Re-Ordering Justice: Towards A New Methodological Approach to Studying Transitional Justice Author(s): BRIAN GRODSKY Source: Journal of Peace Research , november 2009, Vol. 46, No. 6 (november 2009), pp. 819-837 Published by: Sage Publications, Ltd. Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/25654498 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Sage Publications, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of Peace Research This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms journal of ? The Author(s), 2009. Reprints and permissions: http://www.sagepub. co. uk/journalsPermissions. nav, vol. 46, no. 6, 2009, pp. 819-837 Sage Publications (Los Angeles, London, New Delhi, RESEARCH Singapore andWashington DC) http:lljpr.sagepub.com DOI 10.1177/0022343309340108 Re-Ordering Justice: Towards A New Methodological Approach to Studying Transitional Justice* BRIAN GRODSKY Department of Political Science, University of Maryland, Baltimore County Scholars and policymakers have turned increasing attention to questions of transitional justice, those legal responses to a former regime's repressive acts following a change in political systems. Although there is a rich, interdisciplinary literature that addresses the value of various transitional justice meas ures, theoretical arguments for how and under what conditions we should expect to see these measures implemented tend to gravitate to intuitively appealing relative power considerations. But attempts at parsimony have tended to leave the dependent variable either overly restrictive or poorly defined, yield ing theories that are difficult to test. In this article, the author proposes a 'transitional justice spectrum' based on a hierarchical series of possible accountability mechanisms and designed to allow research ers to conduct more rigorous, cross-national tests of justice arguments. The objective here is not to posit a broad theory of transitional justice, but to open the debate into a methodological weakness in the transitional justice literature. The article includes seven accountability mechanisms: cessation and codification of human rights violations; condemnation of the old system; rehabilitation and compensa tion for victims; creation of a truth commission; purging human rights abusers from public function; criminal prosecution of 'executors' (those lower on the chain-of-command); criminal prosecution of commanders (those higher on the chain-of-command). Introduction Over the past 15 years, scholars and policy makers have turned increasing attention to questions of transitional justice, those legal responses to a former regime's repressive acts following a change in the political system. Although a rich, interdisciplinary literature addresses the value of various transitional jus tice measures, theoretical arguments concern ing how and under what conditions we should expect to see these measures implemented * I would like to thank JPR Associate Editor Anne Julie Semb, reviewer Eileen Babbitt, an anonymous reviewer, and Devin Hagerty for their very helpful comments on earlier drafts of this article. Correspondence: bgrodsky@ umbc.edu. are limited. The current literature, born as oppressive regimes from Latin America to Eastern Europe began to fall in the 1970s and 1980s, evolves around intuitively appeal ing relative power considerations. But attempts at parsimony have frequently left the dependent variable either overly restrict ive or poorly defined, yielding theories that are difficult to test. In this article, I propose a 'transitional justice spectrum' based on a hierarchical series of possible accountability mechanisms and designed to allow research ers to conduct more rigorous, cross-national tests of transitional justice arguments. This article is not intended to posit - or directly refute - a broad theory of transitional justice, a task that even the most renowned 819 This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 820 journal of VEACE RESEARCH volume 461 number 61 november 2009 scholars have declared extraordinarily diffi cult (Elster, 2004). Rather, it is meant to open a debate into a methodological issue: how best to test existing and future theories. The transitional justice spectrum is intended to serve as a yardstick to assess causality in transitional justice decisionmaking, an ana lytical tool that will impose greater clarity on what, and subsequently how, transitional justice researchers are measuring. I begin by explaining the accountability dilemma (why new elites should support or eschew accountability policies) and reviewing arguments concerning determinants of tran sitional justice. I focus on the central argu ment in the literature, which contends that the relative strength of new and old elites is the primary determinant of accountability policy. I then elaborate on a mechanism that can be used to test this and other transi tional justice causal theories. Finally, I briefly discuss ways this spectrum can be used. Transitional Justice: Determinants of Action Transitional justice scholars frequently approach their subject equipped with legal and normative arguments for why new elites might pursue various forms of accountability (Vinjamuri & Snyder, 2004). One under lying theme is the need for the new state to acknowledge the former regime's role in human rights abuses. A lack of exposure may preclude society from reaching a consensus on the historical wrongs and therefore dam age attempts to form a new societal bond (O'Donnell & Schmitter, 1986: 30). Hayner (2001: 27) highlights the important role per ceptions of 'truth' play in a stratified, post transition society, suggesting that disparate versions of a country's repressive history fuel political tensions that may turn violent. Indeed, this fear has proven legitimate in countries such as Rwanda and Yugoslavia, where recent cases of massive rights violations were at least partly rooted in historic abuses. By individualizing blame, accountability policies can end the 'dangerous culture of collective guilt' that contributes to long-term instability (Kritz, 1996: 128). With respect to democratic consolida tion, transitional justice proponents argue that accountability signals the start of insti tutional reforms, demonstrates that all citi zens are liable under the same law, and can encourage public support for previously absent democratic values, such as equality and participation (Crocker, 1999: 47-54; Graybill, 1999: 5; Huntington, 1991: 213; Jaspers, 1995: 198-199). Justice can help forge a common historical understanding, demonstrate new elites' institutional disap proval of rights violations and even enable a new government to enhance its own legitim acy by constructing a wall between itself and the former regime (Jaspers, 1995). Criminal prosecutions may satisfy victim demands and clear the way for otherwise unattainable victim compensation (Landsman, 1996: 82) and might deter future leaders tempted by injustice (D'Amato, 1994: 503). Even a relatively moderate accounting, however, may lead to political instability (O'Donnell & Schmitter, 1986). Though legal scholars question the legitimacy of potentially unpopular blanket amnesties (Burke-White, 2001: 13; Hayner, 1996b), risks, ranging from military coups to social divisiveness and civil war, may prompt new elites to abandon private preferences for harsh accountability (Zalaquett, 1992: 1431). These risks have for centuries forced polit ical elites to wrestle with whether to punish or forgive members of oppressive regimes (Elster, 2004). Contemporary debate can be traced back to the immediate post-World War II period, when the victorious Allied forces applied still-evolving international judicial norms to vanquished powers accused of heinous war crimes (Teitel, 2003). The Nuremberg and Tokyo trials were a leap in This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Brian Grodsky Transitional Justice 821 international human rights, but they took place under 'exceptional political conditions' (Teitel, 2003: 70) that quickly disappeared. During the Cold War, bipolar power strug gles eclipsed the nascent transitional justice movement (Evans, 1996). As harsh authori tarian regimes in Latin America, Africa, and Southern and Eastern Europe fell in the 1970s and 1980s, incoming elites sought to balance the norms of justice that emerged in the post-war era with political constraints present in the absence of all-out military victory. Retributive measures, such as mass criminal trials, were frequently replaced with more lenient policies, including blanket amnesties and truth commissions. Perhaps as a result of these systemic observa tions, various theoretical arguments designed to identify key determinants of, or impediments to, pursuing justice in post-repressive states are bound by a common thread: a focus on the relative power of incoming and outgoing elites (Aguilar, 2001: 99; Barahona De Brito, Gonzales-Enriquez &C Aguilar, 2001: 11; Benomar, 1995: 41; Huyse, 1995: 63; Roehrig, 2002: 199; Sieder, 2001: 162; Sutter, 1995: 121; Zalaquett, 1992: 1432). While these arguments include a range of independent variables, relative power tends to operate as a trump card where the greater the relative strength of the old elites compared to the new, the less likely we should see new elites pursue 'harsh' forms of justice (Huyse, 1995:78). Strands of this relative power hypothesis are differentiated by definitions of power and underlying processes. Huntington's widely cited political elite level typology explains transitional justice as a function of top-level political power as mediated by the transition process from authoritarian rule to democ racy (Huntington, 1991: 230-231). Elites rising to power through revolution are most likely to implement harsh forms of retribu tive justice, since the former regime's power base (and ability to meddle in the new state) is presumably destroyed. By contrast, new regimes empowered following a negotiated transition or old elite-led transformation (where authoritarian leaders control the speed and character of change to democracy) often give explicit or implicit amnesties to members of the still-powerful old regime and should therefore show restraint in the accountability sphere. Other scholars adhering to the relative power logic define power more broadly, taking into account state structures. O'Donnell & Schmitter (1986: 28), for example, empha size the continued presence in key power ministries of those actors complicit in prior abuses. In the South American context, the military is particularly relevant; in Eastern Europe, the police and secret services might receive more attention (Rosenberg, 1995). Loyalties to the old regime and potential feelings of complicity among members of the state apparatus could impair a new elite's capacity to rule, much less engage in transi tional justice. Finally, others apply an even broader defin ition of power, based on public support. Zalaquett (1995), for example, introduces the role of non-elites, arguing that a state's social (e.g. ethnic, religious) structure may preclude certain types of justice that could antagonize intrasocietal relations. Some also consider the role of memory and temporal as well as qualitative aspects of past rights abuses (Aguilar, 2001: 97; Elster, 2006: 11; Huyse, 1995: 71-73; O'Donnell & Schmitter, 1986: 30; Pion-Berlin, 1994). Dangers of transitional justice are more than elite-based, with potential immediate consequences out side of the official realm. Even Huntington, despite his succinct typology, acknowledges this, referring frequently to referenda and quoting one Romanian government official as saying, 'If we publish the [secret police] files as some people have suggested, there could literally be something worse than a civil war with friend turning against friend This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 822 journal of Peace research volume 461 number 61 november 2009 once they find out what is contained in them' (Huntington, 1991: 230). While these arguments all look at justice as a function of power, they differ with respect to who determines the relative power of old and new, as well as with regard to the implicit or explicit mechanisms that make relative power a serious constraint. Support ers of Huntington's political elite argument seem to stress normative aspects of the bar gaining process but also, like state structure proponents, imply the risk of a coup or failed state (marked by the inability of new elites to implement policies) where relatively weak new elites pursue retributive justice upsetting to the old guard. By contrast, those focused on societal conditions warn that aggressive justice could prompt civic unrest and even civil war depending on attitudes, and per haps level of complicity, of broader society. Ultimately, however, each argument focuses on new elite's fears that powerful elements implicated in yesterday's rights violations can destabilize the political sphere if they perceive justice policies as threatening. These various relative power arguments all point astutely to potential risks of transitional justice, but each comes with a set of potential weaknesses. Challengers to elite-level argu ments might ask why post-oppositionists should respect deals made through arm twisting by illegitimate outgoing elites, par ticularly in cases where new elites quickly and democratically accrue more political power than predicted by transition type. While state structure explanations address this, they leave unaddressed important ques tions about the cohesiveness of subpolitical actors, most of whom were probably not directly complicit in past violations. Structur alists also side-step the issue of mass partici pation in the initial regime change, a factor that may embolden post-oppositionists. The most obvious weakness of public attitude explanations is, as with the preceding strains of relative power, a lack of elasticity. Are public attitudes non-malleable, structurally determined by experiences and perceptions of past injustices? Or are they more dynamic, influenced by perceptions of present govern mental successes and failures (Holmes, 1994: 34; Walicki, 1997), or even subject to elite persuasion (Jacobs et al., 1998; Koch, 1998; Powlick, 1991)? The purpose of raising these weaknesses is not to directly challenge these theories but to suggest the need for more vigorous scrutiny. The shortcomings described demonstrate the types of holes and inconsistencies prone to fester in theories not tested using clear meas ures of validity. Indeed, perhaps because of the natural appeal of relative power explanations, scholars frequently defend them by largely anecdotal evidence. Huntington, for example, evaluates his popular argument by referring to a range of cases, from the Philippines to Romania, that appear to support his thesis. To pick one example, I look at the case of Uruguay, which Huntington claims had, under military rule, the highest proportion of political prisoners in the world (Huntington, 1991: 211). According to Huntington, the transitional justice policies of Uruguay's new leaders, who came to power through nego tiations, were severely constrained by the prevailing power of military leaders who first promised to obstruct criminal prosecutions and then made threats in order to (success fully, Huntington says) influence a public referendum on the subject (Huntington, 1991: 226-229). Similarly, the new regime's relative weakness left it unable to pursue a truth commission which, according to one general, would have compromised the amnesty military leaders assured themselves by handing over power. Instructive as this study is, Huntington is guilty of over-simplification, resting his theory that across cases 'justice was a function of pol itical power' (Huntington, 1991: 228) on the observation of only two aspects of justice, criminal prosecutions and truth commissions. This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Brian Grodsky Transitional Justice 823 Even arguments intended to look beyond relative power frequently revert to this binary indicator. Huyse (1995:76), for example, con cludes that 'the need to avoid confrontation' prompts new elites to exchange criminal pros ecutions for truth commissions as the least unsatisfactory solution' (Huyse, 1995: 78). Sieff & Wright (1999: 759), who argue that relative power sets the parameters for the application of the norms of justice', similarly conclude that if new elites believe peace and justice are reconcilable they will prosecute, but otherwise they will opt for truth commis sions (Sieff & Wright, 1999: 769). This focus on the 'usual suspects' of transitional justice (criminal trials, amnesties or truth commis sions) is problematic. First, these terms may marginalize other justice measures that have been used (perhaps successfully) by polit ical elites around the world. Indeed, scholars have explored the pros and cons of a gamut of intermediate policies, including public apolo gies, victim compensation, and banning per petrators from public office (Crocker, 1999; Gibney & Roxstrom, 2001; Kritz, 1996; Minow, 1998: 23; Reilly, 2002). More importantly, underspecification of the dependent variable makes it difficult to produce hypotheses and empirical observa tions that succinctly correlate power to jus tice type. How can one correlate transitional justice and power when there is no clear understanding of how the many transitional justice measures relate to one another? How do these policies compare to one another qualitatively, and under what conditions will a new leadership decide to implement which steps? While relative power might correlate nicely with the likelihood of criminal pros ecutions, this does not provide strong evi dence that justice is a function of power - only that one type of justice appears to be affected by this particular independent variable. If transitional justice policies are a function of relative power, it seems both the primary independent variable (old-new elite power) and dependent variable (justice type) should be defined incrementally. If, for example, we begin doing this and concede that prosecu tions and administrative purges are 'harsher' than truth commissions, then relative power proponents might expect a weak new elite leadership to launch truth commissions rather than prosecutions or purges. But what if, for example, the new leadership instead conducts purges but finds itself unable to launch an independent truth commission (as was the case, for example, in some post communist states)? This may be suggestive that something other than (and perhaps exclusive of) relative power is at work. By specifying the dependent variable, we estab lish clear expectations that can be evaluated systematically and objectively. Scholars addressing the broad range of transitional justice options to date tend to refrain from outlining a clear policy hierarchy (Minow, 1998: 23; Reilly, 2002). Rankings tend to be restricted to the obvi ous, when discussion touches on only two or three policy options (especially blanket amnesties, truth commissions, and criminal prosecutions) and general policy guidelines remain limited to the 'how to', rather than 'when to' or 'when not to', of one specific accountability policy (Hayner, 1996b; Landsman, 1996). Authors are clearly cog nizant of the different risk levels involved in the policy options, but there has been no attempt to systematically address this. Yet, without explicitly defining the dependent variable in ways that allow one to measure risk, it is difficult to have confidence in the widespread consensus that relative power is the key determinant of justice. Vagueness of the dependent variable there fore renders relative power arguments obtuse, perhaps prompting skeptical authors to chal lenge them by positing new arguments rather than explicitly identifying evidence to reject the prevailing ones. Moran, for exam ple, found little support for relative power This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 824 journal of PEACE RESEARCH volume 461 number 61 november 2009 arguments in Central Europe, arguing instead that justice is influenced by psychological determinants based on die degree to which opponents in the former system could voice their opposition or emigrate (Moran, 1994). In an analysis of three Latin American states, Pion-Berlin (1994) found that while the nature of rights violations and relative power issues set the boundaries for political action, elite preferences and strategic calculation shaped concrete policy outcomes within these confines. The fact that these arguments seem to have had little resonance in the transitional justice literature may result from the grow ing belief that there is no single determinant (Elster, 2006), but it may also follow from the difficulty in explicitly taking on the prevailing argument without adequate instruments. Transitional Justice Spectrum The goal of this section is not to challenge the relative power argument per se, but to suggest ways of testing it and other theor etical arguments concerning transitional justice. The first step towards this objective involves specifying the dependent variable, accountability mechanisms available to a new regime. There exists a range of possible actions that leaders can undertake to pursue accountability for human rights violations. Through a review of the democratization and transitional justice literatures, I have identi fied seven frequently used policies and placed them in a 'transitional justice spectrum'. These mechanisms are ranked by the degree to which they personalize responsibility, as well as by the severity of each policy's reper cussions for the perpetrators. These measures co-vary early in the spectrum, but after stage four, when concrete individuals are already targeted, severity increases independently. (1) Cessation and codification of human rights violations; (2) Condemnation of the old system; (3) Rehabilitation and compensation for victims; (4) Creation of a truth commission; (5) Purging human rights abusers from public function; (6) Criminal prosecution of executors' (those lower on the chain-of-command); (7) Criminal prosecution of commanders (those higher on the chain-of-command). The logic of the spectrum is twofold. Most broadly, it organizes justice mechanisms along a continuum that gradually proceeds from restorative (alleviating victims' pain) to retributive (punishing perpetrators). At the same time, and not coincidentally, this spectrum incorporates a relative power logic, since each incremental step up the accountability ladder involves implementa tion of a more provocative, or threatening, policy, with respect to members of the old regime. This spectrum operationalizes risk in ways that should explicitly allow justice scholars to observe strengths and weak nesses of relative power arguments, which should dictate the highest level of account ability feasible for a new leadership. In the straightforward case of Huntington, for example, we should find weak regimes (e.g. those handed power by old elites) to go no further than stage 1; moderately strong regimes might pursue up to stage 4; and only the strongest regimes (e.g. those aris ing out of revolution) should pursue stages 5 through 7. In cases where these expec tations are not met, use of this spectrum might suggest other determinants. In my own research (described below), I used elite interviews, in which I questioned how and why each of these measures was or was not applied, to generate and test alternative theories. In the remainder of this section, I describe each step on the proposed spectrum, includ ing a brief discussion of the measure's pros and cons, a theoretical rationale for its risk This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Brian Grodsky Transitional Justice 825 assessment rating and a series of examples illustrating how this measure has been carried out in practice, as well as the threats associ ated with it. It is important to emphasize that while readers may disagree with the specific ordering of these measures (e.g. preferring to switch stages 2 and 3 or 6 and 7), this should not detract from the use of this spectrum as a general tool. Moreover, such disagree ments - and especially empirical evidence to back them - should generate further discus sion that might strengthen future versions of this instrument. I. Cessation and Codification of Human Rights Violations In a democratizing state, one basic task for the new regime is to halt rights violations. New leaders can codify the most brutal rights violations orchestrated by previous political elites by signing, ratifying, and integrating into domestic law major inter national human rights conventions. On the international stage, external states often base future cooperation on their potential partner's reputation information (how they upheld past international commitments, including those in the human rights sphere) (Donnelly, 1986: 608; Fearon, 1998; Gelpi, 1997; Putnam, 1988). The heavy invest ment (e.g. long process) involved in treaty negotiation and ratification is also sugges tive that participating parties intend to remain true to their promises (Chayes & Chayes, 1993). Indirectly, international treaties can alter a signing state's political institutions as subunits of different govern ments come together in treaty monitoring bodies, where conflicting loyalties to the home state and treaty mission become fluid, even resulting in new coalitions that influ ence a state's home capital rather than the reverse (Burley & Mattli, 1993; Keohane & Nye, 1974). Ratification of international rights agreements can also alter internal political opportunity structures, emboldening opposition groups and expanding their collective action 'repertoire' in ways that make them more formidable opponents to potential rights violators (Pharr, 1990; Tarrow, 1991, 1994). Because cessation and codification of vio lations involves exclusively positive steps, without indirectly or directly confronting old power holders or rights abusers who linger in the state apparatus, this measure is essen tially risk-free. The cessation of rights viola tions and adoption of international rights norms mark a new course in a country's poli tics but do not personally threaten the old power holders. New political elites do not confront (either directly or indirectly) those complicit in past abuses, yet they ensure pro accountability forces in society that their most essential judicial needs are met. A review of signatories to the Inter national Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), the ICCPR's first proto col allowing the Human Rights Commit tee to accept private citizen complaints, and the Convention against Torture suggests that incoming regimes do use international human rights agreements to signal a new era of liberty (UNHCR, 2004). During a major period of liberalization in Algeria (1989), for example, the country's new lead ers passed all of these agreements in a three month span. A similar pattern is clear in such diverse states as Angola (1992, as the country embarked on multi-party elections), Sudan (1986, just after the fall of President Numeiry), Argentina (1986, following the country's 'dirty war'), and Benin (1992, following democratic elections that ended decades of military rule). Soon after the fall of communism, most former Soviet and East Bloc states signed on to at least one human rights convention protecting political rights formerly denied. That so many associated with previous rights abuses pushed for the codification of these guarantees is evidence of the low risk of this stage. This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 826 journal of PEACE RESEARCH volume 461 number 61 november 2009 II. Condemnation of the Old System The exclusively positive nature of stage 1 is supplanted by a broad and impersonal attack in the form of a general declaration of con demnation of the old system. This can take a variety of shapes, from parliamentary laws and resolutions to public speeches by high-level government officials. The goal, according to Jaspers (1995: 198), is to make 'a clear dis tinction between the transitional government and the previous regime'. Formal condemna tion of, or apology for, past abuses is typically seen as restorative, a first step towards soci etal reconciliation (McGregor, 2001). But condemnation also serves a mild retributive function, the gateway to culpability in which groups are implicated in past misdeeds. Despite sharing some retributive charac teristics, new elites at this early stage of cen sure avoid threatening their predecessors by condemning the system rather than specific actors, The unpleasantness of political humi liation is in some ways diminished by pre existing societal awareness of abuses (Kritz, 1996). Perhaps more importantly, members of the old elite remain generally protected by ambiguity and their own capacity to explain away their personal roles (Payne, 2001). Gray masses from repressive bureaucracies can off set responsibility by claiming to be cogs in the machine, personally unaware of what was ulti mately being churned out. The increased weight of condemna tion (relative to the mere codification of rights violations) is demonstrated by the fierce resistance states put up to impersonal rebukes of their countries on the interna tional stage (Cain, 1999; Donnelly, 1988). At the United Nations, for example, Security Council resolutions with no legal enforce ment power are protested in tense debates, walkouts, and even official vetoes (IPNSA, 2004). On the domestic stage, condemna tion may be met with tolerance or repen tance on the side of the condemned, but it can also draw negative reactions (Gilligan, 2003; Lindner, 2001). Only after six years of debate did Spanish right-wing parties finally agree in 2002 to an embarrassing resolution condemning the rule of dictator Francisco Franco, who had died more than 20 years earlier (Aguilar & Humblebaek, 2002: 132). Argentinean ex-general and former ruler Jorge Videla, sentenced to life imprisonment in 1985 for his role in murders, abduction, and torture, was indignant when pardoned five years later, calling for 'the army's vindi cation and the reparation of military honors' {Toronto Star, 1991). In each case, affiliates of the former regime denied wrongdoing and resisted public rebuke. III. Rehabilitation and Compensation for Victims Rehabilitation, including the annulment of sentences issued in the context of polit ical repression, and compensation are two restorative measures aimed at improving the lives of former victims (Posner & Vermeule, 2004). Like condemnation, they can also mark a break with the past. Rehabilitation involves returning full civil rights to those unrightfully persecuted, whether practically (for those still alive) or symbolically. Because compensation requires potentially heavy state financial allocations, it may be more costly and controversial. Scholars argue that fiscal measures can help 'right' past wrongs materially as well as symbolically (Crocker, 1999: 51), and some go so far as to argue that victims' 'well-being should not be sacrificed in the interest of national reconciliation' (Landsman, 1996: 86). Intergovernmental organizations have claimed post-repressive states are obliged to provide legal and finan cial redress to former victims (CE, 1996; UN, 1993, 1996). In contrast to vague condemnations, rehabili tation and compensation may be seen by affili ates of the former regime as a step towards personal accountability. If this family suf fered, who inflicted the pain? Perhaps for This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Brian Grodsky Transitional Justice 827 this reason, the commander-in-chief of the Chilean navy rejected a presidential promise to provide reparations as a 'foolish and offen sive way of dealing with established concepts and rules such as security, intelligence, due obedience and others' (BBC, 1991a). Simi larly, when the Spanish right-wing Popular Party finally agreed to legislation condemn ing Franco-era totalitarianism, it continued to oppose clauses mandating rehabilitation and reparations for Franco's political pris oners (Aguilar & Humblebaek, 2002: 132). Political liability inherent in public expen ditures (Simpson & van Zyl, 1995) has prompted politicians from Sri Lanka (Rees, 1990) to Czechoslovakia (Green, 1990) to water down compensation measures or cre ate legal obstacles designed to reduce the number of beneficiaries. The Argentinean government in 1992, for example, prom ised to compensate former convicts of mili tary courts but not judicial courts and other categories of victims (Chaudhary, 1992). This may serve a dual function, since associ ates of the old regime sometimes balk at the notion that the rules they helped create or enforce were somehow wrong (Kalisz, 2003; Paprzycki, 2003). IV. Creation of a Truth Commission Truth Commissions, or officially sanctioned, temporary bodies established to clarify past abuses, are frequently cited as a 'third way' between criminal prosecutions and blanket amnesties (Hayner, 1996a, 2001; Sieff & Wright, 1999). Truth commissions perform several functions, from providing an environ ment in which victims and/or perpetrators can tell their stories to supplying an official forum for 'a meaningful acknowledgment of past abuses' (Kritz, 1996: 138). Com missions can be public or private, aggressive or passive, empowered with legal rights of forgiveness (amnesty) or deprived of legal authority. They can be functional (estab lishing official records of death necessary for relatives to attain benefits) or metaphysical (generating open discussions intended to ease tensions; Hayner, 2001). Hearings are often victim-oriented, providing what Crocker calls a 'public platform for victims' where they 'receive sympathy for their suffering' (Crocker, 1999: 48; Graybill, 1999; Hayner, 2001). But they can also be understood as society-oriented, to the degree that they aim to promote reconciliation, or policy-oriented, when they document abuse patterns useful in reforming the system or organs in question. Though usually branded restorative mech anisms, truth commissions mark the tran sition from earlier accountability measures that only indirectly assigned responsibility to later measures that explicitly personalize blame. Retributive aspects may be subtle (rights violators are not formally deprived of their freedom or livelihoods), but profound effects of public humiliation (Cohen, 2003: 1075; Riezler, 1943; Shweder, 2003), rang ing from social ostracism to political defeat, have led some to label this 'concealed ret ribution' (McGregor, 2001: 38; Hayner, 2001: 24; Osiel, 2000; Zalaquett, 1995). While alleged perpetrators may be dismissive (Payne, 2001; Shapiro, 2003), identifica tion of former rights violators, particularly in public truth commissions, is one step up the ladder towards personal accountability and directly threatening those aligned with the former system. Investigation of the much-heralded South African Truth and Reconciliation Commis sion (TRC) highlights the risks inherent in this process. Former South African President F. W. de Klerk used continued white power to press for amnesty for his constituents (de Klerk, 1999: 288). ANC leaders, contending with anti-amnesty constituents, accepted a truth commission characterized by conditional amnesties as a compromise (Eades, 1999; Jackson, 1998; Newham, 1995; Waldmeir, 1997: 213; Wilson, 2001: 7). Even then, many whites saw the truth commission as a This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 828 journal of PEACE RESEARCH volume 467'number 61' no v ember 2009 threat rather than a bargain, a witch-hunt' in the words of the TRC chair (TRC, 1995). As a result, many in the potentially danger ous security services chose to remain in the shadows rather than risk speaking up and then being denied amnesty (Davenport, 1998). Security services in other states have been more vocal, with members of El Salvador's military opposing a UN-sponsored Truth Commission on the grounds that 'because of a few bad (members), an entire institu tion is being judged' (Wilkinson & Miller, 1992; Alder, 1993). Some new leaders may purposely limit the scope or powers of the commission to avoid upsetting the new bal ance (Dicklitch & Lwanga, 2003). V Purging Human Rights Abusers from Public Positions While stages 1 through 4 of this transitional justice spectrum spare former rights abusers formal sanction, employment bans for the first time impinge on their civil liberties. According to some scholars, such bans can increase societal trust in critical public insti tutions and enhance rule-of-law concepts (Kritz, 1996) and can also act as a (restora tive) form of affirmative action by creating positions for people previously denied jobs on account of their political views (Esquith, 1999). On the other hand, such purges bring about a range of practical and ethical con cerns about whom to target and what sorts of limitations to apply (Baehr, 2000; CE, 1996; Rigby, 2001). Purges can be destabilizing, whether because they weaken state capacity (by expunging the only trained specialists) or create strong incentives for collective action on the part of banned actors (Kritz, 1996). As provocative as this measure may seem to some elites, there are ways to lessen the risk of destabilizing collective action by those being purged. Older functionaries, for exam ple, may be able to transition into (early) retirement, while the younger ones may either have less experience with the former regime (and therefore be allowed to stay in their positions) or be able to relatively eas ily find a new source of income (Kozlowski, 2004; Moran, 1994). By adopting a new profession or accepting a lesser role in pub lic life, members of the former regime may continue to enjoy freedom and avoid crim inal liability in the new order. At the same time, human rights offenders are punished for their actions and separated from the new government. The tension between an urge to purge and a fear of potential destabilization may suf fice to delay or even reverse policy. Immedi ately after taking power from the military in Greece, for example, Karamanlis dismissed senior level ministry personnel and launched a vetting of the old bureaucracy that resulted in 108,000 disciplinary actions, mostly involv ing termination (Kritz, 1996; Nanda, 1998: 391). Yet, the government waited for the retirement of a brigadier loyal to the former regime before feeling secure enough to purge the higher military ranks, retiring more than 200 army officers {Economist, 1975a: 12). In El Salvador, an official report calling for purges of officers accused of rights viola tions and corruption sent rumors of a mili tary coup through the country (Wilkinson & Miller, 1992). Even purges that followed a military victory, such as that after World War II, frequently resulted in rollbacks, per haps as a result of these pressures. In Japan, for example, less than 9,000 of an initially purged 202,000 remained punished once the Allies left; similarly, Italians reinstated under a 1948 amnesty most of the 2,000 government employees purged there (Nanda, 1998: 391). VI. Criminal Prosecution of'Executors* Since the Nuremberg Trials of Nazi lead ers following World War II, and through subsequent international treaties such as the Convention on the Prevention and Punish ment of the Crime of Genocide (1948) and This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Brian Grodsky Transitional Justice 829 the Convention Against Torture (1984), international law has promoted the prosecu tion of human rights criminals (Ratner & Abrams, 2001). Over the years, intergovern mental organizations and local courts have increasingly justified and encouraged criminal prosecutions based on international human rights law (CE, 1996; Fletcher & Weinstein, 2002; Roht-Arriaza, 1996). Scholars have argued prosecutions of individuals can cre ate a historical record, satisfy victims' desires for justice, and further democratic values of equality and accountability (Huntington, 1991; Jaspers, 1995; McGregor, 2001) while reducing the risk of collective guilt (Kritz, 1996) and vigilante justice {Economist, 1976: 47; McGregor, 2001). Criminal prosecutions raise the sever ity of consequences for rights violations to a new level (deprivation of freedom), but come with a myriad of practical difficulties. A lack of qualified lawyers or judges, espe cially those not tainted by activities under the previous regime they are to try, has been blamed for multi-year pre-trial detentions in countries such as Ethiopia and Rwanda and overly lenient sentences in other states (AFP, 1997; Kritz, 1996: 133; Naszkowska, 1992; von Kellenbach, 2003). There are also ethical and legal questions concern ing 'retrospective justice' (Nino, 1996: 166-179). Finally, there are concerns that the severity of the repercussions could lead to resistance by those accused or even whole institutions whose personnel fear extended witch hunts. Such fears prompted the Argentinian defense minister in 1986 to order expedited trials of the 300 officers awaiting justice so as to avoid 'an image of collective judgment' which could provoke military unrest (Graham, 1986). A series of army mutinies eventually forced the government to end prosecutions (Barham, 1992), and upon taking power, President Carlos Menem quickly pardoned the 39 senior officers convicted.1 Thinly veiled threats from military leaders in Ecuador (LARP, 1980) and Chile (BBC, 1991a,b) were successful in at least temporarily thwarting trials there, as well. Opposition to a 2002 UN call for criminal prosecutions in Sierra Leone (AN, 2002a) prompted one local newspaper to warn that attempts at criminal justice may cause great harm where weapons remain in the hands of those complicit (AN, 2002b). VII. Criminal Prosecution of Commanders Limited capabilities or fears that wide-scale trials could disrupt state operations may prompt new elites to launch a more limited set of trials that still demonstrate a commit ment to justice (Crocker, 1999; Kritz, 1996; McGregor, 2001). Pursuing leaders, or the most culpable (Kritz, 1996: 6), may allevi ate the danger that lower-level functionaries feel they are scapegoats (Kamali, 2001: 107; Osiel, 2000: 126; Rigby, 2001: 104-105), but can be potentially more risky for sev eral reasons. First, lower ranking officials may regardless see senior-level prosecutions as the first phase of a witch hunt (Roehrig, 2002: 199). Second, senior-level leaders may command respect and organizational loyalty useful in orchestrating a reaction at lower levels. Finally, this ripple effect may reach far deeper, creating perhaps unexpected societal reactions in a world where even the most brutal dictators seem capable of evok ing immense emotional solidarity. Fifty years after Stalin's funeral, which drew tens of thousands, one attendee recalled, 'It was as if we lost the father of the family, the person who took care of us. We felt like orphans' (Rosenberg, 2003). These pressures are visible in a range of cases. Weeks before new elites moved to 1 Interestingly, President Kirchner in 2003 felt secure enough to sponsor a law annulling immunity for approxi mately 2,000 former military men allegedly tied to pre-1983 abuses (Hennigan, 2003). This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 830 journal of Peace research volume 461 number 61 november 2009 arrest and extradite to the Hague deposed Yugoslav dictator Slobodan Milosevic, opin ion polls suggested only 11 % of Yugoslavs supported his extradition (Holley, 2001) and approximately 1,000 people created a 'people's guard' to defend his home (Mitic, 2001). Post-oppositionist Prime Minister Zoran Djindjic, an advocate of criminal jus tice, warned that high-profile extraditions might lead to civil war (RFE/RL, 2002). An apartheid-era South African president warned the new government in 1995 that prosecutions of apartheid-era leaders would 'awaken the tiger in the Afrikaner' (DPA, 1995). The durability of this emotional bond was evidenced following the arrest by British authorities of Augusto Pinochet in 1998, eight years after he left power, which brought 3,000 pro-Pinochet demonstrators to the streets of Santiago (DPA, 1998). Associates of the old regime lingering in the state apparatus frequently lead the defense of their leaders. Less than a year after losing power, Greek officers launched a failed coup to secure an amnesty for imprisoned leaders of the former junta, convincing the new gov ernment to reduce those leaders' sentences {Economist, 1975a: 12,1975b: 15, 1975c: 12). Similarly, a series of army mutinies in Argentina contributed to government decisions to at first expedite trials and later issue amnesties for those senior officials convicted of human rights crimes (Barham, 1992; Graham, 1986). A continent away and a decade later, Malawi's army intercepted a brewing military coup on the eve of the trial of former Malawian ruler Hastings Kamuzu Banda, accused of involve ment in several political murders (AFP, 1995a,b; Mponda, 1995). Discussion By identifying and theoretically rank-ordering a range of accountability policies, this 'tran sitional justice spectrum' qualifies vague labels of lenient and harsh prevalent in the theoretical transitional justice literature, and it allows researchers to empirically test causal theories of transitional justice across cases. In the preceding section, I provided evidence that each incremental step up the spectrum involves more personalized responsibility and more severe repercussions to the old elite. Some of this evidence was closely linked to old elite reactions, symptoms of discomfort associated with a given measure. As men tioned above, this spectrum can be used to indicate the success of the relative power arguments, since - according to mat logic states with the strongest old elites should eschew the harshest retributive measures. And the simple nature of the spectrum is designed to make it durable across contexts. For example, while the passage of time or the nature of abuses might affect the type of justice pursued, each incremental step up the spectrum should at any point in time be more provocative than the previous stage. In other words, truth commissions will always be less provocative (or risky) than purges, which will always be less confrontational than prosecutions. But this spectrum is also a useful tool for evaluating or generating other theories related to transitional justice. Here, the spectrum functions in two ways. First, it essentially pos its relative power as the null hypothesis and gives us an ordinal tool to identify possible inconsistencies. This might be particularly useful in large-TV studies, where comparisons of cross-sample data could indicate general trends. Second, the spectrum provides a useful (if basic) checklist of important justice policies that have been implemented around the world. As with any broad framework, this list is not intended to be exhaustive, and additional measures, such as property restitution, might also be added to suit the context. Archival or interview data might be used to explore the determinants of each of these policies. Taken in the aggregate, these data could support existing theories or identify new variables. This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Brian Grodsky Transitional Justice 831 In my own research, I used this spectrum to explore why political elites pursued or eschewed various forms of justice in four diverse post-communist states: Uzbekistan, Serbia, Croatia, and Poland (Grodsky, forth coming). My theoretical argument focused on economic-based motivations, but I used this spectrum as a tool to assess other (includ ing relative power) arguments as well. My evidence was based on analyses of local and international media reports and more than 215 elite interviews conducted (in the local languages) primarily with post-oppositionists in various influential government posts and non-governmental actors involved in human rights. During the 50?90-minute meetings, interviewees were asked for their perceptions concerning why the new leadership (un)suc cessfully launched or did not launch each mechanism on the spectrum. The results of my fieldwork were fascinat ing. Across my cases (including in Uzbekistan, where any transition collapsed along with the Soviet Union), I found political elites were particularly sensitive to how various measures of justice would affect their ability to pro vide public goods to expecting populations (Grodsky, 2008b). Post-opposition elites tended to drive the accountability process, but the direction they took was usually limited by the degree to which they expected the public would perceive their activities as facilitating or hindering other, especially economic, poli cies. Relative power was deterministic only to the degree that it made measures practically impossible (e.g. post-oppositionists lacked the required votes to pass a particular law) or particularly costly (when old elites threatened to thwart other public goods-related bills as a consequence of tough accountability mea sures). The threat of voter backlash, rather than a coup or civil war, was ultimately the key constraint on justice. If Huntington applied this spectrum to the case of Uruguay discussed above, he might well find that relative power was the key determinant of justice policy. But if, for example, purges of the military (an aspect of the dependent variable that Huntington does not consider here) were instigated in the absence of truth commissions, this would highlight a weakness to his theory. Using the spectrum as a checklist in a more thorough qualitative study, Huntington might find that other factors, aside from relative power, had an important effect. For example, per haps new elites relatively supportive of lift ing the amnesty did not actively push for a 'yes' vote in the referendum, believing that a campaign for this cause would be seen by constituents as too much energy spent on past problems rather than the problems of today. Or perhaps voters who upheld the military amnesty in the referendum were not swayed by comments from the military, but by perceptions that the justice system had its hands full enough already, perhaps fight ing corruption. If earlier, less risky stages on the spectrum - such as legal rehabilitation or condemnation - were also left unaddressed, this might point to the perception among political elites that the public was simply uninterested in justice. As indicated above, this spectrum may be useful in large-TV studies where there are sufficient data concerning efforts at justice in a group of countries. If the relative power argument is correct, there should be a cor relation between the power of new elites (e.g. measured by transition type or seats in gov ernment/legislature) and the highest degree of justice pursued. But my two years of field work, trying out this spectrum, point to two areas of caution, concerning questions of reform authenticity and interaction effects. With respect to the former, users of this spec trum must be aware as they code data for each country that there may be significant differences between what I call 'genuine' and 'artificial' accountability reforms. For exam ple, a truth commission conducted in demo cratic, post-apartheid South Africa obviously This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 832 journal of PEACE RESEARCH volume 461 number 61 november 2009 differs substantially from one imposed in authoritarian Uzbekistan or Chad (Grodsky, 2008a). In other words, how measures are pursued can be just as important as whether they are pursued. Context is important and, as always, studies are only as strong as their data. This observation leads to a second cau tion for using this spectrum, particularly in large-TV studies: under certain conditions there may be interaction among various components of the dependent variable. In particular, in the relatively few cases where there are international pressures for a par ticular form of justice, leaders pursuing one form of justice may argue the enacted mechanism makes alternative justice poli cies immaterial. Serbian cooperation with the International Criminal Tribunal for the former Yugoslavia (ICTY), for example, may have precluded more aggressive bureaucratic cleansing or local criminal trials. Conversely, there is much evidence that Yugoslav President Vojislav Kostunica launched a truth commis sion in order to reduce pressure for unpopu lar handovers to the ICTY. This interaction makes it impractical to look for a correlation between one policy and another, or measure results cumulatively, under such circum stances. Still, in these unique cases it seems that the relative power argument could be assessed according to the highest stage of jus tice pursued (using the spectrum as an ordi nal measure). The fact that Serbian political leaders made so many high-level handovers to the ICTY in exchange for international support and despite the strength of former elites suggests a need to at least reconsider relative power arguments. Finally, it should be emphasized that as much as this justice spectrum is designed to deal with a significant weakness in the current theoretical literature, it is also an invitation to begin a broader debate on this subject. In order to produce coherent theories that explain why and how leaders pursue accountability for past human rights violations, we must agree on a measuring stick. This article suggests one such instru ment and opens the floor for suggestions of other mechanisms that may substitute or complement this one. The collective goal should be to increase our capacity to gener ate and test transitional justice theories in ways that are more rigorous and therefore more satisfying. References AFP, 1995a. 'President Muluzi Surprised at Rumors of Coup Plot', Agence France Presse (AFP), 23 April (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). AFP, 1995b. 'Senior Army Officer Sought on Coup Plot Charges', Agence France Presse (AFP), 26 April (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). AFP, 1997. 'More than 5,000 Ethiopians Charged with "Red Terror" Crimes', Agence France Presse (AFP), 13 February (http://www.lexis nexis.com). Aguilar, Paloma, 2001. 'Justice, Politics and Mem ory in the Spanish Transition', in Alexandra Barahona De Brito, Carmen Gonzales Enriquez & Paloma Aguilar, eds, The Politics of Memory: Transitional Justice in Democrat izing Societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Aguilar, Paloma & Carsten Humblebaek, 2002. 'Collective Memory and National Identity in the Spanish Democracy: The Legacies of Francoism and the Civil War', History and Memory 14(1-2): 121-164. Alder, Daniel, 1993. 'Salvadoran Judge Orders Release of Death Squad Killer', United Press Inter national, 3 April (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). AN, 2002a. 'Sierra Leone; Rights Body Wel comes UN Special Court', Africa News, 22 January [UN Integrated Regional Informa tion Networks] (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). AN, 2002b. 'Sierra Leone; Standard Voice Let the Special Court Wait', Africa News, 23 January [Standard Times] (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). Baehr, Peter R., 2000. 'Controversies in the Current International Human Rights Debate', Human Rights Review 2(1): 7-32. Barahona De Brito, Alexandra; Carmen Gonzales-Enriquez & Paloma Aguilar, 2001. This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Brian Grodsky Transitional Justice 833 'Introduction', in Alexandra Barahona De Brito, Carmen Gonzales-Enriquez & Paloma Aguilar, eds, The Politics of Memory: Tran sitional Justice in Democratizing Societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press (1-39). Barham, John, 1992. 'Mothers Who Mourn Their Lost Innocents: Argentina's "Disap peared" Children', Financial Times, 9 May: X (http: / / www. lexis-nexis. com). BBC, 1991a. 'Chile Navy's Opinion of Rettig Report; Government Supports Report's Veracity', BBC Summary of World Broadcasts, 1 April [Radio Nacional, Santiago, March 28, 1991] (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). BBC, 1991b. 'Chilean President's Address and Comments on Human Rights Violations Report', BBC Summary of World Broadcasts, 6 March. [Television Nacional de Chile, Santiago, 5 March] (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). Benomar, Jamal, 1995. 'Justice After Transitions', in Neil J. Kritz, ed., Transitional Justice, vol. 1. Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace Press (32-41). Burke-White, William W, 2001. 'Reframing Impunity: Applying Liberal International Law Theory to an Analysis of Amnesty Legislation', Harvard International Law Journal42: 467-534. Burley, Anne-Marie & Walter Mattli, 1993. 'Europe Before the Court: A Political Theory of Legal Integration', International Organiza tion 47(1): 41-76. Cain, Kenneth L., 1999. 'The Rape of Dinah: Human Rights, Civil War in Liberia, and Evil Triumphant', Human Rights Quarterly 21(2): 265-307. CE, 1996. 'Resolution # 1096 on Measures to Dismantle the Heritage of Former Com munist Totalitarian Systems': 1096 (http:// assembly.coe.int/Documents/AdoptedText/ ta96/eres 1096.htm). Chaudhary, Vivek, 1992. 'Argentinians Angry at "Selective" Compensation for Army's Victims', The Guardian, 26 September: 11 (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). Chayes, Abram & Antonia Handler Chayes, 1993. 'On Compliance', International Organ ization 47(2): 175-205. Cohen, Dov, 2003. 'The American National Conversation about (Everything but) Shame', Social Research 1 ?(4): 1075-1108. Crocker, David A., 1999. 'Reckoning with the Past: A Normative Framework', Ethics and International Affairs 13: 43-64. D'Amato, Anthony, 1994. 'Peace vs. Account ability in Bosnia', American Journal of Inter national Law 88(3): 500-506. Davenport, T. R. H., 1998. The Birth of a New South Africa. Buffalo, NY: University of Toronto Press. de Klerk, F. W., 1999. The Last Trek - A New Beginning: The Autobiography. New York: St. Martin's. Dicklitch, Susan & Doreen Lwanga, 2003. 'The Politics of Being Non-Political: Human Rights Organizations and the Creation of a Positive Human Rights Culture in Uganda', Human Rights Quarterly 25(2): 482-509. Donnelly, Jack, 1986. 'International Human Rights: A Regime Analysis', International Organization 40(3): 599-642. Donnelly, Jack, 1988. 'Human Rights at the United Nations 1955-1985: The Question of Bias', International Studies Quarterly 32(3): 275-303. DPA, 1995. 'Former Apartheid Leader Rejects South Africa's Truth Commission', Deutsche Presse-Agentur, 21 November (http://www. lexis-nexis.com). DPA, 1998. 'Chilean Police Use Fire Hoses To Control Pinochet Supporters', Deutsche Presse-Agentur, 19 October (http://www.kxis nexis.com). Eades, Linday Michie, 1999. The End of Apartheid in South Africa. Westport, CT: Greenwood. Economist, 1975a. 'The army and Mr. AverofE, 20 September: 12 (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). Economist, 1975b. 'Blood Doesn't Cleanse', 30 August: 15 (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). Economist, 1975c. 'Military Coup Attempt Foiled', 1 March: 12 (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). Economist, 197'6. 'Judge Better, Lest You Be Judged', 18 December: 47 (http://www.lexis nexis.com). Elster, Jon, 2004. Closing the Books: Transitional Justice in Historical Perspective. New York: Cambridge University Press. Elster, Jon, 2006. 'Introduction', in Jon Elster, ed., Retribution and Reparation in the Tran sition to Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press (1-14). This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 834 journal of PEACE RESEARCH volume 461 number 61 november 2009 Esquith, Stephen L., 1999. 'Toward a Democratic Rule of Law: East and West', Political Theory 27(3): 334-356. Evans, Tony, 1996. U.S. Hegemony and the Proj ect of Universal Human Rights. New York: St. Martin's. Fearon, James D., 1998. 'Bargaining, Enforce ment, and International Cooperation', Inter national Organization 52(2): 269-305. Fletcher, Laurel E. & Harvey M. Weinstein, 2002. 'Violence and Social Repair: Rethinking the Contribution of Justice to Reconciliation', Human Rights Quarterly 24(3): 573-639. Gelpi, Christopher, 1997. 'Crime and Punish ment: The Role of Norms in International Crisis Bargaining', American Political Science Review 91(2): 339-360. Gibney, Mark & Erik Roxstrom, 2001. 'The Status of State Apologies', Human Rights Quarterly 23(4): 911-939. Gilligan, James, 2003. 'Shame, Guilt, and Vio lence', Social Research 1 ?(4): 1149-1180. Graham, Bradley, 1986. 'Buenos Aires Presses Trials of Military; Restructuring Effort Con tinues to Lag', Washington Post, 29 April: AI 1 (http: / / www. lexis-nexis. com). Graybill, Lyn, 1999. To Punish or Pardon: A Comparison of the International Criminal Tribunal for Rwanda and the South African Truth and Reconciliation Commission', Human Rights Review 2(4): 3-18. Green, Peter S., 1990. 'Czechs Agree on Payment to Victims of Stalinism', United Press Inter national, 24 November (http://www.lexis nexis.com). Grodsky, Brian, 2008a. 'Justice Without Transi tion: Truth Commissions in the Context of Repressive Rule', Human Rights Review 9(3): 281-297. Grodsky, Brian, 2008b. 'Weighing the Costs of Accountability: The Role of Institutional Incentives in Pursuing Transitional Justice', Journal of Human Rights 7(4): 353-375. Grodsky, Brian, forthcoming. The Costs of Justice: Understanding How New Leaders Choose to Respond to Previous Rights Abuses. Advance con tract with University of Notre Dame Press. Hayner, Priscilla B., 1996a. 'Commissioning the Truth: Further Research Questions', Third World Quarterly 17(1): 19-30. Hayner, Priscilla B., 1996b. 'International Guide lines for the Creation and Operation of Truth Commissions: A Preliminary Proposal', Law and Contemporary Problems 59(4): 173-180. Hayner, Priscilla B., 2001. Unspeakable Truths: Confronting State Terror and Atrocity. New York: Routledge. Hennigan, Tom, 2003. 'Argentina Lifts Ban on "Dirty War" Military Trials', The Times, 22 August: 18 (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). Holley, David, 2001. 'Serbs Face Their Past, Dose of Truth at a Time', Los Angeles Times, 17 April: Al. Holmes, Stephen, 1994. 'The End of Decommun ization', East European Constitutional Review 3(3-4): 33-36. Huntington, Samuel, 1991. The Third Wave: Democratization in the Late Twentieth Century. Norman, OK: University of Oklahoma Press. Huyse, Luc, 1995. 'Justice after Transition: On the Choices Successor Elites Make in Dealing with the Past', Law & Social Inquiry 20(1): 51-78. IPNSA, 2004. 'Mideast: U.S. Blocks U.N. Rebuke of Israel for Assassination', Inter Press News Service Agency, 23 March (http://www. ipsnews.net). Jackson, John, 1998. 'The 1994 Election: An Analysis', in F. H. Toase & E. J. Yorke, eds, The New South Africa: Prospects for Domestic and International Security. New York: St. Martin's. Jacobs, Lawrence R.; Eric D. Lawrence, Robert Y. Shapiro & Steven S. Smith, 1998. 'Congres sional Leadership of Public Opinion', Political Science Quarterly 113(1): 21?41. Jaspers, Karl, 1995. 'The Question of German Guilt', in Neil J. Kritz, ed., Transitional Justice: How Emerging Democracies Reckon with For mer Regimes vol. 1. Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace Press (157-171). Kalisz, Ryszard, 2003. Personal communication, 22 December. Kamali, Maryam, 2001. 'Accountability for Human Rights Violations: A Comparison of Transitional Justice in East Germany and South Africa', Columbia Journal of Trans national Law 40(1): 89-142. Keohane, Robert O. & Joseph S. Nye, 1974. 'Trans governmental Relations and International Organization', World Politics 27: 39?62. This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Brian Grodsky Transitional Justice 835 Koch, Jeffrey W., 1998. 'Political Rhetoric and Political Persuasion: The Changing Structure of Citizens' Preferences on Health Insurance During Policy Debate', Public Opinion Quar terly 62(2): 209-229. Kozlowski, Krzysztof, 2004. Personal communic ation, 21 January. Kritz, Neil J., 1996. 'Coming to Terms with Atrocities: A Review of Accountability Mech anisms for Mass Violations of Human Rights', Law and Contemporary Problems 59(4): 127-152. Landsman, Stephan, 1996. 'Alternative Responses to Serious Human Rights Abuses: Of Prosecu tion and Truth Commission', Law and Con temporary Problems 59(4): 81-92. LARP, 1980. 'Ecuador's Former Junta Warns Accusers in Corruption Probe', Latin American Regional Reports, 29 February (http://www. lexis-nexis.com). Lindner, Evelin Gerda, 2001. 'Humiliation and Human Rights: Mapping a Minefield', Human Rights Review 2(3): 46-63. McGregor, Lorna, 2001. 'Individual Account ability in South Africa: Cultural Optimum or Political Facade?', American Journal of Inter national Law 95(1): 32-45. Minow, Martha, 1998. Between Vengeance and Forgiveness. Boston, MA: Beacon. Mitic, Aleksandar, 2001. 'Thousands Join Bel grade Anti-NATO Demo Two Years After Bombings', Agence France Presse, 24 March (http: //www. lexis-nexis. com). Moran, John P., 1994. 'The Communists Tortur ers of Eastern Europe - Prosecute and Punish or Forgive and Forget', Communist and Post Communist Studies 27 (\): 95-109. Mponda, Felix, 1995. 'Banda Murder Case Monday Puts African Democracy and Law on Trial', Agence France Presse, 23 April (http:// www.lexis-nexis.com). Nanda, Ved P., 1998. 'Civil and Political Sanc tions as an Accountability Mechanism for Massive Violations of Human Rights', Denver Journal of International Law and Politics 26(3): 389-397. Naszkowska, Krystyna, 1992. 'Gruba Kreska Olszewskiego', Gazeta Wyborcza, 26 May: 2. Newham, Gareth, 1995. 'Truth and Reconciliation: Realising the Ideals', Indicator SA 12(4): 7-12. Nino, Carlos Santiago, 1996. Radical Evil on Trial. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. O'Donnell, Guillermo & Philippe C. Schmitter, 1986. 'Tentative Conclusions about Uncer tain Democracies', in Guillermo O'Donnell, Philippe C. Schmitter & Laurence White head, eds, Transitions from Authoritarian Rule: Prospects for Democracy. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press (15-36). Osiel, Mark J., 2000. 'Why Prosecute? Critics of Punishment for Mass Atrocity', Human Rights Quarterly 22(1): 118-147. Paprzycki, Leszek, 2003. Personal communica tion, 12 December. Payne, Leigh A., 2001. 'Collaborators and the Politics of Memory in Chile', Human Rights Review 2(3): 8-26. Pharr, Susan J., 1990. Losing Face: Status Politics in Japan. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press. Pion-Berlin, David, 1994. 'To Prosecute or To Pardon? Human Rights Decisions in the Latin American Southern Cone', Human Rights Quarterly 16(1): 105-130. Posner, Eric A. & Adrian Vermeule, 2004. 'Tran sitional Justice as Ordinary Justice', Harvard Law Review 117(3): 761-825. Powlick, Philip J., 1991. 'The Attitudinal Bases for Responsiveness to Public Opinion among American Foreign Policy Officials', Journal of Conflict Resolution 3 5 (4): 611 -641. Putnam, Robert, 1988. 'Diplomacy and Domes tic Politics: The Logic of Two-Level Games', International Organization 42(3): 427-460. Ratner, Steven R. & Jason S. Abrams, 2001. Accountability for Human Rights Atrocities in International Law: Beyond the Nuremberg Legacy. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Rees, Christian, 1990. 'Lonely Vigil for the Loss of Innocents', The Independent, 15 October: 14 (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). Reilly, Ben, 2002. 'Democratic Levers for Conflict Management', in Peter Harris, Ben Reilly & Mark Anstey, eds, Democracy and Deep-Rooted Conflict: Options for Negotia tors. Stockholm: International Institute for Democracy and Electoral Assistance (http:// www. idea, int/publications/democracy_and_ deep_rooted_conflict/ebook_chapter4_9. html#491). This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 836 journal of PEACE RESEARCH volume 461 number 61 november 2009 RFE/RL, 2002. 'Yugoslavia: Djindjic Says Serbia Will Not Extradite Mladic', Radio Free Europe/ Radio Liberty (RFE/RL), 23 February (http:// wwsv.rferl.org). Riezler, Kurt, 1943. 'Comment on the Social Psychology of Shame', American Journal of Sociology 48(4): 457-465. Rigby, Andrew, 2001. Justice and Reconcilia tion: After the Violence. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner. Roehrig, Terence, 2002. The Prosecution of For mer Military Leaders in Newly Democratic Nations. Jefferson, NC: McFarland. Roht-Arriaza, Naomi, 1996. 'Combatting Impu nity: Some Thoughts on the Way Forward', Law and Contemporary Problems 59(4): 93-102. Rosenberg, Steve, 2003. 'Shades of spring on Stalin legacy', BBC News, 5 March (http:// news.bbc.co.uk/2/hi/europe/2821573.stm). Rosenberg, Tina, 1995. 'Overcoming the Legacies of Dictatorship', Foreign Affairs 74(3): 134-153. Shapiro, David, 2003. 'The Tortured, Not the Torturers, Are Ashamed', Social Research 70(4): 1131-1148. Shweder, Richard A., 2003. 'Toward a Deep Cul tural Psychology of Shame', Social Research 70(4): 1109-1130. Sieder, Rachel, 2001. 'War, Peace, and Memory Politics in Central America', in Alexandra Barahona De Brito, Carmen Gonzales Enriquez & Paloma Aguilar, eds, The Politics of Memory: Transitional Justice in Democratiz ing Societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press (161-190). Sieff, Michelle & Leslie Vinjamuri Wright, 1999. 'Reconciling Order and Justice? New Institu tional Solutions in Post-Conflict States'', Jour nal of International Affairs 52(2): 757-779. Simpson, Graeme & Paul van Zyl, 1995. 'South Africa's Truth and Reconciliation Commis sion', Temps Modernes 585: 394-407. Sutter, Daniel, 1995. 'Settling Old Scores: Potholes along the Transition from Authori tarian Rule', Journal of Conflict Resolution 39(1): 110-128. Tarrow, Sidney, 1991. '"Aiming at a Moving Target": Social Science and the Recent Rebel lions in Eastern Europe', PS: Political Science and Politics 24(1): 12-20. Tarrow, Sidney, 1994. Power in Movement: Social Movements, Collective Action and Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press. Teitel, Ruti G., 2003. 'Transitional Justice Genealogy', Harvard Human Rights Journal 16: 69-94. Toronto Star, 1991. 'Freed Argentine Junta Leader Accused of Provoking Unrest', (Reuters), 1 January. A16 (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). TRC, 1995. 'Archbishop Desmond Tutu's Address to the First Gathering of the Truth and Reconciliation Commission', Truth and Reconciliation Commission (TRC) Press Release, 16 December. UN, 1993. The Right to Restitution, Compen sation and Rehabilitation for Victims of Gross Violations of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms'. UN Doc. E/CN.4/Sub.2/1993/8 (http://www.unhchr.ch). UN, 1996. 'Basic Principles and Guidelines on the Right to Reparation for Victims of Gross Violations of Human Rights and Humanitar ian Law'. UN Doc. E/CN.4/Sub.2/1996/17 (http://www.unhchr.ch). UNHCR, 2004. 'Status of Ratifications for the Principal International Human Rights Trea ties' (http://www.unhchr.ch). Vinjamuri, Leslie & Jack Snyder, 2004. 'Advocacy and Scholarship in the Study of International War Crime Tribunals and Transitional Justice', Annual Review of Political Science 7: 345-362. von Kellenbach, Katharina, 2003. 'Vanishing Acts: Perpetrators in Postwar Germany', Holo caust and Genocide Studies 17(2): 305-329. Waldmeir, Patti, 1997. Anatomy of a Miracle: The End of Apartheid and the Birth of the New South Africa. New York: Norton. Walicki, Andrzej S., 1997. 'Transitional Justice and the Political Struggles in Post-Communist Poland', in A. James McAdams, ed., Tran sitional Justice and the Rule of Law in New Democracies. Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press (185-238). Wilkinson, Tracy & Marjorie Miller, 1992. 'Salvador Military Awaits Probe', Toronto Star, 13 October: A19 (http://www.lexis-nexis.com). Wilson, Richard A., 2001. The Politics of Truth and Reconciliation in South Africa: Legiti mizing the Post-Apartheid State. New York: Cambridge University Press. This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Brian Grodsky Transitional Justice 837 Zalaquett, Jose, 1992. 'Balancing Ethical Imperatives and Political Constraints: The Dilemma of New Democracies Confronting Past Human Rights Violations', Hastings Law Journal 43(1425): 1424-1438. Zalaquett, Jose, 1995. 'Confronting Human Rights Violations Committed by Former Gov ernments: Principles Applicable and Political Constraints', in Neil J. Kritz, ed., Transitional Justice, vol. 1. Washington, DC: United States Institute of Peace Press (3-31). BRIAN GRODSKY, b. 1974, PhD in Political Science (University of Michigan, 2006); Assistant Professor, University of Maryland, Baltimore County (2006- ); current main interests: democratization, global civil society, human rights. Forthcoming book: The Costs of Justice: Understanding How New Leaders Choose to Respond to Previous Rights Abuses (forthcoming, University of Notre Dame Press, 2010). This content downloaded from 147.251.61.35 on Fri, 25 Sep 2020 21:06:11 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms