelations. Indeed,unfetteredmarkets can undo I-Thou relations and allow I-It onesto dominate. The Third Way doesnotleadto afree marketanymorethan it favors football without rules orreferees.The markethasalwaysoperatedwithin a socialcontext, which hasincludedafabric of socialvalues,laws,andregulatorymechanisms.The role of the government is not to abolish these but to adapt them to changing conditions, especiallyto the cyber-age. The main questionThird Waysocietiesstrugglewith is whento allow market forcesa free rein andwhento put upcontainingwalls. (An obviousexampleof an areathe market mustbe kept frompenetratingis the distribution of transplantable human organs.)There are significant differencesamongThird Way societieson this viewpoint, which reflectshow muchprogresstheyhavemadeonthis journey, especially betweensocietiesthathave beenThatcherized(mainly the US andthe UK) andthose thathave nottravelled far downthis road. However, all Third Way societiesshouldbemuch clearer abouttheareasinto which marketforces mustbe prevented from intruding. This is essential if the proper balance betweenthe instrumental realm and that ofendsis to beachievedand sustained. Third Way societiesarecurrentlymakingnumerousincrementalchangesthat favor marketforces.Theseinclude greaterflexibility in work rules,lowerpersonal, capital gains andcorporatetax rates,lower benefits,higherco-insurancecharges, further privatization, enabling firms to issue sharesto their workers, enabling workers to purchasesharestax free,reforms of insolvencyand muchelse. Suchchangeswill remainunnecessarilythreateningandunprincipled aslong as it is not clearly indicated which social boundaries will not be breached. EspeciallY,significantonthis matteris the questionof whetherpeoplecanreliably assumethat whateverthe changesin economic policy, they will still havesecure safety nets protecting their basic health insurance,retirement income and basic subsistence.Canpeopletake for grantedthat evenif thesenetswere setat lower levels,no onewould be allowed to fall throughthem? Will work beavailable for all thosewho seekit or arepressuredto find employment? Will the income from work be sufficient to keeppeople out of poverty? Will training be available for thosemade redundant by technologically driven changes?While details can be debated,people in agoodsocietyare accordeda basicsenseofeconomicsecurity. Markets cannotbe free from public oversight and regulation. To a limited extent one can and should rely on the market to self-regulate (for instance, industries agreeing not to target young children in their advertising), and communitiescanplaya containingrole. For example,manyconsumergroupsplay an important role as unofficial 'watchdogs' of corporatebehavior. But the main responsibility for containing the market-experience shows-must restwith the state.To ensurethatstateregulationsdo notbecomeexcessive,theyshouldremain in effect only if examinations show that they do not unnecessarilyrestrainthe market or that they cannot be replaced by better regulations or other ways of achieving the samesocialpurposes. The notion thatcyberspacecanbea newutopian world, free from statecontrols,in whichpeoplegovernthemselves,is without reality orjustice. Cyberspacehaslong since turned from a virtual village into a metropolis in which people do need protection.As the proportion of transactionsconductedincyberspacecontinuesto increase,so mustpublic oversight. Prescriptiondrugssold onthe internet cannot be free from the protections that customersrequire off-line. Taxes cannotbe avoided.Messagestransmitted by drug lords,pedophilesandterrorists cannotbe exemptfrom the reachof the law. Libel onthe internetis not different from any other. Somecontrols canbe exerted by parentsand educators.Otherscan rely on self-regulationand transparency(for example,the posting of privacy policies and the useof trustmarks). However, increasinglythe virtual world will becomelike the restof the world, and will needthesamecarefulbalanceof freedomandpublic scrutiny. While thebasicneedfor containingcyberspace'seconomicandtechnological forces is the sameas in other markets,the tools may well be different. Because cyberspaceknows no nationalborders,developmentof worldwide agreementsand enforcementmustbe achievedas rapidly aspossible. . Ensuring basic accessfor all is anotherrole for the state,so thatcyberspace does not become another arena for social exclusion. This will be especially important asmore educationandvoting takesplace in virtual formats. Given the close associationbetweenwork and a senseof self-worth, which is a vital foundationof ends-basedrelationships,public policy shouldaim bothto hold inflation at bay and also to stimulate the economy,enabling higher growth in general and low unemployment especially. Given recent evidence that higher growth and lower unemployment than previously considered possible can be achieved without rekindling serious inflation, and given the inhumanity of joblessnessevenin astatewith broadwelfareprovisions-public policy shouldtilt more toward growth and lesstoward inflation fighting. An annual growth rate above3 percentand anunemploymentrate below 5 percentshouldbeconsidered realistic targets. 26 Expanding available work throughthe market until unemploymentis low is the mostdesirableoutcome.However,to the extentthatthis is impractical,policies which distributeavailable work arepreferableto thosethat protectjob privileges but keepunemploymenthigh (for instance,bycurbingpart-time work). Surelyit is betterfor all who seekandareableto work to beemployedthan for someto have high salariesand benefits well protected,only to be highly taxed in orderto pay unemploymentbenefitsto thosewho are kept out of the labormarket.The Dutch approachto employmentis closerto anends-respectingmodelthanthatof several otherThird Way countries (Hemerijck & Visser 2001). As a last resort,communityjobs shouldbeavailable for all thosewho cannot find gainful. work in the marketplace or public sector!4 These could include environmentalimprovementsandteachingaides,aswell asotherwork thatwould not be carried out if it had to be paid for. Thus, community jobs would not competewith otherforms of job creationor with thosewho hold low-payingjobs. The state should be attentive to environmental needs and coordinate those activities neededto shoreupthe environment,but it shouldnot shoulderthemall!5 To someextentenvironmentalprotectioncanbereconciled with marketinterests, andbecomea sourceof newjobs andtechnologicalinnovation. At the sametime, the state in a good societyrecognizesour duty to passonthe environmentto our children in good or better condition thanwe inherited it, and that sucha social commitmententails some netpublic costs. Thesecostscanbe reducedaspeople increasinglyrecognizethatprotecting the environmentis apart of everyone's socialmoral responsibilities,an important sourceof communityjobs anda place for volunteering!6 To help sustainthe three-way partnership,the state fosters communities where they existandhelpsprime their developmentwhere theyhavefailed. It is careful notto contributeto their ossificationanddecaybypreemptingtheirrole. Hence,as arule the stateshould not bethe first sourceof socialservices.Small loans,child care,sick care,counselingand muchelseis bestprovided in the first instanceby membersof the immediate and extended family, local and other communities, voluntary associations,workplacesandothers.Whenthestatebecomesthe first or sole source of these services, it undermines, demoralizes and bureaucratizes relationships thatare atthe core of communallife. In orderto encouragecommunities' role in social services,all stateagencies should have citizen participation advisory boards. Their taskwould be to find ways for citizensto participate asvolunteers in delivering someservicescurrently carried bythe state.They shouldalsoplaya role in providing timely, relevantand informed feedbackonthe performanceof serviceproviders. The stateshould fostereconomic and social entrepreneurship,andtherefore notimposetaxesorregulations which disabletheeconomicenginesof innovation andchange.At the sametime, taxesshould not disadvantagethosewho labor in favor ofthosewhoinvest.If taxesarewithheld at source,theyshouldbewithheld from both workers and investors. (Becauseof the dangersof capital flight, to proceedmaywell require carrying this measureout onthe levelof the EU, or most likely the OECD.) 27 4.2 ThePrivateSector 'We arenot againstmarket-basedeconomybutmarket-basedsociety.'Lionel Jospin,PrimeMinisterof France. Third Waysocietiesrecognizethatthe marketisthe bestenginefor productionof goods and services,of work andthusjobs, of economicprogress.Moreover,theprivate sector may foster innovation that adapts the economy to changing conditions and opportunities. While muchattentionis properly paidto socialproblemscreatedby marketforces -factory closures,loss of job security, overwork in someindustries and idlenessin others -such problems should not blind us to the basic merit of strong economic growth. So,for example,rising internationaltraderaisesa hostof problemsconcerning laborand environmentalstandards,butwe shouldalsorecognizethattrade,inthelong run, benefits most societiesand most membersof society. Thosewho lose theirjobs asa resultshouldbe helped by the community andthe state. Policies such as the United StatesTrade Adjustment Assistance (providing targeted support for those dislocated by economic change) should be increased, allowing redundant workers to be retrained and, if necessary,resettled, or given communityjobs!7 Someclaim thatmost socialstandardsmustbesuspendedfor a nationto beableto competein the globaleconomy.While someadaptationsare necessary,eachshouldbe critically examined.It is empirically incorrectandmorally falseto assumethata society cannotrespondto the negativeeffects of globalization, or that,if it could respond,the loss of economic efficiency would apriori not be worth paying. It is equally importantto recognizethatglobalization calls for the developmentof national, regional and global social and political institutions. As corporations and internetbusinessesincreasinglybecomecross-nationalandglobal forces,sobalancing groups-from laborunionsto environmentalists-must link armsacrossnationallines, andregulatoryandotherpublic institutions mustbe regionalandglobal in scope.Limits on violations of the environment, land mines, trade in ivory and much else are preliminary and ratherweak examples,but they point to what mustbe done. 4.3 TheArt of Combinations The tendencyto view the state and the market as opposites, at least as alternative approachesto social issues,concealsthe fact thatsomeof the bestand most important work of a society thataspiresto be good is conductedeither by the third sectoror by hybrids. Thesearevariousamalgamsin which elementsof two or eventhreesectorsare combined.Examplesfollow. Their purposeis to urge much greaterattentionto these neitherprivate norpublic nor communalbodies.Assumingasystematicexaminationof their qualitiesandlimitations would showthat in manyareastheseare superiorto pure sectortypes,manymore missions should be entrustedtot thesehybrids. Examplesinclude: .Religious institutions and voluntary associationsthatprovide social services,but arefinanced in part by the government. .Privately run or not-for-profit cultural institutions, suchasuniversities,museums andtheatres,whose initial capitalcostsor start-upfundsareprovided bythe state. 28 Theseinstitutions maycontinueto rely onsomepartial governmentsubsidiesbut should drawthe majority of theiroperatingfunds from theirgift shops,restaurants, entranceticket-salesandsoon. .State vouchers that allow people to purchase community services or market products, for instance,housing allowancesand pre-schoolchild care. .Public corporations,suchasthePublic BroadcastCorporation(whichprovides for public TV) andthe National Public Radio (NPR). Thesepublic media outletsare especially important in an age of increasingly commercial forms of communi- cation. There is muchmore scopefor combinations in mattersconcerningutilities (especially water),public services(transportation),andmanyothers.Letusswearoff thesimplistic market-or-governmentdichotomy. 4.4 TheKnowledgeSocietyandCurtailingScarcity Much has been stated,correctly, aboutthe importanceof fostering the transition to a knowledge-based economy. Such a transformation -which entails prioritizing investment in people (via educationand lifelong learning)as well as technology -is said to be essentialfor prosperity. It could alsobe a good way to reducemenial labor and increasethe numberof jobs that are stimulating, family-friendly andcompatible with theneedsof the environment. However, surprisingly little attentionhasbeenpaid to an attribute ofaknowledge-basedeconomythat byitselfjustifies heavyinvestmentin it: its potential to reducescarcity and enhancesocialjustice. Knowledge as a resource differs greatly from those relied upon in industrial societies-capital goods,from steelto petrol- in that it canbe sharedand consumed manytimes over. Thus,if a factoryusesa tonof steel,this steelis no longeravailableto anyotheruserand,asa result,issuesof resourceallocationand scarcityarise.However, when a person puts a design on the internet -for a better mousetrap,car, home, software program or whatever -millions can use it and the originator still has the original.2 Similarly, manythousandsof peoplecandownloadapieceof music,poetry or film and it can still be consumedagain.While not all knowledgeis or canbeshared in this manner,a growing numberof new 'goods' arebeing sharedonthe internet in this way. Of course, there are tricky problems that must be worked out concerning intellectual property andpatentrights. However,oneshould not overlookthatthereare very largebodiesof knowledge thatcanbesharedlegally inthis almostmiraculousnew way -including numerousbooks,music,and art for which the copyright hasexpired and thatare in thepublic domain.Thesameshouldhold for mostinformationproduced by the government,from national statisticsto text of parliamentarydebates. The morepeoplesatisfy theirwantsbydrawing onfree knowledge,saybyreading downloaded files, playing chessonthe internet orjoining virtual self-help groups,the scarcerscarcity becomesand the smallerthe I-It sectora societymustbear. Scarcity will neverbeeliminated. However,themorepeople(oncetheirbasicmaterialwantsare sated)draw on opensourcesof knowledge (including culture), the more ends-based their relations canbecome. Lastbut not least.thereis aprofound connectionbetweenfosteringtheknowledgebasedeconomyandenhancingsocialjustice. Most earliertheoriesof justice arebased onthe ideaof transferring largeamountsof resourcesfrom thehavesto the have-nots. 29 This raisesobvious political difficulties. However,to the extentthatthosewhosebasic needsare met draw their additional satisfaction from non-scarceresources,the door opensto a whole new world, in which thosebetteroff may well belessopposedto the transferof materialgoodsto thoselessendowed.And thosewho havelesscould benefit from non-scarceknowledge resources,oncethe community andstateensurethatthey havethe basic skills andresourcesneededto accessthe newworld of knowledge. This may seemfar-fetched,visionary andutopian. Yetwhile suchaworld maybe far in our future, its harbingersare all aroundus. The more we fostera transition to a knowledge-basedeconomyandbasic accessfor all, the closerwe cometo living in a society that is driven less by scarcity-and is more equitableasa result. 4.5 ,imiting Corruption Few issues concerning the proper balance between market and state are more imporant than preventing those with economic power from also concentrating political power. In numerous free societies there is a growing stream of private monies into public handseither in the old-fashioned form of personal bribery and favors, or in the modern form of special interests 'contributing' funds to political parties, legislators or government officials in exchange for special treatment at the public's cost. Few things are more corrosive for the Third Way than the corruption of public institutions. Such doublefisted concentration of power violates a profound precept of a truly democratic society, whereby all member are equal citizens, whatever their wealth differences. Trust is a key element of ends-based relationships; while general social trust among the general public has been diminishing, trust in public leaders and institutions is particularly vulnerable. The American public has become rather cynical of a political system in which limiting the role of private monies in public life is almost impossible. European societies must pay more attention to this matter than they have hitherto. While the problem may well be less severe in the UK than in many other societies, the best time to lock the barn is before the horse is stolen. Several new laws and regulations in the UK seek to curb the corruption of politics -these include banning foreign funding and paid questions, declaring all interests in a public register, and publicizing donations to political parties over £ 2,000. It remains to be seen whether these will suffice to protect public life from private monies:9 5 Sustainingthe Communityof Communities 5.1 Devolution Coupled with Nation Building The Labour governmenthaslived upto itspromiseof devolution. However,theprocess has revealed a slew of new issuesto be addressed.One concernsways to devolve further 'down', bringing power closerto the people,to the level of communities rather than regions such as Scotland and Wales, or even cities as large as London. If devolution is extendeddownward,citizens will havemore opportunitiesto participate in their own government,andaremore likely to becomepolitically engaged. A more urgent challenge is learning to devolve power while reinforcing the loyalties and bonds that maintain a national society. The mere mention of Scottish independence,and the intense squabblesbetweenregions over variation in central government funding, are indications thatthis issuerequires urgentattention. 30 A strong economy, reallocation of wealth, sound environmentalprograms and respectfor basiclaws can only be advancedif smallercommunitiesarepartsof moreencompas ones. England or Scotland alone could not achieve the kind of international leadershipandeconomic power Britain currentlyprovides.In the current environment,nationscannotavoid fragmentationwithout activeleadershipandconcrete society-building measures.. The questfor suchmeasuresis, for the most part, yet to beundertaken.Formingnationwide work groups,projects andprograms that cutacrossregionalborders-for example, economic development programs encompassing northeastEngland and southernScotland-might servethis end.Changingthe National Curriculumto include more historical material focusing on the achievementsof the union and less on civil wars might help.'Honoring thosewho foster unity ratherthan separatenesswould be useful. But thesealone will not suffice. Much new thinking is still required on this issue. The vision of societyasa community of communitiesappliesto geographic,racial and ethnic communities alike. A good society thrives on a diversity of cultures that enrichespeople's lives throughthe arts,music,dance,socialcontact,cuisineandmuch more. But sucha multicultural society cannot flourish without a sharedframework, which itself will evolve overtime. Its elementsinclude commitmentto a democratic way of life, to basic laws or the constitution, to mutual respectand,above all, to the responsibility to treatall othersasendsin themselves.Diversity shouldnotbecomethe oppositeof unity, but should exist within unity. Sustaining a given community of communities does not contradictthe gradual development of more encompassingcommunities, such as the EuropeanUnion or, eventually, a world community. These too will be composed of networks of communities rather than hundreds of millions of individuals, or evenhundreds of fragmented socialentities. It is foolish to believe thatthe collapseof nationsdoesnot matter becausethe fragments may thenjoin the larger Europeancommunity in what Philip Dodd (1995)refersto as'the Euro-federalist solution to the presentbattle over Britain'. Suchnotions are unduly optimistic about the pace and scopeof Europe's developmentas a true community. They disregard the fact that more encompassing communities are not composedof numerous small fragments: they arean additional layer of community, ratherthan one thatpreemptsthe others. Finally, deeper involvement in the EU is best preceded by extensive moral dialogues, not merely one referendum about the euro. While there seemsto be considerable support for joining a European community, below the surfacethere are strong euro-scepticalsentimentsthat mustbe takenseriously. 5.2 Limiting Inequality Societycannotsustainitself asa communityof communities if disparitiesinwell-being and wealth betweenelites andthe restof societyaretoo great.While we maydebate exactly what socialjustice entails,there is little doubt what community requires. If some members of a community become further removed from the daily living conditions of most other members -leading lives of hyper-affluence in gated communitie~,with chauffeured limousines,servantsand personaltrainers-they lose contactwith the restof the community. Suchisolation not only frays socialbondsand insulatesprivileged people from the moral cultures of the community, but alsoblinds 31 themto the realities of their fellow citizens' lives. This in turn maycausethemto,favor unrealistic policies ('let them eat cake'), which further underminesthe community's trust in them. To preventthis problemit hasbeensuggestedthatthestateshouldprovide equality of outcomes.However,during the twentieth centurywe havelearnedthatthis treatment goesagainstthe grainof afreesociety.As a result,evencommandandcontrolsocieties have beenunable truly to implement this approach.We also learnedthat, when it is approximated, it undermines creativity, excellence and motivation to work, and is unfair to thosewho do applythemselves.Furthermore,the resulting laborcostsareso high asto rendera societyuncompetitive in the global economy. Equality of opportunity has been extolled as a substitute. However, to ensure equality of opportunity for all, everyonemusthavea similar startingpoint. Thesecan beprovided only if all are accordedcertain basics,which we havealreadyestablished is a core part of treating all asendsand not merely asmeans. Additional policies to curb inequality further canbemadeto work at bothendsof the scale. Specialeducationefforts to bring children from disadvantagedbackgrounds upto par, suchasSurestart(in the UK) andHead Start(in the US),andtraining workers releasedfrom obsolescentindustries for newjobs, areexamplesof programsproviding a measureof equality of outcometo make equality of opportunitypossible.However, the results often revealthemselvesvery slowly. Hence inthe shorterrun greatereffects will be achieved by raising tax credits and the minimum wage and by creating initiatives that encouragesharingof resourcesbetweencommunities. Raising the minimum wage invites the criticism thatpeoplewill bepriced out of thejobs market. However, if the level of minimum wageis tied to whatpeopleneedto provide for their basicneeds,it is the moral obligation of agood societyto provide for this standard of living. The only alternative to a proper minimum wage would be welfare payments-which tendto be degrading,developdependencyandarepolitically more unattractivethan minimum wage. However, it doesnot follow thatthe minimum wage should automaticallybetied to a relative poverty line -one thatrisesasquickly as otherwages in society. A rich basic minimum is defined in absoluteterms,not asa statisticalartifact. Fora long time it hasbeenknown thatthe poor will be with us,evenif they work, aslong astheyhaveno assets.Peoplewho own assets,especiallyaplaceof residence (whetherahouseor anapartment),aremore likely to 'buy' into a society,to feelandbe part of the community and to be an active memberof it. One major way to advance home ownership is through schemesthat allow those on low incomes to obtain mortgages,asprovided intheUnited Statesby federallycharteredcorporationssuchas FannieMae. More shouldto be done onthis front. We suggestthatthis might be achievedby following the samemodelusedin the EarnedIncome Tax Credit in the US andthe Working Families Tax Credit in the UK: providing low incomepeople with earnedinterest on mortgages.Thosewhoseincome is below a certain level may earn, say,two dollars for every dollar they setasideto provide them with the seedmoney for buying a home. Alternatively, 'sweat' equity might be used asthe future owners' contribution, for instanceif they work on their housing sites.While raising the income and ownershipof the poor might ensurethat everybody can afford the basic minimum essentialto the core principle of a good society, suchmeasureswill not suffice for thepurposesof communitybuilding. Other 32 measuresthatpreventeverhigherlevelsof inequalityshouldbe undertakenif wealthier people are not to becometoo distancedfrom the restof society. Suchmeasuresm.ayinclude maintaining progressivetaxation from mostif not all sources,increasing inheritance tax andensuring that tax on capital is paid as it is on labor. Given that such measurescannotbe adopted if they seriously endangerthe competitive status of a country, they would be difficult to implement solely at the national level. A number of inequality curbing measures may well require cointroduction or harmonization at leastwithin the EU and preferably with the OECD countries; better yet (in the long term) worldwide. Ultimately this matter,as with many others,will not be properly addresseduntil there is a seachange in the moral culture of societyandthe purposesthatanimateit. Major reallocation of wealth cannotbe forced by a democratic society,andvigorous attemptsto impose it will causea flight of wealth and damagethe economy in other ways. In contrast, history from early Christianity to Fabian socialismteachesus thatpeople who shareprogressivevalues will be inclined to sharesomeof their wealthvoluntar A good society seeksto promote such values through a grand moral dialogue ratherthan by dictates. 6 The NextGrand Dialogue:A ModerateReturnof Counterculture? The good societyunderstandsthat ever-increasinglevels of material goods are not areliable source of human well-being and contentment,let alone of a morally sound society. It recognizes that the pursuit of well-being through ever higher levels of consumptionis Sisyphean.This is notan argumentin favor of poverty andself-denial. However, extensive data shows that, once basic material needs are well sated and securelyprovided for, additionalincomedoesnotaddto happiness(Myers 2000). Theevidence shows that profound contentment is found in nourishing ends-based relationships,in bonding with others,in communitybuilding andpublic service,andin cultural and spiritual pursuits. Capitalism neveraspiredto addressthe needsof thewhole person; at best it treats a person as an economic entity. Statist socialismsubjuga ratherthan inspired people. It is left to good societiesto fill the void. The mostprofound problems thatplaguemodernsocietieswill be fully addressed only when thosewhosebasic needshave beenmet shift their priorities up Maslow'sscale of human needs.That is, onlY after theyaccorda higher priority to gaining andgiving affection, cultivating culture, becoming involved in community service andseeking spiritual fulfillment. Sucha shift in priorities is also required before we can truly come into harmony with the environment, as these higher priorities replace material consumption. Sucha new setof priorities may also be the only conditions ~nder which those who are well endowed would be willing to support serious reallocation of wealth andpower,astheir personalfortuneswould no longerbebased on amassingever largeramountsof consumergoods:OIn addition, transitioning to aknowled economy would free millions of people (one hopes all of them, gradually)to relateto eachotherasmembersoffamilies and communities,thus layingthe socialfoundations for a societyin which ends-basedrelationshipsdominatewhile instrumentalonesare well contained. The upward shift in priorities, a returnto a sortof moderatecounterculture,a turnto voluntary simplicity -these requireagranddialogue aboutour personaland shared goals. Intellectuals andthe media canhelp launchsucha dialogue and model theftew fOnDSof behavior. Public leaders can nurse the recognition of these values, by moderating consumption at public eventsand ceremonies,and by celebrating those whose achievementsare compatible with the good society ratherthan with a merely affluent one. But ultimately, suchashift lies in changesin the heartsand minds, in the valuesand conduct,of usall. We shallnot travelfar toward agood societyunlesssuch a dialogue is launchedandadvancedto a positive conclusion. NoteD I. This essaygrew out of adiscussionbetweenGeoffMulgan andmyself. I amindebtedto Tom Bentleyfor numerousanddetailed suggestionsandqueries.I alsobenefitted greatlyfrom commentsbyStevenLukes,JohnGray, Martin Albrow and RobinNiblett for commentson a previousdraft. I washelpedmuchby editorial assistanceby Natalie Klein, JenniferAmbrosino, andRachelMears andby researchassistanceby Matthew Home andJasonMarsh. A ratherdifferentversion of this essayis published intheUnited Statesunder the title Next: TheRoad to the GoodSociety, NewYork: Basic Books,2000. 2. E. Frazer, Official Fellow, Tutor, and Lecturer in Politics at the University of Oxford, has written that 'Tony Blair's communitarianism wasinfluenced by the philosophy of JohnMacMurray.' Frazer1999:25. 3. On this point seeChait 1998: 19. 4. According full attention tothe importanceof communitiesis what is mostlacking on the Third Way, which otherwiseretraces quite closely newcommunitarianthinking. OncommunitarianismseeEtzioni 1993; Etzioni 1996;Tam1998; Gray1996;Giddens 1998; Selznick 1992; The CommunitarianNetwork Website. 5. Seefor instanceAltman 1973; Barabaz1984: Johnson1976; Harrison etal. 1991. 6. The reasonfor this is thatsocial servicesarelabor intensive,and labor costsrise more rapidly than capital costsbecauselabor flows are not nearly asfluid and global ascapitalflows. Ergo, workers in onecountry have a greaterability to gain or maintain higher wages and benefits than those in anothercountry. In contrast, banks and other financial institutions cannot charge significantly higher interestratesthansimilar institutionsin othercountries.For instance,thedifferencesin yield thatAmericanand Europeanbanksprovide areminusculecomparedto the differences insalariesandbenefits theirworkersearn. Giventhat general inflation ratesreflect both labor and capital costs,and given that one componentB capital B is lower than the average,it is a mathematicalcertainty thatthe other B labor B will behigher. 7. For discussionof this concept,seeLeadbeater& Christie 1999aswell asLeadbeater1997. Seealso Etzioni 1993. 8. For more discussionseeLeadbeater1996. 9. For backgrounddiscussionsseeJupp1999; Gray1996;Hargreaves& Christie 1998; Hargreaves& Christie 1999;Kruger 1998; Mulganetal.1997. 10. To the extent thatthe Blair governmentis increasinglyseenasa 'nanny state' that nagsthe public andtries to establishmoral codesfrom above,a clarification of the government position on this issueseemsto becalledfor. II. The valuesenshrinedin thelawsof the stateinturn maybeassessedbydrawing on still moreencompassinglaws,suchasthose of the EU andtheUN. For more discussionseeEtzioni 1996: Chapter8. 12. As the UK movescloserto having a written constitution, or as it adoptsEU codes,the Americanmalaiseof litigiousnessmay becomemorecommonon theseshores.At thesametime itis not atall obviousthatwritten constitutionsare superiorto basiclaws, common law and strong democratictraditions. 13. While I generally agree with Anthony Giddens,we differ on this point. He writes, 'Government has a whole clusterof responsibilities for its citizensandothers,including theprotectionof thevulnerable. Old-style democracy,however,wasinclinedto treat rights asunconditional claims. With expanding individualism should come an extensionof individual obligations... As an ethical principle, "no rights withoutresponsibilities" must apply notonly to welfare recipients, but to everyone.' 14. To keep this crucial point in mind, one may refer to 'voluntary moral culture' as distinct from the coercive one, found in Afghanistan and Iran in an extremeform and, in more moderateways, in many non-freesocieties. 15. 'Inclusion refers in itsbroadestsenseto citizenship,to the civil andpolitical rights andobligations thatall membersof asocietY shouldhave,notjust formally, butasa realityof their lives' (Giddens1998:102-103).As Philip Selznick putit,' All personshave thesameintrinsic worth... Everyonewho is apersonisequally anobjectof moralconcern. This isthe essenceof justice.' Selznick addsthatthe most importantthreatto socialjustice is socialsubordination. Hencesocialpower should be'dispersedandbalanced' but not wiped out. SeeSelznickn.d.: 63. 16. IntheUnited States,the stateof Oregoncontributedto thedialogueonappropriatehealthcareprovisions. In itshealthcareplan, thestateranked688 medical proceduresaccordingto their costsandbenefits; ultimately, it wasdecided thatthe first 568services listed would becovered by the OregonMedicaid program.Whether or notthis was the right cutoff point cannot bedetermined without adetailedexaminationof theplan. The caseshows,however, thatthediscussionof what mustbeincluded can bemadein rather specific termsrather than asan abstractmoral principle (Houston Chronicle News Service1993). 17. The conditions under which 'trade offs' mayoccur is discussedat length in Etzioni 1999. Briefly, a trade off should be consideredonly if there isa major socialproblem,for instancethe rapid spreadof HIV, if thereareno effective treatmentsthat do not entail trade offs, and if the intrusions proffered areasminimal aspossible. 18. The problems that arise from the increasedcommercialization of the media and the concentration of ownershipdeservea separatetreatment. Suffice itto sayhere thatpublicly ownedandoperatedmediashouldbecherishedandsupportfor it expanded, bestby granting them largeendowments. 19. For further discussionof 'sciencecourts', see SmithII 1999. Seealso Mazur1993. 20. Thesecan beamelioratedto someextentby high levelsof immigration, but thatwould poseahostof challengesall by itself,by 34 deepeningthe tensionsraisedby multiculturalism. 21. One must, of course, stressthat no stigma should be attachedto families that cannot have children or seethemselvesas psychologically ill qualified to bring themup. 22. The latter provides couples with the opportunity to bind themselvesvoluntarily to higher level of commitmentby agreeingto participate in premarital counseling,counselingwhile married if onespouserequestsit, anddelayingdivorce for two yearsif one partnerfiles for it, except in caseswhere a crime hasbeencommitted. See,for example,Etzioni & Rubin1997. 23. This approachdeservessomeelaboration. Peoplewho areinclined to commit crimesaredeterredby two factors thatrelateto one anotherastwo variables in a mathematicalformula: sizeof penalty(Pe) multiplied by the probability of being caughtand punished(Pr) equalspublic safety. That is, ahigher level of public safetycan beachievedby increasingeithervariable. Given that Prcosts muchlessthan Pe inhumansocial andeconomicterms,increasingPr is obviouslypreferable. Moreover, given thatdata show1hatincreasesin Praremuch moreeffective than inPe,thesefactsaloneprovide acompelling reasonfor trying to increasePr ratherthan Pe inthe next years(Grogger 1991,seeespeciallypage304). 24. This is of coursemuch lessof anissuewhen unemploymentislow. However,having communityjobs asanintegralpart of the programis importantevenif thesejobs becomea major factor only inothersituations. 25. 1 draw hereon Mulgan etaI. 1997: 19. 26. Seethe community recycling initiatives describedin Murray 1999. 27. To whatextentthe EuropeanStructural Fund coversthis matterremainsto beestablished. 28. Someminimal useof traditional resourcesareinvolved, suchaschargesfor connectingto the internet,butthecostsfor theseare trivial. 29. Among themattersthatmayneedmore attentionarethewayscandidatesgetaroundexpenditurelimits by notreportingcertain costs,under-reporting expenses(such astravel expensesfor the candidateandhis family), and bystocking up on electioneering supplieswell before theelection. SeeKlein 1999. 30. For additional discussion,seeEtzioni 1998. 35 Literatuur Altman,I. 1973 'An EcologicalApproachto theFunctioningof SociallyIsolatedGroups',in: J.E.Rasmussen(ed.),Manin IsolationandConfinement,Chicago:Airline,241- 270. Anderson,B. 1991 ImaginedCommunities,London:Verso. Anderson,V. 1991 AlternativeEconomicIndicators,London:Routledge. Atkinson,D. 1994 TheCommonSenseofCommunity,London:Demos. Barabaz,A.F. 1984 'Antarctic Isolation and Imaginative Involvement:Preliminary Findings', InternationalJournal ofClinicalandExperimentalHypnosis32,296-300. Barber,B. 1998 APlaceFor Us:HowtoMakeSocietyCivil andDemocracyStrong,NewYork: Hill & Wang. Bellah,R.N. etal.1991 TheGoodSociety,NewYork: Knopf. Bentley,T. 1998 LearningBeyondtheClassroom,London:Routledge. Blair,T. 1997 NewBritain,Boulder:WestviewPress. Blair,T. 1998 TheThirdWay:NewPoliticsfor theNewCentury,London:FabianSociety. Blair,T. & G. Schroder1999 Europe:TheThirdWay/DieneueMitte,London:LabourPartyandSPD. Boswell,J. 1994 Communityand theEconomy:The TheoryofPublic Co-operation,London: Routledge. Briscoe,I. 1995 In WhoseService:Making CommunityService Workfor the Unemployed, London:Demos. Butcher,H. etat. (eds.)1993 CommunityandPublicPolicy,London:PlutoPress. Chait,J. 1998 'The SlipperyCenter',TheNewRepublic,November16,19. Clarke,R. (ed.)1990 EnterprisingNeighbours:The Developmentof the CommunityAssociation Movementin Britain,London:NFCO. Clear,T.R.& D.R.Karp 1999 TheCommunityJusticeIdeal,Boulder:WestviewPress. Coenen,H. & P. Leisink1993 Workand Citizenshipin theNewEurope,Aldershot:EdwardElgar. CommissiononGlobalGovernance1995 OurGlobalNeighbourhood,Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress. 36 Communitarian Network Website,The . Culpitt, I. 1992 Welfareand CitiZenship,London: Sage. Demaine,J. & H. Entwhistle (eds.) 1996 Beyond Communitarianism: Citizenship, Politics and Education, London: Macmillan. Dodd, P. 1995 TheBattle Over Britain, London: Demos. Donnison, D. 1991 A Radical Agenda: After theNew Right and the Old Left, London: Rivers Oram Press. Economist, The 1998 'Goldilocks Politics', The Economist,December19. E1shtain,J.B. 1989 Democracy on Trial, New York: Basic Books. Etzioni, A. 1993 The Spirit of Community: Rights, Responsibilities and the Communitarian Agenda,New York: Crown. Etzioni, A. 1996 TheNew GoldenRule: Communityand Morality in a D~mocratic Society,New York: Basic Books. Etzioni, A. 1998 'Voluntary Simplicity: Characterization,SelectPsychological Implications, and Societal Consequences',Journal ofEconomic Psychology 19-5,619-644. Etzioni, A. 1999 The Limits of Privacy, New York: Basic Books. Etzioni, A. 2001 Next: TheRoad to the GoodSociety,New York: BasicsBooks. Etzioni, A. & P. Rubin 1997 Opportuning Virtue: Lessons of the Louisiana Covenant Marriage Law, Washington, DC: The CommunitarianNetwork. Fratiglioni, L. etal. 2000 'Influence of Social Networks on Occurrence of Dementia', The Lancet 355- 9212, April15, 1315. Frazer,E. 1999 The Problems of CommunitarianPolitics: Unity and Conflict, Oxford: Oxford .University Press. Giddens,A. 1994 Beyond Left and Right: The Future of Radical Politics, Cambridge: Polity Press. Giddens,A. 1998 The Third Way: TheRenewal ofSocial Democracy,Cambridge: Polity Press. Goodhart, D.1994 TheReshaping ofthe GermanSocial Market, London: IPPR. 37 Gray, J. 1996 After Social Democracy: Politics, Capitalism and the Common Life, London: Demos. Grogger,J. 1991 'Certainty vs. Severityof Punishment',Economic Inquiry 29,297-309. Hall, J.A. (ed.), 1995 Civil Society,Cambridge: Polity Press. Hargreaves,I. & I. Christie 1998 Tomorrow's Politics, London: Demos. Hargreaves,I. & I. Christie 1999 To Our Mutual Advantage,London: Demos. Harrison, A.A. et al. 1991 From Antarctica to OuterSpace:Life in Isolation and Confinement,New York: Springer-Verlag. Hemerijck, A. & J. Visser2001 'The Dutch Model: An Obvious Candidate for the "Third Way"?' The European Journal ofSociology42-1,221-242. Hockey, L. 1997 Partners in Learning: Ten CommunityBasedCase Studies,London: LGMB. Houston Chronicle News Service 1993 'OK Expected for OregonHealth Plan', TheHouston Chronicle, March 18,AS. Hurley, M.L. & L. Schiff 1996 'This Town Made Wellnessa Way of Life', Businessand Health 14-12,39-43. Joas,H. 1994 'Communitarianism in Germany', TheResponsiveCommunity5-1,24-29. Johnson,R. 1976 Culture and Crisis in Confinement,Lexington: Lexington Books. Jupp,B. 1999 Living Together: CommunityLife on Mixed Tenure Estates,London: Demos. Klein, L. 1999 'On the Brink of Reform: Political Party Funding in Britain', Case Western ReserveJournal ofLaw 31-1,1-46. Koryushkin, A. & G. Meyer (eds.) 1999 Communitarianism, Liberalism, and the Quest for Democracy in PostCommunist Societies,St. Petersburg:St. PetersburgUniversity Press. Kruger, D. 1998 Access Denied?,London: Demos. Leadbeater,C. 1996 TheSelf-Policing Society,London: Demos. Leadbeater,C. 1997 Civic Spirit: TheBig Ideafor a New Political Era, London: Demos. Leadbeater,C. & S. Martin 1998 The Employee Mutual, London: Demos. Leadbeater,C. & I. Christie 1999 To Our Mutual Advantage,London: Demos. 38 Luke, J.S& K. R. Neville 1998 'Cl;Irbing Teen Pregnancy: A Divided Community Acts Together', The ResponsiveCommunity 8-3, 62-72. Mazur, A. 1993 'The ScienceCourt: Reminiscenceand Retrospective',Risk 4-1, 161. Miller, D. 1990 . Market, Stateand Community,Oxford: ClarendonPress. Miller, D. 1995 On Nationality, Oxford: ClarendonPress. Mulgan, G. 1997 Connexity:. How to Live in a Connected World, Boston: Harvard Business SchoolPress. Mulgan, G. et al. 1997 TheBritish Spring: A Manifestofor the ElectiQnAfter Next,London: Demos. Murray, R. 1999 Creating Wealth,London: Demos. Myers, D.G. 2000 The American Paradox: Spiritual Hunger in an Age of Plenty, New Haven: Yale Univeristy Press. Nathanson,S. 1998 Economic Justice,New York: Prentice Hall Academic. Oldfield, A. 1990 Citizenship and Community: Civic Republicanism and the Modern World, London: Routledge. Putnam,R.D. 2000 Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival ofAmerican Community,New York: Simon& Schuster. Sampson,R. 1997 'Neighborhoods and Violent Crime: A Multilevel Study of Collective Efficacy', Science277, August 14,918-924. Selznick,Ph. 1992 The Moral Commonwealth: Social Theory and the Promise of Community, Berkeley: University of California Press. Selznick,Ph.n.d. 'Social Justice: A Communitarian Perspective',manuscript. Smith II, G.P. 1999 'Judicial Decision Making in the Age of Biotechnology', Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics & Public Policy 13,93. . Srole,L. etal. 1962 Mental Health in the Metropolis: The Midtown Manhattan Study,New York: McGraw-Hill. Stuster,J. 1996 Bold Endeavors: Lessonsfrom Polar and SpaceExploration, Annapolis: Naval Institute Press. Tam,H.B. 1998 Communitarianism: A New Agenda for Politics and Citizenship, New York: New York University Press. 39 Teles,S.M.n.d. 'An Apologia for the Third Way', paperpresentedat a recentAmerican PoliticalScienceAssociationconvention. Walz,M. 1994 SocialIsolation and SocialMediatorsof theStressof Illness,Hamburg:Lit Verlag. Warpole,K. & L. Greenhalgh1997 ParkLife,London:Demos. Wilkinson,H. 1997 'No TurningBack', in: G. Mulgan(ed.),Life AfterPolitics: NewThinkingfor theTwenty-firstCentury,London:FontanaPress. Wilkinson,H. 1999 TheProposal:GivingMarriageBackto thePeople,London:Demos. Wuthnow,R. 1994 Sharing the Journey: Support Groups and America's New Questfor Community,NewYork: FreePress. 40 Disability & Society, Vol. 19, No. 3, May 2004 Social capital, social inclusion and services for people with learning disabilities Peter Batesa * and Fabian A. Davisb a National Development Team, Ipswich, UK; b Bromley Mental Health Services, Oxleas NHS Trust, Chislehurst, Kent, UK Both social capital and social inclusion have emerged as significant concepts for human services in the last decade and yet their inter-relationship remains largely unexplored. This article argues that, whilst they are similar in their vision for a healthy society, they adopt sufficiently different perspectives to stimulate and challenge each other. This can be well illustrated by reference to services for people with a learning disability. Commissioners and providers of learning disability services are encouraged through this article to harness both concepts in order to assist in the process of modernizing services and increasing life opportunities for the people they support. It is argued that it is not possible to understand the full consequences of adopting either theoretical position without an adequate understanding of the other. Examples are given of the implications of this for advocacy services, day opportunities, rural communities, transition and staff training. Introduction The concept of social capital (Putnam, 2000) has become popular just as the English White Paper ‘Valuing People’ (Department of Health, 2001b) has required learning disability services to work towards social inclusion. This article points a spotlight on useful insights in both social capital and social inclusion approaches that may help in the development of learning disability services, and notes some of the hazards of an unthinking adoption of either of these frameworks in isolation from the other. Social capital: investment in human society Mrs Rose has decided to re-open the old school in our village as a community centre. She sent round a questionnaire asking each household how they could contribute their time and skills. She had 94 responses—more than the number of households in the village. As she says, ‘I don’t know why I’m doing this. I’m nearly 80 and I won’t live to see this place open. But there’s such a lot of talent in this community and somebody’s got to get people together.’ I always had the capacity to get involved, but I’m only using my capacity because Mrs Rose asked. (Ritchie, 2001) Robert Putnam (2000) calls buildings, plant and equipment physical capital; people, *Corresponding author: National Development Team, Unit 10, Hill View Business Park, Old Ipswich Road, Claydon, Ipswich IP6 0AJ, UK. Email: pbates@ndt.org.uk ISSN 0968-7599 (print)/ISSN 1360-0508 (online)/04/030195-13  2004 Taylor & Francis Ltd DOI: 10.1080/0968759042000204202 196 P. Bates & F. A. Davis skills, knowledge and experience human capital; and social networks and norms of trust and reciprocity social capital. This distinction was taken up Prime Minister Tony Blair when he said that ‘in the future, we need to invest in social capital as surely as we invest in skills and buildings’ (Corrigan & Miller, 1999). Putnam (2000) goes on to observe that the term ‘social capital’ has been coined at least six times during the twentieth century, while Schuller (2000) has suggested that its roots lie in a variety of intellectual traditions, including Alexis de Tocqueville (1835) on voluntary associations, Elizabeth Bott (1957) on social networks, John Dewey (1929) on shared concerns, Jurgen Habermas (1984) on trust, Amitai Etzioni (1996) on communitarianism and Albert Bandura (1977) on self-efficacy. Despite this rich intellectual heritage, the notion of social capital remains fluid and lacks a precise definition, so, for example, Grootaert (2001) offers a list of 50 indicators that have been used in empirical studies, while the Social Action Research Project (Health Development Agency, 1999) baseline study used the following six components as a working definition: • Participation in the local community: do you think of yourself as part of the local area? Are you an active member of a local group? Have you participated in voluntary or religious activities? • Reciprocity: have you done or received a favour from someone living nearby? Do local people look after each other? Who would you turn to for advice or to share some good news? • Feelings of trust and safety: in your own home or going out at night. Have you been a victim of crime? Can people round here be trusted? • Social connections: have you chatted with family, friends or neighbours recently? Do you have close friends round here? How many people did you talk to yesterday? Do you go outside this area to visit your friends? • Citizen power: have you formally complained about a local service? Have you joined a committee to fight for a local cause? • Community perception: do you pick up other people’s rubbish? Do you enjoy living here? Are there enough community facilities and public transport? Social inclusion Social inclusion is another fluid term with a variety of meanings (Bates, 2002a). For the purposes of this article, social inclusion means ensuring that people with learning disabilities have full and fair access to activities, social roles and relationships directly alongside non-disabled citizens. Over the past 30 years an informal network of writers (Wolfensberger, 1972; O’Brien, 1987; Falvey et al., 1994; Rusch & Hughes, 1989) have shown how support can be provided so that people with disabilities can be employed rather than attend a sheltered workshop, live in their own home rather than in a hostel, and participate in friendships and community life with a diverse array of citizens, rather than conducting their whole lives within segregated disability services. Since New Labour established the Social Exclusion Unit in 1997 (Social Social capital, social inclusion and services 197 Exclusion Unit, 1998), the notion of social exclusion has also been used to embrace poverty, unemployment and threats to community safety, along with poor access to healthcare and decent housing. Recent policy convergence We would argue that social capital is an idea whose time has come. It has been enthusiastically adopted by the World Bank, American, European and UK governments, and has permeated the areas of health, education, community care, community regeneration and employment (Mitchell & Harrison, 2001). Increasing social capital is expected to generate improvements in all the above areas because it is argued that increased civic participation will invigorate government, information flowing through informal networks can enhance job prospects, supportive friendships buffer against distress and illness, reciprocal relationships create a culture where learning and contribution flourishes, and heightened trust leads to a reduction in crime. As such, social capital theory should be of interest to Local Strategic Partnerships, Learning Disability Partnership Boards, Health Improvement Programmes, Community Safety Partnerships, and a host of other initiatives that directly or indirectly impact the lives of people with learning disabilities. The 2001 White Paper ‘Valuing People’ (Department of Health, 2001b) introduces person-centred planning (O’Brien, 1987) as a driver to promote service change. The White Paper assumes that the majority of people with a learning disability will want to move towards an independent life in the community, leading to the demise of segregated services. A major part of this change is to be day service modernization by 2006 and the promotion of social inclusion will be an essential component of this change (Love et al., 2002). As a result, many services are looking towards social inclusion advocates and social ‘capitalists’ for a comprehensive and detailed conceptual framework within which to plan and manage such major change. Thus, developments in learning disability provision, social inclusion and social capital all meet in the growing policy emphasis upon citizenship, so that ‘the world disabled people will occupy will extend way beyond their specialist services’ (Simons, 1998). Contrasting social inclusion and social capital The introduction above has hinted at some significant challenges to learning disability services that emerge from singular analyses of the implications of adopting either a social capital or social inclusion perspective. The Health Development Agency’s framework for social capital is now used to look at some of these areas and to explore implications where the two theories need to be considered in tandem. Real examples from services for people with learning disabilities are used to illustrate the synergy or divergences between the two theoretical discourses. 198 P. Bates & F. A. Davis Participation in the local community Those people who have been deliberately segregated in prisons, long-stay hospitals and other institutions are rarely mentioned in social capital thinking, while social inclusion advocates strongly assert that society should find ways of bringing this group back home (Mansell, 1993). A brief glance at policy documents such as Valuing People would suggest that services should promote inclusion, but despite this, current service arrangements often segregate learning disabled people, particularly those with the least natural ability to articulate their interests. However, bringing people back home demands more than relocating their beds— relationships have to change as well. In both social capital and inclusion thinking, service users are recognized as citizens, and the traditional focus on the relationship between worker and service user is replaced by an emphasis upon the reciprocal relationship between citizen and community: Two women with learning disabilities wanted to take up yoga. No local groups existed, so the worker found a tutor and a community hall, and put adverts around the neighbourhood. A mixed group of citizens joined and everyone welcomed each other—including the people with learning disabilities. Nine years later the group is still running—long after the worker moved to another job. (Christine Burke, personal communication) This paradigm shift is also enacted as people are supported to take up open employment and to participate in community Timebanks (Reed & Boyle, 2002) and local exchange trading schemes (Seyfang, 2001). Advocates of social inclusion have rightly highlighted the importance of waged employment as a route to income, status and relationships, while social capitalists point the spotlight on informal roles and relationships. In addition to the opportunity to earn a wage, people with learning disabilities may participate in the community via education, volunteering or leisure pursuits. Mainstream learning providers have a renewed focus upon developing citizens’ social and civic skills, and this may lead to a renaissance of non-vocational training to counter the recent emphasis upon developing only those skills that directly contribute to the economy. Such a shift in emphasis would have a disproportionately beneficial effect upon people with learning disabilities. Similarly, a social capital perspective highlights the benefits of volunteering. For many years, services have arranged a few opportunities for people with learning disabilities to become volunteers in the community. Each placement must find a path between employment (volunteering as work simulation in order to attain vocational experience and skills) and community participation (volunteering as a means to harness altruistic endeavour and build affiliation and membership). Social capitalists helpfully wrest volunteering back from a single-minded attempt to use volunteering solely as work preparation and remind us that volunteering builds community, trust and reciprocity. Care is needed to ensure that volunteering opportunities are safe, rewarding, and respectful and contribute to the formation of social capital (Bates, 2002b): The VALUES project based at Leicester Volunteer Centre supports people with Social capital, social inclusion and services 199 learning disabilities to contribute their time and skills to the local community. Individuals make a difference in the museum, charity shops, environmental projects, and lunch clubs—all sorts of places. Reciprocity The way in which people with learning disabilities are perceived by others can be even more important to their capacity to contribute to the development of social capital and their own social inclusion than their disability. For example, if members of the public label people with learning disabilities as fraudulent, attention seeking, disinterested in civic affairs or unable to make a positive contribution to the community, this will limit their potential for reciprocal relationships with nondisabled community members. While it can be hard to identify the unique contribution that a particular person enjoys making and for which they will be genuinely appreciated, without opportunity this may never be discovered at all. The two theoretical positions bring complimentary insights to the topic of reciprocity. Putnam (2000) makes a distinction between bonding and bridging relationships in which bonding relationships form between people who share a common bond, while bridging relationships bring diverse people together. Respectful bonding relationships between people with learning disabilities are important, of course, but social inclusion theorists envisage a society in which bridging relationships span all the structural divisions in society (Amado, 1993). An included life with an ordinary home, job and leisure pursuits (rather than segregated in residential units, day centres and ‘group trips’) is a prerequisite for building these socially inclusive bridging relationships. Social inclusion theorists argue that society should nurture relationships between people with a learning difficulty and those without (e.g. Amado, 1993) and assert that everyone can feel at home in mainstream society, while social capital theorists do not make this explicit. Any service would be limited by adopting a social capital analysis alone as this could lead to a diminished vision that confined bonding relationships to those between peers in a day centre and bridging relationships to those that formed between centres, such as at the Special Olympics. Bridging social capital provides what Granovetter (1973) referred to as weak ties—a valuable source of information and contacts that can help people with everything from job-finding to problem solving. Similarly, while Putnam rather derides ‘mail-order’ membership, belonging to an association that collects subscriptions and provides publicity can contribute to a sense of identity and provide material for conversation with others. Social capital reminds us of the importance of nurturing these connections with ‘insignificant others’ alongside more intimate connections: Building sustainable relationships Seventeen people with learning disabilities have fenced 144 gardens on the Oakwood Estate in Bridgend. As well as forming a tight-knit team, they have gained work experience and qualifications in amenity horticulture by linking with the local college. One group member said ‘my self esteem has improved, I feel physically fitter and I feel 200 P. Bates & F. A. Davis being part of the group is helpful for character building.’ Using locally grown renewable timber, the fencing has created ‘defensible spaces’ as a means of reducing crime and nuisance. Stolen cars used to be driven on the lawns between the houses, but now that the gardens are in place there is no room. They say that it is all about creating sustainable projects and sustainable relationships. The people with learning disabilities feel safe and welcome on the estate. Local residents hold the project in very high esteem and they advocate for and defend its members if the need arises. Local children have joined in with painting the fences during school holidays, leading to a reduction in vandalism. One tenant said, ‘We find that friends and neighbours are far more willing to pull together and to help each other, and are once more gaining pride and enjoyment in our community’. Feelings of trust and safety Putnam’s position moves us from the privacy of a friendship into the public arena by including the concept of ‘thin trust’ in his description of social capital. Thin trust is present when strangers view each other as potential friends and absent when they regard each other as potential enemies. Campbell’s team (1999) failed to find much thin trust in an English housing estate, and the MENCAP (1999) inquiry into bullying showed just how reasonable it is for many people with learning disability to avoid public spaces and public transport, especially the school run. Unfortunately, inclusion advocates tend to ignore the shameful reality of bullying, oppression and discrimination that is a daily experience for many people with learning disabilities (MENCAP, 1999). It is curious to note that Valuing People is silent on the matter of bullying, while the Department of Health does require mental health services to address it (Department of Health, 2001a). It is here that social capitalists have the advantage, since their goal of increasing thin trust precisely attends to this agenda. We all have to run the gauntlet of meeting strangers from time to time and negotiate our way through thin trust in order to locate the new friends and colleagues with whom we might enjoy thick trust, but there are extra challenges for visible minorities, and this includes some people with learning disabilities. Social capitalists task us with addressing these problems by challenging media stereotypes, providing learning disabilities equality training, and actively promoting positive relationships between people with and without disabilities. While social capitalists are developing instruments to measure these things, they have no guidance to offer on which tools are needed to make these changes, so we must look for advice to inclusion advocates, as well as media studies, community development, health promotion and students of the social psychology of stigma. Inclusion advocates who wish to build links with community development workers may find that social capital is the linking concept that will bring them together. Any examination of trust and safety quickly moves into a consideration of structural inequalities. Despite this, few inclusion advocates or social capitalists have given much attention to the way in which structural inequalities around race or gender impact upon the lives of people with learning disabilities. Social capital can systematically oppress women (Riddell et al., 2001), people from black and ethnic Social capital, social inclusion and services 201 minority communities (Campbell & MacLean, 2002), people with disabilities, and, as Putnam notes, terrorist groups are strong on bonding relationships. Campbell (2000) sums all this up as ‘antisocial capital’, although it is likely that many groups have a mixture of benevolent and toxic effects, and few, if any, are unambiguously virtuous or destructive. Staff will need to respond to these complexities at a number of levels. First, a focus on leisure and voluntary participation in the community will require services to offer support in the evenings and weekends in ordinary community locations away from learning disability premises, and so working arrangements will need to support these activities. Secondly, staff will need to respond imaginatively to bullying, thin trust and structural inequality. Social connections Both social inclusion and social capital theorists invite us to think about people with learning disabilities as citizens who are able to make a contribution to the whole community. This clashes with the current reality, where perhaps only a third of the people utilizing learning disability services have even one non-disabled friend (Robertson et al., 2001). Friendships between people with learning disabilities and non-disabled people must overcome some difficulties, especially where there are inequities in communication skills, disposable income and freedom of choice (Zetlin & Murtaugh, 1988), but can be very rewarding for participants (Newton et al., 1995). Indeed, we think that people with learning disabilities may well have the potential to make an above-average contribution to the community. Inclusion advocates have been eager to support people with learning disabilities to take up positive social roles, such as householder, employee or student. While lip service has been paid to participation as well as presence in the community, social capitalists insist that attention is given to the quality of social relationships in these settings. Simply achieving the status of a student does not build social capital if there are few opportunities for networking and relationship building. Bridging relationships with non-disabled students are not enhanced if the student is attending a special class, at a special time and taking lunch in a special, segregated cafeteria. Just as important is the support that is made available, for co-location alone does not guarantee the development of friendships. So, for example, poorly skilled jobcoaches may unwittingly detach learning disabled workers from their non-disabled work colleagues in order to provide intensive task training. There are also particular challenges that arise from taking a focus on informal and unregulated relationships. A learning disabled customer is legally entitled to fair and equal service from the bar staff, but the Disability Discrimination Act 1995 does not govern the behaviour of other drinkers in the public house. This means that a host of awkward, unfriendly or downright hostile responses may be more in evidence in unregulated social relationships—exactly in those areas that are well covered by social capitalists. A second reason why discrimination may be amplified in unregulated relationships revolves around the practical transaction with the bar staff. This is governed by 202 P. Bates & F. A. Davis clear rules for the encounter (placing an order, pulling the pint, paying for the drink), while the informal connections with other drinkers in the pub are less defined and, consequently, more difficult to negotiate. Similarly, in the workplace, practical tasks may enable people with learning disabilities to demonstrate their abilities at work and so allow social interaction to grow as their competence is recognized, whilst equal opportunities policies constrain potentially negative responses of colleagues. In contrast, unregulated places that are about talking and little else may provide few opportunities for this kind of broader relationship to emerge and so people who don’t seem to fit in may be more comprehensively ostracized. One person said, ‘I have a job, but no-one wants to go out with me in the evenings’. Social capitalists demand that these challenges are addressed. An analysis of social capital through the life-course reveals how there are particular rites of passage when capital accrues or is lost. A move into residential care, perhaps on the death of a parent, can wipe out stocks of social capital—especially if it involves relocation into a different neighbourhood (Riddell et al., 2001). Indeed, entry into any care system may burn-off social connections, trust and reciprocity. Staff need to be aware that addressing these issues can be just as important as the selection of appropriate accommodation, medication or counselling. Citizen power Both social inclusion and social capital theories offer a familiar challenge in this domain—that of increasing service user participation and advocacy. Traditional services have been characterized by ‘vertical’ relationships in which staff hold power over service users, while social capitalists and service user advocates seek ‘horizontal’ relationships (Riddell et al., 1999). There are a number of potential pit falls to watch out for here. As a social capital perspective gains ground, there are the ever-present dangers to be avoided, includ- ing: • preferring ‘white’ social capital over culturally diverse manifestations of relationships, trust and civic participation; • adding informal community connections to the list of things that it is acceptable to ‘prescribe’ for people using services; • reproducing traditional power relationships of control and containment within new community locations; • that individuals who do not engage may be blamed for their situation. From our experience these problems can come about because both social capital and inclusion theorists risk unduly focusing on ‘slotting in’, rather than transforming society. From this standpoint, society is perceived as fundamentally just and stable, so that learning disability services simply need to locate a menu of vacant slots and help the person to decide what they would like to do, learn the correct behaviour and then engage in the social opportunity of their choice. Bourdieu (1983) challenges this perception by reminding us how the ‘old boy’ networks use social capital to Social capital, social inclusion and services 203 maintain their power and control, and advises us that this kind of social capital should be dismantled and replaced by more equitable relationships. Paradoxically and despite the above we suggest that it is also vital to take an optimistic overview of communities. Reviews of supported employment (Riddell et al., 1997) and volunteering (Bates, 2001b) note that expansion of the service is restricted, not by a shortage of ‘hosts’ willing to offer opportunities to people with learning disabilities, but by a shortage of state funding and therefore support staff. By extension we may assume that there will be plenty of informal social settings that would welcome people with learning disabilities, so long as we could arrange adequate support. A further example of the synergy possible by taking a dual perspective involves advocacy services. These have devoted much time to supporting people with learning disabilities to engage in formal decision-making processes. Service users have learnt how committees work, how records are kept and distributed, as well as the subtler tasks of lobbying and negotiating with senior managers. Meanwhile, social capitalists have observed that, while the general membership of civic and community associations have been falling, there has been an even faster decline in the number of people willing to take office in these associations. In addition, recent urban regeneration and service improvement strategies have emphasized the value of public consultation and involvement, and sought new methods of reaching traditionally excluded groups. This means that market expansion and labour shortages in these community and civic associations neatly coincides with a new generation of skilled and experienced people who happen to also have a learning difficulty. Advocacy groups that have traditionally focused on long-term bonding in order to reform the learning disability service could build bridging relationships with local community organizations and campaigns. Some people with learning disabilities might eventually leave the advocacy group in order to join other advocates for the local community improvements that most interest them as citizens. While there is general approval for specific social roles, such as that of employee or student, taking an active part in civic, political or informal associations does not earn universal praise. Staff operate within a contemporary society that appears to place great store on garden redesign, for example, but which ridicules train spotting. This might result in staff feeling comfortable about arranging a taxi for the learning disabled person who wants to attend the agricultural college, but the same worker may be less willing to arrange transport to a meeting of the local branch of railway enthusiasts! Separating out one’s rights as a citizen from one’s rights as an employee or for that matter as a service user, can lead to contradictory allegiances for staff. A person’s interests or eagerness to write to the newspapers about litter may embarrass the day service staff member or spill over into unwelcome publicity for an employer. Despite this, social capitalists demand that we support people with learning disabilities who wish to vote, contribute to public discussions or agitate for social change. In addition, those who provide formal or informal civic education should be equally interested in the parallel questions, ‘How do I contribute to my community?’ and ‘How can I transform my community?’ Paulo Freire (1972) and other educators 204 P. Bates & F. A. Davis of the liberation school have shown how the task of transforming society can be attempted through alliances between disabled and non-disabled people; that is, through the development of bridging social capital. Community perception In a recent training seminar, one day-centre worker described his own leisure time as occupied entirely with solitary visits to the off-licence and watching TV game shows, and therefore he did not see why isolation was a problem for disabled people. We do not know if staff in learning disability services engage in community life to a greater or lesser extent than the average, but it is likely that the personal attitudes of staff will have a real impact on the lives of service users. This is illustrated by a Department of Health study where inappropriate staff attitudes and behaviour was the most frequently cited barrier to access by disabled people (Disability Matters Limited & NHS Executive, 1999). This suggests that there is some danger of staff defining service users’ lives by their own personal choice of lifestyle, either by assuming that people with learning disabilities will not be interested in community engagement or by evangelically promoting their own personal interests. Staff in learning disability services may also favour urban settings, as they appear to offer more venues to people who use services, despite the high transport costs of bringing everyone into a single point. Small, rural communities have fewer events and buildings, but arguably more networks and informal opportunities to connect. When there are more bridging relationships between groups in small communities, positive or negative reputations can also spread quickly, and create or deny a new resident a chance of a fresh start in a new social setting. This means that workers engaged in community relocation should recognize informal networks as sources of social capital and develop strategies in supporting service users to navigate them successfully. Staff and other allies therefore have a two-fold task: to recognize the unique individuality of the learning disabled person and to similarly recognize the unique attributes of the many available communities to which that person might contribute. Such creative and individualized responses defy simple categorizations and press us to create systems that promote artistry, rather than the regimented production of standardized care packages. Since people with learning disabilities are likely to want and need unique arrangements, there is a danger that the introduction of standard monitoring systems will close down their leisure options to those listed on monitoring forms, whilst treating the richness of local human communities as no more than an arrangement of blank, featureless buildings and facilities. Discussion Attention to social capital is welcome as long as this emphasis does not eclipse other important goals in the minds of service developers. For example, Wilkinson (1996) asserts that income inequality is a fundamental cause of health inequality and that Social capital, social inclusion and services 205 social capital plays no more than a mediating role in this relationship, while Putnam (2000) sees social capital as the primary factor. We would argue therefore that working on social capital must not become a cheap alternative to reducing income inequality and must not divert us from the task of developing services that provide for basic human dignity (Morgan, 2001). As long as many learning disabled people lack a decent home, satisfactory income, good health, meaningful employment, and freedom from discrimination and abuse they are unlikely to view or be viewed as an asset to their neighbourhoods. The complimentary relationship between social inclusion and social capital reminds us that promoting social capital as a human service aim is a legitimate and long-term solution to the isolation and segregation of many devalued groups. However, it is not a panacea and needs bolstering with other approaches. Social capitalists collect a diverse array of data from whole populations, as illustrated by the range of issues under discussion. As there are a host of comparative indicators already in use with the general population, some of these might also be suitable for collecting aggregate data about people with learning disabilities and comparing findings with the general population in order to discover the size of the ‘inclusion gap’ (Love et al., 2002). However, population-level data is a poor source of guidance for what to offer to named individuals, and so care is needed in interpreting these findings: Sue lives in a suburb and works long hours in the city. She leaves early each morning and gets home late at night. Almost every weekend she travels to visit friends in other parts of the country. As a result, she does not know her neighbours. Despite her house being often empty, she is safe from burglary as many of her neighbours are unemployed and they maintain a vigorous neighbourhood watch group. Social inclusion theorists would look at Sue’s connections with her neighbours, while social capitalists look at the whole street and recognize that she benefits from the social capital built up by her neighbours. At the individual level, those staff who work on developing social capital therefore also need to be skilled in recognizing other factors and have access to the expertise of social inclusion advocates in how to choose, get and keep a home, a job and a social life. Managers should be aware of the tension and difference in priorities that each theoretical position taken on its own could have on resource allocation, and strike an appropriate balance that supports people who use services and simultaneously invests in the whole community. Service designers need to strike a balance between attempting to develop new ‘social capital or inclusion projects’, and the subtler task of threading the approach through existing services. Conclusion If interpreted with care, the concept of social capital provides a helpful additional perspective to learning disability services that are striving to promote social inclusion. The relationship is reciprocal, however, as inclusion advocates working with learning disabled people have insights and experience that will support the pro- 206 P. Bates & F. A. Davis motion of social capital for the whole community, as well as service users. Finally, many of the issues that have been highlighted in this article apply equally to many other groups who are at risk of exclusion. There is room for further dialogue. References Amado, A.N. (Ed.) (1993) Friendships and community connections between people with and without developmental disabilities (Baltimore, Paul H Brookes). Bandura, A. (1977) A social learning theory (New Jersey, Prentice Hall). Bates, P. (Ed.) (2002a) Working for inclusion (London, Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health). Bates, P. (2002b) A real asset: a manual for supported volunteering (Manchester: National Development Team). Bott, E. (1957) Family and social network (London, Tavistock). Bourdieu, P. (1983) The forms of capital, in: A. H. Halsey, H. Lauder, P. Brown & A. Stuart Wells (Eds) Education: culture, economy, society (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Campbell, C. (2000) Social capital and health: contextualizing health promotion within local community networks, in: S. Baron, J. Field & T. Schuller (Eds) Social capital: critical perspectives (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Campbell, C. & MacLean, C. (2002) Ethnic identities, social capital and health inequalities: factors shaping African-Caribbean participation in local community networks, Social Science and Medicine, 55(4), 643–657. Campbell, C., Wood, R. & Kelly, M. (1999) Social capital and health (London, Health Education Authority). Corrigan, P. & Miller, C. (1999) Social capital: the basic building block of social cohesion— management briefing, August 1999 (London, Office for Public Management). Department of Health (2001a) Making it happen: a guide to delivering mental health promotion, implementation plan for Standard One of the National Service Framework for Mental Health (London, Department of Health). Department of Health (2001b) Valuing people: a new strategy for learning disability for the 21st century, Department of Health Cmd 5806 (London, DoH). De Tocqueville, A. (1835) Democracy in America, Volume 1. Available online at: http:// xroads.virginia. edu/ ϳHYPER/DETOC/toc indx.html (accessed 16 July 2003). Dewey, J. (1929/1958) Experience and nature (New York, Dover). Disability Matters Limited and NHS Executive (1999) Working in partnership to implement Section 21 of the Disability Discrimination Act 1995 across the NHS. Available online at: www.doh.gov.uk/pub/docs/doh/section21dda.pdf (accessed 16 July 2003). Etzioni, A. (1996) The new golden rule: community and morality in a democratic society (New York, Basic Books). Falvey, M., Forest, M., Pearpoint, J. & Rosenberg, R. (1994) All my life’s a circle: using the tools: circles, MAPS and PATH (Toronto, Inclusion Press). Freire, P. (1972) Pedagogy of the oppressed (Harmondsworth, Penguin). Granovetter, M.S. (1973) The strength of weak ties, American Journal of Sociology, 78, 1360– 1380. Grootaert, C. (2001) Social capital the missing link? in: P. Dekker & E. M. Uslaner (Eds) Social capital and participation in everyday life (London, Routledge). Habermas, J. (1984) The theory of communicative action: reason and the rationalization of society (Boston, Beacon Press). Health Development Agency (1999) Social Action Research Project. Available online at: www.hadonline.org.uk/html/resources/websites.html (accessed 16 July 2003). Social capital, social inclusion and services 207 Love, W., Bates, P. & Whitehead, S. (2002) Day Service Modernization Toolkit Part 1 (Bristol, Valuing People Support Team). Available online at: http://www.valuingpeople.gov.uk/documents/DayService1.pdf (accessed 18 March 2004). Mansell, J. (Chair) (1993) Services for people with learning disabilities and challenging behaviour or mental health needs (London, Department of Health. HMSO). MENCAP (1999) Living in fear (London, MENCAP). Mitchell, D. & Harrison, M. (2001) Studying employment initiatives for people with mental health problems in developing countries: a research agenda, Research and Development in Primary Care, 2, 107. Morgan, A. (2001) Overview and progress report on the Health Development Agency’s programme of research on social capital and health (London, Health Development Agency). Newton, J., Olson, D. & Horner, R. (1995) Factors contributing to the stability of social relationships between individuals with mental retardation and other community members, Mental Retardation, 33, 383–393. O’Brien, J. (1987) A guide to lifestyle planning: using the activities catalog to integrate services and natural support systems, in: B. Wilcox & G. T. Bellamy (Eds) A comprehensive guide to the activities catalog: an alternative curriculum for youth and adults with severe disabilities (Baltimore, Paul H Brookes). Putnam, R.D. (2000) Bowling alone: the collapse and revival of American community (New York, Simon Schuster). Reed, Z. & Boyle, D. (2002) Growing strong communities, in: P. Bates (Ed.) Working for inclusion (London, Sainsbury Centre for Mental Health). Riddell, S., Baron, S., Stalker, K. & Wilkinson, H. (1997) The concept of the learning society for adults with learning disabilities: human and social capital perspectives, Journal of Education Policy, 12(6), 473–483. Riddell, S., Baron, S. & Wilson, A. (1999) Social capital and people with learning difficulties, Studies in the Education of Adults, 31(1), 49–65. Riddell, S., Wilson, A. & Baron, S. (2001) Gender, social capital and lifelong learning for people with learning difficulties, International Studies in Sociology of Education, 11(1), 3–23. Ritchie, P. (2001) The future’s purple, paper given at the SHS conference, Edinburgh 24–25 May. Robertson, J., Emerson, E., Gregory, N., Hatton, C., Kessissoglou, S., Hallam, A. & Linehan, C. (2001) Social networks of people with intellectual disabilities in residential settings, Mental Retardation, 39, 201–214. Rusch, F.R. & Hughes, C. (1989) Overview of supported employment, Journal of Applied Behavior Analysis, 22(4), 351–363. Schuller, T. (2000) Exploiting social capital: learning about learning, inaugural lecture at Birkbeck College, 9 February 2000. Seyfang, G. (2001) Spending time, building communities: evaluating time banks and mutual volunteering as a tool for tackling social exclusion, Voluntary Action: The Journal of the Institute of Volunteering Research, 4(1), 29–48. Simons, K. (1998) Home, work and inclusion: the social policy implications of supported living and employment for people with learning disabilities (York, Joseph Rowntree Foundation). Social Exclusion Unit (1998) Bringing Britain together: a national strategy for neighbourhood renewal, Cmd 4045 (London, Stationery Office). Wilkinson, R.G. (1996) Unhealthy societies: the afflictions of inequality (London, Routledge). Wolfensberger, W. (1972) Normalization: the principle of normalisation in human services (Toronto, National Institute on Mental Retardation). Zetlin, A.G. & Murtaugh, M. (1988) Friendship patterns of mildly learning handicapped and nonhandicapped high school students, American Journal on Mental Retardation, 92, 447– 454. 7 How to Write a Research Proposal? 7 1. Esterberg, Kristin G. 2002. "Strategies for beginning research." Pp. 25-41 in Qualitative Methods in Social Research. Boston: McGraw-Hill. 2. Henn, Matt, Mark Weinstein, and Nick Foard. 2006. "Designing a Research Proposal." Pp. 249-272 in A Short Introduction to Social Research. London: SAGE Publications. N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J gU.’))’). 2U*UxJ,/ CsOOEIC 7OSROsgc TfsRs OF osCEIa wU♦♦’). *♦xJ♦U- ’* —'♦U) —)U —' ♦/U /xJ-U*♦ ♦x*q* '—J VU.’))’). JU*UxJ,/UJ* 5—š -— #—! q)—š ’' #—! /x>U x .——- ’-Ux '—J x JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦v 5—š ,x) #—! ♦Ujj ’' ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦ ’* -—xVjUv 0!*♦ x* ’(K—J♦x)♦m /—š ,x) #—! ♦Ujj ’' ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ ’* š—J♦/ -—’).v M>U) UèKUJ’U),U- JU*UxJ,/UJ* *—(UP ♦’(U* /x>U ♦J—!VjU '’)-’). x ♦—K’,m VU.’))’). x )Uš JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦m '’.!JP ’). —!♦ /—š ♦— *♦xJ♦m ,/——*’). x JU*UxJ,/ *♦Jx♦U.#m —J -U>Uj—K’). x .U)UJxj JU*UxJ,/ Kjx) F/U '’J*♦ *♦UK ’) x)# JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦ ’* -U,’-’). —) x .U)UJxj ♦—K’, x)♦/U) JU'’)’). ♦/U ♦—K’, N!KK—*U #—! xJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) /—(UjU**)U** —J ’) *♦!-U)♦*e xj,—/—j !*U 5—(UjU**)U** ’) .U)UJxj š—!j- VU 'xJ ♦—— V’. x ♦—K’,«U>U) '—J *—(U—)U -—’). x ”/ : -’**UJ♦x♦’—)«*— #—! š—!j- /x>U ♦— '’)- x šx# ♦— (xqU #—!J JU*UxJ,/ (—JU (x)x.UxVjU b—! ,—!j- '—,!* —) ­!*♦ —)U x*KU,♦ —' /—(UjU**)U**m *!,/ x* ♦/U UèKUJ’U),U* —' š—JqUJ* ’) /—(UjU** */Uj♦UJ* —J ♦/U U''U,♦* —' /—(UjU**)U** —) ,/’j-JU) F— )xJJ—š -—š) ♦/U ♦—K’, —' *♦!-U)♦ xj,—/—j !*Um #—! ,—!j- '—,!* —) ♦/U J—jU —' xj,—/—j x♦ *♦!P -U)♦ KxJ♦’U* —J ♦/U U''U,♦* —' xj,—/—j ,—)*!(K♦’—) —) x,x-U(’, x,/’U>UP (U)♦ b—! xj*— )UU- ♦— ♦/’)q xV—!♦ ♦/U -’''UJU)♦ xKKJ—x,/U* #—! ,—!j- ♦xqU ♦— #—!J JU*UxJ,/m x* JU'jU,♦U- ’) ♦/U KxJx-’.(* -’*,!**U- ’) 4/xK♦UJ c g!♦ š/x♦ -— #—! -— ’' #—! -—)í♦ q)—š š/x♦ .U)UJxj ♦—K’, ’)♦UJU*♦* #—!v 5—š -— #—! VU.’) ♦/U)v iT ih 45p”FM2 i N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J gU.’))’). 2U*UxJ,/ CsIsRSOEIC EgsS7 5—š -— #—! .U)UJx♦U !*U'!jm ’)♦UJU*♦’). ’-Ux*v A♦í* /xJ- ♦— .’>U *—!)- x->’,U —) '’)-’). .——- JU*UxJ,/ ♦—K’,*m '—J *U>UJxj JUx*—)* H)U KJ—VjU( ’* ♦/x♦ šU -—)e♦ !*!xjj# ♦/’)q xV—!♦ š/UJU .——- ’-Ux* ,—(U 'J—( F/U# *UU( *—(UP /—š *UJU)-’K’♦—!*m x *♦J—qU —' (x.)’'’,U)♦ j!,q N!KK—*U #—! xJU šxjq’). -—š) ♦/U *♦JUU♦ x)- *!--U)j# )—♦’,U ♦/x♦ (—*♦ —' ♦/U *♦JUU♦j’./♦* xJU —!♦ —) —)U Vj—,q V!♦ '!),♦’—)’). —) ♦/U )Uè♦ b—! xj*— )—♦’,U ♦/x♦ ♦/U ♦Jx*/ *UU(* ♦— VU K’,qU- !K —) ♦/x♦ Vj—,q V!♦ )—♦ —) ♦/U '’J*♦ —)U F/’* jUx-* #—! ♦— š—)-UJ xV—!♦ /—š -’''UJU)♦ )U’./V—J/——-* .x’) x,,U** ♦— ,’♦# *UJ>’,U* HJ *!KK—*U #—! JUx- x) xJ♦’,jU ’) ♦/U )Uš*KxKUJ —J *UU x KJ—.Jx( —) F7 ♦/x♦ *KxJq* #—!J ,!J’—*’♦# xV—!♦ /—š /—(UjU** KU—KjU *!J>’>U ’) ♦/U š’)♦UJ ’) ,—j- ,j’(x♦U* HJ (x#VU #—! /x>U x j—).P*♦x)-’). ’)♦UJU*♦ ’) *K—J♦* —J #—!). ,/’j-JU)m x)- *— JU*UxJ,/ ’-Ux* *UU( ♦— ,—(U )x♦!Jxjj# F/U*U xJU xjj jU.’♦’(x♦U šx#* ♦— ’-U)♦’'# x JU*UxJ,/ ♦—K’, A' #—! -—)í♦ /x>U x)# ’)♦UJU*♦* x♦ xjjm #—!íjj '’)- ’♦ -’''’,!j♦ ♦— '’)- x) ’)♦UJU*♦’). JU*UxJ,/ ♦—K’, g!♦ (—*♦ —' !* xJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) x♦ jUx*♦ ­8z-'0:J1o H'♦U)m ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/UJ* VU.’) š/UJU ♦/U# xJU F/x♦ ’*m ♦/U# j——q x♦ ♦/U’J —š) j’>U* ♦— *UU ’' ♦/U# ,x) '’)- x)#♦/’). ’)♦UJU*♦’). ♦— *♦!-#m x) !)P !*!xj x).jU —J K!❖❖j’). U>U)♦ —J K/U)—(U)—) F/U) ♦/U# ♦J# ♦— JU'’)U ♦/U ♦—K’, ’)♦— x (—JU (x)x.UxVjU«x)- JU*UxJ,/xVjU«'—J( B—J Uèx(KjUm 4xJ—j BJUU-(x)m x .Jx-!x♦U *♦!-U)♦ Jx’*’). x #—!). ,/’j-m )UU-U- ♦— -— x JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦ '—J x ,—!J*U —) JU*UxJ,/ (U♦/—-* N/U /xVUU) KxJ♦’,’Kx♦’). ’) x (—♦/UJ*e .J—!Km x)- *— */U -U,’-U- ♦— *♦!-# ’♦ F/U KJ—­U,♦ U>U)♦!xjj# VU,x(U /UJ (x*♦UJí* ♦/U*’*m ♦’♦jU- ®NU♦♦’). N♦x#Px♦P5—(U N♦x)-xJ-*? p) M♦/)—.JxK/’, N♦!-# —' ♦/U N—!♦/jx)- Y—♦/UJ* p**—,’x♦’—)$ sBJUU-(x) cRRWS Mjj’—♦ “’UV—š šJ—♦U ’) ♦/U KJU'x,U ♦— /’* V——q M-)) M0-z O08 p xz ♦/x♦ /U /x- VUU) -’x.)—*U- š’♦/ ,x),UJ x)- /x- x j’(’♦U- j’'U UèKU,♦x),#m *— /U -U,’-U- ♦— >—j!)♦UUJ x♦ x *—!K q’♦,/U) p* /U K!♦ ’♦m ®A -’- )—♦ šx)♦ ♦— *KU)(# jx*♦ (—)♦/* —) ♦/U ci♦/ 'j——J —' x .—>UJ)(U)♦ —''’,U V!’j-’).m *— x♦ TI A JU♦’JU- —) -’*xV’j’♦# 'J—( (# ­—V —' iaP*—(U #UxJ* x* x) x)♦/J—K—j—.’*♦ š’♦/ ♦/U ux♦’—)xj A)*♦’♦!♦U —' YU)♦xj 5Uxj♦/C scRRlm K >’’’S gU,x!*U /U 'Uj♦ KJU♦♦# .——- '—J x j—♦ j—).UJ ♦/x) /U UèKU,♦U-m /U *♦xJ♦U- >—j!)♦UUJ’). x♦ x /—(UjU** */Uj♦UJ x* šUjj 5U VU,x(U ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) ♦/U j’>U* —' ♦/U š—(U) x♦ ♦/U */Uj♦UJm *— /U VU.x) ♦xq’). '’Uj- )—♦U* x)- ♦/’)q’). xV—!♦ ♦/U */Uj♦UJ* x* x *’♦U ’) š/’,/ ♦— -— JU*UxJ,/ Oj♦’(x♦Uj#m /U -’- x) ’)P-UK♦/ *♦!-# —' ♦/U j’>U* —' /—(UjU** š—(U) H♦/UJ JU*UxJ,/UJ*m ♦——m /x>U šJ’♦♦U) xV—!♦ /—š ♦/U# -U>Uj—KU- ♦/U’J JU*UxJ,/ ’)♦UJU*♦* “#)) :x>’-(x) scRRRS šJ—♦U xV—!♦ ♦/U UèKUJ’U),U —' j—*’). /UJ (—♦/UJ ♦— ,x),UJ š/U) */U šx* cl x)- /—š ♦/x♦ */xKU- /UJ wU)UJx♦’). A-Ux* iW -U,’*’—) ♦— *♦!-# š/x♦ */U ,xjj* ®(—♦/UJj—** $ F/U K—’)♦ ’*m ’' #—! j——q xJ—!)- x♦ #—!J —š) U)>’J—)(U)♦m #—! (x# '’)- ♦/U VU.’))’).* —' x JU*UxJ,/ ♦—K’, g!♦ */—!j- #—! *♦—K ♦/UJUv 8/x♦ š—!j- /xKKU) ’' JU*UxJ,/UJ* VU.x) —)j# š’♦/ ♦/U’J —š) UèKUJ’U),U* x)- )U>UJ ,—)*’-UJU- —♦/UJ*íKUJ*KU,♦’>U*v A) 'Jx(’). JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)*m ’♦í* ’(K—J♦x)♦ ♦— JU(U(VUJ ♦/x♦ /—š KU—KjU *UjU,♦ JU*UxJ,/ KJ—VjU(* ’* )—♦ x )U!♦Jxj KJ—,U** 2x♦/UJm JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)* xjšx#* JU'jU,♦ ­8z-8J-/­ ’)♦UJU*♦* x)- KJ’—J’♦’U*«U’♦/UJ ♦/U JU*UxJ,/UJí* —Jm ’' ♦/U JU*UxJ,/UJ ’* .U♦♦’). '!)-’). 'J—( *—(U—)U Uj*Um ♦/U KU—KjU š/— xJU -—’). ♦/U '!)-’). 8/’jU ♦/’* ’* )—♦ )U,U**xJ’j# x Vx- ♦/’).m #—! -— )UU- ♦— ♦/’)q xV—!♦ ♦/U >xJ’U♦# —' KUJ*KU,♦’>U* ♦/x♦ -’''UJU)♦ KU—KjU VJ’). ♦— JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦* 4—)*’-UJ ♦/U '—jj—š’). Uèx(KjU? 4’♦# —''’,’xj* ’) x (’-šU*♦UJ) ,’♦# VUP ,x(U ,—),UJ)U- š’♦/ -J!. !*U ’) x K——J *U,♦’—) —' ♦—š) F/x♦ *U,♦’—) ,—)P ♦x’)U- x j—šP’),—(U K!Vj’, /—!*’). ,—(KjUèm K—K!jx♦U- (x’)j# V# K——J š—(U) x)- ♦/U’J ,/’j-JU)m ♦/x♦ šx* ’) Vx- ,—)-’♦’—)m š’♦/ jUxq# J——'*m -’jxK’-x♦U- ’)♦UJ’—J*m x)- ,J!(Vj’). *♦UK* 4’♦# —''’,’xj* ,—)>U)U- x *UJ’U* —' (UU♦’).* x♦ ♦/U /—!*’). ,—(KjUè ♦— ♦J# ♦— -Uxj š’♦/ ♦/U KJ—VjU( p )!(VUJ —' KU—KjU x♦♦U)-U- ♦/U (UU♦’).*m ’),j!-’). ♦/U (x)x.UJ* —' ♦/U /—!*’). ,—(KjUèm (U(VUJ* —' x) x)♦’-J!. ♦x*q '—J,Um >xJ’—!* .—>UJ)(U)♦ —''’,’xj*m ♦/U K—j’,Um x jU.xj x’- x♦♦—J)U#m JU*’-U)♦* —' ♦/U /—!*’). ,—(KjUèm x)- x 'Uš !)’>UJ*’♦# JU*UxJ,/UJ* H>UJ ♦/U ,—!J*U —' ♦/U (UU♦’).*m ’♦ VU,x(U ,jUxJ ♦/x♦ ♦/U š—(U) š/— j’>U- ’) ♦/U ,—(KjUè -’-)í♦ *UU -J!.* x* x (x­—J KJ—VjU( ’) ♦/U’J ,—((!P )’♦# F/U (x’) KJ—VjU(m 'J—( ♦/U’J KUJ*KU,♦’>Um šx* ♦/U -’jxK’-x♦U- ,—)-’P ♦’—) —' ♦/U V!’j-’).* ♦/U# j’>U- ’) F/U# xj*— 'Uj♦ /xJx**U- V# ♦/U ,—(KjUè *U,!J’♦# .!xJ-*m (—*♦ —' š/—( šUJU —''P-!♦# K—j’,U —''’,UJ* g!♦ ♦/U (x)P x.UJ* —' ♦/U ,—(KjUè -’-)í♦ *UU ♦/’).* ’) ♦/U *x(U šx# x♦ xjj F/U# 'Uj♦ ♦/x♦ ’' ♦/U š—(U) ,—!j- ­!*♦ ®K!jj ♦/U(*Uj>U* !K V# ♦/U’J —š) V——♦*♦JxK*$ x).U♦ ­—V* s—J /!*Vx)-* š’♦/ ­—V*Sm ♦/U# š—!j- Kx# (—JU JU)♦ x)- ♦/U V!’j-P ’).* š—!j- *——) VU '’èU- F/U# 'Uj♦ ♦/U *U,!J’♦# .!xJ-* šUJU )UU-U- ♦— KJ—P ♦U,♦ ♦/U V!’j-’).* x)- ♦/x♦ ’' ♦/U š—(U) /x-)í♦ VJ—qU) x)# jxš* ♦/U) ♦/U# /x- )—♦/’). ♦— 'UxJ 'J—( ♦/U K—j’,U F/U jU.xj x’- x♦♦—J)U# /x- #U♦ x)—♦/UJ ’)♦UJKJU♦x♦’—) —' ♦/U KJ—VjU(«x* x ,’>’j J’./♦* >’—jx♦’—) B’)xjj#m —)U .Jx-!P x♦U *♦!-U)♦ JU*UxJ,/UJ š/— šx* *♦!-#’). ♦/U (UU♦’).* ’)♦UJKJU♦U- ♦/U -#)x(’,* VU♦šUU) (x)x.U(U)♦m K—j’,Um .—>UJ)(U)♦ —''’,’xj*m x)- ♦/U ♦U)P x)♦* ’) ♦UJ(* —' *♦x♦U x♦♦U(K♦* ♦— ,—)♦J—j K——J š—(U) sYx*!-x cRRIS c5F ])—Z”V m-zV”V’zVY m- ­VN”-m-. ()”V NL)—z *); ”V’VN”G*V”’ G)(V —J ;mz* z*Vm” z)JmG’x ])— (m.*z ;N-z z) ”VNY ’)(V )F z*V ’z)”mV’ m- ,áK):'K':;- 487:8)81* K­ H;-.*UK* W:L-S VYmzVY L] oN””] B­N’’-V” N-Y :)’N--N nV”z" iI 45p”FM2 i N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J gU.’))’). 2U*UxJ,/ N— š/—*U ’)♦UJKJU♦x♦’—) —' ♦/U *’♦!x♦’—) šx* ,—JJU,♦v 8/x♦ šx* ♦/U ®JUxj$ KJ—VjU(v 8x* ’♦ -J!.*v :’jxK’-x♦U- /—!*’).v ”—j’,U /xJx**(U)♦v N—,’xj ,—)♦J—jv A♦ -UKU)-* —) š/—*U KUJ*KU,♦’>U #—! ♦xqU F/’* ’* š/x♦ A (Ux) š/U) A *x# ♦/x♦ KJ—VjU(* xJU )U>UJ )U!♦Jxj p KJ—VjU( ’* xjšx#* x KJ—VjU( L8. *—(U—)U N—,’—j—.’*♦* *—(U♦’(U* JU'‘J ♦— ♦/’* x* ♦/U ®-U'’)’♦’—) —' ♦/U *’♦!x♦’—) $ A) x)# *—,’xj *U♦♦’).m KU—KjU (xqU x**!(K♦’—)* xV—!♦ š/x♦ ♦/U# ♦/’)q ’* /xKKU)’). x)- /—š ♦— ’)♦UJKJU♦ ♦/U x,♦—J* x)- U>U)♦* 2U*UxJ,/UJ* xJU xj*— ’)>—j>U- ’) x KJ—,U** —' *—,’xj ’)♦UJx,♦’—) F/U#m ♦——m (xqU x**!(K♦’—)* xV—!♦ š/x♦ ♦/U# ♦/’)q ’* /xKKU)’). x)- -U'’)U ♦/U *’♦!P x♦’—) ’) -’>UJ*U šx#* 5—š JU*UxJ,/UJ* ,/——*U ♦— 'Jx(U ♦/U’J JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)* JU'jU,♦* ♦/U’J *U)*U —' š/x♦ ®♦/U$ KJ—VjU( ’* 8/x♦ ’' #—! šUJU .—’). ♦— JU*UxJ,/ ♦/’* *’♦!x♦’—)v 8/—*U KUJ*KU,♦’>U š—!j- #—! ♦xqU ’)♦— x,,—!)♦v 8/#v gslEgEIC TfSO OF Rs7sSRlf 8/U) #—! xJU '’J*♦ -U,’-’). š/x♦ ♦— JU*UxJ,/m #—! )UU- ♦— x*q #—!J*Uj' x )!(VUJ —' ;!U*♦’—)* B’J*♦m š/x♦ -— #—! xjJUx-# q)—š xV—!♦ ♦/U ♦—K’,v p)’' #—! -—)í♦ q)—š >UJ# (!,/m /—š ,x) #—! .U♦ (—JU ’)'—J(x♦’—)v w—’). ♦— ♦/U j’VJxJ# —J *UxJ,/’). ♦/U A)♦UJ)U♦ xJU .——- šx#* ♦— jUxJ) (—JU xV—!♦ x ♦—K’, sx)- šUíjj -’*,!** ♦/U*U '!J♦/UJ jx♦UJ ’) ♦/U ,/xK♦UJSm V!♦ ♦/U#íJU )—♦ ♦/U —)j# šx#* b—! ,x) xj*— ♦xjq ♦— —♦/UJ KU—KjUm *!,/ x* x KJ—'U**—J —J x)—♦/UJ *♦!-U)♦m š/— /x>U x) ’)♦UJU*♦ ’) ♦/U ♦—K’, b—! ,x) >’*’♦ Kjx,U* ♦— .U♦ (—JU ’)'—J(x♦’—) B—J Uèx(KjUm ’' #—! xJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) /—(UjU** KU—KjUm #—! (’./♦ >—j!)♦UUJ x♦ x */Uj♦UJ —J >’*’♦ ♦/U *’♦U p *U,—)- ;!U*♦’—) #—! )UU- ♦— ,—)*’-UJ ’*m 5—š -— #—! 'UUj xV—!♦ #—!J K—♦U)♦’xj ♦—K’,v :— #—! /x>U >UJ# *♦J—). 'UUj’).* xV—!♦ ’♦v A' *—m #—!J 'UUjP ’).* (’./♦ jUx- #—! ♦— '—,!* —) —)U KxJ♦’,!jxJ xJUx x)- x>—’- —♦/UJ* —J Vj’)#—! ♦— —♦/UJ KUJ*KU,♦’>U* b—! (x# VU ♦—— V’x*U- ♦— -— x .——- ­—V —J ♦— !)-UJ*♦x)- —♦/UJ*íK—’)♦* —' >’Uš A♦í* ’(K—J♦x)♦ ♦— JU(x’) —KU) ♦— x >xJ’U♦# —' KUJ*KU,♦’>U* gU’). x (U(VUJ —' ♦/U .J—!K #—! xJU *♦!-#’). ,x) VU V—♦/ K—*’♦’>U x))U.x♦’>U ”U—KjU —'♦U) /x>U *♦J—). 'UUj’).* xV—!♦ ♦/U KU—KjU x)- .J—!K* ♦/U# xJU ’)>—j>U- š’♦/ A' #—! xJU *♦!-#’). x 'x(’j’xJ .J—!Km #—!íjj )UU- ♦— VU U*KU,’xjj# ,xJU'!j ♦— JU(x’) —KU)P(’)-U- B—J Uèx(KjUm ’(x.’)U ♦/x♦ #—! xJU x (U(VUJ —' x ,x(K!* *—J—J’♦# —J 'Jx♦UJ)’♦# b—! q)—š ♦/x♦ *♦!-U)♦* š/— xJU)í♦ ’)>—j>U- ’) ♦/U*U .J—!K* —'♦U) /x>U )U.x♦’>U —K’)’—)* xV—!♦ ♦/U(m x)- #—! šx)♦ ♦— -— JU*UxJ,/ ♦— ♦J# ♦— ,—!)♦UJ ♦/U*U *♦UJU—♦#KU* b—!J ’)>—j>U(U)♦ /UjK* #—! .x’) x,,U** ♦— (U(VUJ*m x)- ♦/x♦ ’* ,UJ♦x’)j# K—*’P ♦’>U g!♦ #—! xJU *— ’)>U*♦U- ’) */—š’). ♦/U K—*’♦’>U *’-U ♦/x♦ #—! xJU)í♦ xVjU :U,’-’). 77/x♦ ♦— 2U*UxJ,/ iR ♦— *UU x)# —♦/UJ K—’)♦* —' >’Uš A) ♦/’* ,x*Um VU’). x (U(VUJ (’./♦ /’)-UJ #—!J xV’j’♦# ♦— -— .——- JU*UxJ,/ p* #—! -U>Uj—K #—!J JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦m #—! )UU- ♦— qUUK x) —KU) (’)xV—!♦ ♦/U KU—KjU x)- U>U)♦* ’) #—!J JU*UxJ,/ *U♦♦’). x)- ♦— JU(x’) —KU) ♦— (!j♦’KjU -U'’)’♦’—)* —' ♦/U *’♦!x♦’—) A' #—! ,j—*U #—!J*Uj' —'' ♦— xj♦UJ)x♦’>U UèKjx)x♦’—)* ♦—— *——)m #—! (x# (’** ’(K—J♦x)♦ ’)*’./♦* ’)♦— #—!J JU*UxJ,/ *U♦♦’). n); ?) M)— d—”- N d)JmG m-z) N v—V’zm)-s H),U #—!í>U *U♦♦jU- —) x .U)UJxj ♦—K’,m ’♦í* ♦’(U ♦— ♦!J) ’♦ ’)♦— x JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—) A) ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/m #—!J JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—) (x# */’'♦ —),U #—! VU.’) #—!J ’)>U*♦’.x♦’—) A) 'x,♦m (x)# *,/—jxJ* xJ.!U ♦/x♦ x .——- ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/UJ (!*♦ /x>U ♦/U xV’j’♦# ♦— JU(x’) —KU) ♦— š/x♦ ♦/U '’Uj- *U♦♦’). —J JU*UxJ,/ *’♦U /x* ♦— —''UJ F/U# VUj’U>U ♦/x♦ ♦/U (—*♦ ’(K—J♦x)♦ ♦/’). ’* *’(P Kj# ♦— .— —!♦ ’)♦— ♦/U '’Uj- ♦— *UU š/x♦ ’* —!♦ ♦/UJU A xJ.!U ♦/x♦ x) ’)’♦’xj '—,!* ’* ’(K—J♦x)♦ M>U) ♦/—!./ #—!J JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—) (x# ,/x).U«x)*—(U♦’(U* -Jx(x♦’,xjj#«—),U #—! VU.’) š—Jqm #—! *♦’jj )UU- ♦— *♦xJ♦ *—(UP š/UJU H♦/UJš’*Um #—! (x# /x>U -’''’,!j♦# '’.!J’). —!♦ /—š ♦— VU.’) #—!J JU*UxJ,/ p* #—!J JU*UxJ,/ KJ—.JU**U*m /—šU>UJm #—! )UU- ♦— qUUK x) —KU) (’)- ♦— —♦/UJ ;!U*♦’—)* ♦/x♦ (x# xJ’*U ’) ♦/U ,—!J*U —' #—!J JU*UxJ,/«;!U*P ♦’—)* ♦/x♦ (x# VU U>U) (—JU ’(K—J♦x)♦ ♦/x) ♦/U —)U* #—! ’)’♦’xjj# -U>’*Up* x '’J*♦ *♦UKm ♦J# VJx’)*♦—J(’). x j’*♦ —' ;!U*♦’—)* xV—!♦ #—!J ♦—K’, F/U) #—! ,x) U>xj!x♦U š/U♦/UJ ♦/U ;!U*♦’—)* ,x) VU x)*šUJU- !*’). ♦/U JU*—!J,U* #—! /x>U x♦ /x)- “U♦e* *x# #—!eJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) ♦/U .U)UJxj ♦—K’, —' xV—J♦’—)m V!♦ #—!íJU )—♦ *!JU /—š ♦— )xJJ—š #—!J ♦—K’, -—š) FJ# x*q’). *—(U ;!U*♦’—)*? 8/x♦ ’* ♦/U UèKUJ’U),U —' xV—J♦’—) j’qU '—J š—(U)v o 5—š -— x,♦’>’*♦* —) V—♦/ *’-U* —' ♦/U -UVx♦U ♦/’)q xV—!♦ xV—J♦’—)v 8/x♦ -— ♦/U# ♦/’)q š—(U)í* J—jU* */—!j- VUv 5—š -— xV—J♦’—) ,j’)’, *♦x'' -Uxj š’♦/ ♦/U ♦/JUx♦* —' >’—jU),Uv :—U* ’♦ ,/x).U ♦/U šx# ♦/U# ♦/’)q xV—!♦ ♦/U’J š—Jqv 5—š /x>U (U-’x K—J♦Jx#xj* —' xV—J♦’—) ,/x).U- —>UJ ♦’(Uv u—♦’,U /—š ♦/U*U ;!U*♦’—)* xJU xjj x)*šUJxVjUm x♦ *—(U jU>Ujm š’♦/ JU'UJU),U ♦— ♦/U U(K’J’,xj š—Jj- s♦/U š—Jj- —' ♦/U *U)*U*S b—! ,—!j- x*q š—(U) š/— /x>U /x- xV—J♦’—)* š/x♦ ♦/U’J UèKUJ’U),U ’* j’qUy #—! ,—!j- —V*UJ>U ♦/U *♦x'' ’) x ,j’)’,y #—! ,—!j- Uèx(’)U )Uš* x,,—!)♦* —' xV—J♦’—) ♦— *UU /—š ♦/U# /x>U ,/x).U- la 45p”FM2 i N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J gU.’))’). 2U*UxJ,/ 4—(KxJU ♦/—*U ;!U*♦’—)* š’♦/m *x#m ♦/U '—jj—š’).? A* xV—J♦’—) x .——- —J x Vx- ♦/’).v N/—!j- š—(U) VU xVjU ♦— ,/——*U ♦— /x>U x) xV—J♦’—)v F/U*U q’)-* —' ;!U*♦’—)* JUxjj# ,x)í♦ VU x)*šUJU- š’♦/ JU'UJU),U ♦— ♦/U U(P K’J’,xj š—Jj- 8/’jU ♦/U# (x# VU ’(K—J♦x)♦ -'0:7K) ;!U*♦’—)*m ♦/U# xJU)í♦ x(U)xVjU ♦— *—,’xj JU*UxJ,/ F/!*m #—! )UU- ♦— ,—)*’-UJ š/U♦/UJ ♦/U JUP *UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)* #—! KJ—K—*U ,x) VU x)*šUJU- š’♦/ JU'UJU),U ♦— ♦/U ®JUxj$ š—Jjb—! xj*— )UU- ♦— x*q #—!J*Uj' š/x♦ #—!J —š) x**!(K♦’—)* xV—!♦ xV—JP ♦’—) x)- ♦/U š—(U) š/— /x>U ♦/U( xJU A' #—! /x>U /x- x) xV—J♦’—) #—!JP *Uj' —J q)—š *—(U—)U š/— /x* /x- —)Um ♦/x♦ š’jj ,UJ♦x’)j# */xKU #—!J ♦/’)q’). xV—!♦ ♦/U ♦—K’, A' #—! /x>U *♦J—). 'UUj’).* KJ— —J ,—)m ♦/—*U š’jj ’)'j!U),U #—!J ’)’♦’xj ;!U*♦’—) x* šUjj b—! )UU- ♦— ,—)*’-UJ š/U♦/UJ #—!J —š) ’)>U*♦(U)♦* ’) ♦/U ’**!U š’jj xjj—š #—! ♦— ’)>U*♦’.x♦U ’♦ š’♦/ x) —KU) (’)- 5’ z*V d)JmG 5-zV”V’zm-.s uUè♦m #—! )UU- ♦— ,—)*’-UJ š/U♦/UJ #—!J JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—) ’* ’)♦UJU*♦’). p .——- ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/UJ ,x) (xqU ­!*♦ xV—!♦ x)# ♦—K’, ’)♦UJU*♦’). g!♦ ’' #—! xJU V—JU- V# —J ’)-’''UJU)♦ ♦— #—!J KJ—­U,♦m #—! KJ—VxVj# —!./♦ ♦— ,/——*U x)—♦/UJ —)U :—’). ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/ ,x) ♦xqU x j—). ♦’(Um x),—(KjU♦’). x JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦«U>U) —)U ♦/x♦ #—! xJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’)«,x) VU -’''’,!j♦ A♦í* ♦—!./ ♦— qUUK .—’). š/U) #—!íJU V—JU- V# #—!J ♦—K’, N—(UP ♦’(U*m VU.’))’). JU*UxJ,/UJ* K’,q ;!U*♦’—)* VU,x!*U ♦/U# ♦/’)q ♦/U# š’jj VU Ux*# —J VU,x!*U ♦/U’J KJ—'U**—J —J x->’*UJ *!..U*♦U- ♦/U ♦—K’, F/U*U xJU K——J JUx*—)* ♦— ,/——*U x ♦—K’,m !)jU**m —' ,—!J*Um #—! xjJUx-# /x>U x) ’)♦UJP U*♦ ’) ♦/U ♦—K’, u— JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦ ’* ♦J!j# Ux*#m x)- U>U) ♦/U Ux*’U*♦ JU*UxJ,/ VU,—(U* -’''’,!j♦ š/U) #—! -—)í♦ šx)♦ ♦— -— ’♦ 8*)’V bV”’JVGzmQV p*)—­Y M)— dNyVs H),U #—!í>U *U♦♦jU- —) x ♦U)♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)m #—! )UU- ♦— ♦/’)q xV—!♦ /—š #—! š’jj VU.’) ♦— xKKJ—x,/ ’♦ p♦ ♦/’* *♦x.Um ,—)*’-UJ /—š ♦xq’). -’''UJU)♦ KUJ*KU,♦’>U* š’jj jUx- #—! ♦— U(VxJq —) >UJ# -’''UJU)♦ JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦* A' #—!J ♦—K’, ’* /—(UjU**)U**m '—J Uèx(KjUm #—! š’jj '’)- #—!J*Uj' (—>’). -—š) x >UJ# -’''UJU)♦ Kx♦/ ’' #—! -U,’-U ♦— *♦!-# š—JqUJ* ’) /—(UP jU** */Uj♦UJ* ♦/x) ’' #—! -U,’-U ♦— *♦!-# /—(UjU** KU—KjU ♦/U(*Uj>U* N’(’P :U,’-’). 8/x♦ ♦— 2U*UxJ,/ lc jxJj#m #—! š’jj '’)- #—!J*Uj' -—’). x >UJ# -’''UJU)♦ JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦ ’' #—! ,/——*U ♦— ,—)-!,♦ #—!J JU*UxJ,/ ’) x *(xjj */Uj♦UJ ♦/x♦ /—!*U* /—(UjU** š—(U) x)- ♦/U’J 'x(’j’U* Jx♦/UJ ♦/x) x jxJ.U */Uj♦UJ ♦/x♦ KJ—>’-U* ♦U(K—P JxJ# /—!*’). '—J *’).jU (U) FJ# ♦— j’*♦ x* (x)# KUJ*KU,♦’>U* x* #—! ,x) VU'—JU #—! *U♦♦jU —) x ♦U)♦x♦’>U '—,!* g!♦ U>U) ♦/U)m ’♦í* ’(K—J♦x)♦ ♦— qUUK x ;!U*♦’—)’). x♦♦’♦!-U p)- x* #—! ,—)♦’)!U š’♦/ #—!J š—Jqm #—! */—!jJU(x’) —KU) ♦— x* (x)# KUJ*KU,♦’>U* x* K—**’VjU b—! xj*— )UU- ♦— ,—)*’-UJ /—š -’''UJU)♦ KxJx-’.(* (’./♦ */xKU -’''UJP U)♦ xKKJ—x,/U* ♦— #—!J JU*UxJ,/ pj♦/—!./ #—! -— )—♦ )UU- ♦— *U♦♦jU —) x KxJx-’.( x♦ ♦/’* UxJj# *♦x.Um ’♦e* /UjK'!j ♦— ♦/’)q xV—!♦ /—š ♦/U*U ,/—’,U* š’jj x''U,♦ #—!J JU*UxJ,/ 8’♦/ x *—,’xj ,—)*♦J!,♦’—)’*♦ xKKJ—x,/m '—J Uèx(P KjUm #—! š—!j- šx)♦ ♦— Kx# ,j—*U x♦♦U)♦’—) ♦— /—š ’)-’>’-!xj* -U'’)U x),JUx♦U *—,’xj JUxj’♦# 8’♦/ x ,J’♦’,xj xKKJ—x,/m #—! š—!j- šx)♦ ♦— 'Jx(U #—!J JU*UxJ,/ *— ♦/x♦ ’♦ š—!j- VU !*U'!j ’) ,JUx♦’). *—,’xj ,/x).U “U♦í* ,—)*’-UJ ♦/U Uèx(KjU —' U-!,x♦’—) ’) KJU*,/——j* x)- q’)-UJ.xJP ♦U)* p 'U(’)’*♦ JU*UxJ,/UJ (’./♦ '—,!* —) .U)-UJ JUjx♦’—)* ’) ♦/U ,jx**P J——(«KUJ/xK* —) /—š V—#* x)- .’Jj* ’)♦UJx,♦ x)- /—š .U)-UJ ’* KJ—-!,U♦/J—!./ ♦/x♦ ’)♦UJx,♦’—) s*UUm '—J Uèx(KjUm F/—J)U cRRlS p *—,’xj ,—)*♦J!,P ♦’—)’*♦ (’./♦ '—,!* —) ’)♦UJx,♦’—) x* šUjj g!♦ ♦/’* JU*UxJ,/UJ (’./♦ VU (—JU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) UèKj—J’). /—š ,/’j-JU) ,—(U ♦— -U'’)U ♦/U ,jx**J——( x* x C*,/——j$ x)- /—š ♦/U# jUxJ) ♦/U UèKU,♦x♦’—)* '—J VU/x>’). ’) ♦/x♦ *U♦♦’). s*UUm '—J Uèx(KjUm 4—J*xJ— x)- Y—j’)xJ’ iaaaS p K—*♦(—-UJ)’*♦ (’./♦ '—,!* —) ♦/U (!j♦’KjU x)- 'Jx.(U)♦U- JUxj’♦’U* š’♦/’) x)- xJ—!)- ♦/U *,/——j *U♦♦’).? ♦/U JUxj’♦’U* —' ,/’j-JU)m ♦Ux,/UJ*m x-(’)’*♦Jx♦—J*m x)- —♦/UJ* F/’* JU*UxJ,/UJ (’./♦ UèKj—JU ,/’j-JU)í* ,xJ♦——)*m ,—((UJ,’xj ,!j♦!JUm x)—♦/UJ ♦Uè♦* ♦/x♦ */xKU ,/’j-JU)í* JUxj’♦’U* p K—*’♦’>’*♦ (’./♦ VU.’) š’♦/ x ♦/U—J# xV—!♦ U-!,x♦’—)«'—J Uèx(KjUm ♦/x♦ ,/’j-JU) š/— x♦♦U)- KJU*,/——j x-­!*♦ VU♦♦UJ ♦— q’)-UJ.xJ♦U) ♦/x) ♦/—*U š/— -— )—♦«x)- '—,!* ♦/U JUP *UxJ,/ —) ♦/x♦ ;!U*♦’—) 5’ z*V :V’VN”G* gVN’mL­Vs H),U #—!í>U *U♦♦jU- —) x ♦U)♦x♦’>U ;!U*♦’—)m #—! )UU- ♦— x*q š/U♦/UJ #—! ,x) x,♦!xjj# -— ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ B—J Uèx(KjUm ’' #—! xJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) *♦!-#’). KU—KjU ’) /—(UjU** */Uj♦UJ*m #—! )UU- ♦— .U♦ KUJ(’**’—) 'J—( ♦/U */Uj♦UJ *♦x'' sKJ—VxVj# ♦/U -’JU,♦—JS x)- 'J—( ♦/U JU*’-U)♦* ♦/U(*Uj>U* N—(U .J—!K* xJU JUjx♦’>Uj# Ux*# ♦— .x’) x,,U** ♦— s*!,/ x* —♦/UJ *♦!-U)♦*Sy —♦/UJ* xJU JUjx♦’>Uj# -’''’,!j♦ s*!,/ x* KU—KjU š/— xJU ’)>—j>U- ’) ’jjU.xj x,♦’>’♦’U*m j’qU -J!. *(!..jUJ*S b—! (x# xj*— )UU- ♦— .x’) KUJ(’**’—) 'J—( x) ’)*♦’♦!P ♦’—)xj JU>’Uš V—xJ- x♦ #—!J *,/——jm š/’,/ *,J!♦’)’❖U* KJ—­U,♦* '—J U♦/’,xj KJ—VjU(* li 45p”FM2 i N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J gU.’))’). 2U*UxJ,/ H),U #—!í>U -U♦UJ(’)U- ♦/x♦ #—! ,x) .x’) x,,U** ♦— ♦/U .J—!K #—! xJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) *♦!-#’).m #—! )UU- ♦— ♦/’)q xV—!♦ š/x♦ —♦/UJ JU*—!J,U* #—! š’jj )UU- B’J*♦m ,—)*’-UJ ':z-o :—’). ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/ ,x) ♦xqU x .JUx♦ -Uxj —' ♦’(U A' #—! xJU ♦J#’). ♦— *♦!-# x .J—!K ♦— š/’,/ ’♦ (x# VU -’''’,!j♦ ♦— .x’) x,,U** —J ♦/x♦ (x# VU /—*♦’jU ♦— JU*UxJ,/UJ*m VU *!JU #—! /x>U U)—!./ ♦’(U ♦— -U>Uj—K ♦/U q’)-* —' JUjx♦’—)*/’K* #—! š’jj )UU- ♦— -— ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ B—J Uèx(KjUm *!KK—*U #—! xJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) ’jjU.xj -J!. !*Um x* x)♦/J—K—j—.’*♦ N♦U>U) f—U*♦UJ ’* sf—U*♦UJ cRRdS NKU,’'’,xjj#m #—! xJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) /—š 5A7 (’./♦ VU ♦Jx)*(’♦♦U- x(—). *♦JUU♦ KU—KjU š/— ’)­U,♦ -J!.* A♦ š’jj ♦xqU x j—). ♦’(U VU'—JU ♦/U# ♦J!*♦ #—! U)—!./ ♦— ,—)'’-U ’) #—!m *— #—! )UU- ♦— ,—)*’-UJ š/U♦/UJ #—! /x>U U)—!./ ♦’(U ♦— .x’) ♦J!*♦ p)—♦/UJ ’(K—J♦x)♦ JU*—!J,U ’* z8J-*o :—’). ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/ ,x) ,—*♦ (—)U# A' #—! xJU .—’). ♦— -— ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ '!jjP♦’(Um #—! *♦’jj )UU- ♦— *!KK—J♦ #—!J*Uj' A' #—! xJU .—’). ♦— ’)♦UJ>’Uš KU—KjUm #—! )UU- ♦— K!J,/x*U —J /x>U x,,U** ♦— x JUj’xVjU ♦xKU JU,—J-UJ x)- x!-’—♦xKU* b—! xj*— (’./♦ /x>U ♦— /’JU *—(U—)U ♦— ♦Jx)*,J’VU ’)♦UJ>’Uš ♦xKU*m !)jU** #—! Kjx) ♦— -— ’♦ #—!J*Uj' b—! (x# /x>U ♦— ♦Jx>Uj *—(Uš/UJU Uj*U ♦— .U♦ ♦— #—!J JU*UxJ,/ K—K!jx♦’—) —J ♦— '’)- -—,!(U)♦* ’) x) xJ,/’>U b—! (x# )UU- ♦— K!J,/x*U '’j(* —J —♦/UJ ♦Uè♦* ♦— x)xj#❖U p)- ♦/UJU (x# VU —♦/UJ ,—*♦* x* šUjj F/U ;!U*♦’—) —' 'Ux*’V’j’♦# ,x) VU KxJ♦’,!jxJj# -’''’,!j♦ ’' #—! xJU ♦J#’). ♦— ,—)-!,♦ x JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦ —>UJ ♦/U ,—!J*U —' x *U(U*♦UJ b—! (x# /x>U .JUx♦ ’-Ux* '—J JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦*m V!♦ ♦/U KJ—­U,♦* xJU ♦—— x(V’♦’—!* ♦— VU ,xJJ’U- —!♦ —>UJ cd —J *— šUUq* H),U #—! '’)xjj# .x’) x,,U** ♦— #—!J JUP *UxJ,/ K—K!jx♦’—) —J -x♦xm ’♦ ’* ♦/U U)- —' ♦/U *U(U*♦UJ x)- ♦’(U ♦— šJxK ♦/’).* !K F/!*m #—! (x# '’)- ’♦ Ux*’UJ ♦— VU.’) š’♦/ x *U♦♦’). ♦/x♦ #—! xjJUx-# q)—š —J ,x) .x’) x,,U** ♦— g!♦ ♦/’* (Ux)* #—!íjj /x>U ♦— VU U*KUP ,’xjj# ,xJU'!j xV—!♦ ♦/U KJU,—),UK♦’—)* x)- V’x*U* #—! VJ’). ♦— #—!J š—Jq 5’ z*V :V’VN”G* 8)”z* ?)m-.s p '’)xj ’**!U ’* š/U♦/UJ #—! ­08á)U -— x KxJ♦’,!jxJ KJ—­U,♦ 0!*♦ VU,x!*U #—! xJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- x)- /x>U ♦/U JU*—!J,U* #—! )UU-m ’♦ -—U*)í♦ (Ux) #—! */—!jx,♦!xjj# -— ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ F/U qU# ’**!U ’* š/U♦/UJ ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ /x* x)# K—♦U)♦’xj !*U* —J VU)U'’♦* 8’jj #—!J JU*UxJ,/ (xqU x ,—)♦J’V!♦’—)m U’♦/UJ ♦— ’)-’>’-!xj* —J ♦— x jxJ.UJ .J—!K —J ♦— —!J .U)UJxj q)—šjU-.U Vx*Uv :—U* ’♦ /x>U ♦/U ,xKx,’♦# ♦— /xJ( x)#—)U«U’♦/UJ #—!J*Uj' —J ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ KxJ♦’,’P Kx)♦*v gU'—JU #—! VU.’) x)# JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦m #—! )UU- ♦— ,—)*’-UJ ♦/U K—♦U)♦’xj VU)U'’♦* x)- J’*q* sF/U*U U♦/’,xj ’**!U* š’jj VU ,—)*’-UJU- ’) -U♦x’j ’) 4/xK♦UJ l S p.x’)m jU♦í* *x# #—! xJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) JU*UxJ,/’). KU—KjU ’) /—(UjU** */Uj♦UJ* b—! ♦/’)q ♦/U *♦!-# (’./♦ /x>U K—♦U)♦’xj VU)U'’♦* VU,x!*U KU—KjU :U>Uj—K’). x 2U*UxJ,/ N♦Jx♦U.# ll (’./♦ VU (—JU *#(Kx♦/U♦’, ♦— ♦/U KJ—VjU(* —' ♦/U /—(UjU** ’' ♦/U# !)-UJP *♦——- š/x♦ ♦/U’J j’>U* šUJU j’qU F/U# (’./♦ VU (—JU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) V!’j-’). x''—J-xVjU /—!*’). —J /x>’). ♦/U .—>UJ)(U)♦ *KU)- (—JU (—)U# —) *!V*’P -’❖U- /—(U* 8/’jU ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ (’./♦ )—♦ /x>U x) ’((U-’x♦U K—*’♦’>U ’(Kx,♦ —) ♦/U KxJ♦’,’Kx)♦*í ♦/U(*Uj>U*m #—! ♦/’)q ♦/x♦ ’) ♦/U j—). J!) #—!J š—Jq (’./♦ /UjK -UV!)q *♦UJU—♦#KU* xV—!♦ /—(UjU** KU—KjU ?2723Ob56B S :2p2S:ln pd:Sd2BM H),U #—!í>U ,/—*U) x ♦—K’, x)- 'Jx(U- x JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)m #—! )UU- ♦— -U>Uj—K x JU*UxJ,/ *♦Jx♦U.# NKU,’'’,xjj#m #—! )UU- ♦— x--JU** ♦/U*U ;!U*♦’—)*? 5—š š’jj #—! .x♦/UJ ♦/U -x♦xv 8/x♦ q’)- —' K—K!jx♦’—) —J *U♦♦’). š’jj #—! *♦!-#v 8’jj #—! !*U ’)P-UK♦/ ’)♦UJ>’Uš*m —J -— x) —V*UJ>x♦’—)xj *♦!-#m —J š—Jq š’♦/ ®♦Uè♦*$ sš/’,/ ,x) ’),j!-U ♦/’).* j’qU V——q* x)- (x.xP ❖’)U* V!♦ xj*— (U-’x *!,/ x* F7 */—š*m (—>’U*m x)- *—).*Sv 5—š š’jj #—! VU.’) ♦— x)xj#❖U x)- (xqU *U)*U —' ♦/U -x♦x #—! /x>U ,—jjU,♦U-v :’''UJU)♦ JU*UxJ,/ ♦Jx-’♦’—)* *!..U*♦ *—(Uš/x♦ -’''UJU)♦ *♦Jx♦U.’U* 8Uíjj ,—)*’-UJ ♦/U*U )Uè♦ ?mFFV”V-z d”NYmzm)-’x ?mFFV”V-z pzN”zm-. b)m-z’ :UKU)-’). —) š/’,/ JU*UxJ,/ ♦Jx-’♦’—) #—! ,/——*Um #—! š’jj VU.’) #—!J JU*UxJ,/ 'J—( >UJ# -’''UJU)♦ *♦xJ♦’). K—’)♦* gU'—JU #—! .U♦ ♦—— 'xJ ’) #—!J š—Jqm ♦/U)m #—! )UU- ♦— ,—)*’-UJ š/’,/ ♦Jx-’♦’—)s*S (xqU* ♦/U (—*♦ *U)*U ♦— #—! p,,—J-’). ♦— ♦/U K—*’♦’>’*♦ KxJx-’.(m š/’,/ šU -’*,!**U- ’) 4/xKP ♦UJ cm ♦/U .—xj —' *—,’xj JU*UxJ,/ ’* ♦/U—J# ♦U*♦’). F/!*m ’) ♦/’* ♦Jx-’♦’—)m #—! )UU- ♦— *U♦♦jU —) x ♦/U—J# 6-L8.- #—! VU.’) #—!J JU*UxJ,/ 2U*UxJ,/UJ* š/— š—Jq š’♦/’) ♦/’* ♦Jx-’♦’—) !*!xjj# *KU)- (!,/ ♦’(U JU*UxJ,/’). š/x♦ —♦/P UJ* /x>U '—!)- xV—!♦ ♦/U’J ♦—K’, F/U# ♦/U) -U>Uj—K 0*"8'0-­-­S —J *♦x♦UP (U)♦* ♦/x♦ ,x) VU ♦U*♦U-m Vx*U- —) ♦/U*U ♦/U—J’U*m š/’,/ —'♦U) xJU 'Jx(U- ’) ,x!*xj jx).!x.U? ®è ,x!*U* s—J x''U,♦*S #$ —J ®F/U (—JU —' èm ♦/U jU** —' #$ F/U) ♦/U# -U>Uj—K x JU*UxJ,/ -U*’.) ♦/x♦ ♦/U# ,x) !*U ♦— ♦U*♦ ♦/U’J /#P K—♦/U*U* F/U# !*U ♦/U JU*!j♦* —' ♦/U’J U(K’J’,xj ♦U*♦* ♦— -U♦UJ(’)U š/U♦/UJ ♦/U’J ♦/U—J# ’* !*U'!j ld 45p”FM2 i N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J gU.’))’). 2U*UxJ,/ “U♦í* *x# #—!íJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) Jx♦’—)xj ,/—’,U ♦/U—J# sBJ’U-(x) x)- 5U,/♦UJ cRIISm š/’,/ *♦x♦U* ♦/x♦ KU—KjU x,♦ x,,—J-’). ♦— ♦/U’J VU*♦ ’)♦UJP U*♦* NKU,’'’,xjj#m #—!íJU ’)♦UJU*♦U- ’) xKKj#’). Jx♦’—)xj ,/—’,U ♦/U—J# ♦— -’>—J,U b—! ♦/’)q ♦/x♦m ’' KU—KjU 'UUj ♦/U# š’jj .U♦ (—JU —!♦ —' -’>—J,’). ♦/x) *♦x#’). ’) x (xJJ’x.Um ♦/U# š’jj ,/——*U ♦— -’>—J,U b—!íJU xšxJU ♦/x♦ Jx’*’). ,/’j-JU) x'♦UJ x -’>—J,U ,x) VU /xJ-m *— #—! ♦/’)q ♦/x♦ KU—KjU š’♦/ ,/’j-JU) /x>U jU** ♦— .x’) 'J—( x -’>—J,U ♦/x) ♦/—*U š’♦/—!♦ b—!J /#K—♦/UP *’* (’./♦ VU ♦/’*? 4—!KjU* š/— /x>U ,/’j-JU) xJU jU** j’qUj# ♦— -’>—J,U ♦/x) ,—!KjU* š/— /x>U )— ,/’j-JU) b—! ,—!j- ♦U*♦ ♦/’* V# ,—(KxJ’). ♦/U -’>—J,U Jx♦U —' ,—!KjU* š/— /x>U ,/’j-JU) š’♦/ ♦/x♦ —' ,—!KjU* š/— -— )—♦ L!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/UJ* JxJUj# š—Jq š’♦/’) ♦/’* K—*’♦’>’*♦ ♦Jx-’♦’—) F/x♦ ’*m ♦/U# xJU (!,/ jU** j’qUj# ♦— ♦U*♦ /#K—♦/U*U* ♦/x) xJU ;!x)♦’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/UJ* x)- xJU (!,/ (—JU j’qUj# ♦— š—Jq š’♦/’) —)U —' ♦/U —♦/UJ ♦Jx-’P ♦’—)* -’*,!**U- ’) 4/xK♦UJ c A)*♦Ux- —' 6-1:JJ:J1 š’♦/ x ♦/U—J#m ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/UJ* xJU (—JU j’qUj# ♦— VU.’) š’♦/ x) Uèx(’)x♦’—) —' ♦/U U(K’J’,xj š—Jj- A) ♦/U )x♦!Jxj’*♦’, x)- ,—)*♦J!,♦’—)’*♦ ♦Jx-’♦’—)*m JU*UxJ,/UJ* ’((UJ*U ♦/U(*Uj>U* ’) ♦/U *—,’xj š—Jj-* —' ♦/U’J JU*UxJ,/ *!V­U,♦* H)j# š/U) ♦/U# /x>U VUU) ’) x *U♦♦’). '—J x j—). ♦’(U -— ♦/U# VU.’) ♦— -U>Uj—K ♦/U—J’U* N—(U ,xjj ♦/’* x 1.8áJU-U '0-8.* KUJ*KU,♦’>U s4/xJ(x❖ iaaay N♦Jx!** x)- 4—JV’) cRRISm ’) š/’,/ ♦/U x’( ’* ♦— -U>Uj—K ♦/U—J# .J—!)-U- ’) ♦/U U(P K’J’,xj š—Jj- A' #—! ,/——*U ♦/’* xKKJ—x,/m #—!J '’J*♦ *♦UK ’* ♦— -U,’-U —) x '’Uj- *U♦♦’). —J *’♦U '—J #—!J JU*UxJ,/ p♦ ♦/’* *♦x.Um xj♦/—!./ #—! */—!j- -— x j’VJxJ# *UxJ,/ ♦— -U♦UJ(’)U ’' —♦/UJ* /x>U *♦!-’U- ♦/U *x(U q’)-* —' *’♦U*m #—! */—!j- )—♦ ♦J# ♦— -U>Uj—K ♦U*♦xVjU /#K—♦/U*U* 2x♦/UJm #—! */—!j- '—,!* —) /—š #—! (’./♦ .x’) x,,U** ♦— ♦/U *’♦U x)- VU.’) V!’j-’). JUjx♦’—)*/’K* š’♦/ ♦/U KU—KjU ♦/UJU 2U*UxJ,/UJ* š—Jq’). š’♦/’) x ,J’♦’,xj JU*UxJ,/ ♦Jx-’♦’—) (’./♦ -U,’-U ♦— -— K7':8J .-­-K.70S ’) š/’,/ ♦/U —V­U,♦’>U ’* ♦— KJ—-!,U *—(U q’)- —' *—,’xj ,/x).U B—J Uèx(KjUm #—! (’./♦ š—Jq š’♦/ x ,—xj’♦’—) ♦/x♦ *UUq* ♦— U)/—(UjU**)U** ’) #—!J ,—((!)’♦# A) ♦/’* ,x*Um #—! '’J*♦ )UU- ♦— ’-U)♦’'# ♦/U *♦xqU/—j-UJ*«♦/U KU—KjU š/— /x>U x *♦xqU ’) Uj’(’)x♦’). /—(UjU**)U** HV>’—!*j#m KU—KjU š’♦/—!♦ /—(U* -—m V!♦ š/— Uj*Uv N/Uj♦UJ š—JqUJ*v 4—(P (!)’♦# x.U),’U*v uU’./V—J/——- JU*’-U)♦*v b—! xj*— )UU- ♦— ’-U)♦’'# š/— /x* ♦/U K—šUJ ♦— U''U,♦ ,/x).U x)- š/x♦ ♦/U KU—KjU #—! xJU š—Jq’). š’♦/ ♦/’)q )UU-* JU*UxJ,/’). B—J Uèx(KjUm ♦/U# (’./♦ VUj’U>U ♦/x♦ ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ */—!j- '—,!* —) ♦/U ,—*♦ —' /—!*’). ’) ♦/U ,—((!)’♦# x)- —) KU—KjUí* šx.U* A) x,♦’—) JU*UxJ,/m Jx♦/UJ ♦/x) VU.’) š’♦/ x ♦/U—J#m #—! )UU- ♦— VU.’) š’♦/ x ,jUxJ *♦x♦U(U)♦ —' ♦/U )UU-* x)- KJ’—J’♦’U* —' ♦/U .J—!K 8/’jU ♦/U -’*,!**’—) —' JU*UxJ,/ KxJx-’.(* ’) 4/xK♦UJ c (x# /x>U *UU(U- xV*♦Jx,♦m ♦/U ,/—’,U —' x KxJx-’.( /x* JUxjPj’'U ’(Kj’,x♦’—)* F/U :U>Uj—K’). x 2U*UxJ,/ N♦Jx♦U.# lT ,/—’,U* #—! U>U)♦!xjj# (xqU š’jj -U♦UJ(’)U š/U♦/UJ #—! ♦!J) '’J*♦ ♦— ♦/U K!Vj’*/U- JU*UxJ,/m —J ♦— ♦/U U(K’J’,xj š—Jj- A) JU*UxJ,/ ♦/x♦ -Jxš* —) ♦/U K—*’♦’>’*♦ ♦Jx-’♦’—)m #—! )UU- ♦— /x>U šUjjP-U>Uj—KU- /#K—♦/U*U* VU'—JU #—! VU.’) #—!J JU*UxJ,/ A) JU*UxJ,/ ♦/x♦ -Jxš* —) ♦/U )x♦!Jxj’*♦’, —J ,—)*♦J!,P ♦’—)’*♦ ♦Jx-’♦’—)*m #—! )UU- ♦— 'Jx(U x .U)UJxj JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—) x)- ,/——*U x *’♦U '—J #—!J JU*UxJ,/ A) JU*UxJ,/ ♦/x♦ -Jxš* —) K—*♦(—-UJ)’*♦ ♦Jx-’♦’—)*m #—! (’./♦ '—,!* —) ♦Uè♦* A) ♦/’* xKKJ—x,/m xj♦/—!./ ’♦í* x .——- ’-Ux ♦— JUxx♦ jUx*♦ *—(U —' ♦/U K!Vj’*/U- j’♦UJx♦!JU VU'—JU #—! VU.’) sx)- (x)# JU*UxJ,/UJ*m (#*Uj' ’),j!-U-m š—!j- ’)*’*♦ ♦/x♦ #—! -— *—Sm #—! -—)í♦ VU.’) š’♦/ xjJUx-# '—J(U- /#K—♦/U*U* A)*♦Ux-m #—! -U>Uj—K #—!J ♦/U—J# x)- x) ’),JUx*’).j# JU'’)U- JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—) x* #—! ,—)-!,♦ ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ d]JV’ )F :V’VN”G* pz”NzV.mV’ H),U #—! /x>U *U♦♦jU- —) x JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—) x)- JU*UxJ,/ ♦Jx-’♦’—)m #—! )UU- ♦— -U,’-U /—š #—! š’jj ,—jjU,♦ #—!J -x♦x NKU,’'’,xjj#m #—! )UU- ♦— x--JU** ♦/U*U ’**!U*? 8/x♦ JU*UxJ,/ *♦Jx♦U.# š’jj #—! !*Uv 8/x♦ K—K!jx♦’—) —J *’♦U š’jj #—! *♦!-#v 8/x♦ ♦Uè♦* š’jj #—! ,/——*Uv 8/x♦ š’jj #—!J U>’-U),U ,—)*’*♦ —'v FJx)*,J’K♦* —' ’)♦UJ>’Uš*v HV*UJ>x♦’—)xj )—♦U*v pJ,/’>xj (x♦UJ’xj*m j’qU jU♦♦UJ* —J -’xJ’U* —J x) —J.x)’❖x♦’—)e* JU,—J-*v N—).* —J >’-U—♦xKU* —'F7 KJ—.Jx(*v 5—š š’jj #—! *KU)- #—!J ♦’(Uv “’*♦U)’). x)- ♦xjq’). ♦— KU—KjUv HV*UJ>’).v w—’). ♦/J—!./ K!Vj’*/U- (x♦UJ’xj*v 8x♦,/’). x!-’—P ♦xKU*v b—! ,x) ,/——*U 'J—( *U>UJxj .U)UJxj JU*UxJ,/ *♦Jx♦U.’U* 8/’,/ —)U #—! *U♦P ♦jU —) -UKU)-* —) #—!J JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)m ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ ♦Jx-’♦’—) #—! *UU #—!J*Uj' x* š—Jq’). ’)m x)- #—!J —š) ’)-’>’-!xj KJU'UJU),U* k6­-.;K':8JK) 4'áU:-­ A) ♦/U )x♦!Jxj’*♦’, —J ,—)*♦J!,♦’—)’*♦ ♦Jx-’♦’—)*m #—! (’./♦ ,—)-!,♦ x) 86­-.;K':8JK) ­'áU*S ’) š/’,/ #—! .x♦/UJ -x♦x V# —V*UJ>’). ’)♦UJx,♦’—) ’) x KxJ♦’,!jxJ *’♦U s*!,/ x* x *♦JUU♦ ,—J)UJ —J /—(UjU** */Uj♦UJS HV*UJ>x♦’—)xj *♦!-’U* xJU !*U'!j š/U) #—! šx)♦ ♦— !)-UJ*♦x)- /—š KU—KjU VU/x>U ’) x KxJ♦’,!jxJ *U♦♦’). —J š/U) #—! šx)♦ x) ’)P-UK♦/ !)-UJ*♦x)-’). —' x KxJ♦’,!jxJ ,!j♦!JU —J .J—!K A) x) —V*UJ>x♦’—)xj *♦!-#m #—! (’./♦ ,/——*U lh 45p”FM2 i N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J gU.’))’). 2U*UxJ,/ ♦— KxJ♦’,’Kx♦U B—J Uèx(KjUm #—! (’./♦ >—j!)♦UUJ x♦ x /—(UjU** */Uj♦UJm x* Mjj’—♦ “’UV—šm š/—( šU -’*,!**U- ’) 4/xK♦UJ cm -’- HJ #—! (’./♦ ,/——*U *’(Kj# ♦— —V*UJ>U ’) x K!Vj’, Kjx,U s*!,/ x* x */—KK’). (xjj —J x K!Vj’, KxJqEm š’♦/—!♦ KxJ♦’,’Kx♦’). pJ'-.;:-j­ Yx)# ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/UJ* ,/——*U ♦— ,—)-!,♦ '—J(xj ’)P -UK♦/ :J'-.;:-j­ š’♦/ KU—KjU F/U*U ,x) VU JUjx♦’>Uj# *♦J!,♦!JU- —J !)*♦J!,P ♦!JU- A)♦UJ>’Uš* xJU .——- JU*UxJ,/ ♦U,/)’;!U* š/U) #—! šx)♦ ♦— q)—š š/x♦ KU—KjU ♦/’)q —J 'UUj xV—!♦ *—(U♦/’). 2U*UxJ,/UJ* —'♦U) ,—(V’)U —V*UJ>x♦’—)xj ♦U,/)’;!U* š’♦/ U’♦/UJ '—J(xj —J ’)'—J(xj ’)♦UJ>’Uš* A) '—JP (xj ’)♦UJ>’Uš*m ♦/U JU*UxJ,/UJ *U♦* x KxJ♦’,!jxJ ♦’(U x)- Kjx,U '—J x) ’)♦UJP >’Uš A)'—J(xj ’)♦UJ>’Uš* ♦U)- ♦— xJ’*U *K—)♦x)U—!*j# ’) ♦/U ,—!J*U —' —V*UJ>x♦’—) B—J Uèx(KjUm #—! (’./♦ -U,’-U ♦— '—J(xjj# ’)♦UJ>’Uš KU—KjU š/— >—j!)♦UUJ ’) x /—(UjU** */Uj♦UJ ’) —J-UJ ♦— !)-UJ*♦x)- ♦/U’J UèKUJ’P U),U*m x* šUjj x* ♦— —V*UJ>U x)- ’)'—J(xjj# ’)♦UJ>’Uš */Uj♦UJ JU*’-U)♦* ’J86'.á­:;- P-K­á.-­ u—♦ xjj JU*UxJ,/ ’)>—j>U* ♦xjq’). š’♦/ —J —V*UJ>’). KU—KjU ’J86'.á­:;- .-­-K.70 ’)>—j>U* Uèx(’)’). /!(x) ♦Jx,U*m —J U>’-U),U —' /!(x) x,♦’>’♦# B—J Uèx(KjUm ’' #—! šx)♦ ♦— q)—š š/’,/ (x.x❖’)U* ’) ♦/U j’VJxJ# xJU (—*♦ K—K!jxJm #—! (’./♦ *♦!-# š/’,/ —)U* *UU( ♦— /x>U ♦/!(VU- Kx.U* —J *UU( ♦— /x>U VUU) /Ux>’j# KUJ!*U- p )!(VUJ —' JUP *UxJ,/UJ* /x>U *♦!-’U- K!Vj’, .Jx''’♦’ 4xJ—j’)U 4—jU scRRcSm '—J Uèx(KjUm x)xj#❖U- ♦/U šJ’♦’). —) šxjj* ’) š—(U)e* Vx♦/J——(*m xJ.!’). ♦/x♦ ♦/U .Jx'P '’♦’ ♦/UJU *UJ>U- x* x) xj♦UJ)x♦’>U (Ux)* —' ,—((!)’,x♦’—) 0U'' BUJJUjj scRRTS x)xj#❖U- /’KP/—K .Jx''’♦’ ’) :U)>UJm 4—j—Jx-—m ,—(V’)’). KxJ♦’,’P Kx)♦ —V*UJ>x♦’—) —' .Jx''’♦’ šJ’♦UJ* š’♦/ >’*’♦* ♦— .Jx''’♦’ *’♦U* ’) —♦/UJ ,’♦’U* 5U xJ.!U* ♦/x♦ /’KP/—K .Jx''’♦’ JU'jU,♦* #—!). KU—KjUí* U''—J♦* ♦— JU*’*♦ *—,’xj ,—)♦J—j N—(U♦’(U*m JU*UxJ,/UJ* *♦!-# ®♦Uè♦*$*!,/ x* )Uš*KxKUJ*m V——q*m —J.x)’P ❖x♦’—)xj JU,—J-*m F7 */—š*m x)- ,—!J♦ ♦Jx)*,J’K♦* B—J Uèx(KjUm N/xJ—) 5x#* šx)♦U- ♦— ’)>U*♦’.x♦U š/x♦ */U ,xjjU- ♦/U ®,!j♦!Jxj ,—)♦Jx-’,♦’—)* —' (—♦/P UJ/——-$ scRRhS F— -— *—m */U x)xj#❖U- ,/’j-PJUxJ’). (x)!xj* ♦— ’-U)♦’'# ♦/U q’)-* —' *—,’xj )—J(* '—J (—♦/UJ’). ,—)♦x’)U- ’) ♦/U( x)- ,—)-!,♦U- ’)P -UK♦/ ’)♦UJ>’Uš* š’♦/ (—♦/UJ* —' *(xjj ,/’j-JU) ♦— -U♦UJ(’)U /—š ♦/U# x,♦!xjj# >’UšU- ♦/U’J (—♦/UJ’). M.:KJ1á)K':8J Mx,/ JU*UxJ,/ *♦Jx♦U.# /x* KxJ♦’,!jxJ *♦JU).♦/* x)- šUxqP )U**U* B—J Uèx(KjUm ’)P-UK♦/ ’)♦UJ>’Uš* ,x) KJ—>’-U ’)*’./♦ ’)♦— KU—KjUí* ♦/—!./♦* x)- 'UUj’).*m V!♦ KU—KjUí* VU/x>’—J* -—)í♦ xjšx#* (x♦,/ ♦/U’J š—J-* p)xj#*’* —' ♦Uè♦* ,x) ♦Ujj #—! xV—!♦ *—,’xj ’-Uxj* '—J VU/x>’—Jm V!♦ ♦/U 2Ux-’). ♦/U “’♦UJx♦!JU lW ♦Uè♦* ,x)í♦ ♦Ujj #—! /—š KU—KjU x,♦!xjj# JU*K—)- ♦— ♦/U( B—J ♦/’* JUx*—)m JU*UxJ,/UJ* —'♦U) !*U ♦š— —J (—JU JU*UxJ,/ *♦Jx♦U.’U* F/’* ’* ,xjjU- '.:KJ1á )K':8Jo gU,x!*U -’''UJU)♦ -x♦x ,—jjU,♦’—) *♦Jx♦U.’U* /x>U -’''UJU)♦ *♦JU).♦/* x)- šUxq)U**U*m JU*UxJ,/ -U*’.)* ♦/x♦ ’),j!-U (!j♦’KjU JU*UxJ,/ *♦Jx♦U.’U* ♦U)- ♦— VU ♦/U *♦J—).U*♦ —)U* :2S?56B dn2 35d2:Sdw:2 8/’,/U>UJ JU*UxJ,/ ♦Jx-’♦’—) x)- *♦Jx♦U.# #—! ,/——*Um #—! */—!j- >’*’♦ ♦/U j’VJxJ# UxJj# ’) ♦/U KJ—,U** —' -U*’.)’). #—!J JU*UxJ,/ pj♦/—!./ *—(U )x♦!P Jxj’*♦’, JU*UxJ,/UJ* ,x!♦’—) x.x’)*♦ VU,—(’). ♦—— šU--U- ♦— x KxJ♦’,!jxJ ♦/UP —J# —J >’UšK—’)♦ VU'—JU ’((UJ*’). #—!J*Uj' ’) #—!J '’Uj- *U♦♦’).m A ♦/’)q ♦/’* ,—),UJ) ’* x j’♦♦jU —>UJ*♦x♦U- g# q)—š’). š/x♦ —♦/UJ JU*UxJ,/UJ* /x>U xjJUx-# *x’- xV—!♦ #—!J ♦—K’,m #—! xJU ’) x VU♦♦UJ K—*’♦’—) ♦— ,—(U !K š’♦/ x šUjjP♦/—!./♦P—!♦ JU*UxJ,/ Kjx) p)- x♦ *—(U K—’)♦ -!J’). ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ KJ—P ,U**m #—! š’jj *♦’jj )UU- ♦— ,—)-!,♦ x j’♦UJx♦!JU JU>’Uš ♦— /UjK #—! Kjx,U #—!J —š) JU*UxJ,/ ’) ,—)♦Uè♦ A JU,—((U)- ♦/x♦ #—! VU.’) x)# JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦ V# *’(Kj# VJ—š*’). “——q ♦/J—!./ ♦/U ­—!J)xj* x)- V——q* ♦/x♦ *UU( (—*♦ ’)♦UJU*♦’). ♦— #—!m —J VJ—š*U ♦/J—!./ ♦/U -x♦xVx*U* x>x’jxVjU x♦ #—!J j’VJxJ# A !*!xjj# *q’( ♦/J—!./ ♦/U xV*♦Jx,♦ —J ♦/U ’)♦J—-!,♦’—) ;!’,qj# ♦— *UU ’' A (’./♦ šx)♦ ♦— JUx- ♦/U š/—jU xJ♦’,jU —J V——q F/U) A .— ♦/J—!./ ♦/—*U JUx-’).* ♦/x♦ *UU( (—*♦ !*U'!j ’) (—JU -U♦x’j A JU,—((U)- j——q’). x♦ x* š’-U x >xJ’U♦# —' *—!J,U* x* #—! ,x) p* #—! -— *—m VU *!JU ♦— ♦xqU .——- )—♦U* s’),j!-’). x,,!P Jx♦U ,’♦x♦’—)*S *— ♦/x♦ #—! ,x) j—,x♦U ♦/U *—!J,U* x.x’) x* )UU-U- F/UJUí* )—♦/’). (—JU 'J!*♦Jx♦’). ♦/x) q)—š’). ♦/x♦ #—! /x- ♦/U KUJ'U,♦ *—!J,U V!♦ VU’). !)xVjU ♦— !*U ’♦ VU,x!*U #—! ,x)í♦ '’)- ’♦ x.x’) M>UJ# j’VJxJ# ’* -’''UJU)♦ N—(U /x>U *!V*,J’K♦’—)* ♦— (x)# ­—!J)xj* x)Uè,UjjU)♦ —)Pj’)U *UxJ,/’). ,xKxV’j’♦’U*y —♦/UJ* -—)í♦ Mx,/ j’VJxJ# /x* ’♦* —š) *KU,’xj šx# —' KJ—>’-’). x,,U** ♦— ♦/U (x♦UJ’xj* N—(U j’VJxJ’U* /x>U —)Pj’)U *UxJ,/ *UJ>’,U*m j’qU MgN4H/—*♦ —J A)'—♦Jx,m š/’,/ š’jj -Uj’>UJ š/—jU xJ♦’,jU* ♦— #—! —)Pj’)U H♦/UJ* /x>U x jxJ.U *UjU,♦’—) —' V——q* x)­—!J)xj* ’) KJ’)♦ ♦/x♦ #—! ,x) VJ—š*U ♦/J—!./ b—!J j’VJxJ’x) —J KJ—'U**—J š’jj VU ♦/U VU*♦ KUJ*—) ♦— /UjK #—! *UxJ,/ ’) #—!J —š) j’VJxJ# Y—*♦ j’VJxJ’U* š’jj /x>U x,,U** ♦— N—,’—j—.’,xj pV*♦Jx,♦*m U’♦/UJ ’) KJ’)♦ —J —)Pj’)U H)U —' ♦/U (—*♦ ’(K—J♦x)♦ -x♦xVx*U* '—J *—,’—j—.’*♦*m N—,’—j—.’P ,xj pV*♦Jx,♦* *!((xJ’❖U* ♦/U xJ♦’,jU* ’) ♦/U (—*♦ ’(K—J♦x)♦ ­—!J)xj* ♦/x♦ *—,’—j—.’*♦* K!Vj’*/ ’) g# *UxJ,/’). ♦/’* ’)-Uèm #—! */—!j- VU xVjU ♦— .U♦ x .——- ’-Ux —' š/x♦ —♦/UJ* /x>U *x’- xV—!♦ #—!J ♦—K’, :UKU)-’). —) #—!J lI 45p”FM2 i N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J gU.’))’). 2U*UxJ,/ '’Uj- x)- ♦—K’,m #—! (x# xj*— šx)♦ ♦— *UxJ,/ -x♦xVx*U* *!,/ x* ”*#,/—j—.’,xj pV*♦Jx,♦*m M2A4m —J 4J’(’)xj 0!*♦’,U pV*♦Jx,♦* p.x’)m A *♦J—).j# JU,—((U)♦/x♦ #—! ,/U,q š’♦/ #—!J KJ—'U**—J —J j’VJxJ’x) ♦— *UU š/x♦ JU*—!J,U* —) #—!J ,x(K!* (’./♦ VU /UjK'!j '—J #—! pj♦/—!./ ♦/’* V——q ,x)í♦ /UjK #—! *UxJ,/ #—!J *KU,’'’, j’VJxJ#m ’♦ ,x) .’>U #—! *—(U .U)UJxj ♦’K* —) ,—)-!,♦’). x !*U'!j j’VJxJ# *UxJ,/? c FJ# x )!(VUJ —' -’''UJU)♦ ♦UJ(* '—J ♦/U *x(U ♦/’). :’''UJU)♦ -x♦xP Vx*U* š’jj —'♦U) !*U *—(Uš/x♦ -’''UJU)♦ qU# š—J-*m x)- ♦/U *x(U -x♦xVx*U (x# #’Uj- >UJ# -’''UJU)♦ xJ♦’,jU* ’' #—! !*U ­!*♦ *j’./♦j# -’'P 'UJU)♦ *UxJ,/ ♦UJ(* i A' ♦/U ♦UJ( #—!í>U *UxJ,/U- #’Uj-* ♦—— (x)# ,’♦x♦’—)* ♦— j——q ♦/J—!./m ♦J# )xJJ—š’). ’♦ -—š) B—J Uèx(KjUm A JU,U)♦j# !*U- ♦/U —)Pj’)U >UJ*’—) —' N—,’—j—.’,xj pV*♦Jx,♦* ♦— *UxJ,/ ♦/U ♦UJ( Cš—JqP ’). š—(U) $8/U) A -’- *—m A JU,U’>U- lhhR ®/’♦*$«,jUxJj#m ♦—— (x)# ♦— j——q ♦/J—!./ 8/U) A )xJJ—šU- ♦/U ♦—K’, ♦— Cš—Jq’). š—(U) x)- *Uè!xj /xJx**(U)♦m$A JU,U’>U- dR ,’♦x♦’—)*«*♦’jj x j—♦ ♦— j——q ♦/J—!./m V!♦ x (!,/ (—JU (x)x.UxVjU )!(VUJ l FJ# x )!(VUJ —' -’''UJU)♦ *—!J,U*m ’),j!-’). ♦/U V——q ,x♦xj—.!Um ♦/U ­—!J)xj* sxj*— ,xjjU- *UJ’xj*Sm x)- ♦/U A)♦UJ)U♦ :’''UJU)♦ *—!J,U* š’jj ♦U)- ♦— .’>U #—! >UJ# -’''UJU)♦ q’)-* —' JU*!j♦* d H),U #—!í>U '—!)- x !*U'!j xJ♦’,jU —J V——qm *UU ’' #—! ,x) ♦Jx,q -—š) *—(U —' ♦/U *—!J,U* ♦/U x!♦/—J !*U- F/U# xJU —'♦U) /UjK'!j T p*q x j’VJxJ’x) '—J /UjKm U*KU,’xjj# ’' #—!íJU '’)-’). >UJ# j’♦♦jU ’)'—JP (x♦’—) xV—!♦ š/x♦ #—! ♦/’)q */—!j- VU x K—K!jxJ ♦—K’, g!♦ VU *!JU #—!í>U xjJUx-# ♦/—!./♦ xV—!♦ *—(U K—♦U)♦’xj x).jU* '—J #—!J KJ—­U,♦ F/U j’VJxJ’x) ,x)í♦ ,JUx♦U x JU*UxJ,/ ♦—K’, '—J #—!m V!♦ */U —J /U ,x) /UjK #—! '’)- ♦/U J’./♦ JU*—!J,U*m .’>U) x *KU,’'’, ♦—K’, 27S3wSd56B 82o p5d2p F/U A)♦UJ)U♦ ,x) KJ—>’-U x šUxj♦/ —' (x♦UJ’xj '—J JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦* b—! ,x) .U♦ ’)'—J(x♦’—) 'J—( x >xJ’U♦# —' .—>UJ)(U)♦ x)- KJ’>x♦U *—!J,U*m x* šUjj x* JU*UxJ,/ JUK—J♦*m V——q JU>’Uš*m x)- —♦/UJ !*U'!j ♦Uè♦* Yx)# .—>UJ)(U)♦ x.U),’U* /x>U 8UV *’♦U*m ’),j!-’). ♦/U 4U)*!* g!JUx!m ♦/U g!JUx! —' “xV—J N♦x♦’*♦’,*m x)- ♦/U BgA 5—šU>UJm ♦/U A)♦UJ)U♦ ,x) xj*— jUx- #—! x*♦Jx# p 'J’U)- —' (’)U *x#* ♦/x♦ ♦/U 8—Jj- 8’-U 8UV ’* j’qU x /!.U ,x♦xj—.!U« U>UJ#—)U šx)♦* ♦— *Ujj #—! *—(U♦/’). F/!*m #—! )UU- ♦— U>xj!x♦U 8UV *’♦U* F/U 2U*UxJ,/ ”J—,U** ’) 2U>’Uš ep ,xJU'!jj# VU'—JU JUj#’). —) ♦/U( ’) #—!J JU*UxJ,/ 5UJU xJU x 'Uš ;!U*♦’—)* ♦— x*q ’) ­!-.’). ♦/U !*U'!j)U** —' >xJ’—!* *’♦U*? 8/— *K—)*—JU- ♦/U *’♦Uv A* ’♦ (x’)♦x’)U- V# x ,—((UJ,’xj U)♦UJP KJ’*U —J ’)-’>’-!xj* š/— *♦x)- ♦— .x’) *—(U♦/’).v :—U* ’♦ ,—)♦x’) x->UJ♦’*’).v A* ’♦ (x’)♦x’)U- V# x .—>UJ)(U)♦ x.U),# —J !)’>UJ*’♦# —J JU*UxJ,/ ’)*♦’♦!♦’—)v HJ ’* ’♦ (x’)♦x’)U- V# x) ’)-’>’-!xjv A' *—m š/x♦ ;!xj’'’,x♦’—)* -—U* ♦/U KUJ*—) /x>Uv A* */U —J /U x) UèKUJ♦ ’) ♦/U '’Uj-m —J *—(U—)U š/— ’* (x’)j# ♦J#’). ♦— UèKJU** x KUJ*—)xj K—’)♦ —' >’Ušv :—U* ♦/U *’♦U *UU( —V>’—!*j# V’x*U-v :—U* ’♦ !*U —V>’—!*j# ’)'jx(P (x♦—J# jx).!x.Uv A* ’♦ K!Vj’*/U- V# x K—j’♦’,xj —J *—,’xj —J.x)’❖x♦’—) š’♦/ x KxJ♦’,!jxJ x.U)-xv :—U* ’♦ /x>U x (’**’—) *♦x♦U(U)♦ —J *♦x♦UP (U)♦ —' K!JK—*U x)#š/UJU —) ♦/U *’♦Uv 8/x♦ q’)-* —' *’♦U* ’* ’♦ j’)qU- ♦—v 5—š —'♦U) ’* ♦/U *’♦U !K-x♦U-v A' ’♦ šx* K!Vj’*/U- *U>UJxj #UxJ* x.— x)- /x*)í♦ VUU) !K-x♦U- *’),Um ’♦ KJ—VxVj# ’* )—♦ x KxJ♦’,!jxJj# JUj’P xVjU *—!J,U p* #—! ,—)♦’)!U ♦— -U>Uj—K x)- JU'’)U #—!J JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦m #—! š’jj KJ—VxVj# )UU- ♦— JU♦!J) ♦— ♦/U j’VJxJ# x )!(VUJ —' ♦’(U* p* #—!J JU*UxJ,/ ,/x).U*m *— š’jj ♦/U j’♦UJx♦!JU ♦/x♦ #—! '’)- !*U'!j g!♦ ♦/U*U ♦’K* x♦ jUx*♦ š’jj .U♦ #—! *♦xJ♦Udn2 :2p2S:ln b:Ol2pp 56 :27528 :U>Uj—K’). x .——- JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦ ’* x) —).—’). KJ—,U** F/UJU xJU x )!(P VUJ —' *♦UK* #—! )UU- ♦— ♦xqU š/U) U(VxJq’). —) x JU*UxJ,/ KJ—­U,♦ pj♦/—!./ ♦/U *♦UK* xJU j’*♦U- ’) —)U —J-UJ /UJUm #—! š’jj KJ—VxVj# '’)- ♦/x♦ #—! )UU- ♦— .— Vx,q x)- '—J♦/ VU♦šUU) ♦/U *♦UK* x* #—!J JU*UxJ,/ !)'—j-* b—! */—!j- xj*— JUxj’❖U ♦/x♦ #—!J KJ—­U,♦ (x# */’'♦ ’♦* '—,!* x* #—! jUxJ) (—JU x)- .x♦/UJ (—JU U>’-U),U xV—!♦ #—!J ♦—K’, p♦ Ux,/ —' ♦/U*U *♦x.U*m ♦J# ♦— JU(x’) —KU) ♦— xj♦UJ)x♦’>U Kx♦/* c 4/——*U x .U)UJxj ♦—K’, x)- ♦J# ♦— JU'’)U ’♦ ’)♦— x JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—) i M>xj!x♦U š/U♦/UJ #—!J ♦—K’, ’* ’)♦UJU*♦’).m 'Ux*’VjUm x)- š—J♦/ -—’).«x)- U♦/’,xj 4/xK♦UJ l -’*,!**U* U♦/’,xj ’**!U* ♦/x♦ (x# xJ’*U ’) JU*UxJ,/ l :U>Uj—K x JU*UxJ,/ *♦Jx♦U.# :U,’-U —) ♦/U q’)-* —' -x♦x #—! š’jj ,—jjU,♦m x)- ♦/’)q xV—!♦ /—š #—! š’jj ♦J# ♦— x)xj#❖U —J (xqU *U)*U —' ♦/U( YxqU *!JU ♦/x♦ ♦/U *♦Jx♦U.# ’* ,—)*’*♦U)♦ š’♦/ ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—) #—! K—*U x)- ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ ♦Jx-’♦’—) #—! xJU š—Jq’). š’♦/’) d gU.’) #—!J *UxJ,/ —' ♦/U j’♦UJx♦!JU pj♦/—!./ #—! š’jj KJ—VxVj# )UU- ♦— JU♦!J) ♦— ♦/U j’♦UJx♦!JU x♦ —♦/UJ *♦x.U* ’) ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ KJ—P ,U**m #—! */—!j- VU.’) š’♦/ x .——- *U)*U —' š/x♦ —♦/UJ* š/— /x>U *♦!-’U- ♦/U *x(U ♦—K’, /x>U '—!)T gU.’) ,—jjU,♦’). x)- —J.x)’❖’). #—!J -x♦x 4/xK♦UJ* dPW Uèx(’)U -’''UJU)♦ (U♦/—-* —' ,—jjU,♦’). -x♦xm ’),j!-’). —V*UJ>x♦’—)m ’)♦UJP >’Uš*m ♦Uè♦!xj x)xj#*’*m x)- x,♦’—) JU*UxJ,/ h gU.’) x)xj#❖’). s—J ’)♦UJKJU♦’).S #—!J -x♦x pj♦/—!./ ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/UJ* !*!xjj# (—>U Vx,q x)- '—J♦/ VU♦šUU) x)xj#❖’). x)- ,—jP jU,♦’). -x♦xm ’♦ ’* *—(U♦’(U* /UjK'!j ♦— ♦/’)q —' ♦/U ♦š— x* *UKxJx♦U *♦UK*m x♦ jUx*♦ ’)’♦’xjj# 4/xK♦UJ* I x)- R -’*,!** *♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J ’)♦UJP KJU♦’). -x♦x W 8J’♦U !K #—!J JU*UxJ,/ A) ;!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/m ’♦ ,x) *—(U♦’(U* *UU( x* ’' #—! xJU šJ’♦’). xjj ♦/U ♦’(U 4UJ♦x’)j#m ♦/U KJ—,U** —' —J.x)’❖’). -x♦x U)♦x’j* šJ’♦’).m x* -—U* ’)♦UJKJU♦x♦’—) L!xj’♦x♦’>U JU*UxJ,/UJ* KJU*U)♦ ♦/U’J š—Jq ’) (x)# >U)!U*? x* ­—!J)xj xJ♦’,jU* —J V——q*m x* KJU*U)♦x♦’—)* x♦ KJ—'U**’—)xj ,—)'UJU),U*m x♦ ♦Jx’)’). *U*P *’—)* —J ’)P*UJ>’,U (UU♦’).* '—J KJ—'U**’—)xj*m x)- x* KJU*U)♦x♦’—)* '—J ,—((!)’♦# .J—!K* 4/xK♦UJ ca '—,!*U* —) *♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J šJ’♦’). !K #—!J JU*UxJ,/ x)- KJU*U)♦’). ’♦ ♦— x jxJ.UJ ,—((!)’♦# da 45p”FM2 i N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J gU.’))’). 2U*UxJ,/ vw2pd5O6 gO: dnOwBnd u—š ’* ♦/U ♦’(U ♦— ,—)*’-UJ š/UJU *8á *♦x)- ’) JUjx♦’—) ♦— #—!J JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—) F/’)q Vx,q ♦— ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ ♦Jx-’♦’—)*m —J KxJx-’.(*m —!♦j’)U- ’) 4/xK♦UJ c 8/’,/ —)Us*S *UU( (—*♦ ,—)>’),’). ♦— #—!v :— #—! ♦/’)q JUP *UxJ,/UJ* */—!j- ♦xqU x ,J’♦’,xj K—*’♦’—)v HJ -—U* x (—JU ♦Jx-’♦’—)xj —J’U)♦xP ♦’—) xKKUxj ♦— #—!v 8/x♦ -— #—! ♦/’)q xJU ♦/U *♦JU).♦/* x)- šUxq)U**U* —' ♦/U >xJ’—!* xKKJ—x,/U*v 8/x♦ KUJ*—)xj ’)*’./♦* -— #—! /x>U ’)♦— #—!J KJ—P K—*U- JU*UxJ,/ ♦—K’,v 8/x♦ q’)-* —' *KU,’xj q)—šjU-.U (’./♦ #—! /x>U V# >’J♦!U —' #—!J —š) j’'U UèKUJ’U),U*v 5—š (’./♦ ♦/U*U ’)*’./♦* */xKU ♦/U q’)-* —' JU*UxJ,/ #—! (’./♦ -—v N!..U*♦’—)* '—J B!J♦/UJ 2Ux-’). dc 2U2:l5p2p c p* #—! .— xV—!♦ #—!J -x’j# J—!♦’)Um ♦J# ♦— Kx# KxJ♦’,!jxJ x♦♦U)♦’—) ♦— #—!J *!JJ—!)-’).* NUU ’' #—! ,x) -U>Uj—K x♦ jUx*♦ ♦š— JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)* *KxJqU- V# š/x♦ #—! U),—!)♦UJ ’) #—!J -x’j# j’'U i M>xj!x♦U —)U —' #—!J JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)* ’) ♦UJ(* —' š/U♦/UJ ’♦ ’* ’)♦UJP U*♦’).m 'Ux*’VjUm x)- š—J♦/ -—’). 4—)*’-UJ š/x♦ q’)-* —' JU*—!J,U* #—! š—!j- )UU- ♦— ,—(KjU♦U ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ l F/’)q —' x .U)UJxj JU*UxJ,/ ♦—K’, ♦/x♦ #—! (’./♦ '’)- ’)♦UJU*♦’). 4x) #—! ,—(U !K š’♦/ ♦/JUU —J '—!J -’''UJU)♦ KUJ*KU,♦’>U* —) ’♦v FJ# JU'’)’). ♦/U ♦—K’, ’)♦— *U>UJxj -’''UJU)♦ JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)* d w— ♦— ♦/U j’VJxJ# ♦— *UU š/x♦ ’)'—J(x♦’—) #—! ,x) '’)- xV—!♦ ♦/U JU*UxJ,/ ;!U*♦’—)* #—! -U>Uj—KU- “—,x♦U x♦ jUx*♦ '’>U V——q* —J ­—!J)xj xJ♦’,jU* ♦/x♦ #—! ♦/’)q (’./♦ VU !*U'!j T NUxJ,/ ♦/U A)♦UJ)U♦ ♦— '’)- x♦ jUx*♦ ♦š— -’''UJU)♦ 8UV *’♦U* —' ’)♦UJU*♦ ♦— #—! M>xj!x♦U Ux,/ 8UV *’♦U #—!í>U ,/—*U) ’) ♦UJ(* —' ’♦* K—♦U)♦’xj !*UP '!j)U** —J V’x* h O*U *U>UJxj -’''UJU)♦ JU*UxJ,/ *♦Jx♦U.’U* ♦— j—,x♦U ’)'—J(x♦’—) xV—!♦ #—!J ♦—K’, FJ# *U>UJxj -’''UJU)♦ *UxJ,/ U).’)U* —) ♦/U A)♦UJ)U♦m *!,/ x* bx/—— —J Mè,’♦Um x)- *U>UJxj x,x-U(’, -x♦xVx*U*m *!,/ x* ♦/U ,xJ- ,x♦xj—.!U x)N—,’—j—.’,xj pV*♦Jx,♦* s4/U,q š’♦/ #—!J KJ—'U**—J —J j’VJxJ’x) xV—!♦ ♦/U VU*♦ (U♦/—-* '—J *UxJ,/’). —) #—!J ,x(K!* S 8/x♦ -’''UJU)♦ q’)-* —' (x♦UJ’xj* -— #—! '’)- !*’). Ux,/ *♦Jx♦U.#v pwBB2pd5O6p gO: gw:dn2: :2S?56B l”V’;V­­x 4)*- 8 y-­-K.70 3-­:1Jf ,áK):'K':;- KJU ,áKJ':'K':;- x"".8K70-­o d*)—i ’N-Y ONy’x lSt pN.Vx HhhT S .))Y m-z”)Y—Gzm)- z) ”V’VN”G* YV’m.-x V’JVGmN­­] F)” z*)’V m-zV”V’zVY m- G)(JN”m-. “—N­mzNzmQV N-Y “—N-zmzNzmQV NJJ”)NG*V’ B­N’’-V”x oN””]x N-Y :)’N--N nV”z" fVY’ a ,áK):'K':;- 487:8)81* K­ H;-.*UK* W:L-o d*)—’N-Y ONy’x lSt pN.Vx Hhhh S G)­­VGzm)- )F V’’N]’ L] “—N­mzNzmQV ’G*)­N”’ z*Nz V[N(m-V z*V ­m-yN.V’ LVz;VV- ’)Gm)­).mGN­ ”V’VN”G* N-Y VQV”]YN] ­mFV 3N”VN—x S--VzzVx N-Y 4VFF”V] p*—­z" fVY’ a ?8á.J-*­ M0.8á10 H'0J81.K"0*f y-K):­':7 x778áJ'­ 8L w:-)Uj8.(o o)—­YV”x lOt 8V’zQmV; b”V’’x HhhR S G)­­VGzm)- )F ”V’VN”G*V”’Z NGG)—-z’ )F Y)m-. “—N­mzNzmQV ”V’VN”G* 3Vl)(JzVx uN”.N”Vz ? x N-Y 4VN- 4 pG*V-’—­ 3-­:1J:J1 KJU 28JUá7':J1 H'0J8 1.K"0:7 y-­-K.70o 8N­-—z l”VVyx lSt S­zNum”N b”V’’x Hhhh bN”z )F z*V 2z*-).i ”NJ*V”Z’ d))­ymzx N ’VQV-iL))y .—mYV z) G)-Y—Gzm-. Vz*-).”NJ*mG ”V’VN”G* nxBx xRdxr p,qUJm 0—x)y fx♦U gxJJ#y x)- 0—qU M**U>Uj- cRRh ®HV­U,♦’>’♦# x)- FJ!♦/? ”J—VjU(* ’) :—’). BU(’)’*♦ 2U*UxJ,/ $ ”K haPIW ’) w-z:J:­z KJU 487:K) 20KJ1-f d.:U1:J1 M0-8.* KJU b.K7':7-o OJVx)x x)- 4/’,x.—? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' Ajj’)—’* ”JU** p-jUJm ”x♦J’,’x p cRIT O0--):J1 KJU 3-K):J1o uUš b—Jq? 4—j!(V’x O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** p-jUJm ”x♦J’,’x p m x)- ”U♦UJ p-jUJ cRRc ®N♦xV’j’♦# x)- BjUè’V’j’♦#? Yx’)♦x’)’). 2Ujx♦’—)* š’♦/’) HJ.x)’❖U- x)- O)—J.x)’❖U- wJ—!K* $”K cWlPcIl ’) H& "-.:-J7:J1 w:-)Uj8.(f x J pJ­:U- “:-j 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70o uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U p-jUJm ”x♦J’,’x p m x)- ”U♦UJ p-jUJ cRRd ®N—,’xj 2UKJ—-!,♦’—) x)- ♦/U 4—JK—P Jx♦U H♦/UJ? F/U A)*♦’♦!♦’—)xj’❖x♦’—) —' p'♦UJ*,/——j p,♦’>’♦’U* $ 487:8)81:7K) ,áK.'-.)* lT?laRPliI pj’)*q#m Nx!j :x>’- cRWc yá)-­ L8. yKU:7K)­f x b.K7':7K) b.:z-. L8. y-K):­':7 yKU :7K)­o uUš b—Jq? 2x)-—( 5—!*U pj♦/U’-Um :x>’- “m x)- 2 Nx( Y’,/xj—š*q’ cRRR ®BUxJ ’) ♦/U uUš*? p :’*P ,—!J*U —' 4—)♦J—j $M0- 487:8)81:7K) ,áK.'-.)* da?dWTPTal p(UJ’,x) N—,’—j—.’,xj p**—,’x♦’—) cRRW 4'*)- Dá:U-S i)- U- 8x*/’).♦—)m :4? p(UJ’,x) N—,’—j—.’,xj p**—,’x♦’—) p)-UJ*—)m fx♦/J#)y N!*x) pJ(’♦x.Uy :x)x 0x,qy x)- 0!-’♦/ 8’♦♦)UJ cRRa CgUP .’))’).8/UJU 8U pJU? BU(’)’*♦ YU♦/—-—j—.# ’) HJxj 5’*♦—J# $”K RdPcci ’) w-z:J:­' y-­-K.70 P-'08U­f H&-z")K.* y-KU:J1­ :J '0- 487:K) 47:-J7-­S U-’♦U- V# 0—#,U Y,4xJj u’Uj*U) g—!j-UJm 4H? 8U*♦>’Uš ”JU** p♦q’)*—)m ”x!jm x)- YxJ♦#) 5x((UJ*jU# cRRI CM♦/)—.JxK/# x)- ”xJ♦’,’Kx)♦ HV*UJ>x♦’—) $ ”K ccaPclh ’) 4'.K'-1:-­ 8L ,áK):'K':;- pJqá:.*S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U gxVV’Um MxJj cRRa 4á.;-* y-­-K.70 P-'08U­o gUj(—)♦m 4p? 8x-*š—J♦/ gxJ♦/Ujm :’x)U cRII bá'':J1 8J x""-K.KJ7-­f D-JU-. KJU xU;-.':­:J1o ”/’jx-UjP K/’x? FU(KjU O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** ilW ilI 2MBM2Mu4MN gU,qUJm gU♦♦’)x cRRR CuxJJx♦’>U* —' ”x’) ’) “x♦UJ “’'U x)- 4—)>U)♦’—)* —' N♦—J#♦Ujj’). $?8á.JK) 8Lx1:J1 4'áU:-­ cl?WlPIW gU,qUJm 5—šxJ- N cRhl ká'­:U-.­f 4'áU:-­ :J '0- 487:8)81* 8L 3-;:KJ7-o uUš b—Jq? BJUU ”JU** gU,qUJm 5—šxJ- N cRIh O.:':J1 L8. 487:K) 47:-J':­'­f Y8j '8 4'K.' KJU w:J:­0 V8á. M0-­:­S d88(S 8. x.':7)-o 4/’,x.—? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4/’,x.— ”JU** gU,qUJm 5—šxJ- N cRRI M.:7(­ 8L '0- M.KU-f Y8j '8 M0:J( x68á' V8á. y-­-K.70 O0:)- V8át.- 38:J1 p'o 4/’,x.—? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4/’,x.— ”JU** gU,qUJm 5—šxJ-y gjx),/U wUUJy M>UJU♦♦ 5!./U*y x)- p)*Uj( N♦Jx!** cRWW 6cRhcE d8*­ :J O0:'-f 4'áU-J' 2á)'á.- :J P-U:7K) 47088)o uUš gJ!)*š’,qm u0? FJx)*x,♦’—) gUj.Jx>Um “’)-x “’*qxm x)- fU))U♦/ 0 N(’♦/ ®uU.—♦’x♦U- 7xj’-’♦# ’) 4—jjxV—JxP ♦’>U M♦/)—.JxK/# $,áK):'K':;- pJqá:.* c?hRPIW gUJ.m gJ!,U “ iaac ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70 P-'08U­ L8. '0- 487:K) 47:-J7-­o g—*♦—)? pjj#) tgx,—) gUJ)*m ux),# cRRR ®ÍY# ”J—VjU( x)- 5—š A N—j>U- A♦e? :—(U*♦’, 7’—jU),U ’) 8—(U)í* Yx.x❖’)U* $M0- 487:8)81:7K) ,áK.'-.)* da?ITPcaI g’UJ)x,q’m ”x♦J’,qm x)- :x) 8xj-—J' cRIc CN)—šVxjj Nx(Kj’).? ”J—VjU(* x)FU,/)’;!U* —' 4/x’) 2U'UJJxj Nx(Kj’). $487:8)81:7K) P-'08U­ KJU y-­-K.70 ca?cdcPchl g’)’qm b’♦❖,/xq Yy fU))U♦/ Yx/y x)- NxJx f’U*jUJ cRRR CM♦/’,xj A**!U* ’) 4—)-!,♦’). NUè 2U*UxJ,/ —) ♦/U A)♦UJ)U♦ $ ?8á.JK) 8L 4-& y-­-K.70 lh?IiPRc gjUUm fx♦/jUU) cRRh ®gU,—(’). x 2x,’*♦? 8—(U) ’) 4—)♦U(K—JxJ# f! fj!è fjx) x)- uU—Pux❖’ wJ—!K* $D-JU-. DI-487:-'* ca? hIaPWal gj!(UJm 5UJVUJ♦ cRhR 4*z68):7 pJ'-.K7':8J:­zf b-.­"-7':;- KJU P-'08Uo gUJqUP jU#? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4xj’'—J)’x ”JU** gJ’♦♦—)m :x)x Y cRRR ®4x♦ B’./♦* x)- wx). B’./♦*? ”JU'UJU),U '—J 8—Jq ’) x YxjUP:—(’)x♦U- HJ.x)’❖x♦’—) $487:8)81:7K) ,áK.'-.)* da?dTTPdWd gJ—š)m “ :x>’- cRRl ®N—,’xj 4/x).U F/J—!./ 4—jjU,♦’>U 2U'jU,♦’—) š’♦/ p*’x) u—).—>UJ)(U)♦xj :U>Uj—K(U)♦ HJ.x)’❖x♦’—)* $ Y áz KJ y-)K':8J­ dh?idRPiWd g!Jxš—#m Y’,/xUjm U♦ xj cRRc H'0J81.K"0* ’J68áJUo gUJqUjU#? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4xj’'—J)’x ”JU** 4x),’x)m BJx),U*,x cRRh C”xJ♦’,’Kx♦—J# 2U*UxJ,/ x)- pj♦UJ)x♦’>U N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J p,♦’>’*♦ N—,’—j—.# $ ”K cIWPiaT ’) w-z:J:­z KJU 487:K) 20KJ1-f d.:U1:J1 M0-8.* KJU b.K7':7-S U-’♦U- V# 5U’-’ w—♦♦'J’U- OJVx)x? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' Ajj’P )—’* ”JU** 4x))—)m “#))U 8UVUJy Mj’❖xVU♦/ 5’..’)V—♦/x(y x)- YxJ’x))U “ p “U!). cRRc ®2x,U x)- 4jx** g’x* ’) L!xj’♦x♦’>U 2U*UxJ,/ —) 8—(U) $ ”K caWPccI ’) d-*8JU P-'08U8)81*f w-z:J:­' 4708)K.­0:" K­ W:;-U y-­-K.70S U-’♦U- V# YxJ# YxJ.xJU♦ B—)—š x)- 0!-’♦/ p 4——q gj——(’).♦—)? A)-’x)x O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** 4xKjx)m pJ♦/!J “ cRRi ®8/U) M>’j A)♦J!-U* $YK­':J1­ 2-J'-. y-"8.' ii?iRPli 2MBM2Mu4MN ilR 4/xKq’*m 8U)-# cRRW W:;- 4-& x7'­f O8z-J b-.L8.z:J1 H.8':7 WK68.o uUš b—Jq? 2—!♦jU-.U 4/xJ(x❖m fx♦/# iaaa CwJ—!)-U- F/U—J#? HV­U,♦’>’*♦ x)- 4—)*♦J!,♦’>’*♦ YU♦/—-* $”K TaRPTlh ’) YKJU688( 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- m U-’♦UV# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 4/x♦xšx#m 4#)♦/’x cRRW ®p) Mèx(’)x♦’—) —' ♦/U 4—)*♦Jx’)♦* —) Y!♦!xj A)P ;!’J# ’) x ”xJ♦’,’Kx♦—J# p,♦’—) 2U*UxJ,/ ”J—­U,♦ $ ?8á.JK) 8L 487:K) p­­á-­ Tl?WdWPWhT 4jxJqm 2—.UJy 2x,/Uj “U))—)y x)- “Ux))x Y—JJ’* cRRl ®H' 4xj-U,—♦♦* x)f’).*? wU)-UJU- A(x.U* ’) 2U,U)♦ p(UJ’,x) 4/’j-JU)í* g——q* V# gjx,q x)- u—)Pgjx,q Ajj!*♦Jx♦—J* $D-JU-. 487:-'* W?iiWPidT 4—''U#m p(x)-xm x)- ”x!j p♦q’)*—) cRRh PK(:J1 4-J­- 8L ,áK):'K':;- 3K'Kf 28z")-z-J'K.* y-­-K.70 4'.K'-1:-­o F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 4—jUm 4xJ—j’)U cRRc ®H/ 8’*U 8—(U) —' ♦/U N♦xjj* $ 3:­78á.­- KJU 487:-'* i?dacPdcc 4—jj’)*m ”x♦J’,’x 5’jj cRRa d)K7( w-z:J:­' M08á10'f IJ8j)-U1-S 28J­7:8á­J-­­S KJU '0- b8):':7­ 8L Hz"8j-.z-J'o uUš b—Jq? 2—!♦jU-.U 4—J*xJ—m 8’jj’x(p m x)- “!’*x Y—j’)xJ’ iaaa C”J’(’). M>U)♦* x)- A♦xj’x) 4/’jP -JU)í* FJx)*’♦’—) 'J—( ”JU*,/——j ♦— MjU(U)♦xJ# N,/——j? 2UKJU*U)♦x♦’—)* x)- p,♦’—)* $487:K) b­*708)81* ,áK.'-.)* hl?chPll 4—#m ”x♦J’,q w cRRR ®”xJ♦’,’Kx)♦ HV*UJ>x♦’—)m N/xJU- 2’*q*m x)- ♦/U NUxJ,/ '—J ♦/U 2U*UxJ,/ NUj'p(’-*♦ ”—j’♦’,xj 7’—jU),U $”xKUJ KJU*U)♦U- x♦ ♦/U p(UJ’P ,x) N—,’—j—.’,xj p**—,’x♦’—) x))!xj (UU♦’).m 4/’,x.— :x>’-(x)m “#)) cRRR ®F/U ”UJ*—)xjm ♦/U N—,’—j—.’,xjm x)- ♦/U A)♦UJ*U,♦’—) —' ♦/U Fš— $ ”K WaPIW ’) ,áK):'K':;- 487:8)81* K­ H;-.*UK* W:L-S U-’♦U- V# gxJJ# wjx**)UJ x)- 2—*x))x 5UJ♦❖ F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U :UU.x)m YxJ# 0— cRRc O8z-J :J 487:8)81*f x d:8 d:6):81.K"0:7K) 48á.7-688(o uUš b—Jq? wJUU)š——- ”JU** :U)❖’)m u—J(x) cRIR M0- y-­-K.70 x7'S lJ- U- M).jUš——- 4j’''*m u0? ”JU)♦’,U 5xjj :U)❖’)m u—J(x) cRRR ®”UJ'—J(’). Y—)♦x)x $”K cdWPcTI ’) ,áK):'K':;- 487: 8)81* K­ H;-.*UK* W:L-S U-’♦U- V# gxJJ# wjx**)UJ x)- 2—*x))x 5UJ♦❖ F/—!P *x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U :U)❖’)m u—J(x) iaaa ®F/U ”Jx,♦’,U* x)- ”—j’♦’,* —' A)♦UJKJU♦x♦’—) $ ”K IRWPRii ’) YKJU688( 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- m U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U :U)❖’)m u—J(x) fm x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) cRRI ®A)♦J—-!,♦’—)? M)♦UJ’). ♦/U B’Uj- —' L!xj’♦x♦’>U 2U*UxJ,/ ”K cPld ’) M0- WKJU­7K"- 8L ,áK):'K':;- y­-K.70f M0-8.:-­ KJU p­­á-­S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’)P ,—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U :U)❖’)m u—J(x) fm x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) sU-* S iaaa YKJU688( 8L , áK):'K ':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U :U!♦*,/m BJx),’)U Y cRRR YK);:J1 p' x))f Y8j HqáK))* 40K.-U bK.-J':J1 O8.(­o 4x(VJ’-.Um Yp? 5xJ>xJ- O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** ida 2MBM2Mu4MN :U7x!j♦m YxJ­—J’U “ cRRR W:6-.K':J1 P-'08Uf w-z:J:­z KJU 487:K) y-­-K.70o ”/’jx-UjK/’x? FU(KjU O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** :’,q*—)m wUJxj-’)U iaaa ®pV—J’.’)xj wJx)-(—♦/UJ*í MèKUJ’U),U š’♦/ 5Uxj♦/ ”J—(—♦’—) x)- ”xJ♦’,’Kx♦—J# p,♦’—) 2U*UxJ,/ $,áK):'K':;- Y-K)'0 y-­-K.70 ca?cIIPicd :—-*—)m “’*x cRRI 38Jt' 2K)) ’­ k á' 8L vKz-f M0- ’J'8)U W:;-­ 8L O8z-J KJU D:.)­ :J b88. xz-.:7Ko g—*♦—)? gUx,—) ”JU** :—/x)m :x)’Ujm x)- YxJ♦’) Nx),/U❖P0x)q—š*q’ cRRI ®O*’). 4—(K!♦UJ* ♦—p)P xj#❖U M♦/)—.JxK/’, B’Uj- :x♦x? F/U—JU♦’,xj x)- ”Jx,♦’,xj 4—)*’-UJx♦’—)* $ xJJáK) y-;:-j 8L 487:8)81* id?dWWPdRc :—))Ujj#m :x>’- Bm x)- fJ’*♦’)x 2—** CF/U A)♦UJ)U♦? 5’*♦—J’,xj YU-’x 2U*UxJ,/ —) ♦/U 7’J♦!xj pJ,/’>U* $ Y:­'8.:7K) ?8á.JK) 8L w:)zS yKU:8 iU M-)-;:­:8J cW?ciRPclW Mjj’).*—)m “x!Jx cRRI ®eF/U) b—! f)—š 5—š A BUUjí? M(Kx♦/#m A-U)♦’'’,x♦’—)m x)- 2U'jUè’>’♦# ’) B’Uj-š—Jq $,áK):'K':;- pJqá:.* d?dRiPTcl Mjj’*m 4xJ—j#) cRRI Í®A 5x♦U Y# 7—’,Uí? 4—(’). ♦— FUJ(* š’♦/ Y’)—J g—-’j# N♦’.(x* $487:8)81:7K) ,áK.'-.)* lR?TcWPTlW Mjj’*m 4xJ—j#) cRRR C5UxJ♦'!j p!♦—U♦/)—.JxK/# $ ,áK):'K':;- Y-K)'0 y-­-K.70 R?hhRPhId Mjj’*m 4xJ—j#)m x)- pJ♦/!J ” g—,/)UJ iaaa Cp!♦—U♦/)—.JxK/#m ”UJ*—)xj uxJJxP ♦’>Um 2U'jUè’>’♦#? 2U*UxJ,/UJ x* N!V­U,♦ $”K WllPWhI ’) YKJU688( 8L ,áK) :'K':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- m U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’)P ,—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U Mj*’).UJm 5U’-’ cRRI ®A(x.U* —'8—(U) ’) 4"8.'­ p))á­'.K'-U x)- 4"8.'­ p))á­'.K'-U L8. I:U­oC O)K!Vj’*/U- *U)’—J ♦/U*’*m O)’>UJ*’♦# —' Yx**x,/!*U♦♦*P“—šUjj M(UJ*—)m 2—VUJ♦ Yy 2x,/Uj A BJU♦❖y x)- “’)-x “ N/xš cRRT O.:':J1 H'0J8 1.K"0:7 w:-)UJ8'-­o 4/’,x.—? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4/’,x.— ”JU** M*♦UJVUJ.m fJ’*♦’) cRRW W-­6:KJ KJU d:­-&áK) pU-J':':-­f 28J­'.á7':J1 28zzáJ: ':-­S 28J­'.á7':J1 4-);-­o ”/’jx-UjK/’x? FU(KjU O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** BUJJUjjm 0U'' cRRT ®OJVx) wJx''’♦’? 4J’(Um 4—)♦J—jm x)- 2U*’*♦x),U $V8á'0 48 7:-'* iW?WlPRl B’)Um Y’,/UjjUy “—’* 8U’*y N!*x) 8U*UU)y x)- “——)(!) 8—). iaaa CB—J 8/—(v L!xj’♦x♦’>U 2U*UxJ,/m 2UKJU*U)♦x♦’—)*m x)- N—,’xj 2U*K—)*’V’j’♦’U* $ ”K caWPclc ’) YKJU688( 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- m U-’♦U- V# u—JP (x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U B’)jx#m 8’jj’x(m x)- 0x(U* M 4—>UJ-’jj cRRR ®F/U NUxJ,/ wx(U? HJ.x)’❖xP ♦’—)xj 4—)'j’,♦* x)- ♦/U O*U —' 5Ux-/!)♦UJ* $ 487:8)81:7K) ,áK.'-.)* da? ccPla BjU’♦x*m 0—x) cRRI ®NK’))’). FxjU* 'J—( ♦/U 8—Jj- 8’-U 8UV? L!xj’♦x♦’>U 2UP *UxJ,/ ’) x) MjU,♦J—)’, M)>’J—)(U)♦ $ ,áK):'K':;- Y-K)'0 y-­-K.70 I? iIlPiRl B—)♦x)xm p)-JUxm x)- 0x(U* 5 BJU# cRRI CA)♦UJ>’Uš’).? F/U pJ♦ —' N,’U),U $ ”K dWPWI ’) 28))-7':J1 KJU pJ'-.".-':J1 ,áK):'K':;- PK'-.:K)­S U-’♦U- V# u—JP (x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 2MBM2Mu4MN idc BJx)❖—*’m 2—VUJ♦— cRRax ®N♦Jx♦U.’U* '—J ♦/U ”JU>U)♦’—)m :U♦U,♦’—)m x)- 4—JJU,P ♦’—) —' YUx*!JU(U)♦ MJJ—J ’) :x♦x 4—jjU,♦U- 'J—( FUè♦!xj N—!J,U* $487:8 )81:7K) P-'08U­ KJU y-­-K.70 cI?ddiPdWi BJx)❖—*’m 2—VUJ♦— cRRaV ®4—(K!♦UJPp**’*♦U- 4—-’). —' FUè♦!xj :x♦x? p) pKKj’,x♦’—) ♦— NU(x)♦’, wJx((xJ* $ 487:8)81:7K) P-'08U­ KJU y-­-K.70 cR?iiTPiTW BJx)❖—*’m 2—VUJ♦— cRRI ®uxJJx♦’>U p)xj#*’*«HJ 8/# sx)- 5—šS N—,’—j—.’*♦* N/—!j- gU A)♦UJU*♦U- ’) uxJJx♦’>U $xJJáK) y-;:-j 8L 487:8)81* id?TcWPTTd BJUU-(x)m 4xJ—j cRRW ®NU♦♦’). N♦x#Px♦P5—(U N♦x)-xJ-*? p) M♦/)—.JxK/’, N♦!-# —' ♦/U N—!♦/jx)- Y—♦/UJ* p**—,’x♦’—) $ O)K!Vj’*/U- Y p ♦/U*’*m O)’>UJ*’♦# —' Y’**—!J’Pfx)*x* 4’♦# BJU’JUm ”x!j— cRWa b-UK181* 8L '0- k"".-­­-Uo uUš b—Jq? NUxV!J# ”JU** BJ’U-(x)m :UVJxm x)- Y’,/xUj 5U,/♦UJ cRII ®F/U 4—)♦J’V!♦’—) —' 2x♦’—)xj 4/—’,U F/U—J# ♦— Yx,J—*—,’—j—.’,xj 2U*UxJ,/ $ 487:8)81:7K) M0-8.* h? iacPicI wx(*—)m 0—*/!x cRRI w.-K(­ MK)( dK7(f MK6)8:U MK)( 408j­ KJU 4-&áK) v 8J 78JL8.z:'*o 4/’,x.—? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4/’,x.— ”JU** wx)*m 5UJVUJ♦ 0 cRhi M0- ’.6KJ “:))K1-.­f D.8á" KJU 2)K­­ :J '0- W:L- 8L p'K):KJ xz-.:7KJ­o uUš b—Jq? BJUU ”JU** wx)*m 5UJVUJ♦ 0 cRRR ®”xJ♦’,’Kx)♦ HV*UJ>x♦’—) ’) ♦/U MJx —'eM♦/)—.JxK/# e$ ?8á.JK) 8L 28J'-z"8.K.* H'0J81.K"0* iI?TdaPTdI wx)❖m YxJ*/xjj iaaa C2U*—!J,U* x)- 2U*—!J,U'!j)U**? N♦Jx♦U.’, 4xKx,’♦# ’) ♦/U O)’—)’❖x♦’—) —' 4xj’'—J)’x p.J’,!j♦!JUm cRTRPcRhh $ xz-.:7KJ ?8á.JK) 8L 487:8)81* caT?caalPcahi wxJVUJm YxJ­—J’U cRRT “:7- “-.­Kf d:­-&áK):'* KJU '0- H.8':7:­z 8L H;-.*UK* W:L-o uUš b—Jq? N’(—) tN,/!*♦UJ wx>U)♦xm 0—/) cRRc ®4xJJ#’). H) $487:K) b8):7* icslS?hIPWa wUUm 0x(U* cRRc ®p “’).!’*♦’, pKKJ—x,/ ♦— uxJJx♦’>U $?8á.JK) 8L vK..K':;- KJU W:L- Y:­'8.* c?cTPlR wUUJ♦❖m 4j’''—J- cRWl M0- pJ'-.".-'K':8J 8L 2á)'á.-­o uUš b—Jq? gx*’, g——q* wUJ.U)m fU))U♦/ 0 cRRc M0- 4K'á.K'-U 4-)Lf 3:)-zzK­ 8L pU-J':'* :J 28J'-z"8 .K.* W:L-o gx*’, g——q* wUJ.U)m YxJ# Ym x)- fU))U♦/ 0 wUJ.U) iaaa ®L!xj’♦x♦’>U A);!’J#? FU)*’—)* x)- FJx)*'—J(x♦’—)* $”K caiTPcadh ’) YKJU688( 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- m U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U w’V*—)PwJx/x(m 0 f cRRd ®ÍN♦!''U- A' A f)—š1í? 2U'jU,♦’—)* —) ”—*♦P(—-UJ) BU(’)’*♦ N—,’xj 2U*UxJ,/ $ D-JU-. b)K7- t0 2á)'á.-f x ?8á.JK) 8L w-z:J:­' D-81.K"0* c?iaTPiid wjx**’Um 5U)J# cRRc ®N♦!-#’). Yx♦UJ’xj 4!j♦!JU F—-x# $”K iTlPihh ’) W:;:J1 :J K PK'-.:K) O8.)Uf 2KJKU:KJ KJU xz-.:7KJ x"".8K70-­ '8 PK'-.:K) 2á) 'á.-S U-’♦U- V# wUJxj- ”—,’!* N♦ 0—/)í*m uUš'—!)-jx)-? A)*♦’♦!♦U —' N—,’xj x)- M,—)—(’, 2U*UxJ,/ idi 2MBM2Mu4MN wjx**)UJm gxJJ#m x)- 2—*x))x 5UJ♦❖ sU-* S cRRR ,áK):'K':;- 487:8)81* K­ H;-.* UK* W:L-o F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U w—''(x)m MJ>’). cRWh D-JU-. xU;-.':­-z-J'­o “—)-—)? Yx,(’jjx) w—J-—)m “’)-x cRII Y-.8-­ 8L M0-:. k jJ W:;-­f M0- b8):':7­ KJU Y:­'8.* 8L wKz :)* “:8)-J7-o uUš b—Jq? ”U).!’) g——q* w—♦♦j’UVm pj(xm x)- ”/’j’K wJx/x( cRRl bK.K))-) O8.)U­f x J xJ'0.8"8)81:­' KJU K O.:'-. HJ78áJ'-. xL.:7Ko uUš b—Jq? 4J—š)m cRRl wJUU)š——-m :x>#-- 0y8’jj’x( B——♦U 8/#♦Uy x)- AJx 5xJqx># cRRl ®”xJ♦’,’KxP ♦—J# p,♦’—) 2U*UxJ,/ x* x ”J—,U** x)- x* x w—xj $ Y áz KJ y-)K':8J­ dh?cWRPcRl wJUUJm 4—j’) cRRc Cp4!j♦!JU —' ”—j’♦’,* $487:K) b8):7* icslS?TlPTW wJ—.UJm “’*xy ”x(Ujx Yx#VUJJ#y x)- 0x)U N♦JxqUJ cRRR ®8/x♦ 8U :’-)í♦ “UxJ) gU,x!*U —' 8/— 8—!j- u—♦ Fxjq ♦— O* $ ,áK):'K':;- Y-K)'0 y-­-K.70 R?IiRPIlh w!VJ’!(m 0xVUJ Bm x)- 0x(U* p 5—j*♦U’) cRRW M0- v-j WKJ1áK1- 8L ,áK):'K ':;- P-'08Uo uUš b—Jq? Hè'—J- O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** w!VJ’!(m 0xVUJ Bm x)- 0x(U* p 5—j*♦U’) cRRI CuxJJx♦’>U ”Jx,♦’,U x)- ♦/U 4—P /UJU),U —' ”UJ*—)xj N♦—J’U* $487:8)81:7K) ,áK.'-.)* lR?chlPcIW 5xJ-’).m Nx)-Jx cRIh M0- 47:-J7- ,á-­':8J :J w-z:J:­zo A♦/x,xm ub? 4—J)Ujj O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** 5xJ-’).m Nx)-Jx cRIW CA)♦J—-!,♦’—)? A*F/UJU x BU(’)’*♦ YU♦/—-v$”K cPcd ’) w-z:J:­z 42 P-'08U8)81*S U-’♦U- V# Nx)-Jx 5xJ-’). gj——(’).♦—)? A)-’x)x O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** 5xJ♦*—,qm ux),# cRIW ®F/U BU(’)’*♦ N♦x)-K—’)♦? :U>Uj—K’). ♦/U wJ—!)- '—J x NKU,’'’,xjj# BU(’)’*♦ 5’*♦—J’,xj Yx♦UJ’xj’*( $ ”K cTWPcIa ’) w-z:J:­z 42 P-'08U8)81*S U-’♦U- V# Nx)-Jx 5xJ-’). gj——(’).♦—)? A)-’x)x O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** 5x#*m N/xJ—) cRRh M0- 2á)'á.K) 28J'.KU:7':8J­ 8L P8'0-.088Uo uUš 5x>U)m 4F? bxjU O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** 5—--UJm Ax) cRIR C”—*♦P(—-UJ)’*(m ”—*♦P*♦J!,♦!Jxj’*( x)- ”—*♦PKJ—,U**!xj pJP ,/xU—j—.# $”K hdPWI ’) M0- P-KJ:J1­ 8L M0:J1­f PK'-.:K) 2á)'á.- KJU 4*z 68):7 H&".-­­:8JS U-’♦U- V# Ax) 5—--UJ “—)-—)? O)š’) 5#(x) 5—--UJm Ax) cRRI CF/U A)♦UJKJU♦x♦’—) —' :—,!(U)♦* x)- Yx♦UJ’xj 4!j♦!JU $ ”K ccaPciR ’) 28))-7':J1 KJU pJ'-.".-':J1 ,áK):'K':;- PK'-.:K)­S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 5—j*♦U’)m 0x(U* pm x)- 0xVUJ B w!VJ’!( cRRT M0- x7':;- pJ'-.;:-jo F/—!*x)Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 5—)-x.)U!PN—♦Uj—m ”’UJJU♦♦U cRRh ®A((’.Jx)♦ 8—(U) x)- ”x’- :—(U*♦’, 8—Jq? 2U*UxJ,/m F/U—J#m x)- p,♦’>’*( $”K caTPcii ’) w-z:J:­z KJU 487:K) 20KJ1-f d.:U1:J1 M0-8.* KJU b.K7':7-S U-’♦U- V# 5U’-’ w—♦♦'J’U- OJVx)x? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' Ajj’)—’* ”JU** 5!VUJ(x)m p Y’,/xUjm x)- Yx♦♦/Uš g Y’jU* cRRI ®:x♦x Yx)x.U(U)♦ x)p)xj#*’* YU♦/—-* $ ”K cWRPica ’) 28))-7':J1 KJU pJ'-.".-':J1 ,áK):'K':;PK'-.:K6S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 2MBM2Mu4MN idl 5!(K/JU#*m “x!- cRWa M-K.88z M.KU-f pz"-.­8JK) 4-& :J bá6):7 b)K7-­o 4/’P ,x.—? pj-’)U A.)x,’—m M(’j# u—UjjU iaaa ®p’)í♦ A x B’j’K’)— s8—(x)Svíp) p)xj#*’* —' p!P ♦/—J*/’Krp!♦/—J’♦# F/J—!./ ♦/U 4—)*♦J!,♦’—) —'ÍB’j’K’)xí—) ♦/U uU♦ C 48 7:8)81:7K) ,áK.'-.)* dc?TTcPTWi 0x)U*’,qm 7xjUJ’U cRRI C4'.-'70:J1P H&-.7:­-­ L8. ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70-.­o F/—!P *x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 0x)’*m AJ>’). cRIi D.8á"'0:J(f b­*708)81:7K) 4'áU:-­ 8L b8):7* 3-7:­:8J­ KJU w:K­ 78-­o g—*♦—)? 5—!./♦—) Y’''j’) 0x#xJx♦)Um F—V# MK*♦U’)m x)- pV’.x’j 0 N♦UšxJ♦ cRRc CL!x)♦’♦x♦’>U x)- L!xj’P ♦x♦’>U YU♦/—-* ’) ♦/U N—,’xj N,’U),U*? 4!JJU)♦ BU(’)’*♦ A**!U* x)- ”Jx,♦’,xj N♦Jx♦U.’U* $”K ITPcah ’) d-*8JU P-'08U8)81*f w-z:J:­' 4708)K.­0:" K­ W:;-U y-­-K.70m U-’♦U- V# YxJ# YxJ.xJU♦ B—)—š x)- 0!-’♦/ p 4——q gj——(’).P ♦—)? A)-’x)x O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** fxJKm :x>’- p cRRR CN—,’xj N,’U),Um ”J—.JU**m x)- ♦/U M♦/)—.JxK/UJí* 4Jx'♦ $ ?8á.JK) 8L 28J'-z"8.K.* H'0J81.K"0* iI?TRWPhaR fx♦❖m 0x,q cRRh ®Bx(’j’U* x)- B!))# Y’JJ—J*? p N♦!-# —' ♦/U N—,’xj 4—)*♦J!,P ♦’—) x)- ”UJ*—)xj M(V—-’(U)♦ —' 5!(—J $xz-.:7KJ ?8á.JK) 8L 487:8)81* cac?ccRdPcilW fU)-xjjm “—J’ iaaa ®ÍH5 uHA AíY p uM2:” 5U.U(—)’, Yx*,!j’)’♦# —) x) H)j’)U B—J!( $D-JU-. 42 487:-'* cd?iThPiWd fU—!./m u—Ujy M((x) 4xJ(—)xy x)- “’)-x wJx)-’)U♦♦’ cRRT ®FxjU* 'J—( ♦/U NxJ’PNxJ’? A) NUxJ,/ —' g’.'——♦ $28J;-.1-J7- iIsdS?TPch f’),/Uj—Um 0—U “m x)- ”U♦UJ “ Y,“xJU) cRRI C2U♦/’)q’). 4J’♦’,xj F/U—J# x)L!xj’♦x♦’>U 2U*UxJ,/ $ ”K ihaPiRR ’) M0- WKJU­7K"- 8L ,áK):'K':;- y­-K.70f M0-8.:-­ KJU p­­á-­S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’)P ,—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U fjU’)(x)m N/UJJ#j cRRc ®B’Uj-P8—JqUJ*íBUUj’).*? 8/x♦ 8U BUUjm 8/— 8U pJUm 5—š8U p)xj#❖U $”K cIdPcRT ’) H&"-.:-J7:J1 w:-)Uj8.(f x J pJ­:U- “:-j 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70o uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U f—U*♦UJm N♦UK/U) cRRd ®4—KK’).m 2!))’).m x)- ”xJxK/UJ)xj’x “xš*? 4—)♦UèP ♦!xj 7xJ’xVjU* x)- uUU-jU 2’*q gU/x>’—J p(—). A)­U,♦’—) :J!. O*UJ* ’) :U)>UJ $Y áz KJ k.1KJ:\K':8J Tl?iIWPiRT f—)-—m :—J’))U f cRRa 2.KL':J1 4-);-­f b8j-.S D-JU-.S KJU 3:­78á.­-­ 8L pU-J ':'* :J K ?K"KJ-­- O8.(")K7-o 4/’,x.—? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4/’,x.— ”JU** f—♦x(Jx­!m uxj’)’ ” cRRR CF/U g’J♦/ —' 8UV N’♦U :U*’.) Nq’jj*? Yxq’). ♦/U ”JU*U)♦ 5’*♦—J# $xz-.:7KJ d-0K;:8.K) 47:-J':­' dl?dhdPdWT fJ’U.UJm N!*x) cRIl M0- P:..8. 3KJ7-f pU-J':'* :J K O8z-Jt­ 28zzáJ:'*o ”/’jx-UjK/’x? FU(KjU O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** fJ’U.UJm N!*x) cRRc 487:K) 47:-J7- KJU '0- 4-)Lf b-.­8JK) H­­K*­ 8J KJ x .' w8.zo uUš gJ!)*š’,qm u0? 2!♦.UJ* O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** 0—/)*—)m F’(—♦/# ”y Y’,/xUj BU)-J’,/y 4/’♦Jx N/xj’.Jx(y p)♦/—)# wxJ,#y x)Nx(!Uj w’jjU*K’U iaaa ®p) M>xj!x♦’—) —' ♦/U M''U,♦* —' A)♦UJ>’UšUJ 4/xJP x,♦UJ’*♦’,* ’) x) 2:: FUjUK/—)U N!J>U# —' :J!. O*U $?8á.JK) 8L 3.á1 p­­á-­ la?WWPcai idd 2MBM2Mu4MN “xV—>m 8’jj’x( cRWI ®4J—**’). ♦/U w!j' gU♦šUU) N—,’—j—.# x)- “’).!’*♦’,* $ xz-.:7KJ 487:8)81:­' cl?RlPcal “x(—♦♦m p))U cRRT d:.U 6* d:.Uf 48z- pJ­'.á7':8J­ 8J O.:':J1 KJU W:L-o uUš b—Jq? p),/—J “xJUx!m p))U♦♦Um x)- 0U''JU# N,/!j♦❖ sU-* S cRRh ?8á.J-*­ M0.8á10 H'0J81.K"0*f y-K):­':7 x778áJ'­ 8L w:-)Uj8.(o g—!j-UJm 4H? 8U*♦>’Uš ”JU** “x2—**xm 2xjK/y 4/xJjU* 0xJU♦y Yxjx♦’ wx-.’jy x)- w 2—VUJ♦ 8#)) iaaa ®F/U 4/x).’). 4!j♦!JU —' Bx♦/UJ/——- ’) 4—(’,PN♦J’K Bx(’j’U*? p N’èP:U,x-U p)xj#*’* $?8á.JK) 8L PK..:K1- KJU '0- wKz:)* hi?lWTPlII “x*jU♦♦m gxJVxJxm x)- gxJJ’U F/—J)U cRRW w-z:J:­' 487:8)81*f W:L- Y:­'8.:-­ 8L K P8;-z-J'o uUš gJ!)*š’,qm u0? 2!♦.UJ* O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** “UVjx),m “x!Jx’)U iaaa b.-''* :J báJ(f D:.)­t D-JU-. y-­:­'KJ7- :J K d8*­t 4á6 7á)'á.-o uUš gJ!)*š’,qm u0? 2!♦.UJ* O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** “U4—(K♦Um YxJ.xJU♦ :m x)- 0Ux) 0 N,/U)*!j cRRRx 3-­:1J:J1 KJU 28JUá7':J1 H'0J81.K"0:7 y-­-K.70o 8xj)!♦ 4JUUqm 4p? pj♦xY’Jx ”JU** “U4—(K♦Um YxJ.xJU♦ :m x)- 0Ux) 0 N,/U)*!j cRRRV xJK)*\:J1 KJU pJ'-.".-':J1 H'0J81.K"0:7 3K'Ko 8xj)!♦ 4JUUqm 4p? pj♦xY’Jx ”JU** “UUm 2x#(—)- Y iaaa ’J86'.á­:;- P-'08U­ :J 487:K) y-­-K.70o g!,q’)./x(m M).jx)-? HKU) O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** “U(KUJ♦m “—Jx gUè cRRd ®p uxJJx♦’>U p)xj#*’* —'pV!*U $?8á.JK) 8L 28J'-z"8 .K.* H'0J81.K"0* ii?dccPddc “UJ)UJm 0U))’'UJ Mm x)- “’)-x fxj—' cRRR ®F/U p)’(xj FUè♦? YU**x.U x)YUx)’). ’) FUjU>’*’—) p->UJ♦’*U(U)♦* $ M0- 487:8)81:7K) ,áK.'-.)* da? ThTPTIh “’UV—šm Mjj’—♦ cRhW MK))*/­ 28z-.f x 4'áU* 8L v-1.8 4'.--'78z-. P-Jo g—*♦—)? “’♦♦jUm gJ—š) “’UV—šm Mjj’—♦ cRRl M-)) M0-z O08 p xz f M0- W:;-­ 8L Y8z-)-­­ O8z-Jo uUš b—Jq? ”U).!’) g——q* “’),—j)m b>—))x Nm x)- u—J(x) f :U)❖’) iaaa ®F/U NU>U)♦/ Y—(U)♦? H!♦ —' ♦/U ”x*♦ $”K cadWPcahT ’) YKJU688( 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- m U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U “’),—j)m b>—))x Nm x)- M.—) w!Vx cRIT vK'á.K):­':7 pJqá:.*o gU>UJj# 5’jj*m 4p? Nx.U “’),—j)m b>—))x Nm x)- M.—) w!Vx iaaa C”xJx-’.(x♦’, 4—)♦J—>UJ*’U*m 4—)♦JxP -’,♦’—)*m x)- M(UJ.’). 4—)'j!U),U* $”K chlPcII ’) YKJU688( 8L ,áK):'K ':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- m U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U “—'jx)-m 0—/)m x)- “#) 5 “—'jx)- cRId xJK)*\:J1 487:K) 4-'':J1­S i)- U- gUjP (—)♦m 4p? 8x-*š—J♦/ “—'jx)-m 0—/)m x)- “#) “—'jx)- cRRT xJK)*\:J1 487:K) 4-'':J1­S lJ- U- gUj(—)♦m 4p? 8x-*š—J♦/ “—'jx)-m “#) cRIT x O8.)U 8L 4'.KJ1-.­f k.U-. KJU x7':8J :J ’.6KJ bá6):7 4"K7-o ”J—*KU,♦ 5U’./♦*m A“? 8x>Ujx)- ”JU** 2MBM2Mu4MN idT “#qU*m Y gJ’)♦—) cRRW ®p,♦’>’*♦ ”xJ♦’,’Kx♦—J# 2U*UxJ,/ p(—). ♦/U Yx#x —' w!x♦U(xjx? 4—)*♦J!,♦’). YUx)’).* 'J—( N’♦!x♦U- “x).!x.U $?8á.JK) 8L 48 7:K) p­­á-­ Tl?WiTPWdW Yx,-—)xj-m fU’♦/m x)- 4—j’) F’K♦—) cRRl ®O*’). :—,!(U)♦* $”K cIWPiaa ’) y-­-K.70:J1 487:K) W:L-S U-’♦U- V# u’.Uj w’jVUJ♦ “—)-—)? Nx.U Yx,:—!.xjjm 4—j’)m x)- BJx),U* gx!( cRRW ®F/U :U>’jí*p->—,x♦U? p N♦Jx♦U.# ♦— p>—’- wJ—!K♦/’)q x)- N♦’(!jx♦U :’*,!**’—) ’) B—,!* wJ—!K* $, áK):'K ':;- Y-K)'0 y-­-K.70 W?TliPTda Yx-J’❖m M*♦/UJ A cRRI ®O*’). B—,!* wJ—!K* š’♦/ “—šUJ N—,’—U,—)—(’, N♦x♦!* “x♦’)x 8—(U) $,áK):'K':;- pJqá:.* d?ccdPciR Yx-J’❖m M*♦/UJ iaaa CB—,!* wJ—!K* ’) BU(’)’*♦ 2U*UxJ,/ $ ”K IlTPITa ’) YKJU688( 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- m U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U Yx))’).m ”U♦UJ fm x)- gU♦*# 4!jj!(PNšx) cRRI ®uxJJx♦’>Um 4—)♦U)♦m x)NU(’—♦’, p)xj#*’* $ ”K idhPiWl ’) 28))-7':J1 KJU pJ'-.".-':J1 ,áK):'K':;PK'-.:K)­S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U YxJ,U)q—m Yx!JUU) Hm x)- “’)-x Nx(—*♦ cRRR ®“’>’). š’♦/ 5A7rpA:N?F/U 7—’,U* —' BcA7P”—*’♦’>U Y—♦/UJ* $487:K) O8.( dd?lhPdT YxJ,!*m wU—J.U cRRI ®8/x♦ 4—(U* s0!*♦S p'♦UJ Í”—*♦v F/U 4x*U —' M♦/)—.JxP K/# $”K lIl«dah ’) M0- WKJU­7K"- 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70f M0-8.:-­ KJU p­á-­S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U Yx*!-xm fx❖!#— cRRI ®4—,qJ—x,/U* x)- 4—K*? 8—(U) N♦J!..j’). ’) x) OJVx) NU,♦’—) I 5—!*’). 4—(KjUè $ O)K!Vj’*/U- Y p ♦/U*’*m O)’>UJ*’♦# —' Y’**—!J’Pfx)*x* 4’♦# Y,p-x(*m :x) ” cRRl M0- 4'8.:-­ O- W:;- d*f b-.­8JK) P *'0­ KJU '0- P K(:J1 8L '0- 4-)L uUš b—Jq? w!’j'—J- ”JU** Y,uU’jm “xJJ# g cRRT ®F/U N—'♦ pJ♦* —' HJ.x)’❖’). $487:K) b8):7* ih?chPii Y,u’,—jjm ”x!jU cRRR ®A**!U* ’) FUx,/’). ”xJ♦’,’Kx♦—J# p,♦’—) 2U*UxJ,/ $?8á. JK) 8L 487:K) O8.( HUá7K':8J lT?TcPhi Y’jU*m Yx♦♦/Uš gm x)- p Y’,/xUj 5!VUJ(x) cRRd ,áK):'K':;- 3K'K xJK)*­:­f x J H&"KJU-U 48á.7-688(o F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U Y’j.Jx(m N♦x)jU# cRWd k6-U:-J7- '8 xá'08.:'*o uUš b—Jq? 5xJKUJ t2—š Y’jjUJm uU’j cRRT k á' 8L '0- bK­'f D K* KJU W-­6:KJ Y:­'8.* L.8z eQmu '8 '0b.-­-J'o uUš b—Jq? 7’)♦x.U g——q* Y’*/jUJm Mjj’—♦ w cRRc C2UKJU*U)♦’). :’*,—!J*U? F/U 2/U♦—J’, —'FJx)*,J’K♦’—) $ ?8á.JK) 8L vK..K':;- KJU W:L- Y:­'8.* c?iTTPiIa Y’♦,/Ujjm 2’,/xJ- wm 0J cRRc ®NU,JU,# x)- :’*,j—*!JU ’) B’Uj-š—Jq $ ”K RWPcaI ’) H&"-.:-J7:J1 w:-)Uj8.(f x J pJ­:U- “:-j 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70o uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U Y’♦,/Ujjm 2’,/xJ- w cRRl 4-7.-7* KJU w:-)Uj8.(o uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U Y—U)m ”/#jj’* cRIR O8.(:J1 bK.-J'­f M.KJ­L8.zK':8J­ :J D-JU-. y8)-­ KJU bá6 ):7 b8):7:-­ :J 4j-U-Jo Yx-’*—)? O)’>UJ*’♦# —'8’*,—)*’) ”JU** idh 2MBM2Mu4MN Y—)♦Ujjm BJx),U* cRRR ®B—,!* wJ—!K A)♦UJ>’Uš*? p uUš BU(’)’*♦ YU♦/—- $ v O 4 x ?8á.JK) cc?ddPWc Y—)♦’)’m F/UJU*x cRRh ®wU)-UJ x)- M(—♦’—) ’) ♦/U p->—,x,# '—J gJUx*♦ 4x)P ,UJ A)'—J(U- 4—)*U)♦ “U.’*jx♦’—) $D-JU-. 487:-'* ca?RPil Y—J.x)m :x>’- “ cRII w87á­ D.8á"­ K­ ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70o uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U Y—J.x)m :x>’- “ cRRT C8/#F/’).* sN—(U♦’(U*S w—8J—). ’) B—,!* wJ—!K* $ ,áK):'K':;- Y-K)'0 y-­-K.70 T?TchPTid Y—J.x)m :x>’- “ cRRh ®B—,!* wJ—!K* $ x JJáK) y-;:-j 8L 487:8)81* ii? ciRPcTl Y—J*Um 0x)’,U Y cRRI ®F/U 4—)♦Jx,♦U- 2Ujx♦’—)*/’K? M)*!J’). ”J—♦U,♦’—) —' p)—)#(’♦# x)- 4—)'’-U)♦’xj’♦# $,áK):'K':;- Y-K)'0 y-­-K.70 I?lacPlad Y—J*Um 0x)’,U Y cRRI ®:U*’.)’). B!)-U- L!xj’♦x♦’>U 2U*UxJ,/ $”K ThPIT ’) 4'.K'-1:-­ 8L ,áK):'K':;- pJqá:.*S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)-b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U uxKjU*m ux),# p m š’♦/ M(’j# 4jxJq cRRh ®BU(’)’*♦ ”xJ♦’,’Kx♦—J# 2U*UxJ,/ x)- M(K—šUJ(U)♦? w—’). ”!Vj’, x* N!J>’>—J* —' 4/’j-/——- NUè!xj pV!*U $ ”K chaPcIl ’) w-z:J:­z KJU 487:K) 20KJ1-f d.:U1:J1 M0-8.* KJU b.K7':7-S U-’♦U- V# 5U’-’ w—♦♦'J’U- OJVx)x? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' Ajj’)—’* ”JU** uU!(x)m 8 “xšJU),U cRRd 487:K) y-­-K.70 P-'08U­S i)- U- g—*♦—)? pjj#) t gx,—) uU!♦U)*m 0x(U* 0m x)- “x!Jx 2!V’)*—) cRRW y-­-K.70 M-70J:qá-­ L8. '0- Y-K)'0 47:-J7-­S i)- U- g—*♦—)? pjj#) tgx,—) u’Uj*U)m 0—#,U Y,4xJj cRRa w-z:J:­' y-­-K.70 P-'08U­f H&-z")K.* y-KU:J1­ :J '0- 487:K) 47:-J7-­o g—!j-UJm 4H? 8U*♦>’Uš ”JU** HxqjU#m p)) cRIc ®A)♦UJ>’Uš’).8—(U)? p 4—)♦Jx-’,♦’—) ’) FUJ(* $”K laPhc ’) 38:J1 w-z:J:­' y-­-K.70S U-’♦U- V# 5UjU) 2—VUJ♦* “—)-—)? 2—!♦jU-.U t fU.x) ”x!j ”xJqm 2—VUJ♦ M k J 487:K) 28J'.8) KJU 28))-7':;- d-0K;:8.o 4/’,x.—? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4/’,x.— ”JU**m cRhW ”x♦♦—)m Y’,/xUj L!’)) cRRa ,áK):'K':;- H;K)áK':8J KJU y-­-K.70 P-'08U­S i)U- uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U ”j!((UJm fU) cRRT M-)):J1 4-&áK) 4'8.:-­o “—)-—)? 2—!♦jU-.U ”j!((UJm fU) cRRR ®F/U ÍM♦/)—.JxK/’, N—,’U♦#í x♦ 4U)♦!J#í* M)- $r—♦♦Jxxr 8L 28J'-z"8.K.* H'0J81.K"0* iI?hdcPhdR ”—*x>x,m M(’j 0m x)- 2x#(—)- w 4xJU# cRRW b.81.Kz H;K)áK':8Jf P-'08U­ KJU 2K­- 4'áU:-­S T♦/ U- OKKUJ Nx--jU 2’>UJm u0? ”JU)♦’,U 5xjj ”JU**UJm N♦x)jU#m x)- “’)-x N♦’)*—) cRRI ®:x♦x 4—jjU,♦’—) Y—-U x)- N—,’xj :UP *’JxV’j’♦# g’x* ’) NUj'P2UK—J♦U- 2Uj’.’—!* p♦♦U)-x),U $xz-.:7KJ 487:8)81:7K) y-;:-j hl?clWPcdT ”!),/m Yx!J’,U cRRI ®”—j’♦’,* x)- M♦/’,* ’) L!xj’♦x♦’>U 2U*UxJ,/ $ ”K cThPcId ’) M0- WKJU­7K"- 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 2MBM2Mu4MN idW 2x.’)m 4/xJjU* 4 cRRd 28J­'.á7':J1 487:K) y-­-K.70o F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? ”’)U B—J.U ”JU** 2x♦/­Um 8’jj’x( cRRi ®5—š Y!,/ pj,—/—j :— 8U :J’)qv A♦í* x L!U*♦’—) N— ♦— NKUxq $DK.6K1- dscS?cIPcR 2x♦/­Um 8’jj’x( cRRl ®“U** Bx♦v pšm gxj—)U# $DK.6K1- TsdS?iiPil 2x♦/­Um 8’jj’x(m x)- 4!jjU) Y!JK/# cRRi ®wxJVx.U :U(—.JxK/’,* $xz-.:7KJ 3-z81.K"0:7­ cd?TaPTT 2U’)/xJ❖m N/!jx(’♦ cRRi w-z:J:­' P-'08U­ :J 487:K) y-­-K.70o uUš b—Jq? HèP '—J- O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** 2’,/xJ-*m F/—(x* 0m x)- “#) 2’,/xJ-* cRRI ®O*’). 4—(K!♦UJ* ’) L!xj’♦x♦’>U 2U*UxJ,/ $”K iccPidT ’) 28))-7':J1 KJU pJ'-.".-':J1 ,áK):'K':;- PK'-.:K)­S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 2’,/xJ-*—)m 0x(U* F cRRc CMèKUJ’U),’). 2U*UxJ,/ —) uUš 2Uj’.’—)* x)- 4!j♦*? ”Jx,♦’,xj x)- M♦/’,xj 4—)*’-UJx♦’—)* $”K hiPWc ’) H&"-.:-J7:J1 w:-)U j8.(f x J pJ­:U- “:-j 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70S U-’♦U- V# 8’jj’x( g N/x''’J x)- 2—VUJ♦ p N♦UVV’)* uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U 2’,/xJ-*—)m “x!JUj cRRi CF/U 4—)*U;!U),U* —' ”—U♦’, 2UKJU*U)♦x♦’—)? 8J’♦’). ♦/U H♦/UJm 2UšJ’♦’). ♦/U NUj' $”K ciTPcda ’) pJ;-­':1K':J1 4á6N-7':;:'*f y­-K.70 8J W:;-U H&"-.:-J7-S U-’♦U- V# 4 Mjj’* x)- Y w Bjx/UJ♦# uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U 2’,/xJ-*—)m “x!JUj iaaa ®8J’♦’).? p YU♦/—- —' A);!’J# $ ”K RilPRdI ’) YKJU688( 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- m U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 2’U**(x)m 4x♦/UJ’)U f—/jUJ cRRl vK..K':;- xJK)*­:­o F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 2—)x’m 4xJ—j 2 cRRi ®F/U 2U'jUè’>U NUj' F/J—!./ uxJJx♦’>U? p u’./♦ ’) ♦/U “’'U —' x) MJ—♦’, :x),UJr2U*UxJ,/UJ $”K caiPcid —' pJ;-­':1K':J1 4á6N-7':; :'*f y-­-K.70 8J W:;-U H&"-.:-J7-S U-’♦U- V# 4 Mjj’* x)- Y w Bjx/UJ♦# uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U 2—*’Um p)♦/—)# cRRl Í®5Uí* x “’xJm Aí( p'Jx’-í?FJ!♦/ x)- “’U* ’) x uxJJx♦’>U p,,—!)♦ $487:8)81* iW?cddPcTi 2!♦♦UJm 0x*—)m x)- wJU. N(’♦/ cRRR ®”JU*U),U x)- pV*U),U ’) 7’J♦!xj M♦/)—.P JxK/# $”xKUJ KJU*U)♦U- x♦ ♦/U x))!xj (UU♦’). —' ♦/U p(UJ’,x) N—,’—j—.’,xj p**—,’x♦’—)m 4/’,x.— 2#x)m wUJ#m x)- F/—(x* 8U’*)UJ cRRh ®p)xj#❖’). 8—J-* ’) gJ’U' :U*,J’K♦’—)*? Bx♦/UJ* x)- Y—♦/UJ* :U*,J’VUF/U’J 4/’j-JU) $2á)'á.K) xJ'0.8"8)81* P -'0 8U­ IslS?clPch Nx,q*m 5xJ>U# cRWd ®H) ♦/U p)xj#*xV’j’♦# —' N♦—J’U* V# 4/’j-JU) $”K ichPili —' H'0J8z-'08U8)81*S U-’♦U- V# 2—# F!J)UJ gxj♦’(—JU? ”U).!’) M-!,x♦’—) Nx)-UJ*m 4j’)♦—) 2 cRIR ®HJ.x)’❖x♦’—)xj 4—)*♦Jx’)♦* —)Fx♦♦—— A(x.U*?p N—,’P —j—.’,xj p)xj#*’* —'pJ♦’*♦’, N♦#jU $”K iliPidc ’) M0- P-KJ:J1­ 8L M0:J1­f PK'-.:K) 2á)'á.- KJU 4*z68):7 H&".-­­:8JS U-’♦U- V# Ax) 5—--UJ “—)-—)? O)š’) 5#(x) idI 2MBM2Mu4MN N,xJ,Um 2’q cRRT ®N,/—jxJj# M♦/’,* x)- 4—!J♦J——( p)♦’,*? 8/UJU 2U*UxJ,/UJ* N♦x)- ’) ♦/U M#U* —' ♦/U “xš$xz-.:7KJ 487:8)81:­' RT? IWPccl N,/U.j—''m M((x)!Uj cRRW Í®uxJJx♦’>U p)xj#*’*í?F/’J♦# bUxJ* “x♦UJ $?8á.JK) 8L vK..K':;- KJU W:L- Y:­'8.* W?RWPcah N,/U.j—''m M((x)!Ujm x)- 5xJ>U# Nx,q* cRWd ®HKU)’). OK 4j—*’).* $ ”K illPihd ’) H'0J8z-'08U8)81*S U-’♦U- V# 2—# F!J)UJ Y’--jU*Uèm M)P .jx)-? ”U).!’) g——q* N,/U)*!jm N♦UK/U) “y 0Ux) 0 N,/U)*!jy x)- YxJ.xJU♦ : “U4—(K♦U cRRR H­-J':K) H'0J81.K"0:7 P-'08U­f k6­-.;K':8J­S pJ'-.;:-j­S KJU ,á-­':8JJK:.-­o 8xj)!♦ 4JUUqm 4p? pj♦xY’Jx ”JU** N,/’''(x)m 0—*UK/x cRRc e®B’./♦ ♦/U ”—šUJí?Fš— wJ—!K* Y—V’j’❖U '—J ”Ux,U $ ”K TIPWR ’) H'0J81.K"0* ’J68áJUf b8j-. KJU y-­:­'KJ7- :J '0- P 8U-z P '.8"8):­S V# Y’,/xUj g!Jxš—# U♦ xj gUJqUjU#? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4xj’'—J)’x ”JU** NU’-(x)m AJ>’). cRRI pJ'-.;:-j:J1 K­ ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70f x Dá:U- L8. y­-K.70-.­ :J HUá7K':8J KJU '0- 487:K) 47:-J7-­S i)- U- uUš b—Jq? FUx,/UJ* 4—jjU.U ”JU** N/x''’Jm 8’jj’x( cRRc ®Yx)x.’). x 4—)>’),’). NUj'P”JU*U)♦x♦’—)? N—(U ”UJP *—)xj 2U'jU,♦’—)* —) M)♦UJ’). ♦/U B’Uj- $ ”K WiPIc ’) H&"-.:-J7:J1 w:-)U j8.(f x J pJ­:U- “:-j 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70S U-’♦U- V# 8’jj’x( g N/x''’J x)- 2—VUJ♦ p N♦UVV’)* uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U N/x''’Jm 8’jj’x(m x)- 2—VUJ♦ N♦UVV’)* cRRc H&"-.:-J7:J1 w:-)Uj8.(f x J pJ­:U“:-j 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70o uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U N/!*♦UJm M>Uj#)U cRRI ®F/U u!JU(VUJ. 4—-U? 5’KK—,Jx♦’, M♦/’,* x)- 5!(x) 2’./♦* $WKJ7-' lTc?RWdPRWI N’xm p/P/’—q iaaa x 4'áU* 8L pJ'-.JK':8JK) 4'áU-J'­t v-'j8.(­o O)K!Vj’*/U”/ : -’**UJ♦x♦’—)m O)’>UJ*’♦# —' Y’**—!J’Pfx)*x* 4’♦# N(xjjm N♦UK/U) p cRRT ®p,♦’—)PHJ’U)♦U- 2U*UxJ,/? Y—-Uj* x)- YU♦/—-* $ ?8á.JK) 8L PK..:K1- KJU '0- wKz:)* TW?RdcPRTh N(’♦/m :—J—♦/# cRIW ®8—(U)í* ”UJ*KU,♦’>U x* x 2x-’,xj 4J’♦’;!U —' N—,’—jP —.#$ ”K IdPRh ’) w-z:J:­z KJU P-'08U8)81*S U-’♦U- V# Nx)-Jx 5xJ-’). gj——(’).♦—)? A)-’x)x O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** N(’♦/m “—!’* Y cRRI ®g’—.JxK/’,xj YU♦/—- $”K cIdPiid ’) 4'.K'-1:-­ 8L ,áK) :'K':;- pJqá:.*S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) tb>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U N(’♦/m ”/’j cRRR ®B——-FJ!,qí* ”xJ♦# 5x♦ $,áK):'K':;- pJqá:.* T?iddPihc N—,’—j—.# 8J’♦’). wJ—!K cRRc x Dá:U- '8 O.:':J1 487:8)81* bK"-.­S i)- UuUš b—Jq? N♦ YxJ♦’)í* ”JU** N—/JxV’m ux-UJ ®5’*♦—J’,’❖’). 2U>—j!♦’—)*? 4—)*♦’♦!♦’—)xj 2U>—j!♦’—)* ’) ♦/U H♦♦—(x) M(K’JUm AJx)m x)- 2!**’xm cRaTPcRaI $xz-.:7KJ ?8á.JK) 8L 487:8) 81* caa?clIlPcddW N♦x,U#m 0!-’♦/ cRRc d.K;- v-j wKz:):-­f 4'8.:-­ 8L 38z-­':7 ’"0-K;K) :J WK'Mj-J':-'0 2-J'á.* xz-.:7Ko uUš b—Jq? gx*’, g——q* N♦x,U#m 0!-’♦/ cRRh ®4x) F/UJU gU x BU(’)’*♦ M♦/)—.JxK/#v$ ”K IIPcac ’) w-z:J:­z KJU 487:K) 20KJ1-f d.:U1:J1 M0-8.* KJU b.K7':7-S U-’♦U- V# 5U’-’ w—♦♦'J’U- OJVx)x? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' Ajj’)—’* ”JU** 2MBM2Mu4MN idR N♦x,qm 4xJ—j cRWd x )) k á. I:Jf 4'.K'-1:-­ L8. 4á.;:;K) :J K d)K7( 28zzáJ:'*o uUš b—Jq? 5xJKUJ t2—š N♦x,qm 4xJ—j cRRh ®8J’♦’). M♦/)—.JxK/#? BU(’)’*♦ 4J’♦’,xj ”Jx,♦’,U $ ”K RhPcah ’) w-z:J:­' 3:)-zzK­ :J w:-)Uj8.(S U-’♦U- V# :’x)U “ 8—j' g—!jP -UJm 4H? 8U*♦>’Uš N♦U’)VUJ.m 2—))’U 0 cRRh ®p->—,x,# 2U*UxJ,/ '—J BU(’)’*♦ ”—j’,# HV­U,♦’>U*? MèKUJ’U),U* š’♦/ 4—(KxJxVjU 8—J♦/ $”K iiTPiTT ’) w-z:J:­z KJU 487:K) 20KJ1-f d.:U1:J1 M0-8.* KJU b.K7':7-S U-’♦U- V# 5U’-’ w—♦♦'J’U- OJVx)x? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' Ajj’)—’* ”JU** N♦—U,qUJm 2x)-# cRRR ®pJU p,x-U(’,* AJJUjU>x)♦v 2—jU* '—J N,/—jxJ* ’) ”xJ♦’,’P Kx♦—J# 2U*UxJ,/ $xz-.:7KJ d-0K;:8.K) 47:-J':­' di?IdaPIdd N♦Jx!**m p)*Uj(m x)- 0!j’U♦ 4—JV’) cRRa dK­:7­ 8L ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70f D.8áJU-U M0-8.* b.87-Uá.-­ KJU M-70J:qá-­o uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U N♦Jx!**m p)*Uj(m x)- 0!j’U♦ 4—JV’) cRRI ®wJ—!)-U- F/U—J# YU♦/—-—j—.#? p) H>UJ>’Uš $ ”K cTIPcIl ’) 4'.K'-1:-­ 8L ,áK):'K':;- pJqá:.*S U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U N♦J’).UJm MJ)U*♦F cRRh p,♦’—) y-­-K.70f x YKJU688( L8. b.K7':':8J-.­o F/—!*x)Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U FUšq*V!J#m 2’,/xJ-m x)- ”x♦J’,’x wx.)U cRRW Cp**!(U- x)- ”JU*!(U- A-U)♦’P ♦’U*? ”J—VjU(* —' NUj'P”JU*U)♦x♦’—) ’) B’Uj- 2U*UxJ,/ $487:8)81:7K) 4"-7'.áz cW?ciWPcTh F/U—K/x)—m 0x)U♦m x)- fxJU) 4!J♦’* cRRh C2U'jU,♦’—)* —) x FxjU F—j- Fš’,U $ ”K cTcPcWh ’) ?8á.J-*­ M0.8á10 H'0J81.K"0*f y-K):­':7 x778áJ'­ 8L w:-)U j8.(S U-’♦U- V# p))U♦♦U “xJUx! x)- 0U''JU# N,/!j♦❖ g—!j-UJm 4H? 8U*♦P >’Uš ”JU** F/—(K*—)m N/xJ—) cRRT D8:J1 x )) '0- OK*f M--JK1- D:.)­/ MK)-­ 8L 4-&S y8 zKJ7-S KJU b.-1JKJ7*o uUš b—Jq? 5’jj t8x). F/—J)Um gxJJ’U cRRl D-JU-. b)K*f D:.)­ KJU d8*­ :J 47088)o uUš gJ!)*š’,qm u0? 2!♦.UJ* O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** F!,/(x)m wx#U cRRI ®5’*♦—J’,xj N—,’xj N,’U),U? YU♦/—-—j—.’U*m YU♦/—-*m x)YUx)’).* $”K iiTPiha ’) 4'.K'-1:-­ 8L ,áK):'K':;- pJqá:.*S U-’♦U- V# u—JP (x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N “’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 7’-’♦,/m pJ♦/!J 0m x)- N♦x)'—J- Y “#(x) iaaa CL!xj’♦x♦’>U YU♦/—-*? F/U’J 5’*♦—J# ’) N—,’—j—.# x)- p)♦/J—K—j—.# $”K lWPId ’) YKJU688( 8L ,áK):'K ':;- y-­-K.70S i)- U- m U-’♦U- V# u—J(x) f :U)❖’) x)- b>—))x N0“’),—j) F/—!*x)- Hxq*m 4p? Nx.U 8xj♦UJ*m Ax) cRRW ®7’U♦)x( G’KK—* $?8á.JK) 8L PK'-.:K) 2á)'á.- i?hcPWT 8xj❖UJm N!*x) cRRI M0:J(:J1 x68á' '0- dK6*f D-JU-. KJU M.KJ­:':8J­ :J'8 bK. -J'088Uo ”/’jx-UjK/’x? FU(KjU O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** 8UVVm M!.U)U 0y :—)xj- F 4x(KVUjjy 2’,/xJ- N,/šxJ♦❖y “UU NU,/JU*♦y x)- 0x)U♦ gUjUš wJ—>U cRIc v8J.-K7':;- P-K­á.-­ :J '0- 487:K) 47:-J7-­S i)U- g—*♦—)? 5—!./♦—) Y’''j’) 8UJ)UJm H*šxj-m x)- YxJq w N,/—UK'jU cRIW 4*­'-zK':7 w:-)Uj8.(f H'0J8 1.K"0:7 xJK)*­:­ KJU 3K'K PKJK1-z-J'S 7—j!(U i uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U iTa 2MBM2Mu4MN 8/’♦♦’UJm ux),# cRRT w-z:J:­' D-J-.K':8J­f M0- b-.­:­'-J7- 8L '0- yKU:7K) O8z-J/­ P8;-z-J'o ”/’jx-UjK/’x? FU(KjU O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** 8/#♦Um 8’jj’x( B——♦U cRdl 4'.--' 28z-. 487:-'*o 4/’,x.—? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4/’P ,x.— ”JU** 8/#♦Um 8’jj’x( B——♦U cRRc ®F/U N—,’xj N,’U),U* ’) ♦/U O)’>UJ*’♦# $xz-.:7KJ d-0K;:8.K) 47:-J':­' ld?hcIPhld 8/#♦Um 8’jj’x( B——♦U cRRT ®“UxJ)’). 'J—( ♦/U Y—)-Jx.—) 4——KUJx♦’>U MèKUP J’U),U $4'áU:-­ :J 28z"K.K':;- pJ'-.JK':8JK) 3-;-)8"z-J' la?TIPhI 8/#♦Um 8’jj’x( B——♦U cRRh CL!xj’♦x♦’>U N—,’—j—.# x)- :U,—)*♦J!,♦’—)’*( C ,áK):'K':;- pJqá:.* i?iiaPiih 8/#♦Um 8’jj’x( B——♦U cRRR CF/U Y—)-Jx.—) 4——KUJx♦’>U* ’) cRWh x)- cRRI $ pJUá­'.:K) 42WK68. y-)K':8J­ y-;:-j Ti?dWIPdIc 8/#♦Um 8’jj’x( B——♦U cRRl 4'.--' 28z-. 487:-'*S d♦/ U- 4/’,x.—? O)’>UJ*’♦# —' 4/’,x.— ”JU** 8—j,—♦♦m 5xJJ# B cRRa O.:':J1 ’" ,áK):'K':;- y-­-K.70o uUšV!J# ”x"0,m 4p? Nx.U 8—j,—♦♦m 5xJJ# B cRRR H'0J81.K"0*f x O K* 8L 4--:J1o 8xj)!♦ 4JUUqm 4p? pjP ♦xY’Jx ”JU** 8—j'm :x)’Uj 2 cRRc ®5’./P2’*q YU♦/—-—j—.#? 2U'jU,♦’—)* —) “Ux>’). x) H!♦P jxš N—,’U♦# $”K iccPiil ’) H&"-.:-J7:J1 w:-)Uj8.(f x J pJ­:U- “:-j 8L , áK) :'K':;- y-­-K.70o uUšV!J# ”xJqm 4p? Nx.U 8—j'm :’x)U “ sU- S cRRh w-z:J:­' 3:)-zzK­ :J w:-)Uj8.(o g—!j-UJm 4H? 8U*♦P >’Uš ”JU** Gx>Ujjxm ”x♦J’,’x cRIW O8z-Jt­ O8.( KJU 20:7KJ8 wKz:):-­f 2KJJ-.* O8.(-.­ 8L '0- 4KJ'K 2)K.K “K))-*o A♦/x,xm ub? 4—J)Ujj O)’>UJ*’♦# ”JU** Gx>Ujjxm ”x♦J’,’x cRRh ®BU(’)’*♦ A)*’-UJ :’jU((x*? 4—)*♦J!,♦’). M♦/)’, A-U)P ♦’♦# š’♦/ 4/’,x)x A)'—J(x)♦* $”K clIPcTR ’) w-z:J:­' 3:)-zzK­ :J w:-)U j8.(S U-’♦U- V# :’x)U “ 8—j' g—!j-UJm 4H? 8U*♦>’Uš 10 Designing a Research Proposal ✓✓ To examine the role of the proposal within research ✓✓ To inform readers of the criteria by which successful proposals are judged ✓✓ To examine an example of a successful research proposal ✓✓ To identify distinctions between quantitative and qualitative proposals ✓✓ To provide a framework structure for a research proposal •• Introduction •• What is a research proposal? •• The reviewers’ assessment criteria •• Quantitative and qualitative research proposals •• Is there a formula for writing successful research proposals? •• Outline of the proposed research •• Summary •• Recommended reading Introduction All researchers should be able to prepare a proposal for a research topic to a professional standard. Being able to produce such a proposal is an important skill. Intending doctoral students are required to prepare such a proposal when applying for studentships and seeking formal registration for their project. Such requirements are also common on many university Masters courses. Outside of the academic arena, there are also many organisations that provide funding for social research. Where this is the case, how do you convince a funding body that may be assessing a large number of competing proposals that your research is worthy of support in preference to the others that it will look at? You may have a great idea that immediately captures the imagination, but are you capable of transforming this idea into a feasible project? 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 249 The research proposal is the means by which we are able to demonstrate that we are able to do this. As such, it allows us to spell out what exactly is the research problem that we are intending to investigate, why this is worthy of investigation, and how we intend to carry out the research. In putting such a proposal together we shall not only need to demonstrate our knowledge of the area in which we are interested, but also be required to show that we have the necessary methodological competence and sensitivity to carry out the research. This chapter covers the essential ground in constructing a high-quality research proposal. Specifically, it considers: • What is a research proposal? • What is the value of a research proposal? • What should be included in a good research proposal? • How should a research proposal be structured? • By what standards are research proposals assessed? What is a research proposal? The research proposal is an application that is prepared by a research student, university academic, or professional researcher for support prior to embarking upon a research study. At one level, the objectives of a research proposal may be seen as providing a statement about the purposes of the research, how it is to be carried out, the resource implications of the proposed investigation, as well as the timescale for completion. At another level, however, the research proposal is an argument. Through the document, you are presenting a case, in which the intention is to convince others of the general merits and feasibility of the proposed study. The research proposal should therefore aim to convey three key aspects of an intended research project: 1. its objectives and scholarly significance; 2. your technical qualifications; and 3. the level of funding required. The objectives and scholarly significance of the proposed study The general research issues to be examined, together with the methodological strategy to be pursued, need to be carefully explained to the reviewer. Each must also be fully justified. The proposal, then, should communicate your specific intentions. This involves a clear overview of the purpose of the proposed study and of its importance, A Short Introduction to Social Research 250 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 250 together with a step-by-step plan for conducting it. The research problem(s) needs to be identified, questions or hypotheses should be stated, and key terms defined. You must specify and justify which target group is to be included in the sample, together with the research design to be adopted, the research instrument(s) to be used, the procedures to be followed, and the methods of analysis to be used. All of these aspects of the project should be covered, and at least a partial review of previous related literature must be included. This will enable you to ‘ground’ your project theoretically – to make explicit links between this and existing ideas and debates that are taking place within the wider academic or policy community. The literature review will also enable you to demonstrate the suitability of your proposed research strategy. Your case will be strengthened if you: (a) reference the type of methods used by other authors in the past to conduct similar studies; (b) are then able to demonstrate from this that you have appraised the effectiveness of these approaches in generating data to examine the issues at hand, and therefore justified your own choice of research strategy. The technical qualifications of the researcher This will need to be stated, whether you are a student intending to commence with a Masters or doctoral research programme, or a project leader applying for funding support. Your experience and level of expertise should be carefully set out, in terms of both your knowledge of the subject area and your methodological ‘qualifications’ and skills. (Note that when applying for funding, it should not be assumed that by ‘experience’, precedence is inevitably given to those who are well published with a long history of research in the field, over new and aspiring researchers. As we shall see, an application is judged on the basis of the applicant’s track record to date, which will be measured against the particular stage reached in her or his academic career.) The level of funding required It goes without saying that all review committees will need to be convinced that the intended project provides ‘value for money’. This, as we shall see, does not necessarily mean that cheapest is always best. Instead, it requires that the researcher provides evidence that she or he has carefully costed the proposed project, and that the level of funding sought is warranted, given both the aims and objectives of the study and the methods to be used to implement it. If yours is a proposed Masters dissertation or doctoral thesis, and you are not applying directly for financial support, you will nonetheless need to convince the course team that you have access to sufficient resources to complete your study. Designing a Research Proposal 251 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 251 The reviewers’ assessment criteria The essential criteria for assessment of the research proposal will be broadly the same, regardless of which body the prospective researcher is targeting. This will be the case, whether or not you are applying for funding from an external agency or a university research committee, or to a postgraduate course team in order to receive its approval to proceed with a postgraduate dissertation. The proposal should contain sufficient information to persuade both specialist and non-specialist members of the review committee that the proposed activity is sound and worthy of support under their criteria for the selection of projects. Activity 10.1 Review Committee’s judgement of a research proposal What do you think the research review committee will consider most important in assessing a research proposal? Make a list of the areas that you think members of such a committee would focus upon when considering a research proposal. But what are the key criteria that such bodies use to assess a research proposal? The criteria most typically used by review committees to measure the potential of your research proposal can be listed as: • Track record • Originality • Feasibility • Clarity • Outputs Activity 10.2 Review committee assessment criteria Consider the assessment criteria listed above. Which do you think the research review committee will consider most important in assessing a research proposal? How would you rank them in terms of their priority for such a committee? For each, write short notes explaining why you think it is a low- or high-level criterion for review committees. A Short Introduction to Social Research 252 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 252 Clarity The assessors will be scrutinising a research proposal to ensure that there is an internal coherence to the project: • Is it clearly thought through in terms of what you have set out to do? • Is there a clear identification of the research problem that you intend to investigate? It will be anticipated – indeed expected – by the review committee that the research proposal will not be deficient in these areas. Therefore, clarity is a low-level criterion. Very few research proposals would be expected to fail because they lacked internal coherence. Feasibility Can you achieve what you initially set out to do in your proposal (within your budget and your estimated timescale, and using your initial research strategy)? You should think through your research plans carefully, and try to anticipate all possible issues and detours that you may encounter during your study. But the review committee will be sufficiently experienced in these matters to appreciate that research programmes cannot be precisely mapped out, particularly for emergent qualitative research studies. Certainly, the notion of ‘delivery within budget’ is a red herring. And there will be issues that arise during the course of your study which may impact upon your initial methodological strategy – issues that you could not realistically have predicted at the outset. Perhaps these will be in terms of access difficulties encountered, or sickness of a key ‘gatekeeper’, or ethical matters that arise additional to those discussed in your research design. Feasibility is an important issue, and the review committee will use this as one of the criteria upon which they will assess your research proposal. However, risk will take precedence over predictability. Producing a book on time is of course important, but the review committee will ask the question, ‘will the book be read by 5, or 500, or 5,000 people?’ before they ask, ‘will the applicant meet his/her deadline?’ Similarly, If you can demonstrate that your research is innovative, then your proposal is likely to be considered very seriously by the review committee. The exciting, yet expensive, research idea has a greater likelihood of approval than a proposal that is considerably cheaper, but is nonetheless not as inspiring. Feasibility is an important criterion therefore – more so than clarity – but it is nonetheless a relatively low-level one. Track record Understandably, if your research proposal is to be assessed competitively against those submitted by other candidates, the review committee will take into account Designing a Research Proposal 253 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 253 the track records of each applicant. But an established track record by itself is certainly no guarantee of success. And review committees will be realistic enough to appreciate that a ‘new’ researcher can only develop a good track record if bodies like their own provide the researcher with the support to embark upon a research career. Furthermore, such committees will have different expectations of ‘new’ and more ‘long-standing’ applicants. Indeed, a good track record can be achieved even at a relatively early stage for researchers. The expectations held by assessors of what counts as a good track record is relative to the stage of a research career achieved by a particular applicant. New and aspiring researchers should therefore pitch their application for research support appropriately. Typically, the route to be taken is a ‘staged’ one. It involves the aspiring student applying initially for a university postgraduate course. Paid academic research posts, or practitioner research posts, are likely to follow only after qualification. Such a trajectory may be a long and arduous one, but achieving a good track record comes only with talent and hard work. Outputs This is a very important criterion, more so than those already mentioned. The review committee will be particularly interested in supporting project proposals that have the potential for achieving publication, or which may have ‘utility’ for the wider policy community. Extract 10.1 provides an example taken from a (successful) research proposal – the Youth and Politics project (Henn and Weinstein 2000) – that was awarded a research grant from an external research-funding agency (the Economic and Social Research Council). Here, the applicants were required to demonstrate the relevance of the research for different user groups. Notice that there are very explicit statements from the funding agency concerning its expectations about: • the usefulness of the proposed research for this community; • that there is evidence that such organisations and individuals have had some input into the design of the research; • that the research is of sufficient interest to practitioners that they may have provided tangible support to the project (perhaps in terms of part-funding or a letter of support). You may not have been able to achieve this level of external support, but it will significantly add to the robustness and credibility of your research proposal if you can demonstrate that it has importance to the wider practitioner or policy-making communities. This will be the case regardless of whether or not you are applying for external funding for research, or you are preparing a research proposal for a thesis. A Short Introduction to Social Research 254 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 254 EXTRACT 10.1 Youth and Politics project (Henn and Weinstein 2000) Relevance to ‘user’ groups Please explain below the likely contribution to policy or practice; details of consultation with user groups (such as public, private and voluntary sector practitioners and policy makers) in the development of the research and proposed collaboration/communication with such groups during the research should be included. Details of any potential co-funding or support in kind should also be included here. Do not exceed one side. 1. The proposed research will be of value to policy users and to the wider political community. In previous research, we have dealt with a number of agencies and organisations that have links to youth, including amongst others, the Institute for Citizenship, the Citizenship Team at the Department for Education and Employment, the National Union of Students, various trades unions (notably the GMB), and the party youth sections. Meetings will be held to further progress these links through the research, in terms of: the design of the research and the survey questionnaire; testing out the plausibility and utility of the research findings; the dissemination of the findings through presentations at the end of the research. Together, these organisations will be able to provide invaluable advice and support to the project. 2. Non-technical summaries and briefing papers shall be disseminated to various policy users and other interested groups, including those mentioned in 1. above, but also others such as the British Youth Council, the Young Fabians, as well as all members of the Crick Commission, and think-tanks. 3. Academics will be consulted during the design stage of the research – particularly in terms of discussion of theoretical issues in the development of the questionnaire. 4. Research results will be communicated to the academic community via conferences (the annual meetings of the UK Political Studies Association and the British Sociological Association) and academic journals (papers will be submitted to the ‘British Journal of Political Science’, and ‘Sociology’ in the first instance). 5. Earlier research that we have conducted has already been widely disseminated through the national and local media. It is anticipated that the proposed research will lead to similar levels of media exposure, and press releases will be produced for this purpose. Originality Members of a review committee who are charged with the task of reviewing your research proposal will recognise that the project’s perceived contribution to the Designing a Research Proposal 255 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 255 external users, or its potential for publication in an academic journal, or to gain a good pass on a Masters course, will be largely dependent upon its originality. The potential to generate new knowledge is the key to a good research proposal. If you can convince the review committee that you have met this criterion, then and only then will they assess your proposal on the basis of the other criteria mentioned above. By the same token, if you fail to convince these assessors that you have an original idea that you intend to investigate through your proposed project, then the reviewers are unlikely to consider your application further. But different types of reviewer will have different yardsticks against which to measure ‘originality’: 1. External funding agencies (higher education funding councils like the ESRC, charitable funding bodies like the Nuffield Foundation) – will assess originality in terms of an expected significant contribution to knowledge likely to follow from the proposed research. 2. Ph.D. review committees – will look for indications that the intended study programme has a significant potential for publication. 3. Masters supervisors – will be concerned that the dissertation proposal will lead to an authentic and independent research project. So, how will you discover your ‘big idea’? It is likely to develop organically from your own research interests. Most importantly, you must read widely – adopting too narrow a focus in your reading may limit your ability to discover your research question. You must look consciously for it. This will by necessity involve you in one or more of the following: • Developing an awareness (through reviewing the literature and/or attending conferences) of the research which is currently being developed in your field. As you do so, search for an idea which you consider to be significant by its omission from your field. Try to identify what is conventionally referred to as a research gap in your chosen area. • Challenging current thinking in your field (to do this requires you to be aware of the key issues and debates in your subject area first of all). • Applying an existing idea to a new field or a different academic or policy context. This may not involve you in developing a ‘new’ idea as such, but the way in which you use that existing idea will be innovative. It therefore has the potential to make an original contribution to knowledge. An example might involve you examining a marketing technique that is used widely within the general field of business studies, and researching the extent of its usage by political parties in their campaigning. Through your research, you may gain a greater understanding of the development of modern electioneering methods. The research proposal is therefore an important document. As such, it will take significant time, effort, and patience to get it right. It will also likely involve the A Short Introduction to Social Research 256 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 256 preparation of several drafts, as well as feedback from colleagues in the field, before it is ready for submission. But such preparation has some important potential benefits for the project. Submitting the research proposal enables an expert review committee to evaluate the merits of your research plans, and in so doing – especially where they may offer suggestions for revision – provides important ‘expert’ insight into how to improve the study. Quantitative and qualitative research proposals Prior to the drafting of a research proposal, the nature of the research design to be selected should be set out. Whether one is intending to adopt a broadly qualitative research design, or a strategy that is largely quantitative in nature, is likely to affect the shape and format of the research proposal. Of course, those charged with reviewing proposals would have very clear expectations that certain content will be included in the proposal, regardless of the intended research strategy. However, some elements of a quantitative research proposal will not be included in a qualitative research proposal, and vice versa. Furthermore, quantitative research proposals are likely to be more uniform than those designed for broadly qualitativebased studies. As K.P. Punch (1998, pp.269–70) notes: It is easier in many respects to suggest proposal guidelines for a quantitative study, since there is greater variety in qualitative studies, and many qualitative studies will be unfolding rather than prestructured. An emerging study cannot be as specific in the proposal about its research questions, or about details of the design. When this is the case, the point needs to be made in the proposal. In the remainder of this chapter, the core elements of a research proposal will be reviewed. Where appropriate, the specific aspects that are necessary for drafting either a qualitative or a quantitative proposal will be noted. Is there a formula for writing successful research proposals? A research proposal, then, is a written plan for a study. It spells out in detail what the researcher intends to do. It permits others to learn about the intended research, and to offer suggestions for improving the study. It helps the researcher to clarify what needs to be done, and aims to avoid unintentional pitfalls or unknown problems. Before examining what a research proposal might look like, it is important to be aware that what will be suggested in the remainder of this chapter is intended to serve as a general framework, not a definitive set of instructions. The only general rule that must always be adhered to is that the research proposal should be both Designing a Research Proposal 257 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 257 succinct and complete. Other than that, each university research committee or external funding agency will have its own expectations about the actual format of the research proposal, and some will be more explicit than others in this respect. Research proposals often vary significantly in terms of length. In some cases, application forms that prescribe precisely what is wanted will need to be completed. In others, the researcher will have more latitude to decide upon the format of the proposal. However, the onus will be on the researcher to ‘bend’ to meet the requirements of the university review committee or external funding agency. Outline of the proposed research In the absence of any forms or guidelines, there are general themes that you might use to structure your own research proposal, whether this is for a postgraduate dissertation, or an application for external research funding. However, what follows are ‘elements’ of a proposal – you do not need to have each as a particular heading. Title page This should include each of the following: your name, the title of the proposed project, any collaborating agencies which have been involved in the preparation of the proposal, the date of submission, and, if applicable, the funding agency to which you are applying for support. Abstract The abstract is a brief synopsis of the planned research investigation. It appears at the front of the proposal, but it is usually the last element to be written. It should include two key areas – the major objectives of the proposed study, and the procedures and general methodological strategy that are to be used in order to meet these objectives. The abstract should be approximately one page or less in length. The abstract is an important strategic element of the proposal, and therefore should be afforded considerable attention in the drafting of your proposal. It serves three key interlinked purposes: • The reviewer usually reads it before the full proposal to gain a perspective of the study and of its expected significance. • The reviewer uses it as a reference to the nature of the study if the project comes up for discussion. A Short Introduction to Social Research 258 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 258 • It will sometimes be the only part of the proposal that is read when making preliminary selections of applicant proposals. Read through Extract 10.2. As you do so, look carefully at the two aspects of an abstract outlined above, and note how they are covered. EXTRACT 10.2 Abstract: Youth and Politics project (Henn and Weinstein 2000) Conventional wisdom holds that young people in Britain are alienated from the political process. Moreover, some have suggested that there is an ‘historic political disconnection’ of youth from formal party politics, with this group more likely to participate in new politics formations. Paradoxically, there is a recognition that formalised youth activities are a potentially significant aspect of party development. They serve the purposes of recruiting the future political elite, raising political awareness among young people, and widening the pool of party activists. The aim of this project is to reveal the level of engagement that young people have with party politics in Britain. Specifically, the research will examine whether there is a crisis of democratic legitimacy in terms of the attitudes of young people toward party politics. It will also investigate differences in this respect, along socio-demographic and spatial lines. Importantly, regional analysis will enable an examination of the efficacy of new political institutions in Wales, Scotland and London for strengthening levels of young people’s political engagement. Quantitative data will be collected by means of a national postal survey of young people. This will be the first British nation-wide study to focus exclusively on first-time voters with only limited experience of formal politics. Activity 10.3 Think about a research project that you intend to conduct. Write an abstract of between 200 and 250 words, setting out (a) the general issues and debates/or policy field that you intend to engage with through your study, (b) your specific aims and objectives, and (c) the research strategy that you propose to follow to meet these objectives. Research problem to be investigated There are usually four areas to be addressed in this section of the research proposal: the purpose of the proposed study, a justification for the project, the specific research Designing a Research Proposal 259 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 259 questions that you intend to explore, and a definition of the key terms and concepts that you will examine. However, you will write only one section. This must contain all of these four aspects; you will not deal with each under a separate heading. Purpose of the study This section expects you to state succinctly what the research proposes to investigate. The purpose should be a concise statement, providing a framework to which details are added later. Generally speaking, any study should seek to clarify some aspect of the field of interest that is considered important, thereby contributing both to the overall knowledge in the field and to current practice. Justification for the study The researcher must make clear why this particular study is important to investigate. You must present an argument for the work of the study. As an example, you might be interested in the general field of organisation studies. If you intend to study a particular method through which a local authority deals with harassment at work, you need to make a case that such a study is important, and that people are or should be concerned with it. Perhaps it is particularly prevalent in a particular department compared to the overall situation within the local authority. You might indicate that previous studies have identified a pattern of harassment that is linked to poor morale within the workplace, increased incidences of people suffering from occupational stress, and high levels of absenteeism. Or perhaps, where the issue is not checked, it may lead to poor industrial relations. The net result either way may lead to an erosion of quality within the particular department, and a decline in public confidence in the service. Alternatively, you may be interested in conducting a research study which aims to evaluate the effectiveness of ‘care in the community’ solutions for mental health patients. Existing research may indicate that since the introduction of the current arrangements, there has been a marked increase in the general suicide rate amongst this group, or perhaps an expansion in the rate of homelessness among people with severe learning difficulties. You must also make clear why you have chosen to investigate the particular method adopted by organisations to tackle such problems. In many such proposals, there is the implication that current methods are not adequate to tackle the problem seriously. Coley and Scheinberg (1990, p.41) have developed a useful framework for conceptualising issues for research that helps to justify how research may reveal interesting new insights into the problem. The framework may not, in its entirety, be appropriate for all styles of research, but the general method they adopt is a useful way of beginning to think about how you may structure the ‘case’ for your proposed study: People with ‘A’ characteristics and background live in ‘B’ conditions/environments and have ‘C’ problems/needs that are caused by ‘D’. A Short Introduction to Social Research 260 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 260 People are blocked from solving these problems because of ‘E’. This problem is related to other problems ‘F’, and have ‘G’ short- and long-term impact if not addressed. The impact of their needs/problems on the community is ‘H’. Others have addressed their needs/problems by doing ‘I’, the result of their interventions have been ‘J’. The most promising strategy for intervention now is ‘K’. Key questions to ask yourself at this point are: • Have I identified the specific research problem that I wish to investigate? • Have I indicated what I intend to do about this problem? • Have I put forward an argument as to why this problem is worthy of investigation? The research questions The particular research questions that you intend to examine should be stated next. These are usually, but not always, a more specific form of the problem in question form. For quantitative researchers, research hypotheses will be set out at this stage for reasons of clarity and as a research strategy. If a researcher has a hypothesis in mind, it should be stated as clearly and as concisely as possible. It is unnecessarily frustrating for a reader to have to infer what a study’s hypothesis or hypotheses might be. Examples of the research questions that were to be pursued in the Youth and Politics project noted in Extracts 10.1 and 10.2 are included in Extract 10.3. For qualitative researchers, especially those adopting an emergent research design, the actual research questions and hypotheses will not become clear until the research has begun. Typically, these begin to take shape in the course of data collection and analysis. As K.P. Punch (1998, p.270) notes: If a tightly structured qualitative study is planned, the proposal can proceed along similar lines to the quantitative proposal. If a more emergent study is planned, where focus and structure will develop as the study proceeds, this point should be made clearly (in the research proposal). In the former case, there will be general and specific questions. In the latter case, there will only be general orienting and guiding research questions. Key questions to ask yourself at this point are: • Have I asked the specific research questions that I wish to explore through my research? • Do I have any hypotheses in mind? If so, have I expressed them clearly and appropriately? • Do I intend to investigate a relationship between different phenomena or variables? If so, have I indicated the variables that I think may be related? Designing a Research Proposal 261 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 261 EXTRACT 10.3 Key research questions: Youth and Politics project (Henn and Weinstein 2000) • Popular understanding of parties. • Are young people indifferent, or even hostile to political parties? • What, if anything, do they like about them? • Do their attitudes towards parties significantly differ from those of other sections of the population (such as their parents’ generation)? • Is there evidence to suggest that young people are now more disaffected from parties than at any time since the introduction of universal suffrage? • And is there a case for arguing that young people, given their particular socialisation and formal educational experiences, might actually be more predisposed to party appeals? Activity 10.4 Write down a list of five key questions that you aim to research in your project. As you do, make brief notes to remind yourself why you are asking these questions – what do you aim to achieve in doing so? Definitions of key terms and concepts All key terms should be defined. In a quantitative hypothesis-testing study, these are primarily the terms that describe the variables of the study. Your task is to make your definitions as clear as possible. If previous definitions found in the literature are clear to all, that is well and good. Often, however, they need to be modified to fit your proposed study. It is often helpful to formulate operational definitions as a way of clarifying terms or phrases. While it is probably impossible to eliminate all ambiguity from definitions, the clearer the terms used in a study are – to both you and others – the fewer difficulties will be encountered in subsequent planning and conducting of the study. For instance, if you are conducting a study which involves researching harassment at work, you will want to examine different aspects and dimensions of this key concept. One of these may be violence, and you should carefully define this by taking account of the different forms of violence – physical, verbal, and emotional. Now review the section on operationalising concepts in Chapter 3. In an emergent qualitative-based research study, however, the key concepts that you intend to engage with in your research will not all be clear to you at the outset of your research. The key issues, their dimensions, and how you intend to define A Short Introduction to Social Research 262 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 262 them will only become clear in the course of the actual empirical investigation. Where this is so, you should state this clearly within your proposal. A key question to ask yourself at this point is: • Have I defined all key terms clearly and (if possible) operationally? Review of the literature In a research proposal, the literature review is a partial summary of previous work related to the focus of the study. You will need to demonstrate to a review committee that you are familiar with the major trends in previous research as well as opinions on the topic, and that you understand their relevance to your planned study. The major weakness of many literature reviews is that they cite references without indicating their relevance or implications for the planned study. You need to review the literature comprehensively prior to the development of your research proposal – in order for instance to identify a research gap that will serve as a stimulus for your study. However, the space available for you to develop this in your research proposal will be limited. You will therefore need to be concise and succinct in your review. Cormack (1984) provides a useful overview of the three key uses of a literature review. It will: • provide you with a wide range of documentary information on facts, opinions, and comments concerning the topic to be investigated; • help you to discover whether the topic has already been studied, and, if so, to what extent your work will be affected; • help you to decide which research techniques will be most appropriate for your study. In the early stages, the literature review will consume much of your time and energies. However, it should be regarded as a continuous process, with new information added as the project proceeds. You should take a structured approach to your literature search. Ask yourself, what information are you after? If you are going to use word searches on CD-ROMs or the Internet, you should list all the possible keywords and synonyms that you consider to be relevant to your research question(s). You should also be clear about which timescale you intend to cover in your project (only articles since 1991?), and what the geographic boundaries are that you intend to work within (Australian but not Canadian studies?). Finally, you should be flexible about the range of material that you consider for your literature review – especially if your initial searching fails to uncover a sufficient body of literature for your study. For instance, you may consider studies that investigate the sources and impact of occupational stress in the teaching and nursing professions, and how these experiences apply to the fire Designing a Research Proposal 263 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 263 service in terms of the implications for safety. Or perhaps in a project focusing on youth engagement with politics, you might find it valuable to consider studies that examine the political participation of ethnic minority groups. For more information about consulting the literature, see Chapter 9. Key questions to ask yourself at this point are: • Have I surveyed and described relevant studies that are related to my research problem? • Have I surveyed existing expert opinion on the problem? • Have I summarised the existing state of opinion and research on the problem? Methodology to be used for conducting the research The methodology section should include a discussion of your intended research design, the sample you will examine, the instruments to be used to conduct the investigation, procedural detail for collecting your empirical evidence, and the data analysis technique(s) to be used. Research design The particular research design to be used should be identified, as well as how it applies to the present study. You therefore need to ensure that your choice of approach is justified in this section (see Extract 10.4). Typically, the basic design is fairly clear cut, and fits one of the following models: • Survey research • Historical research • Experimental research • Observational/ethnographic research • Documentary research However, you may want to use a variety of approaches. Combining methods and strategies may help to add depth to your study, as well as enable you to identify whether your approach is valid and reliable. See Chapter 3 for a discussion of this mixed method research design. Emergent qualitative research designs may involve you in approaching your methods more flexibly during the course of the study. As K.P. Punch (1998, p.273) explains, when opting for such a research design: ‘There is a need to explain the flexibility the study requires and why, and how decisions will be made as the study unfolds’. Nonetheless, you should be as explicit as you can be in your proposal about the general research design that you intend to use, and provide as much material about your plans as you are able. A Short Introduction to Social Research 264 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 264 EXTRACT 10.4 Youth and Politics research proposal (Henn and Weinstein 2000) As you read through this extract, notice how the two methods are justified with respect to the project aims and objectives. Focus on attainers As a methodological innovation, we will focus exclusively on ‘attainers’ – young people eligible to vote for the first time when the 2001 electoral register comes into force. As far as we are aware, the proposed study would be the first of its kind to focus solely on attainers. Our intention in limiting our study to this age group is twofold. Firstly, in research terms, attainers are a relatively unique target group. Most social and political surveys that examine the views of young people tend to combine their views with older youths. Hence, attainers will typically be analysed as part of an 18–24 (or 18–25) year old group (see, for instance Parry et al. 1992) or included in studies of students (e.g., Denver and Hands 1990), often alongside respondents with an increasingly mature age profile as Higher Education is opened up to new entrants. Secondly, they will have had minimal formal experience of participating in politics in terms of voting, with the possible exception of the 2001 local elections.They are, therefore, relatively inexperienced politically in comparison to older people and are therefore less likely than their older contemporaries to have formed deep-seated views about politics, parties and politicians. As a consequence, attainers provide a fascinating target group for study in terms of their perceptions of political institutions and actors in Britain. The study will form the baseline for understanding future developments in youth attitudes of, and orientation towards, British political parties as these attainers gain experience of engaging with politics. There is potential therefore to track attitudes over time for comparative purposes. Activity 10.5 Decide what is to be the research design for your intended study. State clearly why you have chosen that particular approach in terms of the aims and objectives you set out for your project in Activity 10.4. Sample In your proposal, you should indicate in considerable detail how you will include participants – the sample – for investigation in your study. You should indicate Designing a Research Proposal 265 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 265 what the size of the sample will be, how members will be selected, and what claims you may legitimately make about the representativeness of your sample. For a quantitative research study, you should aim, if at all possible, to adopt a random sampling technique, or, if this is unrealistic, a quota sampling method should be used in an attempt to maximise representativeness. However, for small-scale projects of the type likely to be undertaken by postgraduate students where your study will be subject to various resource constraints, it may be legitimate to use other less rigorous sampling methods such as the convenience sample. It is more important to complete a project with an unrepresentative sample than abandon the study because it fails to achieve a sample that is representative of your target group. If a convenience sample must be used, relevant demographics (gender, ethnicity, occupation, age, housing, and any other relevant characteristics) of the sample should be described. The legitimate population to which the results of the study may be generalised should be indicated. For emergent qualitative research designs, you are likely to use theoretical sampling to select your research participants. Where this is the case, you are much more likely to include respondents whose presence is designed to maximise theoretical development than to achieve representativeness. Your reasons for choosing this sampling strategy should be indicated (and justified) within this section of the research proposal, together with an acknowledgement that: (a) the sample has been chosen to generate insights (as opposed to definitive conclusions) about your research area; and (b) the results will be indicative, rather than representative, of the views of the wider population. For a further discussion of this point, see the section on case selection from Chapter 3. Key questions to ask yourself at this point are: • Have I described my sampling plan? • Have I described the relevant characteristics of my sample in detail? • If you are using a predominantly quantitative research design, have I identified the population to which the results of the study may legitimately be generalised? • If you are using a predominantly qualitative research design, have I demonstrated that my selection of cases is reasonably typical of what might be expected if I had conducted my research elsewhere? Instruments to be used Whenever possible, existing research instruments should be used in your study, since construction of even the most straightforward test or questionnaire (or selection of questions) is often very time consuming and difficult. Furthermore, doing so will enable you to make comparisons between your findings and the results from the earlier study from which the research instrument was borrowed. However, you cannot justify using an existing research instrument if it is not appropriate for your purpose, even though it may be more convenient. You will therefore need to assess whether existing instruments are suited to your needs. A Short Introduction to Social Research 266 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 266 In the event that appropriate instruments are not available, the procedures to be followed in developing your own research instruments to be used in the study should be described with attention to how validity and reliability will be enhanced. It will be important to indicate within your proposal that you intend to build a pilot stage (Extract 10.5) into your project, or, if the research instrument has already been tested for these purposes, include a version within the appendices. For example, if you are conducting a survey, you should include a specimen questionnaire or some questions that you consider to be good illustrations of what you will ask. For a more qualitative research design, you might include an observation schedule, or a topic guide for in-depth interviews. EXTRACT 10.5 Pilot stage: Youth and Politics research proposal (Henn and Weinstein 2000) As you read through the following extract, you will notice how a pilot study has already been conducted to examine both what sorts of question areas will likely need to be explored for the qualitative part of the project, and how the quantitative aspect will take advantage of an existing research instrument. Pilot research A qualitative-based pilot study, using focus groups, has already been completed by the research team in preparation for this full project (Henn, Weinstein and Wring 1999). This preliminary research was designed to help establish which questions should be asked, as well as their structure. We will also hold meetings with various party youth activists and youth organisers, interested user groups, and academics in order to further our understanding of which questions to include in the questionnaire. In addition, the proposed survey will include questions that appear on other national political opinion studies to enable comparative work with other age groups (including amongst others, the British Social Attitudes surveys, the British Election Studies surveys, and the British Election Panel surveys). Considerable attention will be paid to the design and layout of the questionnaire to ensure an attractive presentation of the postal survey.This will draw on previous experience of conducting postal surveys of this particular target group (Wring, Henn and Weinstein 1999; Henn, Weinstein and Wring 2000). A pilot study will be conducted in the Nottingham area in order to test the efficacy of the questions to be used in the postal survey. Key questions to ask yourself at this point are: • Have I described the instrument(s) to be used? • Have I indicated their relevance to the present study? Designing a Research Proposal 267 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 267 • Have I stated how I will check the reliability and validity of my data collection instruments? • Have I built a ‘piloting the instrument’ stage into the research design? Procedures and data collection Outline your proposed method(s) of research. This should be presented in sufficient detail for the reader to know whether the project is realistic, feasible, and worthwhile. You will need to describe how you intend to access your target group, and contact your research participants. Is your target group one that is typically difficult to involve in research studies of your kind? If so, what steps will you take to maximise your response rate, and minimise bias? What method of data collection will you use? For instance, if your proposed study involves the use of a questionnaire, you should indicate whether you intend to use a self-completion version, or implement it in a face-to-face situation, or via the telephone. It is important to make your procedures of data collection clear so that if another researcher wants to repeat the study in exactly the same way as the original, you have made your procedures as clear as possible so they can be replicated. Certain procedures may change from those previewed in the proposal as the study is carried out, but a proposal should always aim to have this level of clarity as its goal. Explain why you think this is the best method for investigating the research problem. A key question to ask yourself at this point is: • Have I fully described the procedures to be followed in the study – what will be done, where, when, and how? Data analysis The researcher should indicate how the data to be collected will be organised, interpreted, and analysed. You should explain which statistical procedures and tests you intend to use for quantitative-based studies, and why you are choosing to do so. Similarly, if you intend to conduct a qualitative research study, then you should indicate the methods of analysis you will use to analyse the data. Perhaps you intend to quantify the results obtained from your unstructured interviews? If your project is more emergent in nature, you may be proposing to adopt a grounded theory approach. Ethical considerations The review committee will have been alerted to any potential or any actual ethical problems likely to arise from your proposed study while reading the methodology section. The proposal may be reviewed by a committee whose primary objective is to assess the scientific methods of a study, but they will also be aware of ethical issues. It is important that you anticipate gaining written consent from adults or parents or guardians when members of your target group cannot themselves give A Short Introduction to Social Research 268 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 268 approval. Ethical matters may also be relevant to protecting these research participants from any negative consequences of your study. However, you will also need to demonstrate to the review committee that you have taken adequate steps to ensure that both yourself and others associated with your intended project are protected from harm, particularly if the research situation is one that has the potential to place people in positions of danger. At some point in the proposal it is necessary to indicate clearly what you regard as the major ethical issues of the project, and to state clearly how these will be handled. Alternatively you may state that the proposal raises no ethical issues. In order to complete this section effectively and convincingly, you should pay close attention to the ethical guidelines that are set out in the codes of conduct that many academic and professional organisations have developed. For a full discussion of ethics, see Chapter 4. Timescale The amount of time you need to devote to the study should be set out in the proposal. It may be that this is a proposal for a full-time commitment or for only a few hours in a week. But whichever is the case, the research proposal must specify the amount of time involved (Extract 10.6). The review committee will need to know how long the project will take when considering whether to fund it, or, if yours is a proposal for a Masters dissertation, whether the project can be finished within your deadline. EXTRACT 10.6 Timetable for the Youth and Politics project Completion of all preparation and design work (3 months); commencement of survey data collection phase of study (3 months); completion of survey data collection phase of study (6 months); commencement of analysis phase of study (6 months); completion of analysis phase of study (14 months); commencement of writing up of the research (12 months); completion of preparation of any new datasets for archiving (14 months); completion of writing up (18 months). Facilities and resources Describing particular forms of expertise or backup facilities can strengthen a proposal. Good computer and library facilities fall into this category. Where established networks are integral to a project, or co-operation has been obtained from particular agencies or institutions, some indication of this, like a letter of agreement, may be included as a helpful appendix. Designing a Research Proposal 269 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 269 Budget Preparing a research budget is as much a skill as preparing other parts of the proposal. Part of the skill lies in locating other people who know the price of all appropriate commodities: staff time, tape-recorders, photocopying, travel costs, and so on. Preparing a budget means translating the timescale and plan of work into financial terms. In preparing a budget, use a checklist to include main headings such as: • Research salaries • Data collection costs (purchase of equipment and other materials, printing, travelling expenses) • Stationery and postage • Data analysis expenses Pre-submission It is likely that a research proposal will go through many drafts. Indeed, there would be major cause for concern if it did not. There are a number of things to be achieved in reviewing a proposal – not least considering its physical presentation. Legibility, lucidity, and clarity of presentation are all important. While readers of a proposal will not be evaluating its presentation, the relatively small amount of time it takes to ensure a layout that is easily followed will be time well spent. Check carefully that the proposal meets all of the criteria set by the review committee. Perhaps most importantly, ask colleagues to read and comment upon your proposal, and take any criticisms that they may have of it seriously. As Hessler (1992, p.287) states: We assume too much, taking for granted the nuances and assumptions of our research, which is tough on readers who do not share this knowledge ... take nothing for granted. If in doubt, spell it out, even to the point of repeating yourself. Redundancy is not the worst sin in grant writing. SUMMARY This chapter has reviewed the process of constructing a research proposal, setting out the main points that need to be considered in producing a professional and convincing document. As we have seen, in any proposal it is of paramount importance that the research that is envisaged is clearly articulated and is of value to the body looking to support the research. In assessing your proposal, a reviewer will also be looking to see that your proposed study is a feasible one. As well as capturing a reviewer’s imagination with the subject of your research, you will have to satisfy the reviewer that you are in a position to carry the research out to a high standard. Having a bright idea A Short Introduction to Social Research 270 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 270 is the starting point from which you have to construct a compelling case that your research is not only interesting, but also capable of execution. In this respect the reviewer will be looking for you to demonstrate your methodological proficiency and sensitivity. For example, have you adequately addressed the complexities of the sampling strategy that will need to be adopted and are you fully aware of any potential issues that may preclude you obtaining access to your intended research participants? As we have seen, there are different audiences for different sorts of research proposals. If your research is intended to be carried out as part of a Masters course at a university, you may be primarily focused on persuading your tutors that you have located your research in a particular body of specialist literature. On the other hand, if you are applying for funding from an external agency that places a high premium on policy-oriented research then you will need to convince the reviewing panel that your research not only is of academic interest, but also has wider societal value. Of course, all reviewers will have their own set of criteria by which they will judge the proposals that come before them. Unfortunately, there is no easily applied formula that can be applied to all research proposals that can guarantee success. However, the more consideration that you have been able to give to the research you plan to carry out, reflecting on the outline elements that have been covered in this chapter, the more likely it is that you will have produced a proposal that stands up to keen scrutiny. RECOMMENDED READING Blaikie, N. 2000. Designing Social Research. Cambridge: Polity Press. Brewer, E.W., Achilles, C.M. and Fuhriman, J.R. 1993. Finding Funding: Grant Writing for the Financially Challenged Educator. London: Sage. Bryman, A. 2001. Social Research Methods. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Coley, S.M. and Scheinberg, C.A. 1990. Proposal Writing. London: Sage. Hart, C. 2001. Doing a Literature Search: A Comprehensive Guide for the Social Sciences. London: Sage. Designing a Research Proposal 271 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 271 Henn, M. and Weinstein, M. 2000. First-Time Voters’ Attitudes towards Party Politics in Britain [online]. Economic and Social Research Council. Available at (Accessed 9 January 2004). Punch, K.P. 1998. Introduction to Social Research: Quantitative and Qualitative Approaches. London: Sage. Punch, K.P. 2000. Developing Effective Research Proposals. London: Sage. A Short Introduction to Social Research 272 11-Henn-3289 Ch10.qxd 9/21/2005 11:25 AM Page 272 Bibliography Adler, P. 1985. Wheeling and Dealing. New York: Columbia University Press. Aldridge, A. and Levine, K. 2001. Surveying the Social World: Principles and Practice in Survey Research. Buckingham: Open University Press. Allport, G. 1942. The Use of Documents in Psychological Science. New York: Social Science Council. Arber, S. 1993. Designing Samples. In: N. Gilbert (ed.), Researching Social Life. London: Sage. pp.68–92. Arksey, H. and Knight, P. 1999. Interviewing for Social Scientists. London: Sage. Asch, S.E. 1965. Effects of Group Pressure upon the Modification and Distortion of Judgments. In: H. Proshansky and B. Seidenberg (eds), Basic Studies in Social Psychology. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston. pp.393–410. Barker, E. 1984. The Making of a Moonie. Brainwashing or Choice. Oxford: Blackwell. Barnes, J. 1979. Who Should Know What? Social Science, Privacy and Ethics. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Barthes, R. 1967. Elements of Semiology, trans. Annette Lavers and Colin Smith. London: Jonathan Cape. Bechhofer, F. 1974. Current Approaches to Empirical Research: Some Central Ideas. In: R.G. Burgess (ed.), Field Research: A Sourcebook and Field Manual. London: Allen and Unwin. p.211. Becker, H. 1967. Whose Side Are We on? Social Problems, 14, pp.239–47. Becker, H. 1974. Photography and Sociology. Studies in the Anthropology of Visual Communication, 1, pp.3–26. Becker, H.S. and Geer, B. 1960. Participant Observation: The Analysis of Qualitative Field Data. In: R.G. Burgess (ed.), Field Research: A Sourcebook and Field Manual. London: Allen and Unwin. p.239. Behling, J.H. 1984. Guidelines for Preparing the Research Proposal. Lanham, MD: University of Maryland Press. Benn, T. 1988. Out of the Wilderness: Diaries 1963–67. London: Arrow Books. Berg, B. 1998. Qualitative Research Methods for the Social Sciences. Needham Heights, MA: Allyn and Bacon. Berger, A.A.S. 1993. Improving Writing Skills: Memos, Letters, Reports and Proposals. London: Sage. Berger, R. 1990. Nazi Science: The Dachau Hypothermia Experiments. New England Journal of Medicine, 332 (20), pp.1435–40. Bernard, B. 1999. Century. London: Phaidon Press. Bernard, H.R. 1994. Research Methods in Anthropology: Qualitative and Quantitative Approaches. London: Sage. Bilton, T. et al., 1987. Introductory Sociology. London: Macmillan. 12-Henn-3289 Bibliography.qxd 9/30/2005 2:49 PM Page 273 Bingham, N. 2003. Writing Reflexively. In: M. Pryke, G. Rose and S. Whatmore (eds), Using Social Theory: Thinking Through Research. London: Sage. Blaikie, N. 2000. Designing Social Research. Cambridge: Polity Press. Brewer, E.W., Achilles, C.M. and Fuhriman, J.R. (eds) 1993. Finding Funding: Grant Writing for the Financially Challenged Educator. London: Sage. Brewer, J. and Hunter, A. 1989. Multimethod Research: A Synthesis of Styles. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Brooks, N. 1989. Writing a Grant Application. In: G. Perry and F.N. Watts (eds), Behavioural and Mental Health Research: A Handbook of Skills and Methods. Hove, Sussex: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Brunskell, H. 1998. Feminist Methodology. In: C. Seale (ed.), Researching Society and Culture. London: Sage. pp.37–47. Bryman, A. 1988. Quantity and Quality in Social Research. London: Sage. Bryman, A. 1989. Research Methods and Organisation Studies. London: Unwin Hyman. Bryman, A. 1990. Analysing Quantitative Data for Social Scientists. London: Routledge. Bryman, A. 2001. Social Research Methods. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bulmer, M. (ed.) 1982. Social Research Ethics. London: Macmillan. Bulmer, M. 1984. Why Don’t Sociologists Make More Use of Official Statistics? In: M. Bulmer (ed.), Sociological Research Methods. London: Macmillan. pp.131–52. Burgess, R.G. 1982. Field Research: A Sourcebook and Field Manual. London: Allen and Unwin. Burgess, R.G. 1984. In the Field: An Introduction to Field Research. London: Routledge. Butler, D. 1994. The Opinion Polls and the 1992 General Election. London: Market Research Society. Cain, M. 1990. Realist Philosophy and Standpoint Epistemologies or Feminist Criminology as a Successor Science. In: L. Gelsthorpe and A. Morris (eds), Feminist Perspectives in Criminology. Milton Keynes: Open University Press. pp.124–40. Campbell, D. 1995. PC Condon Fuels Race-Crime Furore. Guardian, 8 July, p.5. Cassell, J. 1982. Harms, Benefits, Wrongs, and Rights in Fieldwork. In: J. Sieber (ed.), The Ethics of Social Research: Fieldwork, Regulation, and Publication. New York: Springer. pp.7–31. Cavendish, R. 1982. Women on the Line. London: Routledge. Coghlan, D. and Brannick, T. 2001. Doing Action Research in Your Own Organisation. London: Sage. Coley, S.M. and Scheinberg, C.A. 1990. Proposal Writing. London: Sage. Comte, A. 1974. The Essential Comte: Selected from ‘Cours de philosophie positive’ by Auguste Comte ..., ed. and with an introduction by Stanislav Andreski, trans. and annot. Margaret Clarke. London: Croom Helm. Corbin, J. and Strauss, A. 1990. Basics of Qualitative Research: Grounded Theory Procedures and Techniques. London: Sage. Cormack, D.F.S. 1984. The Research Process in Nursing. Oxford: Blackwell Scientific. Corrigan, P. 1979. Schooling the Smash Street Kids. London: Macmillan. Coulthard, M., Walker, A. and Morgan, A. 2002. People’s Perceptions of Their Neighbourhood and Community Involvement [online]. London: The Stationery Office. Available at (Accessed 28 February 2005). Coxon, A. 1988. Towards a Sociology of AIDS. Social Studies Review, January, pp.84–7. Crewe, I. 1983. Surveys of British Elections: Problems of Design, Response and Bias. Colchester: University of Essex. Crossman, R. 1975. The Diaries of a Cabinet Minister, Vol. 1: Minister of Housing 1964–1966. London: Hamilton. Crotty, M. 1998. The Foundations of Social Research: Meaning and Perspective in the Research Process. London: Sage. Bibliography 274 12-Henn-3289 Bibliography.qxd 9/30/2005 2:49 PM Page 274 Crow, I. 2000. The Power of Research. In: D. Burton (ed.), Research Training for Social Scientists. London: Sage. pp.68–80. Cuba, L. and Cocking, J. 1997. How to Write About the Social Sciences. Harlow: Longman. Day, A. 1996. How to Get Work Published in Journals. Aldershot: Gower. De Saussure, F. 1983. Course in General Linguistics, trans. and annot. Roy Harris. London: Duckworth. De Vaus, D. 1985. Surveys in Social Research. London: UCL Press. De Vaus, D.A. 1996. Surveys in Social Research, 2nd edn. London: UCL Press. Denscombe, M. 2003. The Good Research Guide for Small-Scale Research Projects. Buckingham: Open University Press. Denscombe, M. and Aubrook, L. 1992. It’s Just Another Piece of Schoolwork: The Ethics of Questionnaire Research on Pupils in Schools. British Educational Research Journal, 18, pp.113–31. Denzin, N. 1989. The Research Act: A Theoretical Introduction to Sociological Methods, 3rd edn. New York: McGraw-Hill. Denzin, N.K. and Lincoln, Y.S. 1998a. Collecting and Interpreting Qualitative Materials. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Denzin, N.K. and Lincoln, Y.S. 1998b. Strategies of Qualitative Enquiry. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Denzin, N.K. and Lincoln, Y.S. 1998c. The Landscape of Qualitative Research:Theories and Issues. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Dey, I. 1993. Qualitative Data Analysis: A User-Friendly Guide for Social Scientists. London: Routledge. Diener, E. and Crandall, R. 1978. Ethics in Social and Behavioural Research. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Douglas, J. 1976. Investigative Social Research: Individual and Team Research. London: Sage. Drew, C.J. 1980. Introduction to Designing and Conducting Research. St Louis, MO: C.B. Mosby. Erikson, K. 1967. A Comment on Disguised Observation in Sociology. Social Problems, 12, pp.336–73. ESRC (Economic and Social Research Council). 1995. Writing for Business. Swindon: ESRC. Eysenck, H. 1971. Race, Intelligence and Education. London: MT Smith. Fay, B. 1993. The Elements of Critical Social Science. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.33–6. Festinger, L., Riecken, H. and Schachter, S. 1956. When Prophecy Fails. New York: Harper and Row. Fetterman, D. 1989. Ethnography: Step by Step. London: Sage. Fielding, F. and Gilbert, N. 2000. Understanding Social Statistics. London: Sage. Fielding, N. 1981. The National Front. London: Routledge. Fielding, N. 1993a. Ethnography. In: N. Gilbert (ed.), Researching Social Life. London: Sage. pp.154–71. Fielding, N. 1993b. Qualitative Interviewing. In: N. Gilbert (ed.), Researching Social Life. London: Sage. pp.135–53. Fielding, J. and Gilbert, N. 2000. Understanding Social Statistics. London: Sage. Finch, J. 1993. It’s Great to Have Someone to Talk to: Ethics and Politics of Interviewing Women. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.166–80. Fletcher, D.E. 1997. Organisational Networking and Strategic Change in a Small Family Business. Unpublished doctoral thesis, Nottingham Polytechnic. Foucault, M. (ed.) 1980. Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972–1977. New York: Pantheon. Fowler, F. 1993. Survey Research Methods. London: Routledge. pp.54–68. Frankfort-Nachmias, C. and Nachmias, D. 1996. Research Methods in the Social Sciences, 5th edn. New York: St Martin’s Press. Gelsthorpe, L. 1992. Response to Martyn Hammersley’s Paper ‘On Feminist Methodology’. Sociology, 26 (2), pp.213–18. Bibliography 275 12-Henn-3289 Bibliography.qxd 9/30/2005 2:49 PM Page 275 Gilbert, N. 2001. Writing About Social Research. In: N. Gilbert (ed.), Researching Social Life, 2nd edn. London: Sage. Gill, J. and Johnson, P. 1997. Research Methods for Managers. London: Paul Chapman. Gillespie, T. 1994. Feminist Research: Reclaiming Objectivity. Research, Policy and Planning, 12 (2), pp.23–5. Glaser, B. and Strauss, A. 1967. The Discovery of Grounded Theory: Strategies for Qualitative Research. New York: Aldine. Goldthorpe, J., Lockwood, D., Bechhofer, F. and Platt, J. 1969. The Affluent Worker in the Class Structure. London: Cambridge University Press. Gorden, R. 1980. Interviewing: Strategy, Techniques and Practice. Homewood, IL: Dorsey. Government Statisticians’ Collective, 1993. How Official Statistics Are Produced: Views from the Inside. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.146–65. Graziano, A. and Raulin, M. 1997. Research Methods: A Process of Inquiry, 3rd edn. New York: Addison-Wesley. Guba, E. and Lincoln, Y. (eds) 1989. Fourth Generation Evaluation. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Hakim, C. 1982. Secondary Analysis in Social Research: A Guide to Data Sources and Methods with Examples. London: Allen and Unwin. Hakim, C. 1987. Research Design: Strategies and Choices in the Design of Social Research. London: Routledge. Hakim, C. 1993. Research Analysis of Administrative Records. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.131–45. Hammersley, M. 1992a. On Feminist Methodology. Sociology, 26 (2), pp.187–206. Hammersley, M. 1992b. What’s Wrong With Ethnography? London: Routledge. Hammersley, M. 1993a. What is Social Research? In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Principles of Social and Educational Research: Block 1. Milton Keynes: The Open University. Hammersley, M. (ed.) 1993b. Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. Hammersley, M. 1995. The Politics of Social Research. London: Sage. Hammersley, M. 1997. A Reply to Humphries. Sociological Research Online, [online], 2 (4). Available at (Accessed 20 June 2001). Hammersley, M. and Atkinson, P. 1995. Ethnography: Principles in Practice, 2nd edn. London: Routledge. Hammersley, M. and Gomm, R. 1997. Bias in Social Research. Sociological Research Online, [online], 2 (1). Available at (Accessed 20 June 2001). Hamner, J. and Hearn, J. 1993. Gendered Research and Researching Gender: Women, Men and Violence. British Sociological Association Annual Conference, ‘Research Imaginations’. University of Sussex, 5–8 April. Hanfling, O. 1981. Logical Positivism. Oxford: Blackwell. Harari, H., Harari, O. and White, R.V. 1985. The Reaction to Rape by American Bystanders. Journal of Social Psychology, 125, pp.653–8. Haraway, D. 1991. Simians, Cyborgs and Women:The Reinvention of Nature. London: Free Association. Harding, S. 1987. Is there a Feminist Methodology? In: S. Harding (ed.), Feminism and Methodology. Milton Keynes: Open University Press. pp.1–14. Hart, C. 2001.Doing a Literature Search: A Comprehensive Guide for the Social Sciences.London: Sage. Henn, M. 1998. Opinion Polls and Volatile Electorates: Problems and Issues in Polling Volatile Electorates. Aldershot: Ashgate. Henn, M. and Weinstein, M. 2000. First-Time Voters’ Attitudes Towards Party Politics in Britain [online]. Economic and Social Research Council. Available at Bibliography 276 12-Henn-3289 Bibliography.qxd 9/30/2005 2:49 PM Page 276 (Accessed 9 January 2004). Henn, M., Weinstein, M. and Wring, D. 1999. Young People and Citizenship: A Study of Opinion in Nottinghamshire. Nottingham: Nottinghamshire County Council. Henn, M., Weinstein, M. and Wring, M. 2002. A Generation Apart? Youth and Political Participation in Britain. The British Journal of Politics and International Relations, 4 (2), pp.167–92. Henn, M., Young, M. and Hill, N. 1997. Labour Renewal Under Blair? A Local Membership Study. In: J. Stanyer and G. Stoker (eds), Contemporary Political Studies. Belfast: Political Studies Association. pp.495–509. Henwood, K. and Pidgeon, N. 1995. Remaking the Link: Qualitative Research and Feminist Standpoint Theory. Feminism and Psychology, 5 (1), pp.7–30. Henwood, K.L. and Pidgeon, N.F. 1993. Qualitative Research and Psychological Theorizing. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.14–32. Hessler, R.M. 1992. Social Research Methods. St Paul, MN: West. Hoinville, G. and Jowell, R. 1978. Survey Research Practice. London: Heinemann. Holdaway, S. 1982. ‘An Inside Job’: A Case Study of Covert Research on the Police. In: M. Bulmer (ed.), Social Research Ethics. London: Macmillan. pp.59–79. Homan, R. 1991. The Ethics of Social Research. London: Longman. pp.41–68. Hood, S., Mayall, B. and Oliver, S. (eds) 1999. Critical Issues in Social Research: Power and Prejudice. Buckingham: Open University Press. Howard, K. and Sharpe, J.A. 1983. The Management of a Student Project. Aldershot: Gower. Humphreys, L. 1970. Tearoom Trade: Impersonal Sex in Public Places. Chicago: Aldine. Humphries, B. 1997. From Critical Thought to Emancipatory Action: Contradictory Research Goals? Sociological Research Online, [online], 2 (1). Available at (Accessed 20 June 2001). Humphries, B. 1998. The Baby and the Bath Water: Hammersely, Cealey Harrison and HoodWilliams and the Emancipatory Research Debate. Sociological Research Online, [online], 3 (1). Available at (Accessed 20 June 2001). Irvine, J., Miles, I. and Evans, J. (eds) 1979. Demystifying Social Statistics. London: Pluto Press. Jayaratne, T. 1993.The Value of Quantitative Methodology for Feminist Research. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.109–23. Jones, J. 1995. Understanding Psychological Science. New York: HarperCollins. Jones, P. 1993. Studying Society: Sociological Theories and Research Practices. London: Collins Educational. Jupp, V. and Norris, C. 1993. Traditions in Documentary Analysis. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.37–51. Kane, E. 1990. Doing Your Own Research: Basic Descriptive Research in the Social Sciences and Humanities. London: Boyars. Katz, J. 1972. Experimentation with Human Beings. New York: Russell Sage. Kelly, L., Burton, S.and Regal, L.1994.Researching Women’s Lives or Studying Women’s Oppression? Reflections on what Constitutes Feminist Research. In: M. Maynard and J. Purvis (eds), Researching Women’s Lives from a Feminist Perspective. London: Taylor & Francis, 1994, pp.27–48. Kelman, H. 1972. The Rights of the Subjects in Social Research: An Analysis in Terms of Relative Power and Legitimacy. American Sociologist, 27, pp.989–1015. Kirk, J. and Miller, M.L. 1986. Reliability and Validity in Qualitative Research. London: Sage. Kolakowski, L. 1993. An Overview of Positivism. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.1–8. Krathwohl, D.R. 1988. How to Prepare a Research Project: Guidelines for Funding and Dissertations in the Social and Behavioural Sciences. New York: Syracuse University Press. Bibliography 277 12-Henn-3289 Bibliography.qxd 9/30/2005 2:49 PM Page 277 Krueger, R.A. 1994. Focus Groups: A Practical Guide for Applied Research. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Kuhn, T. 1970. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Kuzwayo, E. 1985. Call Me Woman. London: Women’s Press. Lasswell, H. 1942. Communications Research and Politics. In: D.Waples (ed.), Print, Radio and Film in a Democracy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Laurie, H. and Sullivan, O. 1990. Combining Qualitative and Quantitative Data in the Longitudinal Study of Household Allocations. Sociological Review, 1 (39), pp.113–30. Leedy, P.D. 1989. Practical Research: Planning and Design. London: Macmillan. Levitas, R. and Guy, W. 1996. Interpreting Official Statistics. London: Routledge. Locke, L.F., Spirduso, W.W. and Wilverman, S.J. 1993. Proposals That Work: A Guide for Planning Dissertations and Grant Proposals. London: Sage. Lofland, J. and Lofland, L. 1995. Analyzing Social Settings: A Guide to Qualitative Observation and Analysis, 3rd edn. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth. Macdonald, K. and Tipton, C. 1993. Using Documents. In: N. Gilbert (ed.), Researching Social Life. London: Sage. pp.187–200. Mann, C. and Stewart, F. 2000. Internet Communication and Qualitative Research: A Handbook for Researching Online. London: Sage. Market Research Society, 1992. Report of The Market Research Society Inquiry Into the 1992 General Election. London: Market Research Society. Marsh, C. 1979. Problems With Surveys: Method or Epistemology? Sociology, 13 (2), pp.293–305. Marsh, C. 1982. The Survey Method: The Contribution of Surveys to Sociological Explanation. London: George Allen and Unwin. Mason, J. 1996. Qualitative Interviewing. London: Sage. May, T. 2001. Social Research: Issues, Methods and Process, 3rd edn. Buckingham: Open University Press. Mayhew, H. 1861–1862. London Labour and the London Poor: A Cyclopaedia of the Conditions and Earnings of those that will work, those that cannot work, and those that will not work, 4 vols. London: Griffin Bohn. Maynard, M. 1994. Methods, Practice and Epistemology: The Debate about Feminism and Research. In: M. Maynard and J. Purvis (eds), Researching Women’s Lives from a Feminist Perspective. London: Taylor & Francis. pp.10–26. Maynard, M. 1998. Feminists’ Knowledge and Knowledge of Feminisms: Epistemology, Theory, Methodology and Method. In: T. May and M. Williams, (eds), Knowing the Social World. Buckingham: Open University Press. pp.120–37. McRobbie, A. 1991. Feminism and Youth Culture: From Jackie to Just Seventeen. London: Macmillan. Mies, M. 1993. Towards a Methodology for Feminist Research. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London. pp.64–82. Miles, I. and Irvine, J. 1979. The Critique of Official Statistics. In: J. Irvine, I. Miles, and J. Evans (eds), Demystifying Social Statistics. London: Pluto Press. pp.113–29. Milgram, S. 1963. Behavioural Study of Obedience. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 6, pp.371–8. Millen, D. 1997. Some Methodological and Epistemological Issues Raised by Doing Feminist Research on Non-Feminists. Sociological Research Online, [online], 2 (3). Available at (Accessed 18 May 1999). Miller, D.C. 1991. Handbook of Research Design and Social Measurement. London: Sage. Mishler, E. 1986. Research Interviewing. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Moon, N. 1997. The Opinion Polls Since 1992 – Lessons Learned and Changes Made. Social Research Association News, May, pp.5–6. Bibliography 278 12-Henn-3289 Bibliography.qxd 9/30/2005 2:49 PM Page 278 Morgan, D.L. and Kreuger, R.A. 1998. The Focus Group Kit Vols 1–6. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Moser, C. and Kalton, G. 1971. Survey Methods in Social Investigation. London: Heinemann. Moxley, J. 1992. Publish, Don’t Perish: The Scholar’s Guide to Academic Writing and Publishing. London: Greenwood Press. Neuman, W. 2000. Social Research Methods: Qualitative and Quantitative Approaches, 4th edn. London: Allyn and Bacon. pp.75–82. Newell, R. 1993. Questionnaires. In: N. Gilber (ed.), Researching Social Life. London: Sage. Oakley, A. 1981. Interviewing Women: A Contradiction in Terms. In: H. Roberts, (ed.), Doing Feminist Research. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. pp.30–61. Oakley, A. 1999. People’s Ways of Knowing: Gender and Methodology. In: S. Hood, B. Mayall and S. Oliver (eds), Critical issues in Social Research: Power and Prejudice. Buckingham: Open University Press, pp.154–70. Oakley, A. and Oakley, A. 1979. Sexism in Official Statistics. In: J. Irvine, I. Miles and J. Evans (eds), Demystifying Social Statistics. London: Pluto Press. pp.172–189. O’Connell Davidson, J. and Layder, D. 1994. Methods: Sex and Madness. London: Routledge. Office for National Statistics, 1999. Publications. Office for National Statistics, [online]. Available at (Accessed 2 March 2000). O’Muircheartaigh, C. 1997. Election 97: A Triumph for the Pollsters? Research, Market Research Society, June, pp.14–22. Oppenheim, A. 1993. Questionnaire Design, Interviewing and Attitude Measurement, 2nd edn. Aldershot: Gower. Patrick, J. 1973. A Glasgow Gang Observed. London: Eyre-Methuen. Patton, M. 1987. How to Use Qualitative Methods in Evaluation. London: Sage. pp.70–107. Pawson, R. 1989. A Measure for Measures: A Manifesto for Empirical Sociology. London: Routledge. Peräkylä, A. 1997. Reliability and Validity in Research Based on Tapes and Transcripts. In: D. Silverman (ed.), Qualitative Research: Theory, Method & Practice. London. pp.201–20. Piliavin, I.M., Rodin, J. and Piliavin, A. 1969. Good Samaritanism: An Underground Phenomenon. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 13, pp.289–99. Platt, J. 1981. Evidence and Proof in Documentary Research and Some Specific Problems of Documentary Research. Sociological Review, 29 (1), pp.31–52. Popper, K. 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson. Popper, K. 1972. Objective Knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon. Powdermaker, H. 1966. Stranger and Friend:The Way of an Anthropologist. NewYork:W. W. Norton. Punch, K.P. 1998. Introduction to Social Research: Quantitative and Qualitative Approaches. London: Sage. Punch, K.P. 2000. Developing Effective Research Proposals. London: Sage. Punch, M. 1993. Observation and the Police: The Research Experience. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.181–99. Punch, M. 1986. The Politics and Ethics of Fieldwork. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage. Punch, M. 1998. Politics and Ethics in Qualitative Research. In: N. Denzin and Y. Lincoln (eds), The Landscape of Qualitative Research: Theories and Issues. London: Sage. pp.156–84. Ramazanoglu, C. 1992. On Feminist Methodology: Male Reason Versus Female Empowerment. Sociology, 26 (2), pp.213–18. Reinharz, S. 1983. Experiential Analysis: A Contribution to Feminist Research. In G. Bowles and R. Duelli Klein (eds), Theories of Women’s Studies. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. pp.162–192. Reinharz, S. 1992. Feminist Methods in Social Research. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Reiss, A. 1971. The Police and Public. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Roberts, H. (ed.) 1990. Doing Feminist Research. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Bibliography 279 12-Henn-3289 Bibliography.qxd 9/30/2005 2:49 PM Page 279 Roethlisberger, F.J. and Dickson, W.J. 1939. Management and the Worker. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Romm, N. 1997. Becoming More Accountable: A Comment on Hammersley and Gomm. Sociological Research Online, 2 (1), [online], 2 (3). Available at (Accessed 18 May 1999). Roy, D. 1952. Quota Restriction and Goldbricking in a Machine Shop. American Journal of Sociology, 67 (2), pp.427–42. Ruebhausen, M. and Brim, O. 1966. Privacy and Behaviour in Research. American Psychologist, 21, p.432. Sacks, H. 1995. Lectures on Conversation, ed. E.A. Schegloff with an introduction by G. Jefferson. Oxford: Blackwell. Salkind, N. 2003. Statistics for People Who (Think They) Hate Statistics. London: Sage. Sapsford, R. 1993. Problems, Cases and the Logic of Research Studies. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Principles of Social and Educational Research. Milton Keynes: The Open University. Sapsford, R. 1999. Survey Research. London: Sage. Schofield, J.W. 1993. Increasing the Generalisability of Qualitative Research. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.200–25. Schofield, W. 1993. Sample Surveys. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Principles of Social and Educational Research: Block 2. Milton Keynes: The Open University. pp.75–108. Schumacher, D. 1992. Get Funded!: A Practical Guide for Scholars Seeking Research Support from Business. London: Sage. Schutt, R. 1999. Investigating the Social World. London: Sage. Schwartz, M. 1964. The Mental Hospital: The Researched Person in the Disturbed World. In: A.Vidich, J. Benson and M. Stein (eds), Reflections on Community Studies. NewYork: Harper and Row. pp.85–117. Seale, C. 1998. Researching Society and Culture. London: Sage. Seeman, M. 1972. On the Meaning of Alienation. In: C. Frankfort-Nachmias and D. Nachmias, Research Methods in the Social Sciences. London: Arnold, 1996, pp.32–3. Sieber, J. 1992. Planning Ethically Responsible Research. Newbury Park, CA: Sage. Silverman, D. 1993. Interpreting Qualitative Data: Methods for Analysing Talk, Text and Interaction. London: Sage. Silverman, D. 1998. Harvey Sacks: Social Science and Conversation Analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Silverman, D. 1997. Qualitative Research: Theory, Method and Practice. London: Sage. Silverman, D. 2000. Doing Qualitative Research: A Practical Handbook. London: Sage. Silverman, D. 2001 Interpreting Qualitative Data: Methods for Analysing Talk, Text and Interaction, 2nd edn. London: Sage. Slattery, M. 1986. Official Statistics. London: Tavistock. Smart, C. 1984. The Ties That Bind: Law, Marriage, and the Reproduction of Patriarchal Relations. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. SRA (Social Research Association), 2003. Ethical Guidelines. London: Social Research Association. Stanley, L. and Wise, S. 1983. Breaking Out: Feminist Consciousness and Feminist Research. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Stavenhagen, R. 1993. Decolonializing Applied Social Sciences. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.52–63. Strange, V., Oakley, A. and Forrest, S. 2003. Mixed-sex or Single-sex Sex Education: How Would Young People Like Their Sex Education and Why? Gender & Education, 15 (2), pp.201–14. Strauss, A. and Corbin, J. 1998. Basics of Qualitative Research: Techniques and Procedures for Developing Grounded Theory, 2nd edn. London: Sage. Bibliography 280 12-Henn-3289 Bibliography.qxd 9/30/2005 2:49 PM Page 280 Thatcher, M. 1993. The Downing Street Years. London: HarperCollins. Thomas, W. and Znaniecki, F. 1918–1920. The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Thompson, H. 1967. Hell’s Angels. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Tonkiss, F. 1998. The History of the Social Survey. In: C. Seale (ed.), Researching Society and Culture. London: Sage. pp.58–71. Townend, D. 2000. How Does Substantive Law Currently Regulate Social Science Research? In: D. Burton (ed.), Research Training for Social Scientists. London: Sage. pp.113–21. Trotsky, L. 1975. My Life: An Attempt at an Autobiography. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Van Maanen, J. 1979. On Watching the Watchers. In: P. Manning and J.Van Maanen (eds), Policing: A View from the Street. Santa Monica, CA: Goodyear. pp.309–49. Von Wright, G.H. 1993. Two Traditions. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.9–13. Ward Schofield, J. 1993. Increasing the Generalizability of Qualitative Research. In: M. Hammersley (ed.), Social Research: Philosophy, Politics and Practice. London: Sage. pp.200–25. Warren, C. 1981. Gender Issues in Field Research. London: Sage. Warwick, D. 1983. The Politics and Ethics of Field Research. In: M. Bulmer and D. Warwick (eds), Social Research in Developing Countries: Surveys and Censuses in the Third World. Chichester: Wiley. pp.315–30. Waterhouse, R. 1994. Census Figures Are Abandoned After Two Million Are Missed. Guardian, 23 December, p.1. Webb, E.J., Campbell, D.T., Schwartz, R.D. and Sechrest, L. 1984. The Use of Archival Sources in Social Research. In: M. Bulmer (ed.), Sociological Research Methods. London: Macmillan. pp.113–30. Weber, M. 1949. The Methodology of the Social Sciences. New York: Free Press. Weinstein, M. 2005. A Comparative Analysis of Youth Activism in Mainstream Political Parties and New Social Movements in Britain. Unpublished PhD thesis, Nottingham Trent University. Wetherell, M., Taylor, S. and Yates, S. (eds) 2001a. Discourse as Data: A Guide for Analysis. London: Sage. Wetherell, M., Taylor, S. and Yates, S. (eds) 2001b. Discourse Theory and Practice: A Reader. London: Sage. Willis, P. 1977. Learning to Labour. Farnborough: Saxon House. Wright Mills, C. 1959. The Sociological Imagination. In: R.G. Burgess, Field Research: A Sourcebook and Field Manual. London: Allen and Unwin. p.209. Yablonsky, L. 1968. The Hippy Trip. Harmondsworth: Penguin. Zimbardo, P. 1973. On the Ethics of Intervention in Human Psychological Research. Cognition, 2, pp.243–56. Bibliography 281 12-Henn-3289 Bibliography.qxd 9/30/2005 2:49 PM Page 281 Social Inclusion: Perspectives, Practices and Challenges within the Visegrad Region SOC607 Course Reader 2016 Text selection by Mgr. Elena Gallová Kriglerová; Doc. Ing. Anna Kadeřábková; Mgr. Lenka Kissová; George Ligeti, Ph.D., Csc.; Marcjanna Nóżka, Ph.D.; Mgr. Ivana Rapošová; PhDr. Michal Vašečka, Ph.D. Reader editors Lenka Kissová, Ivana Rapošová Layout by Peter Kotvan Cover page by Michal Kotvan Please, note that this reader is a study material compiled exclusively for the course Social Inclusion: Perspectives, Practices and Challenges within the Visegrad Region. We would like to kindly ask you not to share and circulate it.