1 INTRODUCTION Robert A. Dahl The Argument i. Let mc begin with an elementary proposition about politics that I think no one seriously questions. No government receives indefinitely the total support of the people over whom it asserts its jurisdiction. Certainly the government of a large collection of people, such as the government of a country, is never completely supported in all that it does by all the people whom it claims to govern. In no country, in short, does everyone have the same preferences as to the conduct of the government, using the term conduct in its broadest sense. So much is, I believe, obvious. 2. It is an equally well-grounded observation, I believe — though one more often denied, even in highly influential theories of politics — that differences in what people think they want from the government that rules over them tend toward diversity and multiplicity rather than toward bipolarity: to many groupings rather than merely two. Let me call what people think they want the government to be, or to do, their political preferences, or, if you prefer, their political interests. Whenever the barriers to the expression and organization of political preferences are low, one should expect (as the usual tiling) the emergence of a multiplicity of camps, whereas polarization into two internally cohesive and unified camps would be rare. Although the second proposition may be more debatable than the first, the experiences of the countries described in the chapters of this book lend great weight to it, as I hope to show in a moment. 3. Because people are not in perfect accord as to their political preferences, every political system, if it is to endure, must provide ways for determining which (or whose) political preferences the government responds to. It will be useful to consider two extreme possibilities. At one extreme, a government might respond to the political .preferences of only one person (or perhaps to a tiny and wholly unified minority); it would ignore or override all other preferences. A system of this kind might be 1 Robot A. Ihhl Introduction t ritllrtl ii pure hegemony. At I lie oilier extreme, the political preferences n| evil yiiiie might be weighted equally, :iiul the government would respond always to ihe preferences <>! die greatest number. A system of this kind rnighi he called a pure egnUhmnii democracy. .|. All political systems in some respects constrain the expression, organization, representation, and satisfaction of political preferences. Given the existence of disagreements as to what the government should do (that is to say, given the human condition, if my first assumption is valid), even an egalitarian democracy cannot respond fully to the preferences of hoi Ii i he greatest number and the smaller number who disagree with them. During any given period, therefore, a political system will contain some people who, if there were no barriers or costs to their doing so, would be Opposed to the conduct of the government. •;. Political systems vary a great deal, however, in the barriers or opportunities they provide for the expression, organization, and representation of political preferences and thus in the opportunities available to potential oppositions. To cope adequately with these variations among different political systems poses some difficulties. For example, a moment ago I offered two extreme types, hegemony and egalitarian democracy; yet both are purely theoretical types. Although neither exists in pure form, they do hint at a possible continuum, running from one to the other. However, it is more accurate for our purposes to think not just of one but of two dimensions. One is the dimension of liberalization, or public contestation: the extent to which institutions are openly available, publicly employed, and guaranteed to. at least some members of the political system who wish to contest the conduct of the government. The other is the dimension of participation or inclus'weness: the proportion of the population (or of adults) who are entitled to participate on a more or less equal basis in controlling and contesting the conduct of the government — that is, who are entitled to participate in the system of public contestation. In practice, political systems (particularly if we include historical ones) seem to vary over most of the space enclosed by these two hypothetical dimensions, except perhaps for space near the edges. Although the space can be carved up and labeled in many different ways, for the purposes of this essay it seems to me preferable to run the risk of oversimplification by distinguishing no more than three very general categories (see figure i.i). One: Regimes that impose the most severe limits on the expression, organization, and representation of political preferences and on the opportunities available to opponents of the government. In these systems, individuals are prohibited from expressing public opposition to the incumbent leaders, to their policies and ideology, and to the major social, eco- Vigure 1.1 Types of Regimes Hegemonies (Participation) nomic, and political structures. Organized dissent and opposition are prohibited in any form. I shall call such systems hegemonies. Two: Regimes that impose the fewest restraints on the expression, organization, and representation of political preferences and on the opportunities available to opponents of government. Most individuals are effectively protected in their right to express, privately or publicly, their opposition to the government, to organize, to form parties, and to compete in elections where voting is secret, unintimidated, and honestly counted and where the results of elections are binding according to well-established rules. Ordinarily, the use of violent means is forbidden, and in some cases it is punishable to advocate the use of violence for political purposes. I shall call such systems polyarchies. Three: Mixed regimes, which in various ways .approach hegemonies or polyarchies. Among the countries of the world, these are the most numerous. I shall sometimes call an intermediate regime that more closely 4 Robert A. Ihihl ii|i|iii>;ii lu-s ;i hegemony :i n&ar hc&cviony; one chat more closely :ip-|>icp,u lies polyarchy, ;> near polyarchy; aiul one that provides extensive Opportunities lor public contestation t<> a very small elite, a competitive oliiiiirchy. r>, In any given country, the lower the barriers (the greater the op-poriunities) for expressing, organizing, and representing political preferences, (he greater the number and variety of preferences and interests I Inn will be represented in policy making. The number and variety of preferences and interests represented in policy making are therefore greater if the political regime is a polyarchy than if it is a mixed regime, nml greater under a mixed regime than under a hegemony. Hence the transformation of a hegemony into a mixed regime or polyarchy, or a mixed regime into a polyarchy, would increase the number and variety of preferences and interests represented in policy making. 7. Polarization is an obvious threat to any regime, particularly a polyarchy. But the increase in the number and variety of preferences and interests represented in policy making, as the barriers for expressing, organizing, and representing political preferences are reduced, also helps to create a special risk for each type of regime. By a risk, I mean a sub-si initial probability that a situation will occur which will be seen by those who support the regime as creating a problem for which all solutions entail high costs and which may, if severe, lead to a transformation of the regime. I propose to take for granted points 1, 3, 4, and 5 of the argument, since these seem to me so obvious or axiomatic or contingently useful that it would be tedious and redundant to discuss them further. Let me then concentrate briefly on points 2, 6, and 7 and in so doing draw upon the later chapters of this volume by way of evidence and illustration. Polarization and Plurality That the forces of conflict in society are polarizing, in the sense that they exhibit an irresistible tendency toward a cleavage into two enduring sets of antagonists, is a view that seems to have a powerful attraction. Although it is perhaps best set out in Marxist thought, its reach extends far beyond any particular political philosophy or ideology. Usually this current of thought stresses the strictly economic or purely socioeconomic axis of conflict; thus societies tend to be bipolar along a socioeconomic line of cleavage. The fact is, however, that the great bulk of experience in the past century — whether in traditional, modernizing, industrial, or postindustrial societies — seems to run counter to this Introduction 5 hypothesis. It is rare for a country to divide into two camps along socioeconomic lines; it is rare, indeed, for a country to divide into only two camps along any lines. But it is commonplace for countries to display wore than two sets of conflicting interests. The explanation seems to be that most countries have some conflicts based at least in part on differences in language, religion, race, or ethnic group. Frequently these conflicts cut, wholly or partly, across one another and across differences of status, function, or reward based on economic activity. And they do not disappear or become attenuated with modernization. It is, rather, the conflicts derived from economic differences that often become attenuated, leaving more room, so to speak, for the other conflicts to occur. What is more, different political preferences or interests stimulated by differences in economic function, status, or reward seldom divide a people into only two groups, each with more or less identical preferences. Much more often, it seems, when people respond to economic factors, they divide into more than two groups — frequently, in fact, into a bewildering multiplicity of contesting interests. What seems to vary most from one country to another is, not so much this tendency toward diversity rather than polarization, but rather the extent to which the societal cloth is cut up into separate pieces by a succession of cuts or, alternatively, is woven with strong strands that hold one part to another. In language more familiar to social scientists (but which reverses the metaphor I have just used) I am of course speaking of the extent to which cleavages "reinforce" one another and hence produce "segmentation" or "fragmentation," or instead "crosscut" one another and thus produce a greater tendency toward cohesion. The important — and, one would have supposed, by now obvious — point is the comparative rarity of strongly bipolar social conflicts, particularly along an economic axis, and the comparative frequency of conflict involving more than two sets of contestants. Thus in describing the social basis for opposition in the single-party states of tropical Africa, Foltz refers to the impact of a half-dozen kinds of differences. Language and ethnic group reinforce each other to make tribal differences perhaps the dominant source of conflict; yet differences in region, mode of livelihood, religion, caste, modernity, urban-rural residence, and education reduce the cohesiveness of the tribe and enable politicians to build intertribal coalitions. As elsewhere in the world — India, Canada, Belgium, or Spain, for instance — the most serious conflicts are likely to arise where regional differences coincide with some of the other differences, most notably in language and ethnic groups. It is this kind of combination, in fact, that seems much more likely to lead to polarization or segmentation than any purely socioeconomic difference alone has ever Robert A. Dahl succeeded in doing. Throughout the world, the overt or l;ircnr forces of iiiitioiinlistn continue to be the most powerful sources of political antagonisms. ■Segmentation and pluralism arc central themes in Indian society, as Kiitluiri shows in his essay. In India there has not yet been any clear poliiri/alion of conflict, cither between the dominant Congress party and its opponents or among the incredible variety of castes, subcastes, and <:thnic:, linguistic, and regional groups. Although the differences between the preponderant Hindu population and the Muslim minority are an ever present source of danger, these do not form a principal line of cleavage in political conflicts; most political conflicts occur among Hindus, not between Hindus and Muslims. As to socioeconomic cleavages, the peasantry is of course numerically overwhelming, but it is not a unified force; and conflict between the urban working class and employers is simply one cleavage among many. As Kothari says, "India is still far from becoming a mass society; its pluralism also is of a different kind from t hat in Western democracies. It is less a confrontation between aggregated subsystems and more a coexistence between historically autonomous diversities and identities. Hence the great variety and diffusion of oppositions and their lack of clear-cut boundaries." Tropical Africa and India are, of course, areas where traditional society anil its differences exert an extraordinarily powerful pull, and it would not be unreasonable to argue that as they undergo the changes that come with modernization, traditional societies would be most prone to a diversity of cleavages. Latin America is hardly a region of traditionalism in quite the same sense as India or Africa, though it is an area where the forces Of modernization are nearly everywhere bringing about rapid changes in previous patterns of social, economic, and political life. As Dix points out, in the early decades of this century economic growth and urbanization in a number of Latin American countries, stimulating the expansion of new social sectors — "the industrialists, the middle sectors, and urban and mining proletariats" — helped make traditional political coalitions less effectual and increased the political importance of "categorical groupings based on occupation and economic interest." Yet these bases of conflict and coalition have "far from overwhelmed the past. Modern institutions and orientations often coexist with others that are traditional, sometimes in surprisingly compatible ways." Wealthy industrial entrepreneurs do not see eye to eye with upper-class landowners. The middle classes are at best a nominal category, not cohesive social classes; they are divided in their attitudes toward public policy, in ideology, in their commitment to Catholicism or anticlericalism, and in their personal and party loyalties. The lower, or "popular," classes, to use Dix's term, are divided by more than an urban-rural cleavage; in the countryside, traditional agriculture Introduction vies with modern agriculture, and in the city the skilled worker or the worker employed in a modern industry feels little or no solidarity with the unskilled, with the newly arriving peasant from the countryside, or with the "marginals living in the jerry-built slums that surround many of the large urban centers." As in many Catholic societies, women are more likely to support the church than men, while anticlericals are predominantly male. And of course the generation gap (or gaps) is (or are) us marked in Latin America as anywhere else. Despite palpable evidence of this kind in Latin America as elsewhere in the world, many political activists and intellectuals continue to interpret politics as a struggle between classes. Certainly socioeconomic differences a re sufficiently important as bases of cleavage and conflict in Latin America (as elsewhere) to give considerable credibility to their interpretations. The fact is, however, that other lines of cleavage, and the plurality of cleavages based on socioeconomic differences, so complicate political life in these countries that when political movements base their strategies on a pure class interpretation, they suffer grievous political defeat. Despite the presence of poverty, revolutionary rhetoric, and severe conflict, the Marxist parties of Latin America have failed to acquire a leading role except in Chile, Cuba, and Guatemala, where, in Dix's words, they were "tails to the kites of non-Communist nationalistic revolutions." In the rare cases where a Communist party has acquired a substantial electoral following, as in Chile, or where it is relatively small and hopes to expand its mass following in order to compete effectively in elections, as in Venezuela, party leaders seem to have recognized the failure of the classic strategy based on hopes of polarization. Like Communist leaders in Italy and France, they now seek alliances that would lead to a broad and-heterogeneous collection of interests capable of winning an electoral majority. Many people who cling to the belief that politics in evil and still unredeemed societies must embody an inherent motion toward socioeconomic polarization, apocalypse, and redemption can protect their vision from doubts, which evidence of the kind I have just discussed might otherwise create, by pointing to the persistence of rich and poor, the divergence in their "real interests," the obvious economic origins of many conflicts, and, above all, the expectation that the process of polarization will occur in some indefinite future. None of these arguments can be proved false; in particular, locating apocalypse and redemption in the future surely helps to preserve this faith, as it has others. It would seem reasonable that as the United States lurched recklessly through the process of becoming an advanced industrial society and then went on to become a postindustrial society, the processes of polarization, apocalypse, and redemption, if they were ever to occur anywhere, H Kobcil A. Ihibl Introduction 9 would sillily have occurred (here (iisl of ;ill. I5ur even I lie Civil W;ir docs nut lii I lie schema. The inconvenient experience of the United Stares has lirrn deah with by ignoring ir, by treating it as a unique case, or by postponing 1110 American apocalypse (and redemption) to a yet more distant I ut lire. An alternative test is provided by Japan, which like Russia has in less than a century traveled the path from an agrarian-based feudal society to n highly industrial economy and society — and soon, no doubt, to a post-industrial economy and society. As in Western Europe in the second half of the nineteenth century, so too in Japan during the first third of the t wenticrh century, industrialization created some of the familiar conditions for the exacerbation of twentieth-century class conflict. As Leiserson de-scrihes Taisho Democracy, it appears to have consisted of a competitive oligarchy undergoing a measure of liberalization and democratization; but before this evolutionary process was completed and consolidated, it was interrupted by Showa Fascism, which repressed the public expression of many latent conflicts. It is conceivable, certainly, that Taisho Democracy would ultimately have seen the emergence of political conflict highly polarized along clear-cut socioeconomic lines, but no such development seems to have occurred by the time Showa Fascism took over. Japanese politics since World War II appears to be more polarized than American politics. At the level of electoral conflicts, the Liberal-Di'inocrats and conservative independents gain the preponderant support of large business, farmers, and the national bureaucracy, while their opponents gain more supporters among labor, youth, intellectuals, and the lower middle classes. But as Leiserson's analysis makes clear, not only is this too simple a description, but the results have hardly been a polarization of political conflict along clear-cut socioeconomic lines. Voting patterns are a tangle of socioeconomic interests, party loyalties, personal loyalties, variations in organizational effectiveness, and deference to immediate or remote authority figures. The parties themselves are collections of factions. And some of the most important lines of cleavage, as Leiserson shows, are differences in ideological perspectives that are, it appears, only loosely related to socioeconomic position. In Soviet Russia and in the socialist countries of Eastern Europe, except Yugoslavia, the barriers to the public expression of political preferences are comparatively high. Yet, like other countries, these socialist countries contain within their boundaries people who differ in language, religion, ethnic group, status, economic position, policy views, ideology, personal loyalty, organizational loyalties, and the like. The widespread defection among certain nationality groups in the Soviet Union during World War II may reveal something of the persistence of ethnic and national iden- titics. One of the most powerful arguments against intinducing a plural party system in Yugoslavia is the danger that parties would form around ci hnic groups and intensify ethnic conflicts. Where the barriers to the public expression of preferences are high, as in the Soviet Union, one can only guess at the patterns that conflict would take were the differences allowed to express themselves. In Yugoslavia, Where the barriers have been very much reduced, the variety of interests c la in ling attention is remarkable. And during the brief period when the barriers were dropped in Czechoslovakia, diversity flourished like long-dormant flowers in a desert after a rain. Thus it is a reasonable conjecture that whenever the barriers to the public expression of preferences are reduced in Communist countries, in the long run (should they get through the short-run period of turmoil that may ensue) they will face a problem not so much of polarization as of diversity and possible segmentation. The experiences of the countries described in this volume seem to support what I referred to at the beginning of this chapter as a well-grounded observation: differences in political preferences among the people of a country tend toward diversity and multiplicity rather than bipolarity. To many readers, the proposition, which is hardly a novel one, will seem so nearly self-evident that any appeal to experience of the kind I have just made is an exercise in demonstrating the obvious. Yet some readers, I am sure, will remain unconvinced. Admittedly I have done no more than assert the existence of a very general and ubiquitous tendency, and a statement of a general tendency is a long way from a precise proposition in a comprehensive theory. At a minimum, a satisfactory theory would say something about the variations in the strength and characteristics of this tendency, the conditions under which polarization, even if an infrequent process, would be likely to occur, the causes and consequences of crosscutting rather than reinforcing cleavages, and doubtless many other matters. But perhaps it is enough here simply to give some substance to the assertion that the general tendency exists over long periods and in a great many countries at different stages of socioeconomic development and with different political regimes and economic systems. A hasty reader might be tempted at this point to jump to some unwarranted conclusions. To say that polarization, like the plague, is rare is obviously not to say that it presents no dangers. And because polarization, though rare, is dangerous, one should not leap to the conclusion that a multiplicity of political interests, though more common, inevitably produces cohesion and stability. For diversity, like polarization, can also Robert A. I hi hi iiTiilc problems, even for polyarchies. In what follows ir is tlic problems which sccni to stem from diversity rather than from polarization that I want to stress. But first let me emphasize one further part of the argument. Regimes and Interests < hiv part of the argument I offered at the beginning was that the lower tin MUTterS to, or the greater the opportunities for, expressing, organizing, uad representing political preferences, the greater the number and variety ol (inferences that would be represented in policy making. Hence the number and variety of interests represented in policy making would be greater under a polyarchy than under a mixed regime and greater under I mixed regime than under a hegemony. Therefore the transformation of .1 hi'jioruony into a mixed regime or polyarchy, or of a mixed regime into II polyarchy, would increase the number and variety of preferences and Interests in policy making. If one were not careful about definitions, the argument could of course become circular. Even if a meticulous concern for definitions will enable us to avoid the latent circularity, the hypothesis is not easy to test. Yet i tunges in regime occur, and the results do seem to bear out the argument. W hen hegemonic regimes are suddenly displaced by regimes that provide greater opportunities for opposition — as in Spain after the flight of the l