CHAPTER 3 Politics and the State ‘The purpose of the State is always the same: to limit the individual, to tame him, to subordinate him, to subjugate him.’ MA X ST I R N E R , The Ego and His Own (1845) P R E V I E W The shadow of the state falls on almost every human activity. From education to economic management, from social welfare to sanitation, and from domestic order to external defence, the state shapes and controls; where it does not shape or control it regulates, supervises, authorizes or proscribes. Even those aspects of life usually thought of as personal or private (marriage, divorce, abortion, religious worship and so on) are ultimately subject to the authority of the state. It is not surprising, therefore, that politics is often understood as the study of the state, the analysis of its institutional organizations, the evaluation of its impact on society and so on. Ideological debate and party politics, certainly, tend to revolve around the issue of the proper function or role of the state: what should be done by the state and what should be left to private individuals and associations? The nature of state power has thus become one of the central concerns of political analysis. This chapter examines the feature that are usually associated with the state, from both a domestic and an international perspective. It considers the issue of the nature of state power, and, in the process, touches on some of the deepest and most abiding divisions in political theory. This leads to a discussion of the contrasting roles and responsibilities of the state and the different forms that states have assumed. Finally, it looks whether, in the light of globalization and other developments, the state is losing its central importance in politics. K E Y I S S U E S What is the state, and why does it play such a crucial role in politics? How has state power been analysed and explained? Is the state a force for good or a force for evil? What roles have been assigned to the state? How have responsibilities been apportioned between the state and civil society? To what extent does politics now operate outside or beyond the state? DEFINING THE STATE The term ‘state’ has been used to refer to a bewildering range of things: a collection of institutions, a territorial unit, a philosophical idea, an instrument of coercion or oppression, and so on. This confusion stems, in part, from the fact that the state has been understood in four quite different ways; from an idealist perspective, a functionalist perspective, an organizational perspective and an international perspective. The idealist approach to the state is most clearly reflected in the writings of G. W. F. Hegel (see p. 59). Hegel identified three ‘moments’ of social existence: the family, civil society and the state. Within the family, he argued, a ‘particular altruism’ operates that encourages people to set aside their own interests for the good of their children or elderly relatives. In contrast, civil society was seen as a sphere of ‘universal egoism’ in which individuals place their own interests before those of others. Hegel conceived of the state as an ethical community underpinned by mutual sympathy – ‘universal altruism’. The drawback of idealism, however, is that it fosters an uncritical reverence for the state and, by defining the state in ethical terms, fails to distinguish clearly between institutions that are part of the state and those that are outside the state. Functionalist approaches to the state focus on the role or purpose of state institutions. The central function of the state is invariably seen as the maintenance of social order (see p. 400), the state being defined as that set of institutions that uphold order and deliver social stability. Such an approach has, for example, been adopted by neo-Marxists (see p. 64), who have been inclined to see the state as a mechanism through which class conflict is ameliorated to ensure the long-term survival of the capitalist system. The weakness of the functionalist view of the state, however, is that it tends to associate any institution that maintains order (such as the family, mass media, trade unions and the church) with the state itself. This is why, unless there is a statement to the contrary, an organizational approach to the definition of the state is adopted throughout this book The organizational view defines the state as the apparatus of government in its broadest sense; that is, as that set of institutions that are recognizably ‘public’, in that they are responsible for the collective organization of social existence and are funded at the public’s expense. The virtue of this definition is that it distinguishes clearly between the state and civil society (see p. 6). The state comprises the various institutions of government: the bureaucracy (see p. 361), the military, the police, the courts, the social security system and so on; it can be identified with the entire ‘body politic’. The organizational approach allows us to talk about ‘rolling forward’ or ‘rolling back’ the state, in the sense of expanding or contracting the responsibilities of the state, and enlarging or diminishing its institutional machinery. In this light, it is possible to identify five key features of the state: The state is sovereign. It exercises absolute and unrestricted power, in that it stands above all other associations and groups in society. Thomas Hobbes (see p. 61) conveyed the idea of sovereignty (see p. 58) by portraying the state as a ‘leviathan’, a gigantic monster, usually represented as a sea creature. State institutions are recognizably ‘public’, in contrast to the ‘private’ institutions of civil society. Public bodies are responsible for making and P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 57 CONCEPT The state The state is a political association that establishes sovereign jurisdiction within defined territorial borders, and exercises authority through a set of permanent institutions. These institutions are those that are recognizably ‘public’, in that they are responsible for the collective organization of communal life, and are funded at the public’s expense. The state thus embraces the various institutions of government, but it also extends to the courts, nationalized industries, social security system, and so forth; it can be identified with the entire ‘body politic’. Idealism: A view of politics that emphasizes the importance of morality and ideals; philosophical idealism implies that ideas are more ‘real’ than the material world. Civil society: A private sphere of autonomous groups and associations, independent from state or public authority (see p. 6). enforcing collective decisions, while private bodies, such as families, private businesses and trade unions, exist to satisfy individual interests. The state is an exercise in legitimation. The decisions of the state are usually (although not necessarily) accepted as binding on the members of society because, it is claimed, they are made in the public interest, or for common good; the state supposedly reflects the permanent interests of society. The state is an instrument of domination. State authority is backed up by coercion; the state must have the capacity to ensure that its laws are obeyed and that transgressors are punished. For Max Weber (see p. 82), the state was defined by its monopoly of the means of ‘legitimate violence’. The state is a territorial association. The jurisdiction of the state is geographically defined, and it encompasses all those who live within the state’s borders, whether they are citizens or non-citizens. On the international stage, the state is therefore regarded (at least, in theory) as an autonomous entity. The international approach to the state views it primarily as an actor on the world stage; indeed, as the basic ‘unit’ of international politics. This highlights the dualistic structure of the state; the fact that it has two faces, one looking outwards and the other looking inwards. Whereas the previous definitions are concerned with the state’s inward-looking face, its relations with the individuals and groups that live within its borders, and its ability to maintain domestic order, the international view deals with the state’s outward-looking face, its relations with other states and, therefore, its ability to provide protection against external attack. The classic definition of the state in international law is found in the Montevideo Convention on the Rights and Duties of the State (1933). According to Article 1 of the Montevideo Convention, the state has four features: a defined territory a permanent population an effective government the capacity to enter into relations with other states. This approach to the state brings it very close to the notion of a‘country’. The main difference between how the state is understood by political philosophers and sociologists, and how it is understood by IR scholars is that while the former treat civil society as separate from the state, the latter treat civil society as part of the state, in that it encompasses not only an effective government, but also a permanent population. For some, the international approach views the state essentially as a legal person, in which case statehood depends on formal recognition by other states or international bodies. In this view, the United Nations (UN) is widely accepted as the body that, by granting full membership, determines when a new state has come into existence. Nevertheless, while, from this perspective, states may be legally equal, they are in political terms very different. Although their rights and responsibilities as laid out in international law may be identical, their political weight in world affairs varies dramatically. Some states are classified as‘great powers’, or even‘superpowers’ (see p. 422), whereas others are ‘middle’ or ‘small’ powers and, in cases such as the small highland countries of the Caribbean and the Pacific, they may be regarded as ‘micro-states’. 58 P O L I T I C S Great power: A state deemed to rank amongst the most powerful in a hierarchical state system, reflecting its influence over minor states. CONCEPT Sovereignty Sovereignty, in its simplest sense, is the principle of absolute and unlimited power. However, sovereignty can be understood in different ways. Legal sovereignty refers to supreme legal authority, defined in terms of the ‘right’ to command compliance, while political sovereignty refers to absolute political power, defined in terms of the ‘ability’ to command compliance. Internal sovereignty is the notion of supreme power/authority within the state (e.g. parliamentary sovereignty: see p. 336). External sovereignty relates to a state’s place in the international order and its capacity to act as an independent and autonomous entity. P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 59 Regardless of the different ways in which the state has been understood, there is general agreement about when and where it emerged. The state is a historical institution: it emerged in sixteenth- and seventeenth-century Europe as a system of centralized rule that succeeded in subordinating all other institutions and groups, including (and especially) the Church, bringing an end to the competing and overlapping authority systems that had characterized Medieval Europe. By establishing the principle of territorial sovereignty, the Peace of Westphalia (1648), concluded at the end of the Thirty Years’ War, is often taken to have formalized the modern notion of statehood, by establishing the state as the principal actor in domestic and international affairs. There is less agreement, however, about why the state came into existence. According to Charles Tilly (1990), for instance, the central factor that explains the development of the modern state was its ability to fight wars. In this view, the transformation in the scale and nature of military encounters that was brought about from the sixteenth century onwards (through, for instance, the introduction of gun powder, the use of organized infantry and artillery, and the advent of standing armies) not only greatly increased the coercive power that rulers could wield, but also forced states to extend their control over their populations by developing more extensive systems of taxation and administration. As Tilly (1975) thus put it, ‘War made the state, and the state made war’. Marxists, in contrast, have explained the emergence of the state largely in economic terms, the state’s origins being traced back to the transition from feudalism to capitalism, with the state essentially being a tool used by the emerging bourgeois class (Engels, [1884] 1972). Michael Mann (1993), for his part, offered an account of the emergence of the state that stresses the state’s capacity to combine ideological, economic, military and political forms of power (sometimes called the ‘IEMP model’). The state nevertheless continued to evolve in the light of changing circumstances. Having developed into the nation-state during the nineteenth century, and then going through a process of gradual democratization, the state acquired wider economic and social responsibilities during the twentieth century, and especially in the post-1945 period, only for these, in many cases, to be ‘rolled back’ from the 1980s and 1990s. The European state model, furthermore, spread Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel (1770–1831) German philosopher. Hegel was the founder of modern idealism and developed the notion that consciousness and material objects are, in fact, unified. In Phenomenology of Spirit (1807), he sought to develop a rational system that would substitute for traditional Christianity by interpreting the entire process of human history, and indeed the universe itself, in terms of the progress of absolute Mind towards selfrealization. In his view, history is, in essence, a march of the human spirit towards a determinate endpoint. His major political work, Philosophy of Right (1821), portrays the state as an ethical ideal and the highest expression of human freedom. Hegel’s work had a considerable impact on Marx and other so-called ‘young Hegelians’. It also shaped the ideas of liberals such as T. H. Green (1836–82), and influenced fascist thought. Nation-state: A sovereign political association within which citizenship and nationality overlap; one nation within a single state (see p. 124). to other lands and other continents. This occurred as the process of decolonization accelerated in the decades following World War II, independence implying the achievement of sovereign statehood. One result of this process was a rapid growth in UN membership. From its original 51 member states in 1945, the UN grew to 127 members by 1970, and reached 193 members by 2011 (with the recognition of South Sudan). The state has therefore become the universal form of political organization around the world. However, in order to assess the significance of the state, and explore its vital relationship to politics, two key issues have to be addressed. These deal with the nature of state power and with the roles and responsibilities the state has assumed and should assume. DEBATING THE STATE Rival theories of the state What is the nature of state power, and whose interests does the state represent? From this perspective, the state is an ‘essentially contested’ concept. There are various rival theories of the state, each of which offers a different account of its origins, development and impact on society. Indeed, controversy about the nature of state power has increasingly dominated modern political analysis and goes to the heart of ideological and theoretical disagreements in the discipline. These relate to questions about whether, for example, the state is autonomous and independent of society, or whether it is essentially a product of society, a reflection of the broader distribution of power or resources. Moreover, does the state serve the common or collective good, or is it biased in favour of privileged groups or a dominant class? Similarly, is the state a positive or constructive force, with responsibilities that should be enlarged, or is it a negative or destructive entity that must be constrained or, perhaps, smashed altogether? Four contrasting theories of the state can be identified as follows: the pluralist state the capitalist state the leviathan state the patriarchal state. The pluralist state The pluralist theory of the state has a very clear liberal lineage. It stems from the belief that the state acts as an ‘umpire’ or ‘referee’ in society. This view has also dominated mainstream political analysis, accounting for a tendency, at least within Anglo-American thought, to discount the state and state organizations and focus instead on‘government’. Indeed, it is not uncommon in this tradition for‘the state’ to be dismissed as an abstraction, with institutions such as the courts, the civil service and the military being seen as independent actors in their own right, rather than as elements of a broader state machine. Nevertheless, this approach is possible only because it is based on underlying, and often unacknowledged, assumptions about state neutrality. The state can be ignored only because it is seen as an impartial arbiter or referee that can be bent to the will of the government of the day. 60 P O L I T I C S Pluralism: A belief in, or commitment to diversity or multiplicity; or the belief that power in modern societies is widely and evenly distributed (see p. 100). The origins of this view of the state can be traced back to the social-contract theories (see p. 62) of thinkers such as Thomas Hobbes and John Locke (see p. 31). The principal concern of such thinkers was to examine the grounds of political obligation, the grounds on which the individual is obliged to obey and respect the state. They argued that the state had arisen out of a voluntary agreement, or social contract, made by individuals who recognized that only the establishment of a sovereign power could safeguard them from the insecurity, disorder and brutality of the state of nature. Without a state, individuals abuse, exploit and enslave one another; with a state, order and civilized existence are guaranteed and liberty is protected. As Locke put it, ‘where there is no law there is no freedom’. In liberal theory, the state is thus seen as a neutral arbiter amongst the competing groups and individuals in society; it is an ‘umpire’ or ‘referee’ that is capable of protecting each citizen from the encroachments of fellow citizens. The neutrality of the state reflects the fact that the state acts in the interests of all citizens, and therefore represents the common good or public interest. In Hobbes’ view, stability and order could be secured only through the establishment of an absolute and unlimited state, with power that could be neither challenged, nor questioned. In other words, he held that citizens are confronted by a stark choice between absolutism (see p. 268) and anarchy. Locke, on the other hand, developed a more typically liberal defence of the limited state. In his view, the purpose of the state is very specific: it is restricted to the defence of a set of ‘natural’ or God-given individual rights; namely, ‘life, liberty and property’. This establishes a clear distinction between the responsibilities of the state (essentially, the maintenance of domestic order and the protection of property) and the responsibilities of individual citizens (usually seen as the realm of civil society). Moreover, since the state may threaten natural rights as easily as it may uphold them, citizens must enjoy some form of protection against the state, which Locke believed could be delivered only through the mechanisms of constitutional and representative government. These ideas were developed in the twentieth century into the pluralist theory of the state. As a theory of society, pluralism asserts that, within liberal democracies, power is widely and evenly dispersed. As a theory of the state, pluralism holds that the state is neutral, insofar as it is susceptible to the influence of P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 61 Divine right: The doctrine that earthly rulers are chosen by God and thus wield unchallengeable authority; a defence for monarchical absolutism. Political obligation: The duty of the citizen towards the state; the basis of the state’s right to rule. State of nature: A society devoid of political authority and of formal (legal) checks on the individual; usually employed as a theoretical device. Anarchy: Literally, ‘without rule’; anarchy is often used pejoratively to suggest instability, or even chaos. Thomas Hobbes (1588–1679) English political philosopher. Hobbes was the son of a minor clergyman who subsequently abandoned his family. He became tutor to the exiled Prince of Wales Charles Stewart, and lived under the patronage of the Cavendish family. Writing at a time of uncertainty and civil strife, precipitated by the English Revolution, Hobbes developed the first comprehensive theory of nature and human behaviour since Aristotle (see p. 6). His classic work, Leviathan (1651), discussed the grounds of political obligation and undoubtedly reflected the impact of the CivilWar. It provided a defence for absolutist government but, by appealing to reasoned argument in the form of the social contract, also disappointed advocates of divine right. 62 P O L I T I C S various groups and interests, and all social classes. The state is not biased in favour of any particular interest or group, and it does not have an interest of its own that is separate from those of society. As Schwarzmantel (1994) put it, the state is ‘the servant of society and not its master’. The state can thus be portrayed as a ‘pincushion’ that passively absorbs pressures and forces exerted upon it. Two key assumptions underlie this view. The first is that the state is effectively subordinate to government. Non-elected state bodies (the civil service, the judiciary, the police, the military and so on) are strictly impartial and are subject to the authority of their political masters. The state apparatus is therefore thought to conform to the principles of public service and political accountability. The second assumption is that the democratic process is meaningful and effective. In other words, party competition and interest-group activity ensure that the government of the day remains sensitive and responsive to public opinion. Ultimately, therefore, the state is only a weather vane that is blown in whichever direction the public-at-large dictates. Modern pluralists, however, have often adopted a more critical view of the state, termed the neopluralist (see p. 63) theory of the state. Theorists such as Robert Dahl (see p. 250), Charles Lindblom and J. K. Galbraith (see p. 155) have come to accept that modern industrialized states are both more complex and less responsive to popular pressures than classical pluralism suggested. Neopluralists, for instance, have acknowledged that business enjoys a ‘privileged position’ in relation to government that other groups clearly cannot rival. In Politics and Markets (1980), Lindblom pointed out that, as the major investor and largest employer in society, business is bound to exercise considerable sway over any government, whatever its ideological leanings or manifesto commitments. Moreover, neopluralists have accepted that the state can, and does, forge its own sectional interests. In this way, a state elite, composed of senior civil servants, Focus on . . . Social-contract theory A social contract is a voluntary agreement made amongst individuals through which an organized society, or state, is brought into existence. Used as a theoretical device by thinkers such as Hobbes, Locke and Rousseau (see p. 97), the social contract has been revived by modern theorists such as John Rawls (see p. 45). The social contract is seldom regarded as a historical act. Rather, it is used as a means of demonstrating the value of government and the grounds of political obligation; social-contract theorists wish individuals to act as if they had concluded the contract themselves. In its classic form, social-contract theory has three elements: The image of a hypothetical stateless society (a ‘state of nature’) is established. Unconstrained freedom means that life is ‘solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short’ (Hobbes). Individuals therefore seek to escape from the state of nature by entering into a social contract, recognizing that only a sovereign power can secure order and stability. The social contract obliges citizens to respect and obey the state, ultimately in gratitude for the stability and security that only a system of political rule can deliver. judges, police chiefs, military leaders and so on, may be seen to pursue either the bureaucratic interests of their sector of the state, or the interests of client groups. Indeed, if the state is regarded as a political actor in its own right, it can be viewed as a powerful (perhaps the most powerful) interest group in society. This line of argument encouraged Eric Nordlinger (1981) to develop a state-centred model of liberal democracy, based on ‘the autonomy of the democratic state’. The capitalist state The Marxist notion of a capitalist state offers a clear alternative to the pluralist image of the state as a neutral arbiter or umpire. Marxists have typically argued that the state cannot be understood separately from the economic structure of society. This view has usually been understood in terms of the classic formulation that the state is nothing but an instrument of class oppression: the state emerges out of, and in a sense reflects, the class system. Nevertheless, a rich debate has taken place within Marxist theory in recent years that has moved the Marxist theory of the state a long way from this classic formulation. In many ways, the scope to revise Marxist attitudes towards the state stems from ambiguities that can be found in Marx’s (see p. 41) own writings. Marx did not develop a systematic or coherent theory of the state. In a general sense, he believed that the state is part of a ‘superstructure’ that is determined or conditioned by the economic ‘base’, which can be seen as the real foundation of social life. However, the precise relationship between the base and the superstructure, and in this case that between the state and the capitalist mode of production, is unclear. Two theories of the state can be identified in Marx’s writings. The first is expressed in his often-quoted dictum from The Communist Manifesto ([1848] 1967): ‘The executive of the modern state is but a committee for managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie’. From this perspective, the state is clearly dependent on society and entirely dependent on its economically dominant class, which in capitalism is the bourgeoisie. Lenin (see p. 99) thus described the state starkly as ‘an instrument for the oppression of the exploited class’. A second, more complex and subtle, theory of the state can nevertheless be found in Marx’s analysis of the revolutionary events in France between 1848 and 1851, The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte ([1852] 1963). Marx suggested that the state could enjoy what has come to be seen as ‘relative autonomy’ from the class system, the Napoleonic state being capable of imposing its will upon society, acting as an ‘appalling parasitic body’. If the state did articulate the interests of any class, it was not those of the bourgeoisie, but those of the most populous class in French society, the smallholding peasantry. Although Marx did not develop this view in detail, it is clear that, from this perspective, the autonomy of the state is only relative, in that the state appears to mediate between conflicting classes, and so maintains the class system itself in existence. Both these theories differ markedly from the liberal and, later, pluralist models of state power. In particular, they emphasize that the state cannot be understood except in a context of unequal class power, and that the state arises out of, and reflects, capitalist society, by acting either as an instrument of oppression wielded by the dominant class, or, more subtly, as a mechanism through which class antagonisms are ameliorated. Nevertheless, Marx’s attitude towards P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 63 CONCEPT Neopluralism Neopluralism is a style of social theorizing that remains faithful to pluralist values while recognizing the need to revise or update classical pluralism in the light of, for example, elite, Marxist and New Right theories. Although neopluralism embraces a broad range of perspectives and positions, certain central themes can be identified. First, it takes account of modernizing trends, such as the emergence of postindustrial society. Second, while capitalism is preferred to socialism, free-market economic doctrines are usually regarded as obsolete. Third, western democracies are seen as ‘deformed polyarchies’, in which major corporations exert disproportionate influence. Bourgeoisie: A Marxist term, denoting the ruling class of a capitalist society, the owners of productive wealth. the state was not entirely negative. He argued that the state could be used constructively during the transition from capitalism to communism in the form of the ‘revolutionary dictatorship of the proletariat’. The overthrow of capitalism would see the destruction of the bourgeois state and the creation of an alternative, proletarian one. In describing the state as a proletarian ‘dictatorship’, Marx utilized the first theory of the state, seeing the state as an instrument through which the economically dominant class (by then, the proletariat) could repress and subdue other classes. All states, from this perspective, are class dictatorships. The ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’ was seen as a means of safeguarding the gains of the revolution by preventing counter-revolution mounted by the dispossessed bourgeoisie. Nevertheless, Marx did not see the state as a necessary or enduring social formation. He predicted that, as class antagonisms faded, the state would ‘wither away’, meaning that a fully communist society would also be stateless. Since the state emerged out of the class system, once the class system had been abolished, the state, quite simply, loses its reason for existence. Marx’s ambivalent heritage has provided modern Marxists, or neo-Marxists, with considerable scope to further the analysis of state power. This was also encouraged by the writings of Antonio Gramsci (see p. 175), who emphasized the degree to which the domination of the ruling class is achieved by ideological manipulation, rather than just open coercion. In this view, bourgeois domination is maintained largely through ‘hegemony’ (see p. 174): that is, intellectual leadership or cultural control, with the state playing an important role in the process. Since the 1960s, Marxist theorizing about the state has been dominated by rival instrumentalist and structuralist views of the state. In The State in Capitalist Society ([1969] 2009), Miliband portrayed the state as an agent or instrument of the ruling class, stressing the extent to which the state elite is disproportionately drawn from the ranks of the privileged and propertied. The bias of the state in favour of capitalism is therefore derived from the overlap of social backgrounds between, on the one hand, civil servants and other public officials, and, on the other, bankers, business leaders and captains of industry. Nicos Poulantzas, in Political Power and Social Classes (1968), dismissed this sociological approach, and emphasized instead the degree to which the structure of economic and social power exerts a constraint on state autonomy. This view suggests that the state cannot but act to perpetuate the social system in which it operates. In the case of the capitalist state, its role is to serve the long-term interests of capitalism, even though these actions may be resisted by sections of the capitalist class itself. NeoMarxists have increasingly seen the state as the terrain on which the struggle amongst interests, groups and classes is conducted. Rather than being an ‘instrument’ wielded by a dominant group or ruling class, the state is thus a dynamic entity that reflects the balance of power within society at any given time, and the ongoing struggle for hegemony. The leviathan state The image of the state as a ‘leviathan’ (in effect, a self-serving monster intent on expansion and aggrandizement) is one associated in modern politics with the New Right. Such a view is rooted in early or classical liberalism and, in particular, 64 P O L I T I C S Proletariat: A Marxist term, denoting a class that subsists through the sale of its labour power; strictly speaking, the proletariat is not equivalent to the working class. CONCEPT Neo-Marxism Neo-Marxism (sometimes termed ‘modern’ or ‘western’ Marxism) refers to attempts to revise or recast the classical ideas of Marx while remaining faithful to certain Marxist principles or aspects of Marxist methodology. Neo-Marxists typically refuse to accept that Marxism enjoys a monopoly of the truth, and have thus looked to Hegelian philosophy, anarchism, liberalism, feminism, and even rational-choice theory. Although still concerned about social injustice, neo-Marxists reject the primacy of economics over other factors and, with it, the notion that history has a predictable character. a commitment to a radical form of individualism (see p. 158). The New Right, or at least its neoliberal wing, is distinguished by a strong antipathy towards state intervention in economic and social life, born out of the belief that the state is a parasitic growth that threatens both individual liberty and economic security. In this view, the state, instead of being, as pluralists suggest, an impartial umpire or arbiter, is an overbearing‘nanny’, desperate to interfere or meddle in every aspect of human existence. The central feature of this view is that the state pursues interests that are separate from those of society (setting it apart from Marxism), and that those interests demand an unrelenting growth in the role or responsibilities of the state itself. New Right thinkers therefore argue that the twentiethcentury tendency towards state intervention reflected not popular pressure for economic and social security, or the need to stabilize capitalism by ameliorating class tensions but, rather, the internal dynamics of the state. New Right theorists explain the expansionist dynamics of state power by reference to both demand-side and supply-side pressures. Demand-side pressures are those that emanate from society itself, usually through the mechanism of electoral democracy. As discussed in Chapter 4 in connection with democracy, the New Right argue that electoral competition encourages politicians to‘outbid’ one another by making promises of increased spending and more generous government programmes, regardless of the long-term damage that such policies inflict on the economy in the form of increased taxes, higher inflation and the ‘crowding out’ of investment. Supply-side pressures, on the other hand, are those that are internal to the state. These can therefore be explained in terms of the institutions and personnel of the state apparatus. In its most influential form, this argument is known as the ‘government oversupply thesis’. The oversupply thesis has usually been associated with public-choice theorists (see p. 252), who examine how public decisions are made on the assumption that the individuals involved act in a rationally self-interested fashion. Niskanen (1971), for example, argued that, as budgetary control in legislatures such as the US Congress is typically weak, the task of budget-making is shaped largely by the interests of government agencies and senior bureaucrats. Insofar as this implies that government is dominated by the state (the state elite being able to shape the thinking of elected politicians), there are parallels between the public-choice model and the Marxist view discussed above. Where these two views diverge, however, is in relation to the interests that the state apparatus serves. While Marxists argue that the state reflects broader class and other social interests, the New Right portrays the state as an independent or autonomous entity that pursues its own interests. In this view, bureaucratic self-interest invariably supports‘big’ government and state intervention, because this leads to an enlargement of the bureaucracy itself, which helps to ensure job security, improve pay, open up promotion prospects and enhance the status of public officials. This image of self-seeking bureaucrats is plainly at odds with the pluralist notion of a state machine imbued with an ethic of public service and firmly subject to political control. The patriarchal state Modern thinking about the state must, finally, take account of the implications of feminist theory. However, this is not to say that there is a systematic feminist P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 65 CONCEPT Patriarchy Patriarchy literally means ‘rule by the father’, the domination of the husband–father within the family, and the subordination of his wife and his children. However, the term is usually used in the more general sense of ‘rule by men’, drawing attention to the totality of oppression and exploitation to which women are subject. Patriarchy thus implies that the system of male power in society at large both reflects and stems from the dominance of the father in the family. Patriarchy is a key concept in radical feminist analysis, in that it emphasizes that gender inequality is systematic, institutionalized and pervasive. theory of the state. As emphasized in Chapter 2, feminist theory encompasses a range of traditions and perspectives, and has thus generated a range of very different attitudes towards state power. Moreover, feminists have usually not regarded the nature of state power as a central political issue, preferring instead to concentrate on the deeper structure of male power centred on institutions such as the family and the economic system. Some feminists, indeed, may question conventional definitions of the state, arguing, for instance, that the idea that the state exercises a monopoly of legitimate violence is compromised by the routine use of violence and intimidation in family and domestic life. Nevertheless, sometimes implicitly and sometimes explicitly, feminists have helped to enrich the state debate by developing novel and challenging perspectives on state power. Liberal feminists, who believe that sexual or gender (see p. 163) equality can be brought about through incremental reform, have tended to accept an essentially pluralist view of the state. They recognize that, if women are denied legal and political equality, and especially the right to vote, the state is biased in favour of men. However, their faith in the state’s basic neutrality is reflected in the belief that any such bias can, and will, be overcome by a process of reform. In this sense, liberal feminists believe that all groups (including women) have potentially equal access to state power, and that this can be used impartially to promote justice and the common good. Liberal feminists have therefore usually viewed the state in positive terms, seeing state intervention as a means of redressing gender inequality and enhancing the role of women. This can be seen in campaigns for equal-pay legislation, the legalization of abortion, the provision of child-care facilities, the extension of welfare benefits, and so on. Nevertheless, a more critical and negative view of the state has been developed by radical feminists, who argue that state power reflects a deeper structure of oppression in the form of patriarchy. There are a number of similarities between Marxist and radical feminist views of state power. Both groups, for example, deny that the state is an autonomous entity bent on the pursuit of its own interests. Instead, the state is understood, and its biases are explained, by reference to a ‘deep structure’ of power in society at large. Whereas Marxists place the state in an economic context, radical feminists place it in a context of gender inequality, and insist that it is essentially an institution of male power. In common with Marxism, distinctive instrumentalist and structuralistversions of this feminist position have been developed. The instrumentalist argument views the state as little more than an agent or ‘tool’ used by men to defend their own interests and uphold the structures of patriarchy. This line of argument draws on the core feminist belief that patriarchy is rooted in the division of society into distinct ‘public’ and ‘private’ spheres of life, men dominating the former while women are confined to the later. Quite simply, in this view, the state is run by men, and for men. Whereas instrumentalist arguments focus on the personnel of the state, and particularly the state elite, structuralist arguments tend to emphasize the degree to which state institutions are embedded in a wider patriarchal system. Modern radical feminists have paid particular attention to the emergence of the welfare state, seeing it as the expression of a new kind of patriarchal power. Welfare may uphold patriarchy by bringing about a transition from private dependence (in which women as ‘home makers’ are dependent on men as ‘breadwinners’) to a 66 P O L I T I C S system of public dependence in which women are increasingly controlled by the institutions of the extended state. For instance, women have become increasingly dependent on the state as clients or customers of state services (such as childcare institutions, nursery education and social work) and as employees, particularly in the so-called ‘caring’ professions (such as nursing, social work and education). The role of the state Contrasting interpretations of state power have clear implications for the desirable role or responsibilities of the state. What should states do? What functions or responsibilities should the state fulfil, and which ones should be left in the hands of private individuals? In many respects, these are the questions around which electoral politics and party competition revolve. With the exception of anarchists, who dismiss the state as fundamentally evil and unnecessary, all political thinkers have regarded the state as, in some sense, worthwhile. Even revolutionary socialists, inspired by the Leninist slogan ‘smash the state’, have accepted the need for a temporary proletarian state to preside over the transition from capitalism to communism, in the form of the ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’. Nevertheless, there is profound disagreement about the exact role the state should play, and therefore about the proper balance between the state and civil society. Among the different state forms that have developed are the following: minimal states developmental states social-democratic states collectivized states totalitarian states religious states Minimal states The minimal state is the ideal of classical liberals, whose aim is to ensure that individuals enjoy the widest possible realm of freedom. This view is rooted in social-contract theory, but it nevertheless advances an essentially ‘negative’ view of the state. From this perspective, the value of the state is that it has the capacity to constrain human behaviour and thus to prevent individuals encroaching on the rights and liberties of others. The state is merely a protective body, its core function being to provide a framework of peace and social order within which citizens can conduct their lives as they think best. In Locke’s famous simile, the state acts as a nightwatchman, whose services are called upon only when orderly existence is threatened. This nevertheless leaves the ‘minimal’ or ‘nightwatchman’ state with three core functions. First and foremost, the state exists to maintain domestic order. Second, it ensures that contracts or voluntary agreements made between private citizens are enforced, and third it provides protection against external attack. The institutional apparatus of a minimal state is thus limited to a police force, a court system and a military of some kind. Economic, social, cultural, moral and other responsibilities belong to the individual, and are therefore firmly part of civil society. P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 67 Rights: Legal or moral entitlements to act or be treated in a particular way; civil rights differ from human rights. 68 P O L I T I C S The cause of the minimal state has been taken up in modern political debate by the New Right. Drawing on early liberal ideas, and particularly on free-market or classical economic theories, the New Right has proclaimed the need to ‘roll back the frontiers of the state’. In the writings of Robert Nozick, this amounts to a restatement of Lockean liberalism based on a defence of individual rights, especially property rights. In the case of free-market economists such as Friedrich von Hayek (see p. 37) and Milton Friedman (see p. 138), state intervention is seen as a ‘dead hand’ that reduces competition, efficiency and productivity. From the New Right perspective, the state’s economic role should be confined to two functions: the maintenance of a stable means of exchange or ‘sound money’ (low or zero inflation), and the promotion of competition through controls on monopoly power, price fixing and so on. Developmental states The best historical examples of minimal states were those in countries such as the UK and the USA during the period of early industrialization in the nineteenth century. As a general rule, however, the later a country industrializes, the more extensive will be its state’s economic role. In Japan and Germany, for instance, the state assumed a more active ‘developmental’ role from the outset. A developmental state is one that intervenes in economic life with the specific purpose of promoting industrial growth and economic development. This does not amount to an attempt to replace the market with a ‘socialist’ system of planning and control but, rather, to an attempt to construct a partnership between the state and major economic interests, often underpinned by conservative and nationalist priorities. The classic example of a developmental state is Japan. During the Meiji Period (1868–1912), the Japanese state forged a close relationship with the zaibutsu, the great family-run business empires that dominated the Japanese economy up until World War II. Since 1945, the developmental role of the Japanese state has been assumed by the Japanese Ministry of International Trade and Industry (MITI), which, together with the Bank of Japan, helps to shape private investment decisions and steer the Japanese economy towards international competitiveness (see Robert Nozick (1938–2002) US academic and political philosopher. Nozick’s major work, Anarchy, State and Utopia (1974), had a profound influence on New Right theories and beliefs. He developed a form of libertarianism that was close to Locke’s and clearly influenced by nineteenth-century US individualists such as Spooner (1808–87) and Tucker (1854–1939). He argued that property rights should be strictly upheld, provided that wealth has been justly acquired in the first place, or has been justly transferred from one person to another. This position means support for minimal government and minimal taxation, and undermines the case for welfare and redistribution. Nozick’s rights-based theory of justice was developed in response to the ideas of John Rawls (see p. 45). In later life, Nozick modified his extreme libertarianism. p. 372). A similar model of developmental intervention has existed in France, where governments of both left and right have tended to recognize the need for economic planning, and the state bureaucracy has seen itself as the custodian of the national interest. In countries such as Austria and, to some extent, Germany, economic development has been achieved through the construction of a‘partnership state’, in which an emphasis is placed on the maintenance of a close relationship between the state and major economic interests, notably big business and organized labour. More recently, economic globalization (see p. 142) has fostered the emergence of ‘competition states’, examples of which are found amongst the tiger economies of East Asia. Competition states are distinguished by their recognition of the need to strengthen education and training as the principal guaranteeing economic success in a context of intensifying transnational competition. Social-democratic states Whereas developmental states practise interventionism in order to stimulate economic progress, social-democratic states intervene with a view to bringing about broader social restructuring, usually in accordance with principles such as fairness, equality (see p. 454) and social justice. In countries such as Austria and Sweden, state intervention has been guided by both developmental and socialdemocratic priorities. Nevertheless, developmentalism and social democracy do not always go hand-in-hand. As Marquand (1988) pointed out, although the UK state was significantly extended in the period immediately after World War II along social-democratic lines, it failed to evolve into a developmental state. The key to understanding the social-democratic state is that there is a shift from a ‘negative’ view of the state, which sees it as little more than a necessary evil, to a ‘positive’ view of the state, in which it is seen as a means of enlarging liberty and promoting justice. The social-democratic state is thus the ideal of both modern liberals and democratic socialists. Rather than merely laying down the conditions of orderly existence, the social-democratic state is an active participant; in particular, helping to rectify the imbalances and injustices of a market economy. It therefore tends to focus less upon the generation of wealth and more upon what is seen as the equitable or just distribution of wealth. In practice, this boils down to an attempt to eradicate poverty and reduce social inequality. The twin features of a socialdemocratic state are therefore Keynesianism and social welfare. The aim of Keynesian economic policies is to ‘manage’ or ‘regulate’ capitalism with a view to promoting growth and maintaining full employment. Although this may entail an element of planning, the classic Keynesian strategy involves ‘demand management’ through adjustments in fiscal policy; that is, in the levels of public spending and taxation. The adoption of welfare policies has led to the emergence of socalled ‘welfare states’, whose responsibilities have extended to the promotion of social well-being amongst their citizens. In this sense, the social-democratic state is an ‘enabling state’, dedicated to the principle of individual empowerment. Collectivized states While developmental and social-democratic states intervene in economic life with a view to guiding or supporting a largely private economy, collectivized P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 69 Competition state: A state which pursues strategies to ensure long-term competitiveness in a globalized economy. Tiger economies: Fastgrowing and export-orientated economies modelled on Japan: for example, South Korea, Taiwan and Singapore. Social justice: A morally justifiable distribution of material rewards; social justice is often seen to imply a bias in favour of equality. Welfare state: A state that takes primary responsibility for the social welfare of its citizens, discharged through a range of social security, health, education and other services (albeit different in different societies). 70 P O L I T I C S Political and ideological debate so often revolves around the issue of the state and, in particular, the proper balance between the state and civil society. At one extreme, anarchists claim that states and, for that matter, all systems of rule are illegitimate. Other views range from a grudging acceptance of the state as a necessary evil to a positive endorsement of the state as a force for good. Does the state have a positive or negative impact on our lives? Should it be celebrated or feared? YES NO Debating . . . Is the state a force for good? Key to civilized existence. The most basic argument in favour of the state is that it is a vital guarantee of order and social stability. A state is absolutely necessary because only a sovereign body that enjoys a monopoly of the means of coercion is able to prevent (regrettable, but inevitable) conflict and competition from spilling over into barbarism and chaos. Life in the absence of a state would be, as Hobbes famously put it, ‘solitary, poor, nasty, brutish and short’. This is a lesson that is underlined by the sad misfortunes suffered by so-called ‘failed’ states (see p. 76), where civil war and warlordism take hold in the absence of a credible system of law and order. Foundation of public life. The state differs from other bodies and institutions in that it is the only one that represents the common or collective interests, rather than the selfish or particular ones. The state speaks for the whole of society, not just its parts. As such, the state makes possible a ‘public’ realm of existence, which allows people to be involved in something larger than themselves, discharging responsibilities towards fellow citizens and, where appropriate, participating in making collective decisions. In a tradition that dates back to Aristotle and Hegel, the state can therefore be seen to be morally superior to civil society. Agent of social justice. The state is a key agent of modernization and delivers a range of economic and social benefits. Even supporters of free-market economics acknowledge this in accepting that the economy can only function in a context of civic order that can only be established by the state. Beyond this, the state can counter the inherent instability of a market economy by intervening to ensure sustainable growth and full employment, and it can protect people from poverty and other forms of social disadvantage by delivering publiclyfunded welfare services that no amount of private philanthropy can rival in terms of reach and quality. Cause of disorder. As anarchists argue, the state is the cause of the problem of order, not its solution. The state breeds conflict and unrest because, by robbing people of their moral autonomy and forcing them to obey rules they have not made themselves, it ‘infantalizes’ them and blocks their moral development. This leaves them under the sway of base instincts and allows selfishness, greed and aggression to spread. As moral development flourishes in conditions of freedom and equality, reducing the authority of the state or, preferably, removing it altogether, will allow order to arise ‘from below’, naturally and spontaneously. Enemy of freedom. The state is, at best, a necessary evil. Even when its benefits in terms of upholding order are accepted, the state should be confined to a strictly minimal role. This is because, as state authority is sovereign, compulsory and coercive, the ‘public’ sphere is, by its nature, a realm of oppression. While anarchists therefore argue that all states are illegitimate, others suggest that this only applies when the state goes beyond its essential role of laying down the conditions for orderly existence. Freedom is enlarged to the extent that the ‘public’ sphere contracts, civil society being morally superior to the state. Recipe for poverty. The economy works best when it is left alone by the state. Market economies are selfregulating mechanisms; they tend towards long-term equilibrium, as the forces of demand and supply come into line with one another. The state, in contrast, is a brute machine: however well-meaning state intervention in economic and social life may be, it inevitably upsets the natural balance of the market and so imperils growth and prosperity. This was a lesson most graphically illustrated by the fate of orthodox communist systems, but it has also been underlined by the poor economic performance of over-regulated capitalist systems. states bring the entirety of economic life under state control. The best examples of such states were in orthodox communist countries such as the USSR and throughout Eastern Europe. These sought to abolish private enterprise altogether, and set up centrally planned economies administered by a network of economic ministries and planning committees. So-called ‘command economies’ were therefore established that were organized through a system of ‘directive’ planning that was ultimately controlled by the highest organs of the communist party. The justification for state collectivization stems from a fundamental socialist preference for common ownership over private property. However, the use of the state to attain this goal suggests a more positive attitude to state power than that outlined in the classical writings of Marx and Engels (1820–95). Marx and Engels by no means ruled out nationalization; Engels, in particular, recognized that, during the ‘dictatorship of the proletariat’, state control would be extended to include factories, the banks, transportation and so on. Nevertheless, they envisaged that the proletarian state would be strictly temporary, and that it would ‘wither away’ as class antagonisms abated. In contrast, the collectivized state in the USSR became permanent, and increasingly powerful and bureaucratic. Under Stalin, socialism was effectively equated with statism, the advance of socialism being reflected in the widening responsibilities and powers of the state apparatus. Indeed, after Khrushchev announced in 1962 that the dictatorship of the proletariat had ended, the state was formally identified with the interests of ‘the whole Soviet peoples’. Totalitarian states The most extreme and extensive form of interventionism is found in totalitarian states. The essence of totalitarianism is the construction of an all-embracing state, the influence of which penetrates every aspect of human existence. The state brings not only the economy, but also education, culture, religion, family life and so on under direct state control. The best examples of totalitarian states are Hitler’s Germany and Stalin’s USSR, although modern regimes such as Saddam Hussein’s Iraq arguably have similar characteristics. The central pillars of such regimes are a comprehensive process of surveillance and terroristic policing, and a pervasive system of ideological manipulation and control. In this sense, totalitarian states effectively extinguish civil society and abolish the ‘private’ sphere of life altogether. This is a goal that only fascists, who wish to dissolve individual identity within the social whole, are prepared openly to endorse. It is sometimes argued that Mussolini’s notion of a totalitarian state was derived from Hegel’s belief in the state as an ‘ethical community’ reflecting the altruism and mutual sympathy of its members. From this perspective, the advance of human civilization can clearly be linked to the aggrandisement of the state and the widening of its responsibilities. Religious states On the face of it, a religious state is a contradiction in terms. The modern state emerged largely through the triumph of civil authority over religious authority, religion increasingly being confined to the private sphere, through a separation between church and state. The advance of state sovereignty thus usually went P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 71 Collectivization: The abolition of private property in favour of a system of common or public ownership. Totalitarianism: An allencompassing system of political rule, involving pervasive ideological manipulation and open brutality (see p. 269). CONCEPT Statism Statism (or, in French, étatisme) is the belief that state intervention is the most appropriate means of resolving political problems, or bringing about economic and social development. This view is underpinned by a deep, and perhaps unquestioning, faith in the state as a mechanism through which collective action can be organized and common goals can be achieved. The state is thus seen as an ethical ideal (Hegel), or as serving the ‘general will’ or public interest. Statism is most clearly reflected in government policies that regulate and control economic life, possibly extending to Soviet-style state collectivization. hand in hand with the forward march of secularization. In the USA, the secular nature of the state was enshrined in the First Amendment of the constitution, which guarantees that freedom of worship shall not be abridged, while in France the separation of church and state has been maintained through a strict emphasis on the principle of laïcité. In countries such as Norway, Denmark and the UK,‘established’ or state religions have developed, although the privileges these religions enjoy stop well short of theocratic rule, and their political influence has generally been restricted by a high level of social secularization. Nevertheless, the period since the 1980s has witnessed the rise of the religious state, driven by the tendency within religious fundamentalism (see p. 53) to reject the public/private divide and to view religion as the basis of politics. Far from regarding political realm as inherently corrupt, fundamentalist movements have typically looked to seize control of the state and to use it as an instrument of moral and spiritual regeneration. This was evident, for instance, in the process of ‘Islamization’ introduced in Pakistan under General Zia-ul-Haq after 1978, the establishment of an ‘Islamic state’ in Iran as a result of the 1979 revolution, and, despite its formal commitment to secularism, the close links between the Sri Lankan state and Sinhala Buddhism, particularly during the years of violent struggle against Tamil separatism. Although, strictly speaking, religious states are founded on the basis of religious principles, and, in the Iranian model, contain explicitly theocratic features, in other cases religiously-orientated governments operate in a context of constitutional secularism. This applies in the case of the AKP in Turkey (see p. 280) and, since 2012, the Muslim Brotherhood in Egypt. ECLIPSE OF THE STATE? Since the late 1980s, debate about the state has been overshadowed by assertions about it ‘retreat’ or ‘decline’. The once-mighty leviathan – widely seen to be coextensive with politics itself – had seemingly been humbled, state authority having been undermined by the growing importance of, amongst other things, the global economy, the market, major corporations, non-state actors and international organisations. The clamour for ‘state-centric’ approaches to domestic and international politics to be rethought, or abandoned altogether, therefore grew. However, a simple choice between ‘state-centrism’ and ‘retreat-ism’ is, at best, misleading. For instance, although states and markets are commonly portrayed as rival forces, they also interlock and complement one another. Apart from anything else, markets cannot function without a system of property rights that only the state can establish and protect. Moreover, although states may have lost authority in certain respects; in others, they may have become stronger. Decline and fall of the state Globalization and state transformation The rise of globalization has stimulated a major debate about the power and significance of the state in a globalized world. Three contrasting positions can be identified. In the first place, some theorists have boldly proclaimed the emergence of ‘post-sovereign governance’ (Scholte, 2005), suggesting that the rise of 72 P O L I T I C S Laïcité: (French) The principle of the absence of religious involvement in government affairs, and of government involvement in religious affairs. State religion: A religious body that is officially endorsed by the state, giving it special privileges, but (usually) not formal political authority. globalization is inevitably marked by the decline of the state as a meaningful actor. Power shifts away from the state and towards global marketplaces and transnational corporations (TNCs) (see p. 149) in particular. In the most extreme version of this argument, advanced by so-called ‘hyperglobalists’, the state is seen to be so ‘hollowed out’ as to have become, in effect, redundant. Others, nevertheless, deny that globalization has altered the core feature of world politics, which is that, as in earlier eras, sovereign states are the primary determinants of what happens within their borders, and remain the principal actors on the world stage. In this view, globalization and the state are not separate or, still less, opposing forces; rather, and to a surprising degree, globalization has been created by states and thus exists to serve their interests. Between these two views, however, there is a third position, which acknowledges that globalization has brought about qualitative changes in the role and significance of the state, and in the nature of sovereignty, but emphasizes that these have transformed the state, rather than simply reduced or increased its power. Developments such as the rise of international migration and the spread of cultural globalization have tended to make state borders increasingly ‘permeable’. However, most of the discussion about the changing nature and power of the state has concerned the impact of economic globalization (discussed in more detail in Chapter 6). The central feature of economic globalization is the rise of ‘supraterritoriality’, the process through which economic activity increasingly takes place within a ‘borderless world’ (Ohmae, 1989). This is particularly clear in relation to financial markets that have become genuinely globalized, in that capital flows around the world seemingly instantaneously; meaning, for example, that no state can be insulated from the impact of financial crises in other parts of the world. If borders have become permeable and old geographical certainties have been shaken, state sovereignty, at least in its traditional sense, cannot survive. This is the sense in which governance (see p. 74) in the twentyfirst century has assumed a genuinely postsovereign character. It is difficult, in particular, to see how economic sovereignty can be reconciled with a globalized economy. Sovereign control over economic life was only possible in a world of discrete national economies; to the extent that these have been, or are being, incorporated into a single globalized economy, economic sovereignty becomes meaningless. However, the rhetoric of a‘borderless’ global economy can be taken too far. For example, there has been, if anything, a growing recognition that market-based economies can only operate successfully within a context of legal and social order that only the state can guarantee (Fukuyama, 2005). Increased global competition has also generated pressure to develop more efficient and responsive means of developing public policy and delivering public services. For many, this reflected a shift from government to ‘governance’. As societies became more complex and fluid, new methods of governing have had to be devised that relied less on hierarchical state institutions and more on networks and the market, thus blurring the distinction between the state and society. The‘governance turn’ in politics has been characterized by what has been called the ‘reinvention’ of government, reflected, in particular, in a move away from direct service provision by the state to the adoption of an ‘enabling’ or ‘regulating’ role. Such developments have led, some argue, to the transformation of the state itself, reflecting the rise of what has variously been called the ‘competition’ state, the ‘market’ state or the ‘postmodern’ state. Philip Bobbitt (2002) P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 73 Supraterritoriality: The reconfiguration of geography that has occurred through the declining importance of state borders, geographical distance and territorial location. Economic sovereignty: The absolute authority of the state over national economic life, involving independent control of fiscal and monetary policies, and control over trade and capital flows. went as far as to argue that the transition from the nation-state to what he termed the ‘market state’ heralded a profound shift in world politics, in that it marked the end of the‘long war’ between liberalism, fascism and communism to define the constitutional form of the nation-state. The core feature of the market state is a shift away from ‘top-down’ economic management, based on the existence of discrete national economies, to an acceptance of the market as the only reliable principle of economic organization. Instead of trying to ‘tame’ capitalism, market states ‘go with the flow’. Whereas states were previously judged on their effectiveness in promoting growth and prosperity, alleviating poverty and narrowing social inequality, market states base their legitimacy on their capacity to maximize the opportunities available to citizens, and their ability to ensure effective and unimpeded market competition. The speed with which this has happened varies in different parts of the world, as states embrace the marketstate model with greater or less enthusiasm, and try to adapt it to their political cultures and economic needs. Non-state actors and international bodies A further manifestation of the decline of the state is evident in the rise of nonstate or transnational actors and the growing importance of international organizations. This reflects the fact that, increasingly, major aspects of politics no longer take place merely in or through the state but, rather, outside or beyond the state. Amongst non-state actors, TNCs are often regarded as the most significant, their number having risen from 7,000 in 1970 to 38,000 in 2009. TNCs often dwarf states in terms of their economic size. Based on the (rather crude) comparison between corporate sales and countries’ GDP, 51 of the world’s 100 largest economies are corporations; only 49 of them are countries. General Motors is broadly equivalent, in this sense, to Denmark; Wal-Mart is roughly the same size as Poland; and Exxon Mobil has the same economic weight as South Africa. However, economic size does not necessarily translate into political power or influence. States, after all, can do things that TNCs can only dream about, such as make laws and raise armies. Non-governmental organizations (NGOs) (see p. 248) have also steadily grown in number and influence, particularly since the 1990s. Estimates of the total number of international NGOs usually exceed 30,000, with over 1,000 groups enjoying formal consultative status by the UN. Their expertise, moral authority and high public profiles enable NGOs such as Greenpeace, Amnesty International and Care International to exert a level of influence within international organizations that may at times rival, or even surpass, that of national governments. NGOs are therefore the key agents of what is increasingly called ‘global civil society’ (see p. 106). Other nonstate actors range from the women’s movement and the anti-capitalist movement to terrorist networks, such as al-Qaeda, guerrilla armies and transnational criminal organizations. As such groups have a ‘trans-border’ character, they are often able to operate in ways that elude the jurisdiction of any state. The growth of politics beyond the state has also been apparent in the trend towards political globalization. However, its impact has been complex and, in some ways, contradictory. On the one hand, international bodies such as the UN, the European Union (EU) and the World Trade Organization (WTO) have undermined the capacity of states to operate as self-governing political units. As 74 P O L I T I C S Market state: A state that aims to enlarge citizens’ rights and opportuities, rather than assume control over economic and social life. Political globalization: The growing importance of international bodies and organizations, and of transnation political forces generally. CONCEPT Governance Governance is a broader term than government (see p. 266).Although lacking a settled or agreed definition, it refers, in its widest sense, to the various ways through which social life is coordinated. Government can therefore be seen as one of the institutions involved in governance; it is possible to have ‘governance without government’ (Rhodes, 1996).The wider use of the term reflects a blurring of the state/ society distinction, resulting from changes such as the development of new forms of public management and the growth of public–private partnerships. (See multilevel governance p. 380). the range and importance of decisions that are made at intergovernmental or supranational level has increased, states have been forced to exert influence in and through regional or global bodies, or to operate within frameworks established by them. In the case of the EU, a growing range of decisions (for example, on monetary policy, agriculture and fisheries policy, defence and foreign affairs) are made by EU institutions, rather than member states. This has led to the phenomenon of multilevel governance, as discussed in Chapter 17. The WTO, for its part, acts as the judge and jury of global trade disputes and serves as a forum for negotiating trade deals between and amongst its members. On the other hand, political globalization opens up opportunities for the state as well as diminishes them. This occurs through the ‘pooling’ of sovereignty. For example, the EU Council of Ministers, the most powerful policy-making body in the EU, is very much a creature of its member states and provides a forum that allows national politicians to make decisions on a supranational level. By ‘pooling’ sovereignty, member states of the EU arguably gain access to a larger and more meaningful form of sovereignty. The ‘pooled’ sovereignty of the EU may be greater than the combined national sovereignties of its various member states. Failed states and state-building In the developing world, debate about the decline of the state has sometimes been displaced by concern about weak, failing or collapsed states. Cooper (2004) portrayed what he called the ‘pre-modern’ world as a world of postcolonial chaos, in which such state structures as exist are unable to establish (in Weber’s words) a legitimate monopoly of the use of force, thus leading to endemic warlordism, widespread criminality and social dislocation. Such conditions do not apply consistently across the developing world, however. In cases such as India, South Korea and Taiwan, developing world states have been highly successful in pursuing strategies of economic modernization and social development. Others, nevertheless, have been distinguished by their weakness, sometimes being portrayed as ‘quasi-states’ or ‘failed states’ (see p. 76). Most of the weakest states in the world are concentrated in sub-Saharan Africa, classic examples being Somalia, Sierra Leone, Liberia and the Democratic Republic of the Congo. These states fail the most basic test of state power: they are unable to maintain domestic order and personal security, meaning that civil strife and even civil war become almost routine. The failure of such states stems primarily from the experience of colonialism (see p. 122), which, when it ended (mainly in the post-1945 period), bequeathed formal political independence to societies that lacked an appropriate level of political, economic, social and educational development to function effectively as separate entities. As the borders of such states typically represented the extent of colonial ambition, rather than the existence of a culturally cohesive population, postcolonial states also often encompass deep ethnic, religious and tribal divisions. Although some explain the increase in state failure since the 1990s primarily in terms of domestic factors (such as a disposition towards authoritarian rule, backward institutions and parochial value systems which block the transition from pre-industrial, agrarian societies to modern industrial ones), external factors have also played a major role. This has applied not least through the tendency of globalization to re-orientate developing world economies P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 75 Warlordism: A condition in which locally-based militarized bands vie for power in the absence of a sovereign state. around the dictates of global markets, rather than domestic needs, and to widen inequality. State failure is not just a domestic problem, however. Failed states often have a wider impact through, for example, precipitating refugee crises, providing a refuge for drug dealers, arms smugglers and terrorist organizations, generating regional instability, and, sometimes, provoking external intervention to provide humanitarian relief and/or to keep the peace. In this light, there has been a growing emphasis on state-building, typically associated with the larger process of peacebuilding and attempts to address deep-rooted, structural causes of violence in post-conflict situations. The provision of humanitarian relief and the task of conflict resolution become almost insuperably difficult in the absence of a functioning system of law and order. The wider acceptance of humanitarian intervention (see p. 424) since the early 1990s has meant that ordered rule is often provided, initially at least, by external powers. However this does not constitute a long-term solution. As examples such as Somalia, Iraq and Afghanistan demonstrate, externally-imposed order is only sustainable for a limited period of time, both because the economic and human cost to the intervening powers may be unsustainable in the long run, and because, sooner or later, the presence of foreign troops and police provokes resentment and hostility. Foreign intervention has therefore come, over time, to focus increasingly on the construction of effective indigenous leadership and building legitimate national institutions, such as an army, a police force, a judiciary, a central bank, a tax collection agency and functioning education, transport, energy and healthcare systems. As examples such as Liberia demonstrate, state-building is often a profoundly difficult task (see p. 77). Return of the state? Discussion about the state in the early twenty-first century has been dominated by talk of retreat, decline, or even collapse. The reality is more complex, however. For instance, although globalization may make state borders more‘porous’, globalization has not been imposed on unwilling states; rather, it is a process that has been devised by states in pursuit of what they identify as their national interests. Similarly, international organizations typically act as forums through which states can act in concert over matters of mutual interest, rather than as bodies intent on usurping state power. Moreover, a number of developments in recent years have helped to strengthen the state and underline its essential importance. What explains the return of the state? In the first place, the state’s unique capacity to maintain domestic order and protect its citizens from external attack has been strongly underlined by new security challenges that have emerged in the twenty-first century; notably, those linked to transnational terrorism (as discussed in Chapter 18). This underlines what Bobbitt (2002) viewed as a basic truth:‘The State exists to master violence’; it is therefore essentially a‘warmaking institution’. The decline in military expenditure that occurred at the end of the Cold War, the so-called ‘peace dividend’, started to be reversed in the late 1990s, with global military expenditure rising steeply after the September 11 terrorist attacks and the launch of the ‘war on terror’. Furthermore, counter-terrorism strategies have often meant that states have imposed tighter border controls and assumed wider powers of surveillance, control and sometimes detention, even becoming ‘national security states’. 76 P O L I T I C S CONCEPT Failed state A failed state is a state that is unable to perform its key role of ensuring domestic order by monopolizing the use of force within its territory. Examples of failed states in recent years include Cambodia, Haiti, Rwanda, Liberia and Somalia. Failed states are no longer able to operate as viable political units, in that they lack a credible system of law and order. They are no longer able to operate as viable economic units, in that they are incapable of providing for their citizens and have no functioning infrastructure. Although relatively few states collapse altogether, a much larger number barely function and are dangerously close to collapse. State-building: The construction of a functioning state through the establishment of legitimate institutions for the formulation and implementation of policy across key areas of government. P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 77 Events: During the 1990s, Liberia was often cited as a classic example of a failed state. Its ethnic and religious mixes, widespread poverty, endemic corruption, collapse of institutions and infrastructure, and tendency towards warlordism and violence imperilled the security and welfare of its citizens and affected other states, notably neighbouring Sierra Leone. Liberia, Africa’s oldest republic, had collapsed into civil war in the late 1980s when Charles Taylor’s National Patriotic Front of Liberia (NPFL) rebels overran much of the countryside, seizing the capital, Monrovia, in 1990. Around 250,000 people were killed and many thousands more fled the country as fighting intensified between rebel splinter groups, the Liberian army and West African peacekeepers. The 14year civil war ended in 2003 when, under mounting international pressure and hemmed in by rebels, Taylor stepped down and went into exile in Nigeria (he was later found guilty of war crimes by an international tribunal in The Hague, linked to atrocities carried out in Sierra Leone). A transitional government steered the country towards elections in 2005, which brought the Harvard-educated economist Elaine Johnson-Sirleaf to power, becoming Africa’s first female head of state. Sirleaf was re-elected in an uncontested run-off presidential election in November 2011. Significance: Successful state-building has to overcome at least three challenges. First, new institutions and structures have to be constructed in a context of often deep political and ethnic tension, economic and social dislocation, and endemic poverty. In Liberia, the process of reconstructing the economic and social infrastructure was accelerated once Sirleaf and her Unity Party (UP) assumed power in 2005. Central Monrovia was transformed with improved roads and shining new buildings; investment in education and health saw the building of hundreds of new schools and health facilities, some of them free and affordable; and, alongside the elected presidency and legislature, progress was made in establishing an independent judiciary, and a disciplined police and military. Other important institutions have included Liberia’s Truth and Reconciliation Commission, modelled on the experience of South Africa, and the National Election Commission (NEC), which presided over its first elections in 2011. Nevertheless, many development goals have yet to be achieved, despite considerable sums of money having been provided by international donors. For example, most people in Monrovia still do not have electricity or running water, and unemployment remains extremely high, with young people being most affected. Second, the indigenous leadership and new institutions need to enjoy a significant measure of legitimacy. This is why state-building is invariably linked to the promotion of ‘good governance’, with the eradication of corruption being a key goal. Before contesting the presidency, Sirleaf had resigned her post as head of the Governance Reform Commission, criticizing the transitional government’s inability to fight corruption. However, her opponents claim that her administration is guilty of some of the crimes it associates with previous governments. In 2009, the Truth and Reconciliation Commission implicated Sirleaf in the civil war and recommended that she be banned from public office for 30 years. The 2011 elections were also highly divisive. Sirleaf’s main opponent, Winston Tubman, boycotted the run-off election, claiming that the NEC was biased in favour of the president and had manipulated vote-counting in her favour. Third, successful state-building often requires external support, although this may become more of a hindrance than a help. State-building ‘from above’, associated with military intervention, as in Afghanistan and Iraq, clearly has its drawbacks, not least because indigenous leaders and new institutions are in danger of being seen to serve external interests rather than domestic ones. In the case of Liberia, the support of the Economic Community of West African States (ECOWAS) and the presence of a 15,000-strong UN peacekeeping force certainly aided economic development and helped to keep civil strife under control. Nevertheless, Liberia’s peace may be fragile, and this may be tested either when the UN peacekeeping forces withdraw, or when President Sirleaf leaves office. POLITICS IN ACTION . . . Liberia: a failed state rebuilt? Second, although the days of command-and-control economic management may be over, the state has sometimes reasserted itself as an agent of modernization. Competition states have done this by improving education and training in order to boost productivity and provide support for key export industries. States such as China and Russia each modernized their economies by making significant concessions to the market, but an important element of state control has been retained or re-imposed (these developments are examined in more detail in Chapter 6 in relation to ‘state capitalism’). On a wider level, the state’s vital role in economic affairs was underlined by the 2007–09 global financial crisis. Although the G20 may have provided states with a forum to develop a coordinated global response, the massive packages of fiscal and other interventions that were agreed were, and could only have been, implemented by states. Indeed, one of the lessons of the 2007–09 crash, and of subsequent financial and fiscal crises, may be that the idea that the global economy works best when left alone by the state (acting alone, or through international organizations) has been exposed as a myth. 78 P O L I T I C S SUMMARY The state is a political association that exercises sovereign jurisdiction within defined territorial borders. As a system of centralized rule that emerged in Europe between the seventeenth and nineteenth centuries, and succeeded in subordinating all other institutions and groups, the state came to dominate political life in all its forms. The spread of the European model of the state to other lands and continents has seen the state become the universal form of political organization around the world There are a number of rival theories of the state. Pluralists hold that the state is a neutral body that arbitrates between the competing interests of society. Marxists argue that the state maintains the class system by either oppressing subordinate classes or ameliorating class conflict. The New Right portrays the state as a self-serving monster that is intent on expansion and aggrandizement. Radical feminists point to patriarchal biases within the state that support a system of male power. Those who support the state see it either as a means of defending the individual from the encroachments of fellow citizens, or as a mechanism through which collective action can be organized. Critics, however, tend to suggest that the state reflects either the interests of dominant social groups, or interests that are separate from, and antithetical to, society. States have fulfilled very different roles. Minimal states merely lay down the conditions for orderly existence. Developmental states attempt to promote growth and economic development. Social-democratic states aim to rectify the imbalances and injustices of a market economy. Collectivized states exert control over the entirety of economic life. Totalitarian states bring about all-encompassing politicization and, in effect, extinguish civil society. Religious states are used as instruments of moral and spiritual renewal. Modern debate about the state is dominated by talk of retreat, decline and even collapse. The decline of the state is often explained in terms of the impact of globalization, the rise of non-state actors and the growing importance of international organizations. Most dramatically, some postcolonial states have collapsed, or barely function as states, having a negligible capacity to maintain order. However, the retreat of the state may have been exaggerated and, in relation to security and economic development in particular, the state may be reviving in importance. P O L I T I C S A N D T H E S T A T E 79 Questions for discussion How should the state be defined? Would life in a stateless society really be ‘nasty, brutish and short’? Why has politics traditionally been associated with the affairs of the state? Can the state be viewed as a neutral body in relation to competing social interests? Does the nature and background of the state elite inevitably breed bias? What is the proper relationship between the state and civil society? Does globalization mean that the state has become irrelevant? Have nation-states been transformed into market states? To what extent can state capacity be ‘re-built’? Further reading Hay, C., M. Lister and D. Marsh, The State: Theories and Issues (2006). An accessible, comprehensive and contemporary introduction to the theoretical perspectives on the state and to key issues and controversies. Jessop, B., State Theory: Putting Capitalist States in Their Place (1990). A demanding but worthwhile collection of essays through which Jessop develops his own approach to state theory. Pierre, J. and B. Guy Peters, Governance, Politics and the State (2000). A useful discussion of the phenomenon of governance, and of its implications for the role and nature of the state. Sørensen, G., The Transformation of the State: Beyond the Myth of Retreat (2004). A systematic analysis of the contemporary state that assesses the nature and extent of its transformation in a global era.