"National Security" as an Ambiguous Symbol Author(s): Arnold Wolfers Source: Political Science Quarterly, Vol. 67, No. 4 (Dec., 1952), pp. 481-502 Published by: The Academy of Political Science Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2145138 Accessed: 30-09-2020 14:32 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: https://www.jstor.org/stable/2145138?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms The Academy of Political Science is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Political Science Quarterly This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Volume LXVII December 1952 Number 4 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY NATIONAL SECURITY " AS AN AMBIGUOUS SYMBOL TATESMEN, publicists and scholars who wish to be con S sidered realists, as many do today, are inclined to insist that the foreign policy they advocate is dictated by the national interest, more specifically by the national security interest. It is not surprising that this should be so. Today any reference to the pursuit of security is likely to ring a sympathetic chord. However, when political formulas such as " national interest " or " national security " gain popularity they need to be scrutinized with particular care. They may not mean the same thing to different people. They may not have any precise meaning at all. Thus, while appearing to offer guidance and a basis for broad consensus they may be permitting everyone to label whatever policy he favors with an attractive and possibly deceptive name. In a very vague and general way " national interest" does suggest a direction of policy which can be distinguished from several others which may present themselves as alternatives. It indicates that the policy is designed to promote demands which are ascribed to the nation rather than to individuals, sub-national groups or mankind as a whole. It emphasizes that the policy subordinates other interests to those of the nation. But beyond this, it has very little meaning. When Charles Beard's study of The Idea of National Interest was published in the early years of the New Deal and under the [481] This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 482 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VOL. LXVII impact of the Great Depression, the lines were drawn differently than they are today. The question at that time was whether American foreign policy, then largely economic in scope and motivation, was aimed not at promoting the welfare interests of the nation as a whole but instead at satisfying the material interests of powerful sub-national interest or pressure groups. While it was found hard to define what was in the interest of national welfare or to discover standards by which to measure it, there could be no doubt as to what people had in mind: they desired to see national policy makers rise above the narrow and special economic interests of parts of the nation to focus their attention on the more inclusive interests of the whole. Today, the alternative to a policy of the national interest to which people refer is of a different character. They fear policy makers may be unduly concerned with the " interests of all of mankind ". They see them sacrificing the less inclusive national community to the wider but in their opinion chimeric world community. The issue, then, is not one of transcending narrow group selfishness, as it was at the time of Beard's discussion, but rather one of according more exclusive devotion to the narrower cause of the national self. There is another difference between the current and the earlier debate. While it would be wrong to say that the economic interest has ceased to attract attention, it is overshadowed today by the national security interest. Even in the recent debates on the St. Lawrence Seaway, clearly in the first instance an economic enterprise, the defenders of the project, when seeking to impress their listeners with the " national interest " involved, spoke mainly of the value of the Seaway for military defense in wartime while some opponents stressed its vulnerability to at- tack. The change from a welfare to a security interpretation of the symbol " national interest" is understandable. Today we are living under the impact of cold war and threats of external aggression rather than of depression and social reform. As a result, the formula of the national interest has come to be practically synonymous with the formula of national security. Unless explicitly denied, spokesmen for a policy which would This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms No. 4] NATIONAL SECURITY 483 take the national interest as that priority shall be given t analyzed.' The question is rais ingly more precise formula o men a meaningful guide for action. Can they be expected to know what it means? Can policies be distinguished and judged on the ground that they do or do not serve this interest? The term national security, like national interest, is well enough established in the political discourse of international relations to designate an objective of policy distinguishable from others. We know roughly what people have in mind if they complain that their government is neglecting national security or demanding excessive sacrifices for the sake of enhancing it. Usually those who raise the cry for a policy oriented exclusively toward this interest are afraid their country underestimates the external dangers facing it or is being diverted into idealistic channels unmindful of these dangers. Moreover, the symbol suggests protection through power and therefore figures more frequently in the speech of those who believe in reliance on national power than of those who place their confidence in model behavior, international cooperation, or the United Nations to carry their country safely through the tempests of international conflict. For these reasons it would be an exaggeration to claim that the symbol of national security is nothing but a stimulus to semantic confusion, though closer analysis will show that if used without specifications it leaves room for more confusion than sound political counsel or scientific usage can afford. The demand for a policy of national security is primarily normative in character. It is supposed to indicate what the 1 Hans Morgenthau's In Defense of the National Interest (New York, 1951) is the most explicit and impassioned recent plea for an American foreign policy which shall follow " but one guiding star-the National Interest ". While Morgenthau is not equally explicit in regard to the meaning he attaches to the symbol " national interest ", it becomes clear in the few pages devoted to an exposition of this " perennial" interest that the author is thinking in terms of the national security interest, and specifically of security based on power. The United States, he says, is interested in three things: a unique position as a predominant Power without rival in the Western Hemisphere and the maintenance of the balance of power in Europe as well as in Asia, demands which make sense only in the context of a quest for security through power. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 484 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VOL. LXVII policy of a nation should be in order to be either expedient-a rational means toward an accepted end-or moral, the best or least evil course of action. The value judgments implicit in these normative exhortations will be discussed. Before doing so, attention should be drawn to an assertion of fact which is implicit if not explicit in most appeals for a policy guided by national security. Such appeals usually assume that nations in fact have made security their goal except when idealism or utopianism of their leaders has led them to stray from the traditional path. If such conformity of behavior actually existed, it would be proper to infer that a country deviating from the established pattern of conduct would risk being penalized. This would greatly strengthen the normative arguments. The trouble with the contention of fact, however, is that the term " security " covers a range of goals so wide that highly divergent policies can be interpreted as policies of security. Security points to some degree of protection of values previously acquired. In Walter Lippmann's words, a nation is secure to the extent to which it is not in danger of having to sacrifice core values, if it wishes to avoid war, and is able, if challenged, to maintain them by victory in such a war.2 What this definition implies is that security rises and falls with the ability of a nation to deter an attack, or to defeat it. This is in accord with common usage of the term. Security is a value, then, of which a nation can have more or less and which it can aspire to have in greater or lesser measure.3 It has much in common, in this respect, with power or wealth, two other values of great importance in international affairs. But while wealth measures the amount of a nation's material 2 Walter Lippmann, U. S. Foreign Policy (Boston, 1943), p. 51. 3 This explains why some nations which would seem to fall into the category of status quo Powers par excellence may nevertheless be dissatisfied and act very much like " imperialist " Powers, as Morgenthau calls nations with acquisitive goals. They are dissatisfied with the degree of security which they enjoy under the status quo and are out to enhance it. France's occupation of the Ruhr in 1923 illustrates this type of behavior. Because the demand for more security may induce a status quo Power even to resort to the use of violence as a means of attaining more security, there is reason to beware of the easy and often self-righteous assumption that nations which desire to preserve the status quo are necessarily " peace-loving ". This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms No. 47 NATIONAL SECURITY 485 possessions, and power its ability to control the actions of others, security, in an objective sense, measures the absence of threats to acquired values, in a subjective sense, the absence of fear that such values will be attacked. In both respects a nation's security can run a wide gamut from almost complete insecurity or sense of insecurity at one pole, to almost complete security or absence of fear at the other.4 The possible discrepancy between the objective and subjective connotation of the term is significant in international relations despite the fact that the chance of future attack never can be measured "objectively "; it must always remain a matter of subjective evaluation and speculation. However, when the French after World War I insisted that they were entitled to additional guarantees of security because of the exceptionally dangerous situation which France was said to be facing, other Powers in the League expressed the view that rather than to submit to what might be French hysterical apprehension the relative security of France should be objectively evaluated. It is a well-known fact that nations, and groups within nations, differ widely in their reaction to one and the same external situation. Some tend to exaggerate the danger while others underestimate it. 'With hindsight it is sometimes possible to tell exactly how far they deviated from a rational reaction to the actual or objective state of danger existing at the time. Even if for no other reasons, this difference in the reaction to similar threats suffices to make it probable that nations will differ in their efforts to obtain more security. Some may find the danger to which they are exposed entirely normal and in line with their 4Security and power would be synonymous terms if security could be attained only through the accumulation of power, which will be shown not to be the case. The fear of attack-security in the subjective sense-is also not proportionate to the relative power position of a nation. Why, otherwise, would some weak and exposed nations consider themselves more secure today than does the United States? Harold D. Lasswell and Abraham Kaplan, Power and Society (New Haven, 1950), defining security as "high value expectancy " stress the subjective and speculative character of security by using the term " expectancy " ; the use of the term " high ", while indicating no definite level, would seem to imply that the security-seeker aims at a position in which the events he expects-here the continued unmolested enjoyment of his possessions-have considerably more than an even chance of ma- terializing. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 486 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VOL. LXVII modest security expectations while others consider it unbearable to live with these same dangers. Although this is not the place to set up hypotheses on the factors which account for one or the other attitude, investigation might confirm the hunch that those nations tend to be most sensitive to threats which have either experienced attacks in the recent past or, having passed through a prolonged period of an exceptionally high degree of security, suddenly find themselves thrust into a situation of danger.5 Probably national efforts to achieve greater security would also prove, in part at least, to be a function of the power and opportunity which nations possess of reducing danger by their own efforts.6 Another and even stronger reason why nations must be expected not to act uniformly is that they are not all or constantly faced with the same degree of danger. For purposes of a working hypothesis, theorists may find it useful at times to postulate conditions wherein all states are enemies-provided they are not allied against others-and wherein all, therefore, are 5 The United States offers a good illustration and may be typical in this respect. For a long time this country was beyond the reach of any enemy attack that could be considered probable. During that period, then, it could afford to dismiss any serious preoccupation with security. Events proved that it was no worse off for having done so. However, after this happy condition had ceased to exist, government and people alike showed a lag in their awareness of the change. When Nicholas J. Spykman raised his voice in the years before World War II to advocate a broader security outlook than was indicated by the symbol "Western Hemisphere Defense" and a greater appreciation of the role of defensive military power, he was dealing with this lag and with the dangers implied in it. If Hans Morgenthau and others raise their warning voices today, seemingly treading in Spykman's footsteps, they are addressing a nation which after a new relapse into wishful thinking in 1945 has been radically disillusioned and may now be swinging toward excessive security apprehensions. 6 Terms such as " degree " or " level " of security are not intended to indicate merely quantitative differences. Nations may also differ in respect to the breadth of their security perspective as when American leaders at Yalta were so preoccupied with security against the then enemy countries of the United States that they failed or refused to consider future American security vis-a-vis the Soviet Union. The differences may apply, instead, to the time range for which security is sought as when the British at Versailles were ready to offer France short-run security guarantees while the French with more foresight insisted that the "German danger" would not become acute for some ten years. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms No. 4] NATIONAL SECURITY 487 equally in danger of attack.7 But, while it may be true in the living world, too, that no sovereign nation can be absolutely safe from future attack, nobody can reasonably contend that Canada, for example, is threatened today to the same extent as countries like Iran or Yugoslavia, or that the British had as much reason to be concerned about the French air force in the twenties as about Hitler's Luftwaffe in the thirties. This point, however, should not be overstressed. There can be no quarrel with the generalization that most nations, most of the time-the great Powers particularly-have shown, and had reason to show, an active concern about some lack of security and have been prepared to make sacrifices for its enhancement. Danger and the awareness of it have been, and continue to be, sufficiently widespread to guarantee some uniformity in this respect. But a generalization which leaves room both for the frantic kind of struggle for more security which characterized French policy at times and for the neglect of security apparent in American foreign policy after the close of both World Wars throws little light on the behavior of nations. The demand for conformity would have meaning only if it could be said-as it could under the conditions postulated in the working hypothesis of pure power politics-that nations normally subordinate all other values to the maximization of their security, which, however, is obviously not the case. There have been many instances of struggles for more security taking the form of an unrestrained race for armaments, alliances, strategic boundaries and the like; but one need only recall the many heated parliamentary debates on arms appropriations to realize how uncertain has been the extent to which people will consent to sacrifice for additional increments of security. Even when there has been no question that armaments would mean more security, the cost in taxes, the reduction in social benefits or the sheer discomfort involved has militated effectively against further effort. It may be worth noting in 7 For a discussion of this working hypothesis-as part of the " pure power " hypothesis-see my article on " The Pole of Power and the Pole of Indifference " in World Politics, vol. IV, No. 1, October 1951. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 488 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VOL. LXVII this connection that there seems to be no case in history in which a country started a preventive war on the grounds of security-unless Hitler's wanton attack on his neighbors be allowed to qualify as such-although there must have been circumstances where additional security could have been obtained by war and although so many wars have been launched for the enhancement of other values. Of course, where security serves only as a cloak for other more enticing demands, nations or ambitious leaders may consider no price for it too high. This is one of the reasons why very high security aspirations tend to make a nation suspect of hiding more aggressive aims. Instead of expecting a uniform drive for enhanced or maximum security, a different hypothesis may offer a more promising lead. Efforts for security are bound to be experienced as a burden; security after all is nothing but the absence of the evil of insecurity, a negative value so to speak. As a consequence, nations will be inclined to minimize these efforts, keeping them at the lowest level which will provide them with what they consider adequate protection. This level will often be lower than what statesmen, military leaders or other particularly security-minded participants in the decision-making process believe it should be. In any case, together with the extent of the external threats, numerous domestic factors such as national character, tradition, preferences and prejudices will influence the level of security which a nation chooses to make its target. It might be objected that in the long run nations are not so free to choose the amount of effort they will put into security. Are they not under a kind of compulsion to spare no effort provided they wish to survive? This objection again would make sense only if the hypothesis of pure power politics were a realistic image of actual world affairs. In fact, however, a glance at history will suffice to show that survival has only exceptionally been at stake, particularly for the major Powers. If nations were not concerned with the protection of values other than their survival as independent states, most of them, most of the time, would not have had to be seriously worried about their This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms No. 4] NATIONAL SECURITY 489 security, despite what manip in mustering greater securit trary. What " compulsion " there is, then, is a function not merely of the will of others, real or imagined, to destroy the nation's independence but of national desires and ambitions to retain a wealth of other values such as rank, respect, material possessions and special privileges. It would seem to be a fair guess that the efforts for security by a particular nation will tend to vary, other things being equal, with the range of values for which protection is being sought. In respect to this range there may seem to exist a considerable degree of uniformity. All over the world today peoples are making sacrifices to protect and preserve what to them appear as the minimum national core values, national independence and territorial integrity. But there is deviation in two directions. Some nations seek protection for more marginal values as well. There was a time when United States policy could afford to be concerned mainly with the protection of the foreign investments or markets of its nationals, its " core values " being out of danger, or when Britain was extending its national self to include large and only vaguely circumscribed " regions of special interest". It is a well-known and portentous phenomenon that bases, security zones and the like may be demanded and acquired for the purpose of protecting values acquired earlier; and they then become new national values requiring protection themselves. Pushed to its logical conclusion, such spatial extension of the range of values does not stop short of world domi- nation. A deviation in the opposite direction of a compression of the range of core values is hardly exceptional in our days either. There is little indication that Britain is bolstering the security of Hong Kong although colonies were once considered part of the national territory. The Czechs lifted no finger to protect their independence against the Soviet Union and many West Europeans are arguing today that rearmament has become too destructive of values they cherish to be justified even when national independence is obviously at stake. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 490 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VOL. LXVH The lack of uniformity does not end here. A policy is not characterized by its goal, in this case security, alone. In order to become imitable, the means by which the goal is pursued must be taken into account as well. Thus, if two nations were both endeavoring to maximize their security but one were placing all its reliance on armaments and alliances, the other on meticulous neutrality, a policy maker seeking to emulate their behavior would be at a loss where to turn. Those who call for a policy guided by national security are not likely to be unaware of this fact, but they take for granted that they will be understood to mean a security policy based on power, and on military power at that. Were it not so, they would be hard put to prove that their government was not already doing its best for security, though it was seeking to enhance it by such means as international codperation or by the negotiation of compromise agreements-means which in one instance may be totally ineffective or utopian but which in others may have considerable protective value. It is understandable why it should so readily be assumed that a quest for security must necessarily translate itself into a quest for coercive power. In view of the fact that security is being sought against external violence-coupled perhaps with internal subversive violence-it seems plausible at first sight that the response should consist in an accumulation of the same kind of force for the purpose of resisting an attack or of deterring a would-be attacker. The most casual reading of history and of contemporary experience, moreover, suffices to confirm the view that such resort to " power of resistance " has been the rule with nations grappling with serious threats to their security, however much the specific form of this power and its extent may differ. Why otherwise would so many nations which have no acquisitive designs maintain costly armaments? Why did Denmark with her state of complete disarmament remain an exception even among the small Powers? But again, the generalization that nations seeking security usually place great reliance on coercive power does not carry one far. The issue is not whether there is regularly some such This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms No. 4] NATIONAL SECURITY 491 reliance but whether there a nations concerning their over-all choice of the means upon which they place their trust. The controversies concerning the best road to future security that are so typical of coalition partners at the close of victorious wars throw light on this question. France in 1919 and all the Allies in 1945 believed that protection against another German attack could be gained only by means of continued military superiority based on German military impotence. President Wilson in 1919 and many observers in 1945 were equally convinced, however, that more hope for security lay in a conciliatory and fair treatment of the defeated enemy, which would rob him of future incentives to renew his attack. While this is not the place to decide which side was right, one cannot help drawing the conclusion that, in the matter of means, the roads which are open may lead in diametrically opposed directions.8 The choice in every instance will depend on a multitude of variables, including ideological and moral convictions, expectations concerning the psychological and political developments in the camp of the opponent, and inclinations of individual policy makers.9 After all that has been said little is left of the sweeping generalization that in actual practice nations, guided by their national security interest, tend to pursue a uniform and there- 8 Myres S. McDougal (" Law and Peace " in the American Journal of International Law, vol. 46, No. 1, January 1952, pp. 102 et seq.) rightly criticizes Hans Morgenthau (and George Kennan for what Kennan himself wrongly believes to be his own point of view in the matter; see fn. 15 infra) for his failure to appreciate the role which non-power methods, such as legal procedures and moral appeals, may at times successfully play in the pursuit of security. But it is surprising how little aware McDougal appears to be of the disappointing modesty of the contributions which these "other means " have actually made to the enhancement of security and the quite insignificant contributions they have made to the promotion of changes of the status quo. This latter failure signifies that they have been unable to remove the main causes of the attacks which security-minded peoples rightly fear. 9 On the problem of security policy (Sicherheitspolitik) with special reference to collective security " see the comprehensive and illuminating study of Heinrich Rogge, " Kollektivsicherheit Buendnispolitik Voelkerbund ", Theorie der nationalen und internationalen Sicherheit (Berlin, 1937), which deserves attention despite the fact that it was written and published in Nazi Germany and bears a distinctly "revisionist " slant. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 492 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VOL. LXVII fore imitable policy of security. Instead, there are numerous reasons why they should differ widely in this respect, with some standing close to the pole of complete indifference to security or complete reliance on nonmilitary means, others close to the pole of insistence on absolute security or of complete reliance on coercive power. It should be added that there exists still another category of nations which cannot be placed within the continuum connecting these poles because they regard security of any degree as an insufficient goal; instead they seek to acquire new values even at the price of greater insecurity. In this category must be placed not only the " mad Caesars ", who are out for conquest and glory at any price, but also idealistic statesmen who would plunge their country into war for the sake of spreading the benefits of their ideology, for example, of liberating enslaved peoples. The actual behavior of nations, past and present, does not affect the normative proposition, to which we shall now turn our attention. According to this proposition nations are called upon to give priority to national security and thus to consent to any sacrifice of value which will provide an additional increment of security. It may be expedient, moral or both for nations to do so even if they should have failed to heed such advice in the past and for the most part are not living up to it today. The first question, then, is whether some definable security policy can be said to be generally expedient. Because the choice of goals is not a matter of expediency, it would seem to make no sense to ask whether it is expedient for nations to be concerned with the goal of security itself; only the means used to this end, so it would seem, can be judged as to their fitnesstheir instrumental rationality-to promote security. Yet, this is not so. Security, like other aims, may be an intermediate rather than an ultimate goal, in which case it can be judged as a means to these more ultimate ends. Traditionally, the protection and preservation of national core values have been considered ends in themselves, at least by those who followed in the footsteps of Machiavelli or, for other This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms No. 4] NATIONAL SECURITY 493 reasons of political philosophy, placed the prince, state or nation at the pinnacle of their hierarchy of values. Those who do so today will be shocked at the mere suggestion that national security should have to be justified in terms of higher values which it is expected to serve. But there is a large and perhaps growing current of opinion-as a matter of fact influential in this country for a long time-which adheres to this idea. We condemn Nazis and Communists for defending their own totalitarian countries instead of helping to free their people from tyranny; we enlist support for armaments, here and in Allied countries, not so much on the grounds that they will protect national security but that by enhancing such security they will serve to protect ultimate human values like individual liberty. Again, opposition in Europe and Asia to military security measures is based in part on the contention that it would help little to make national core values secure, if in the process the liberties and the social welfare of the people had to be sacrificed; the prevention of Russian conquest, some insist, is useless, if in the course of a war of defense a large part of the people were to be exterminated and most cities destroyed.'0 While excellent arguments can be made to support the thesis that the preservation of the national independence of this country is worth almost any price as long as no alternative community is available which could assure the same degree of order, justice, peace or individual liberty, it becomes necessary to provide such arguments whenever national security as a value in itself is being questioned. The answer cannot be taken for granted. But turning away now from the expediency of security as an intermediate goal we must ask whether, aside from any moral considerations which will be discussed later, a specific level of 10 Raymond Dennett goes further in making the generalization that, " if economic pressures become great enough, almost any government, when put to the final test, will moderate or abandon a political association " (such as the alliance system of the United States with its usefulness to national security) " if only an alteration of policy seems to offer the possibility of maintaining or achieving living standards adequate enough to permit the regime to survive." "Danger Spots in the Pattern of American Security ", in World Politics, vol. IV, No. 4, July 1952, p. 449. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 494 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VOL. LXVII security and specific means of attaining erally expedient. When one sets out to define in terms o of security to which a nation should aspire, one might be tempted to assume that the sky is the limit. Is not insecurity of any kind an evil from which any rational policy maker would want to rescue his country? Yet, there are obvious reasons why this is not so. In the first place, every increment of security must be paid by additional sacrifices of other values usually of a kind more exacting than the mere expenditure of precious time on the part of policy makers. At a certain point, then, by something like the economic law of diminishing returns, the gain in security no longer compensates for the added costs of attaining it. As in the case of economic value comparisons and preferences, there is frequently disagreement among different layers of policy makers as to where the line should be drawn. This is true particularly because absolute security is out of the question unless a country is capable of world domination, in which case, however, the insecurities and fears would be "internalized " and probably magnified. Because nations must " live dangerously ", then, to some extent, whatever they consent to do about it, a modicum of additional but only relative security may easily become unattractive to those who have to bear the chief burden. Nothing renders the task of statesmen in a democracy more difficult than the reluctance of the people to follow them very far along the road to high and costly security levels. In the second place, national security policies when based on the accumulation of power have a way of defeating themselves if the target level is set too high. This is due to the fact that "power of resistance " cannot be unmistakably distinguished from " power of aggression ". What a country does to bolster its own security through power can be interpreted by others, therefore, as a threat to their security. If this occurs, the vicious circle of what John Herz has described as the " security dilemma" sets in: the efforts of one side provoke countermeasures by the other which in turn tend to wipe out the gains of This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms No. 4] NATIONAL SECURITY 495 the first. Theoretically there seems to be no escape from this frustrating consequence; in practice, however, there are ways to convince those who might feel threatened that the accumulation of power is not intended and will never be used for attack.11 The chief way is that of keeping the target level within moderate bounds and of avoiding placing oneself in a position where it has to be raised suddenly and drastically. The desire to escape from this vicious circle presupposes a security policy of much self-restraint and moderation, especially in the choice of the target level.12 It can never be expedient to pursue a security policy which by the fact of provocation or incentive to others fails to increase the nation's relative power position and capability of resistance. The question of what means are expedient for the purpose of enhancing security raises even more thorny problems. Policy makers must decide how to distribute their reliance on whatever means are available to them and, particularly, how far to push the accumulation of coercive power. No attempt can be made here to decide what the choice should be in order to be expedient. Obviously, there can be no general answer which would meet the requirements of every case. The answer depends on the circumstances. A weak country may have no better means at its disposal than to prove to stronger neighbors that its strict neutrality can be trusted. Potentially strong countries may have a chance to deter an aggressor by creating " positions of strength ". In some instances they may have no other way of saving themselves; while in others even they may find it more expedient to supplement such a policy, if not to 11 Not everyone agrees that this can be done. Jeremy Bentham wrote that " measures of mere self defense are naturally taken for projects of aggression " with the result that "each makes haste to begin for fear of being forestalled." Principles of International Law, Essay IV. 12 The Quakers, in a book on The United States and the Soviet Union: Some Quaker Proposals for Peace (New Haven, 1949), p. 14, state that "it is highly questionable whether security can be achieved in the modern world through an attempt to establish an overwhelming preponderance of military power." This can be read to mean that a less ambitious military target than overwhelming preponderance might be a means of achieving security. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 496 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VOL. LXVII replace it, by a policy intended to nego of his aggressive designs. The reason why " power of resistance " is not the general panacea which some believe it to be lies in the nature of security itself. If security, in the objective sense of the term at least, rises and falls with the presence or absence of aggressive intentions on the part of others, the attitude and behavior of those from whom the threat emanates are of prime importance. Such attitude and behavior need not be beyond the realm of influence by the country seeking to bolster its security. Whenever they do not lie beyond this realm the most effective and least costly security policy consists in inducing the opponent to give up his aggressive intentions. While there is no easy way to determine when means can and should be used which are directed not at resistance but at the prevention of the desire of others to attack, it will clarify the issue to sketch the type of hypotheses which would link specific security policies, as expedient, to some of the most typical political constellations. One can think of nations lined up between the two poles of maximum and minimum " attack propensity ", with those unalterably committed to attack, provided it promises success, at one pole and those whom no amount of opportunity for successful attack could induce to undertake it at the other. While security in respect to the first group can come exclusively as a result of " positions of strength " sufficient to deter or defeat attack, nothing could do more to undermine security in respect to the second group than to start accumulating power of a kind which would provoke fear and countermoves. Unfortunately it can never be known with certainty, in practice, what position within the continuum one's opponent actually occupies. Statesmen cannot be blamed, moreover, if caution and suspicion lead them to assume a closer proximity to the first pole than hindsight proves to have been justified. We believe we have ample proof that the Soviet Union today is at or very close to the first pole, while Canadian policy makers probably place the United States in its intentions toward Canada at the second pole. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms No. 4] NATIONAL SECURITY 497 It is fair to assume that, wh comes a matter of serious co dealing with potential oppone where between but much clo This means, then, that an att even though the intention to have crystallized to the poin If this be true, a security poli avoid accumulating power of at that. Efforts have to be goal of removing the incentiv way of saying that security p to occupy a position as close t capabilities permit. Such a twofold policy presen efforts to change the intentio to the efforts to build up str any policy of concessions, sy be underestimated. The paradox of this situation must be faced, however, if security policy is to be expedient. It implies that national security policy, except when directed against a country unalterably committed to attack, is the more rational the more it succeeds in taking the interests, including the security interests, of the other side into consideration. Only in doing so can it hope to minimize the willingness of the other to resort to violence. Rather than to insist, then, that under all conditions security be sought by reliance on nothing but defensive power and be pushed in a spirit of national selfishness toward the highest targets, it should be stressed that in most instances efforts to satisfy legitimate demands of others are likely to promise better results in terms of security."' That is probably what George Kennan had in mind when he advised policy makers to use self-restraint in the pursuit of the national interest. While in the face of a would-be world conqueror who is beyond the pale of external influence it is dangerous to be di- 13 As A. D. Lindsay puts it, " The search for perfect security . . . defeats its own ends. Playing for safety is the most dangerous way to live." Introduction to Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, p. xxii. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 498 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VOL. LXVII verted from the accumulation of sheer defensive power, any mistake about his true state of mind or any neglect of opportunities to influence his designs, where it has a chance of being successful, violates the rules of expediency. It should always be kept in mind that the ideal security policy is one which would lead to a distribution of values so satisfactory to all nations that the intention to attack and with it the problem of security would be minimized. While this is a utopian goal, policy makers and particularly peacemakers would do well to remember that there are occasions when greater approximation to such a goal can be effected. We can now focus our attention on the moral issue, if such there be.14 Those who advocate a policy devoted to national security are not always aware of the fact-if they do not explicitly deny it-that they are passing moral judgment when they advise a nation to pursue the goal of national security or when they insist that such means as the accumulation of coercive power-or its use-should be employed for this purpose.'5 Nations like individuals or other groups may value things not because they consider them good or less evil than their alternative; they may value them because they satisfy their pride, heighten their sense of self-esteem or reduce their fears. However, no policy, or human act in general, can escape becoming a subject for moral judgment-whether by the conscience of the actor himself or by others-which calls for the sacrifice of other values, as any security policy is bound to do. Here it becomes a matter of comparing and weighing values in order to 14 On the moral problem in international relations see my article on " Statesmanship and Moral Choice" in World Politics, vol. I, No. 2, January 1949, pp. 176 et seq., especially p. 185. In one of his most recent statements on the subject, Reinhold Niebuhr, The Irony of American History (New York, 1945), points specifically to the moral problem involved in security policy-" no imperiled nation ", he writes, "is morally able to dispense with weapons which might insure its survival" (p. 39). 15 It is not without irony that of the two authors who have recently come out for a policy of the national interest, the one, George F. Kennan, who calls for a policy of national self-restraint and humility, usually identified with morality, should deny " that state behavior is a fit subject for moral judgment " (American Diplomacy, 1900-1950, Chicago, 1952, p. 100), while the other, Hans Morgenthau (op. cit.), calling for a policy of unadulterated national egotism, claims to speak in the name of morality. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms No. 4] NATIONAL SECURITY 499 decide which of them are d the evil of sacrificing other try should do more to build up its strength, he is implying, knowingly or not, that more security is sufficiently desirable to warrant such evils as the cut in much-needed social welfare benefits or as the extension of the period of military service.-' Many vivid examplPs of the moral dilemma are being supplied by current controversies concerning American security policy. Is a " deal with fascist Spain " morally justified, provided it added an increment to our security, though principles valued highly by some were being sacrificed? Should we engage in subversive activities and risk the lives of our agents if additional security can be attained thereby? Should we perhaps go so far as to start a preventive war, when ready, with the enormous evils it would carry with it, if we should become convinced that no adequate security can be obtained except by the defeat of the Soviet Union? In this last case, would not the exponents of amoralism have some moral qualms, at least to the point of rationalizing a decision favoring such a war by claiming that it would serve to satisfy not primarily an egotistical national demand for security but an altruistic desire to liberate enslaved peoples? It is easier to argue for the amorality of politics if one does not have to bear the responsibility of choice and decision! Far be it from a political scientist to claim any particular competence in deciding what efforts for national security are or are not morally justified. What he can contribute here is to point to the ambiguities of any general normative demand that security be bought at whatever price it may cost. He may also be able to make it more difficult for advisers or executors of policy to hide from themselves or others the moral value judgments and preferences which underlie whatever security policy they choose to recommend or conduct. The moral issue will be resolved in one of several ways de- 16It would be unrealistic to assume that policy makers divide their attention strictly between ends and means and only after having chosen a specific target level as being morally justified decide whether the means by which it can be attained are morally acceptable. Moral judgment is more likely to be passed on the totality of a course of action which embraces both the desired end and the means which lead to it. This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 500 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VoL. LXVI pending on the ethical code upon which the decision is based. From one extreme point of view it is argued that every sacrifice, especially if imposed on other nations, is justified provided it contributes in any way to national security. Clearly this implies a position that places national security at the apex of the value pyramid and assumes it to constitute an absolute good to which all other values must be subordinated. Few will be found to take this position because if they subscribed to a nationalistic ethics of this extreme type they would probably go beyond security-the mere preservation of values-and insist that the nation is justified in conquering whatever it can use as Lebensraum or otherwise. At the opposite extreme are the absolute pacifists who consider the use of coercive power an absolute evil and condemn any security policy, therefore, which places reliance on such power. For anyone who does not share these extreme views the moral issue raised by the quest for national security is anything but clear-cut and simple. He should have no doubts about the right of a nation to protect and preserve values to which it has a legitimate title or even about its moral duty to pursue a policy meant to serve such preservation. But he cannot consider security the supreme law as Machiavelli would have the statesman regard the ragione di stato. Somewhere a line is drawn, which in every instance he must seek to discover, that divides the realm of neglect, the " too-little ", from the realm of excess, the " toomuch ". Even Hans Morgenthau who extols the moral duty of self-preservation seems to take it for granted that naked force shall be used for security in reaction only to violent attack, not for preventive war. Decision makers are faced with the moral problem, then, of choosing first the values which deserve protection, with national independence ranking high not merely for its own sake but for the guarantee it may offer to values like liberty, justice and peace. He must further decide which level of security to make his target. This will frequently be his most difficult moral task though terms such as adequacy or fair share indicate the kind of standards that may guide him. Finally, he must choose the means and thus by scrupulous computation of values compare This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms No. 4] NATIONAL SECURITY 5O1 the sacrifices, which his choic rity they promise to provide. It follows that policies of nat good or all evil, may be moral depending on their specific ch stances of the case. They may and the consideration which t security; they may instead be to protect national values. Aga instance for the consideration particularly of weaker nations of the recklessness with whic altar of some chimera. The tar ment for being too ambitious being inadequate; the means em costly in other values or for b of variety which arises out of the value computation would meaningless, to pass moral ju " national security policy in ge It is this lack of moral homo curity policy justifies attacks on moral evaluation. The " m mean a wholesale condemnatio tional security-as being an ex of a security policy relying on The exponent of such " mora security for all peoples can be such " good" and altruistic m suasion, a spirit of conciliation world government. If there ar notion, and have influence on to disabuse them of what can illusions. It is worth emphasizing, ho argument, which without rega would praise everything done f ticularly everything done fo This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 502 POLITICAL SCIENCE QUARTERLY [VOL. LXVII power of resistance, is no less guilty of applying simple and abstract moral principles and of failing to judge each case realistically on its merits. In conclusion, it can be said, then, that normative admonitions to conduct a foreign policy guided by the national security interest are no less ambiguous and misleading than the statement of fact concerning past behavior which was discussed earlier. In order to be meaningful such admonitions would have to specify the degree of security which a nation shall aspire to attain and the means by which it is to be attained in a given situation. It may be good advice in one instance to appeal for greater effort and more armaments; it may be no less expedient and morally advisable in another instance to call for moderation and for greater reliance on means other than coercive power. Because the pendulum of public opinion swings so easily from extreme complacency to extreme apprehension, from utopian reliance on " good will " to disillusioned faith in naked force only, it is particularly important to be wary of any simple panacea, even of one that parades in the realist garb of a policy guided solely by the national security interest. ARNOLD WOLFERS YALE UNIVERSITY This content downloaded from 147.251.169.17 on Wed, 30 Sep 2020 14:32:40 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms