The Level-of-Analysis Problem in International Relations Author(s): J. David Singer Source: World Politics, Vol. 14, No. 1, The International System: Theoretical Essays (Oct., 1961), pp. 77-92 Published by: Cambridge University Press Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2009557 Accessed: 20-09-2018 09:17 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to World Politics This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE LEVEL-OF-ANALYSIS PROBLEM IN INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS By J. DAVID SINGER TN any area of scholarly inquiry, there are always sever 1 which the phenomena under study may be sorted and ar purposes of systemic analysis. Whether in the physical or socia the observer may choose to focus upon the parts or upon upon the components or upon the system. He may, for examp between the flowers or the garden, the rocks or the quarry, t the forest, the houses or the neighborhood, the cars or the t the delinquents or the gang, the legislators or the legislative, a Whether he selects the micro- or macro-level of analysis is os a mere matter of methodological or conceptual convenience. Yet the choice often turns out to be quite difficult, and may well become a central issue within the discipline concerned. The complexity and significance of these level-of-analysis decisions are readily suggested by the long-standing controversies between social psychology and sociology, personality-oriented and culture-oriented anthropology, or micro- and macro-economics, to mention but a few. In the vernacular of general systems theory, the observer is always confronted with a system, its sub-systems, and their respective environments, and while he may choose as his system any cluster of phenomena from the most minute organism to the universe itself, such choice cannot be merely a function of whim or caprice, habit or familiarity.2 The responsible scholar must be prepared to evaluate the relative utility-conceptual and methodological-of the various alternatives open to him, and to appraise the manifold implications of the level of analysis finally selected. So it is with international relations. But whereas the pros and cons of the various possible levels of analysis have been debated exhaustively in many of the social sciences, the issue has scarcely been raised among students of our emerging 1 As Kurt Lewin observed in his classic contribution to the social sciences: "The first prerequisite of a successful observation in any science is a definite understanding about what size of unit one is going to observe at a given time." Field Theory in Social Science, New York, I95I, P. I57. 2For a useful introductory statement on the definitional and taxonomic problems in a general systems approach, see the papers by Ludwig von Bertalanffy, "General System Theory," and Kenneth Boulding, "General System Theory: The Skeleton of Science," in Society for the Advancement of General Systems Theory, General Systems, Ann Arbor, Mich., I956, I, part I. This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 78 THE INTERNATIONAL SYSTEM discipline.3 Such tranquillity may be s cation that the issue is not germane t dence that it has already been resolve quietude with a measure of concern. He is quite persuaded of its relevance and certain that it has yet to be resolved. Rather, it is contended that the issue has been ignored by scholars still steeped in the intuitive and artistic tradition of the humanities or enmeshed in the web of "practical" policy. We have, in our texts and elsewhere, roamed up and down the ladder of organizational complexity with remarkable abandon, focusing upon the total system, international organizations, regions, coalitions, extra-national associations, nations, domestic pressure groups, social classes, elites, and individuals as the needs of the moment required. And though most of us have tended to settle upon the nation as our most comfortable resting place, we have retained our propensity for vertical drift, failing to appreciate the value of a stable point of focus.4 Whether this lack of concern is a function of the relative infancy of the discipline or the nature of the intellectual traditions from whence it springs, it nevertheless remains a significant variable in the general sluggishness which characterizes the development of theory in the study of relations among nations. It is the purpose of this paper to raise the issue, articulate the alternatives, and examine the theoretical implications and consequences of two of the more widely employed levels of analysis: the international system and the national sub-systems. I. THE REQUIREMENTS OF AN ANALYTICAL MODEL Prior to an examination of the theoretical implications of the level of analysis or orientation employed in our model, it might be worthwhile to discuss the uses to which any such model might be put, and the requirements which such uses might expect of it. Obviously, we would demand that it offer a highly accurate description of the phenomena under consideration. Therefore the scheme must present as complete and undistorted a picture of these phenomena as is possible; it must correlate with objective reality and coincide with our empirical referents to the highest possible degree. Yet we know that 3An important pioneering attempt to deal with some of the implications of one's level of analysis, however, is Kenneth N. Waltz, Man, the State, and War, New York, I959. But Waltz restricts himself to a consideration of these implications as they impinge on the question of the causes of war. See also this writer's review of Waltz, "International Conflict: Three Levels of Analysis," World Politics, xii (April i960), pp. 453-6i. 4Even during the debate between "realism" and "idealism" the analytical implications of the various levels of analysis received only the scantiest attention; rather the emphasis seems to have been at the two extremes of pragmatic policy and speculative metaphysics. This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE LEVEL-OF-ANALYSIS PROBLEM 79 such accurate representation of a complex and phenomena is extremely difficult. Perhaps a use borrowed from cartography; the oblate spheroid most closely represents is not transferable to the of a map without some distortion. Thus, the exaggerates distance and distorts direction at an move north or south from the equator, while t jection suffers from these same debilities as we m Neither offers therefore a wholly accurate prese enough to reality to be quite useful for certain same sort of tolerance is necessary in evaluati for the study of international relations; if we m sentational accuracy, the problem is to decide w dysfunctional and where such accuracy is abs These decisions are, in turn, a function of the any such model-a capacity to explain the rel phenomena under investigation. Here our concer accuracy of description as with validity of expl have such analytical capabilities as to treat th a fashion which is not only valid and thorough, latter requirement is often overlooked, yet its strategy are not inconsequential.5 It should b primary purpose of theory is to explain, an explanatory requirements are in conflict, the la priority, even at the cost of some representation Finally, we may legitimately demand that offer the promise of reliable prediction. In ment last, there is no implication that it is the most of the three. Despite the popular belief to the c mands less of one's model than does explanati For example, any informed layman can pred 5For example, one critic of the decision-making mode Snyder, H. W. Bruck, and Burton Sapin, in Decision-M Study of International Politics (Princeton, N.J., I954), searcher could deal with all the variables in that model a than a very few comparative studies in his lifetime. See He Strategies for a Science of International Politics," World pp. 28I-95. In defense, however, one might call attenti which many of Snyder's categories could be collapsed int apparently done in the subsequent case study (see not telling criticism of the monograph is McClosky's comment of theory is introduced into the proposal and the relations more concretely, it is likely to remain little more than a like any taxonomy, fairly limited in its utility" (p. 29I). This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 80 THE INTERNATIONAL SYSTEM accelerator of a slowly moving car wil less of the moon will be visible tonight than last night; or that the normal human will flinch when confronted with an impending blow. These predictions do not require a particularly elegant or sophisticated model of the universe, but their explanation demands far more than most of us carry around in our minds. Likewise, we can predict with impressive reliability that any nation will respond to military attack in kind, but a description and understanding of the processes and factors leading to such a response are considerably more elusive, despite the gross simplicity of the acts themselves. Having articulated rather briefly the requirements of an adequate analytical model, we might turn now to a consideration of the ways in which one's choice of analytical focus impinges upon such a model and affects its descriptive, explanatory, and predictive adequacy. II. THE INTERNATIONAL SYSTEM AS LEVEL OF ANALYSIS Beginning with the systemic level of analysis, we find in the total international system a partially familiar and highly promising point of focus. First of all, it is the most comprehensive of the levels available, encompassing the totality of interactions which take place within the system and its environment. By focusing on the system, we are enabled to study the patterns of interaction which the system reveals, and to generalize about such phenomena as the creation and dissolution of coalitions, the frequency and duration of specific power configurations, modifications in its stability, its responsiveness to changes in formal political institutions, and the norms and folklore which it manifests as a societal system. In other words, the systemic level of analysis, and only this level, permits us to examine international relations in the whole, with a comprehensiveness that is of necessity lost when our focus is shifted to a lower, and more partial, level. For descriptive purposes, then, it offers both advantages and disadvantages; the former flow from its comprehensiveness, and the latter from the necessary dearth of detail. As to explanatory capability, the system-oriented model poses some genuine difficulties. In the first place, it tends to lead the observer into a position which exaggerates the impact of the system upon the national actors and, conversely, discounts the impact of the actors on the system. This is, of course, by no means inevitable; one could conceivably look upon the system as a rather passive environment in which dynamic states act out their relationships rather than as a socio-political entity with a dynamic of its own. But there is a natural tendency to endow that upon which we focus our attention with somewhat greater This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE LEVEL-OF-ANALYSIS PROBLEM 81 potential than it might normally be expecte to move, in a system-oriented model, away much national autonomy and independence more deterministic orientation. Secondly, this particular level of analysis alm that we postulate a high degree of uniformi operational codes of our national actors. By def room for divergence in the behavior of our pa the whole. It is no coincidence that our most p and one of the very few text writers focusing system-should "assume that [all] statesmen of interest defined as power."6 If this single-m preted literally and narrowly, we have a sim to economic man or sexual man, and if it be no better off than the psychologist whose hum realization" or "maximization of gain"; all su from the same fatal weakness as the utilitarian ciple. Just as individuals differ widely in what and pain, or gain and loss, nations may diff consider to be the national interest, and we down and refine the larger category. Moreover finds himself compelled to go still further and of both motives and ideological preferences i these represent two of the more useful dimens among the several nations in our internation any empirical concern with the domestic and in the separate nations, the system-oriented appr sort of "black box" or "billiard ball" concept By discounting-or denying-the differences 6 Hans J. Morgenthau, Politics Among Nations, 3rd e Obviously, his model does not preclude the use of po differentiation of nations. 7 The "black box" figure comes from some of the simpler in which the observer more or less ignores what goes concentrates upon the correlation between stimulus an as empirically verifiable, whereas cognition, perception, an to be imputed to the individual with a heavy reliance on variables." The "billiard ball" figure seems to carry the is best employed by Arnold Wolfers in "The Actors in Inte T. R. Fox, ed., Theoretical Aspects of International R I959, pp. 83-i06. See also, in this context, Richard C. Sny Theory-Continued," World Politics, xiii (January i96 Singer, "Theorizing About Theory in International Politics, tion, iv (December i960), pp. 431-42. Both are review a anthology. This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 82 THE INTERNATIONAL SYSTEM positing the near-impossibility of ob at work within them,8 one concludes of our nations in the international sy inadequate foundation upon which to base any causal statements, it offers a reasonably adequate basis for correlative statements. More specifically, it permits us to observe and measure correlations between certain forces or stimuli which seem to impinge upon the nation and the behavior patterns which are the apparent consequence of these stimuli. But one must stress the limitations implied in the word "apparent"; what is thought to be the consequence of a given stimulus may only be a coincidence or artifact, and until one investigates the major elements in the causal link-no matter how persuasive the deductive logic-one may speak only of correlation, not of consequence. Moreover, by avoiding the multitudinous pitfalls of intra-nation observation, one emerges with a singularly manageable model, requiring as it does little of the methodological sophistication or onerous empiricism called for when one probes beneath the behavioral externalities of the actor. Finally, as has already been suggested in the introduction, the systemic orientation should prove to be reasonably satisfactory as a basis for prediction, even if such prediction is to extend beyond the characteristics of the system and attempt anticipatory statements regarding the actors themselves; this assumes, of course, that the actors are characterized and their behavior predicted in relatively gross and general terms. These, then, are some of the more significant implications of a model which focuses upon the international system as a whole. Let us turn now to the more familiar of our two orientations, the national state itself. III. THE NATIONAL STATE AS LEVEL OF ANALYSIS The other level of analysis to be considered in this paper is the national state-our primary actor in international relations. This is clearly the traditional focus among Western students, and is the one which dominates almost all of the texts employed in English-speaking colleges and universities. Its most obvious advantage is that it permits significant differentiation among our actors in the international system. Because it does not require the attribution of great similarity to the national actors, it encour- 8Morgenthau observes, for example, that it is "futile" to search for motives because they are "the most illusive of psychological data, distorted as they are, frequently beyond recognition, by the interests and emotions of actor and observer alike" (op.cit., p. 6). This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE LEVEL-OF-ANALYSIS PROBLEM 83 ages the observer to examine them in greater results of such intensive analysis cannot be ov when the actors are studied in some depth tha really valid generalizations of a comparative na systemic model does not necessarily preclude com among the national sub-systems, it usually eventu comparisons based on relatively crude dimensio On the other hand, there is no assurance that the proach will produce a sophisticated model for t of foreign policy; with perhaps the exception of study,9 none of our major texts makes a serious an describe and explain national behavior in terms of cant variables by which such behavior might b lyzed. But this would seem to be a function, not o employed, but of our general unfamiliarity w sciences (in which comparison is a major preo retarded state of comparative government and po most international relations specialists are lik experience. But just as the nation-as-actor focus permits us t homogenization which often flows from the syst lead us into the opposite type of distortion-a m the differences among our sub-systemic actors. W neither of these extremes is conducive to the deve cated comparison of foreign policies, and such balanced preoccupation with both similarity and d seems to be greatest when we succumb to the tend tiate; comparison and contrast can proceed only formities.'0 One of the additional liabilities which flow in tu to overdifferentiate is that of Ptolemaic paroch emphasizing the differences among the many observer is prone to attribute many of what he c to his own nation and the vices to others, especial the moment. That this ethnocentrism is by no borne out by perusal of the major international re 9Ernst B. Haas and Allen S. Whiting, Dynamics of Inte York, 1956. 10 A frequent by-product of this tendency to overdifferent "second-image fallacy," in which one explains the peacefu nation's foreign policy exclusively in terms of its domestic ec characteristics (op.cit., chs. 4 and 5). This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 84 THE INTERNATIONAL SYSTEM in the United States since i945. Not only through the prism of the American nat degree of attention (if not spleen) is dir it would hardly be amiss to observe tha equally well as studies in American fore quacies of this sort of "we-they" orient yet they remain a potent danger in any utilization of the national actor model. Another significant implication of the sub-systemic orientation is that it is only within its particular framework that we can expect any useful application of the decision-making approach.1" Not all of us, of course, will find its inapplicability a major loss; considering the criticism which has been leveled at the decision-making approach, and the failure of most of us to attempt its application, one might conclude that it is no loss at all. But the important thing to note here is that a system-oriented model would not offer a hospitable framework for such a detailed and comparative approach to the study of international relations, no matter what our appraisal of the decision-making approach might be. Another and perhaps more subtle implication of selecting the nation as our focus or level of analysis is that it raises the entire question of goals, motivation, and purpose in national policy.'2 Though it may well be a peculiarity of the Western philosophical tradition, we seem to exhibit, when confronted with the need to explain individual or collective behavior, a strong proclivity for a goal-seeking approach. The question of whether national behavior is purposive or not seems to require discussion in two distinct (but not always exclusive) dimensions. Firstly, there is the more obvious issue of whether those who act on behalf of the nation in formulating and executing foreign policy consciously pursue rather concrete goals. And it would be difficult to deny, for example, that these role-fulfilling individuals envisage certain specific outcomes which they hope to realize by pursuing a particular 1"Its most well-known and successful statement is found in Snyder et al., op.cit. Much of this model is utilized in the text which Snyder wrote with Edgar S. Furniss, Jr., American Foreign Policy: Formulation, Principles, and Programs, New York, I954. A more specific application is found in Snyder and Glenn D. Paige, "The United States Decision to Resist Aggression in Korea: The Application of an Analytical Scheme," Administrative Science Quarterly, iii (December I958), pp. 34i-78. For those interested in this approach, very useful is Paul Wasserman and Fred S. Silander, Decision-Mating: An Annotated Bibliography, Ithaca, N.Y., 1958. 12 And if the decision-making version of this model is employed, the issue is unavoidable. See the discussion of motivation in Snyder, Bruck, and Sapin, op.cit., pp. 92-I17; note that 25 of the 49 pages on "The Major Determinants of Action" are devoted to motives. This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE LEVEL-OF-ANALYSIS PROBLEM 85 strategy. In this sense, then, nations may b organisms which exhibit purposive behavior. However, purposiveness may be viewed in a somewhat different light, by asking whether it is not merely an intellectual construct that man imputes to himself by reason of his vain addiction to the free-will doctrine as he searches for characteristics which distinguish him from physical matter and the lower animals. And having attributed this conscious goal-pursuing behavior to himself as an individual, it may be argued that man then proceeds to project this attribute to the social organizations of which he is a member. The question would seem to distill down to whether man and his societies pursue goals of their own choosing or are moved toward those imposed upon them by forces which are primarily beyond their control.13 Another way of stating the dilemma would be to ask whether we are concerned with the ends which men and nations strive for or the ends toward which they are impelled by the past and present characteristics of their social and physical milieu. Obviously, we are using the terms "ends," "goals," and "purpose" in two rather distinct ways; one refers to those which are consciously envisaged and more or less rationally pursued, and the other to those of which the actor has little knowledge but toward which he is nevertheless propelled. Taking a middle ground in what is essentially a specific case of the free will vs. determinism debate, one can agree that nations move toward outcomes of which they have little knowledge and over which they have less control, but that they nevertheless do prefer, and therefore select, particular outcomes and attempt to realize them by conscious formulation of strategies. Also involved in the goal-seeking problem when we employ the nation-oriented model is the question of how and why certain nations pursue specific sorts of goals. While the question may be ignored in the system-oriented model or resolved by attributing identical goals to all national actors, the nation-as-actor approach demands that we investigate the processes by which national goals are selected, the internal and external factors that impinge on those processes, and the institutional framework from which they emerge. It is worthy of note that despite the strong predilection for the nation-oriented model in most 13 A highly suggestive, but more abstract treatment of this teleological question is in Talcott Parsons, The Structure of Social Action, 2nd ed., Glencoe, Ill., I949, especially in his analysis of Durkheim and Weber. It is interesting to note that for Parsons an act implies, inter alia, "a future state of affairs toward which the process of action is oriented," and he therefore comments that "in this sense and this sense only, the schema of action is inherently teleological" (p. 44). This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 86 THE INTERNATIONAL SYSTEM of our texts, empirical or even deductiv conspicuously few.'4 Again, one might methodological and conceptual inadequ which international relations specialist any event, goals and motivations are b variables, and if we intend to explain cannot settle for the mere postulation o to go back a step and inquire into the which they become the crucial variabl behavior of nations. There is still another dilemma involv nation-as-actor model, and that concer do we examine our actor's behavior in which allegedly influence that behavior, actor's perception of these "objective f proaches are not completely exclusive of greatly different and often incompat markedly divergent models of national b The first of these assumptions concern causation. One view holds that indivi quasi-deterministic fashion to the real the acts or power of other individuals o and "real" forces or stimuli. An oppos and groups are not influenced in their be but by the fashion in which these for however distorted or incomplete such per of this position, the only reality is the cerned by the human senses; forces that 14 Among the exceptions are Haas and Whitin the chapters in Roy C. Macridis, ed., Foreign Polic N.J., I958, especially that on West Germany by K 15 As early as I934, Edith E. Ware noted that ". . . no longer entirely a subject for political science sociology, geography-all the social sciences-are c understanding . . . of the international system." S in the United States, New York, 1934, p. 172. Fo Karl Deutsch, "The Place of Behavioral Sciences Relations," Behavioral Science, III (July 1958), Relevance of the Behavioral Sciences to the Stud (October i96i), pp. 324-35. 16 The father of phenomenological philosoph Edmund Husserl (i859-I938), author of Ideas: Gen ology, New York, 1931, trans. by W. R. Boyce Gib under the title Ideen zu einer reinen Phdnomen sophie. Application of this approach to social psych work of Koffka and Lewin. This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE LEVEL-OF-ANALYSIS PROBLEM 87 for that actor, and those that do exist do s they are perceived. Though it is difficult t individual, a group, or a nation is affected distance, or a neighbor's physical power on nized and appraised, one must concede that affect the manner in which such forces ar been pointed out, an individual will fall to out of a tenth-story window regardless of forces, but on the other hand such perception is a major factor in whether or not he steps out of the window in the first place."7 The point here is that if we embrace a phenomenological view of causation, we will tend to utilize a phenomenological model for explanatory purposes. The second assumption which bears on one's predilection for the phenomenological approach is more restricted, and is primarily a methodological one. Thus, it may be argued that any description of national behavior in a given international situation would be highly incomplete were it to ignore the link between the external forces at work upon the nation and its general foreign policy behavior. Furthermore, if our concern extends beyond the mere description of "what happens" to the realm of explanation, it could be contended that such omission of the cognitive and the perceptual linkage would be ontologically disastrous. How, it might be asked, can one speak of "causes" of a nation's policies when one has ignored the media by which external conditions and factors are translated into a policy decision? We may observe correlations between all sorts of forces in the international system and the behavior of nations, but their causal relationship must remain strictly deductive and hypothetical in the absence of empirical investigation into the causal chain which allegedly links the two. Therefore, even if we are satisfied with the less-than-complete descriptive capabilities of a non-phenomenological model, we are still drawn to it if we are to make any progress in explanation. The contrary view would hold that the above argument proceeds from an erroneous comprehension of the nature of explanation in social science. One is by no means required to trace every perception, transmission, and receipt between stimulus and response or input and output in order to explain the behavior of the nation or any other human group. Furthermore, who is to say that empirical observation-subject 17 This issue has been raised from time to time in all of the social sciences, but for an excellent discussion of it in terms of the present problem, see Harold and Margaret Sprout, Man-Milieu Relationship Hypotheses in the Context of International Politics, Princeton University, Center of International Studies, 1956, pp. 63-71. This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 88 THE INTERNATIONAL SYSTEM as it is to a host of errors-is any bett informed deduction, inference, or anal flows logically from a coherent theoretical model just as reliable as one based upon a misleading and elusive body of data, most of which is susceptible to analysis only by techniques and concepts foreign to political science and history? This leads, in turn, to the third of the premises relevant to one's stand on the phenomenological issue: are the dimensions and characteristics of the policy-makers' phenomenal field empirically discernible? Or, more accurately, even if we are convinced that their perceptions and beliefs constitute a crucial variable in the explanation of a nation's foreign policy, can they be observed in an accurate and systematic fashion ?18 Furthermore, are we not required by the phenomenological model to go beyond a classification and description of such variables, and be drawn into the tangled web of relationships out of which they emerge? If we believe that these phenomenal variables are systematically observable, are explainable, and can be fitted into our explanation of a nation's behavior in the international system, then there is a further tendency to embrace the phenomenological approach. If not, or if we are convinced that the gathering of such data is inefficient or uneconomical, we will tend to shy clear of it. The fourth issue in the phenomenological dispute concerns the very nature of the nation as an actor in international relations. Who or what is it that we study? Is it a distinct social entity with well-defined boundaries-a unity unto itself? Or is it an agglomeration of individuals, institutions, customs, and procedures? It should be quite evident that those who view the nation or the state as an integral social unit could not attach much utility to the phenomenological approach, particularly if they are prone to concretize or reify the abstraction. Such abstractions are incapable of perception, cognition, or anticipation (unless, of course, the reification goes so far as to anthropomorphize and assign to the abstraction such attributes as will, mind, or personality). On the other hand, if the nation or state is seen as a group of individuals operating within an institutional framework, then it makes perfect sense to focus on the phenomenal field of those individuals who participate in the policy-making process. In other words, people are capable of experiences, images, and expectations, while insti- 18This is another of the criticisms leveled at the decision-making approach which, almost by definition, seems compelled to adopt some form of the phenomenological model. For a comprehensive treatment of the elements involved in human perception, see Karl Zener et al., eds., "Inter-relationships Between Perception and Personality: A Symposium," Journal of Personality, xviii (1949), pp. I-266. This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE LEVEL-OF-ANALYSIS PROBLEM 89 tutional abstractions are not, except in the our actor cannot even have a phenomenal field, there is little point in employing a phenomenological approach.19 These, then, are some of the questions around which the phenomenological issue would seem to revolve. Those of us who think of social forces as operative regardless of the actor's awareness, who believe that explanation need not include all of the steps in a causal chain, who are dubious of the practicality of gathering phenomenal data, or who visualize the nation as a distinct entity apart from its individual members, will tend to reject the phenomenological approach.20 Logically, only those who disagree with each of the above four assumptions would be compelled to adopt the approach. Disagreement with any one would be sufficient grounds for so doing. The above represent some of the more significant implications and fascinating problems raised by the adoption of our second model. They seem to indicate that this sub-systemic orientation is likely to produce richer description and more satisfactory (from the empiricist's point of view) explanation of international relations, though its predictive power would appear no greater than the systemic orientation. But the descriptive and explanatory advantages are achieved only at the price of considerable methodological complexity. IV. CONCLUSION Having discussed some of the descriptive, explanatory, and predictive capabilities of these two possible levels of analysis, it might now be useful to assess the relative utility of the two and attempt some general statement as to their prospective contributions to greater theoretical growth in the study of international relations. In terms of description, we find that the systemic level produces a more comprehensive and total picture of international relations than does the national or sub-systemic level. On the other hand, the atomized and less coherent image produced by the lower level of analysis is somewhat balanced by its richer detail, greater depth, and more intensive portrayal.21 As to explanation, there seems little doubt that the sub- 19 Many of these issues are raised in the ongoing debate over "methodological individualism," and are discussed cogently in Ernest Nagel, The Structure of Science, New York, i96i, pp. 535-46. 20 Parenthetically, holders of these specific views should also be less inclined to adopt the national or sub-systemic model in the first place. 21In a review article dealing with two of the more recent and provocative efforts toward theory (Morton A. Kaplan, System and Process in International Politics, New York, 1957, and George Liska, International Equilibrium, Cambridge, Mass., 1957), Charles P. Kindleberger adds a further-if not altogether persuasive-argument in favor This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 90 THE INTERNATIONAL SYSTEM systemic or actor orientation is consider as it does a more thorough investigati foreign policies are made. Here we are en tions imposed by the systemic level and t the more significant causation. And in te tions seem to offer a similar degree o function of what we seek to predict. Th to prefer predictions about the way in w to a contemplated move on his own na will probably prefer either generalized havior of a given class of nations or tho Does this summary add up to an over of the two models? It would seem no reasons the scholar may be more interes any given time and will undoubtedly shi his research needs. So the problem is rea level is most valuable to the discipline that it be adhered to from now unto e realizing that there is this preliminary c be temporarily resolved prior to any giv it must also be stressed that we have d more common orientations, and that perhaps even more fruitful potentially here. Moreover, the international syst prospective change, and it may well be t will take on new characteristics or tha their place. As a matter of fact, if incap leads to the transformation or decay of steady deterioration and even ultimat state as a significant actor in the world However, even if the case for one or of analysis cannot be made with any cer maintain a continuing awareness as to level here and another there, but we can tion in the midst of a study. And when of the lower, sub-systemic level of analysis: "The everything interacting. One can discuss it intell "Scientific International Politics," World Politic 22 It should also be kept in mind that one cou model which successfully embraces both of thes conceptual clarity and internal consistency. In thi to date, though Kaplan's System and Process in fairly close. This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms THE LEVEL-OF-ANALYSIS PROBLEM 91 selection or replace one with another at approp so with a full awareness of the descriptive, exp implications of such choice. A final point remains to be discussed. Despite one might still be prone to inquire whether th exercise in verbal gymnastics. What, it might b between the two levels of analysis if the em essentially the same? Or, to put it another way between international relations and comparat haps a few illustrations will illuminate the subt ences which emerge when one's level of analysi example, postulate that when the international by political conflict between two of its most p a strong tendency for the system to bipolarize. T proposition. A sub-systemic proposition, dealin empirical referents, would state that when a po in political conflict with another of approxima exert pressure on its weaker neighbors to join it tion, assuming it is true, is theoretically usef verified by a different intellectual operation the crucial thing for theoretical development-o two kinds of statements together to achieve empirical generalizations. To illustrate further, one could, at the system when the distribution of power in the internat diffused, it is more stable than when the disce defined coalitions occurs. And at the sub-sys the same empirical phenomena would produce t when a nation's decision-makers find it diffi nations readily as friend or foe, they tend t more uniform and moderate fashion. Now, t propositions, how much cumulative usefulne tempting to merge and codify the systemic pr illustration with the sub-systemic proposition versa? Representing different levels of analysis frames of reference, they would defy theoreti well be a corollary of the other, but they ar binable. A prior translation from one level to a This, it is submitted, is quite crucial for the t of our discipline. With all of the current empha empirical and data-gathering research as a prer This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 92 THE INTERNATIONAL SYSTEM ing, one finds little concern with the re and discrete data-gathering activities. Even if we were to declare a moratorium on deductive and speculative research for the next decade, and all of us were to labor diligently in the vineyards of historical and contemporary data, the state of international relations theory would probably be no more advanced at that time than it is now, unless such empirical activity becomes far more systematic. And "systematic" is used here to indicate the cumulative growth of inductive and deductive generalizations into an impressive array of statements conceptually related to one another and flowing from some common frame of reference. What that frame of reference should be, or will be, cannot be said with much certainty, but it does seem clear that it must exist. As long as we evade some of these crucial a priori decisions, our empiricism will amount to little more than an ever-growing potpourri of discrete, disparate, non-comparable, and isolated bits of information or extremely low-level generalizations. And, as such, they will make little contribution to the growth of a theory of international relations. This content downloaded from 147.251.109.95 on Thu, 20 Sep 2018 09:17:35 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms