359 European Journal of Politics and Gender • vol 6 • no 3 • 359–376 © European Conference on Politics and Gender and Bristol University Press 2023 Print ISSN 2515-1088 • Online ISSN 2515-1096 https://doi.org/10.1332/251510821X16654996784749 Accepted for publication 11 October 2022 • First published online 02 February 2023 Special Issue: The Field of Substantive Representation: Re-conceptualizing, Measurement, and Implications – What Have we Learned from Gender Research? RESEARCH ARTICLE From women’s presence to feminist representation: second-generation design for women’s group representation Karen Celis, karen.celis@vub.be Vrije Universiteit Brussel, Belgium Sarah Childs, sarah.childs@ed.ac.uk University of Edinburgh, UK Feminist democratic representation is a new design for women’s group representation in electoral politics. We build on the design principles and practices of the 1990s’ presence theorists, who conceived of political inclusion as the presence of descriptive representatives and advocated for gender quota. Our second-generation design foregrounds women’s ideological and intersectional heterogeneity, and details a representative process that enacts three feminist principles: inclusiveness, responsiveness and egalitarianism. A new set of actors – the affected representatives of women – play formal, institutionalised roles in two new democratic practices: group advocacy and account giving. Together, these augmentations incentivise new attitudes and behaviours among elected representatives, and bring about multiple representational effects that redress the poverty of women’s political representation: elected representatives now know more, care more and are more connected to diverse women, including the most marginalised; and the represented are now more closely connected with, more interested in and better represented through democratic politics. Key words representation • women • intersectionality • feminism • democratic design • legislatures Key messages • Despite improvement in the numbers of women in parliaments, representative democracy continues to fail women. • ‘Poverty of representation’ captures the intersectional ways in which women are both underrepresented and misrepresented. • We call for the formal presence within existing legislatures of ‘affected representatives of women’. • Feminist democratic representation incentivises elected representatives to meet the needs of diverse women. Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC Karen Celis and Sarah Childs 360 To cite this article: Celis, K. and Childs, S. (2023) From women’s presence to feminist representation: second-generation design for women’s group representation, European Journal of Politics and Gender, 6(3): 359–376, DOI: 10.1332/251510821X16654996784749 Introduction A lot can be said about the failure of representative democracy to do good by women. The 1990s’ presence theorists’ response was to call for women’s group presence. Reflecting on parliaments full of men, there was agreement that these representatives mostly knew and cared too little about women to stand and act for them (Young, 1990a; 1990b; 2002; Phillips, 1995; Williams, 1998; Mansbridge, 1999). In such situations, women’s political representation would be anything but fair, with women’s interests overlooked and laws and policies biased against them (Williams, 1998: 77). The preferred solution was to repopulate elected political institutions with women representatives, using gender quota1 as their handmaidens. Once present, these newly elected descriptive representatives would embody and signify women’s political equality and, it was hoped, if not expected, deliver fair representation for women, substantively speaking. Today, gender quota are in place in more than 130 countries (Paxton et al, 2020). Yet, despite relative, and, in some instances, significant, improvement in the numbers of women in the world’s parliaments, political equality is still to be achieved (Dahlerup, 2017; Lovenduski, 2019). The term ‘poverty of women’s political representation’ captures the multiple and compounding ways in which women are both underrepresented and misrepresented in formal politics, descriptively, substantively and symbolically. Crudely: parties largely continue to reflect cleavages and ideologies from previous centuries, with the political agenda and party competition remaining very much defined by traditional, masculinised interests; governments and legislatures are insufficiently responsive and accountable to women, with women’s experiences and voices often marginalised or absent from formal political debate; and the average percentage of women in national parliaments remains a mere 25 per cent.2 Like Anne Phillips (1992) three decades ago and Joni Lovenduski (2019) more recently, we hold on to the claim that feminists should not give up on representative democracy. To do so risks turning our backs on the self-same political institutions that are needed to protect women from those seeking to overturn their formal rights, especially so in these turbulent and anti-feminist times (Verloo, 2018). Believing that women’s poverty of political representation is neither natural nor inevitable, and that women can and should be in receipt of good representation, we update and remake the case for women’s group representation in electoral politics. We do so knowing full well that advocates of women’s political representation face renewed criticism from those who query gender as a legitimate political identity (Fukuyama, 2018), and we do so appreciating that feminist acknowledgement of women’s intra-group differences begs elemental questions about the ability of women representatives (disproportionately elite and majority ethnic) to represent those from different and particularly less privileged backgrounds (Smooth, 2011; Schwindt-Bayer and TaylorRobinson, 2011; Celis and Mügge, 2018). We contend that just as it was nearly three decades ago, the normative argument for group representation remains compelling from both democratic and feminist perspectives, being necessary ‘whenever the group’s history and social situation provides Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC From women’s presence to feminist representation 361 a particular perspective on the issue, when the interests of its members are specifically affected, and when its perceptions and interests are not likely to receive expression without that representation’(Young, 2002: 128). The problem is, then, much less the principled case than how women’s group representation is to be designed and enacted. In this article, we rethink how the principles of women’s group representation can be revised, revived and realised (Newton, 2012; Saward, 2020) in order to redesign practices for a revitalised representative politics.3 In an exercise that Mansbridge (2002) calls practice–thought–practice, we build a new, second-generation design, what we call ‘feminist democratic representation’. If the first generation’s intent was to increase the number of women legislators, with the accompanying assumption that these women, especially when they were present in larger numbers, would have feminist substantive effects (Dahlerup, 1988; Childs and Krook, 2008), the representational effects of our second-generation design are intended as multiple: the transformation of representative processes within elected political institutions, along with new representative relationships between elected representatives and those they represent; and women in society seeing formal politics as a critical site of their representation and of themselves becoming central actors of representative democracy. The first generation: women’s inclusion through presence Classic presence theorists – Mansbridge, Phillips, Williams and Young – took issue with the idea that a universal franchise was sufficient to secure for women a foundational democratic principle: political equality. Rule by elected men was paternalistic and patriarchal. The demand to share political power crucially involved a reframing of the principle of inclusion from an individual to a collective basis: as members of a historically excluded, marginalised and oppressed group, women qua women must have seats at the political table (Jónasdóttir, 1989; Young, 1990a; 1990b). Distilling presence theories, women merit political presence because they: (1) ‘find’ themselves a member of the group (in an ascriptive and non-essentialist fashion); (2) recognise a mutual identity and have an affinity with other women; (3) have a broad, shared history of exclusion from politics and society, which is empirically demonstrable and frequently subjectively claimed; and (4), as a consequence of that exclusion, experience laws and institutions biased against them. Fundamental to first-generation theories was a refutation of Pitkin’s (1967) disregard for descriptive representation and its links to substantive representation – her favoured dimension of representation. After Phillips’ (1995) The Politics of Presence, no one would regard descriptive representation as unimportant (Childs and Lovenduski, 2013: 490). At its core, presence theory holds that women’s issues and interests derive from women’s structural position in gendered societies (Phillips, 1995; on the issue of women’s interests, see also Harder, this issue); due to biology and gendered societal roles, women have experiences that are in many ways different from those of men, as well as gendered takes on the situations and experiences that they share with men (Lovenduski, 2005). Men’s ability to acquire knowledge of, and the will and ability to act in, women’s interests (Phillips, 1995: 13; Mansbridge, 1999) is questioned on epistemological grounds. In sum, men lack women’s experiences, and consequently women’s perceptions, concerns and needs are inaccessible to them (Williams, 1998). The original presence claim was (we are at pains to point out) advanced alongside recognition that women are neither homogeneous nor share an exclusive set of Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC Karen Celis and Sarah Childs 362 interests. There was an explicit rejection of essentialism, which does ‘violence to the empirical facts of diversity as well as to the agency of individuals to define the meaning of their social and biological traits’ (Williams, 1998: 6). Overdeterminism was criticised: ‘women’s social position conditions’  (Young, 2002: 97–8, emphasis added). Women’s ‘shared experience’ figures only as a ‘promise of shared concerns’ (Phillips, 1995: 83, emphasis added). Notwithstanding this commitment to difference, the normative assessment of what constituted political equality in general, and fair and just representation for women in particular, became in practice the presence of women’s sex/gendered bodies in representative institutions. This is what counted, normatively speaking, and was what was actually counted (Trimble and Arscott, 2003). Equated with the presence of women’s bodies, presence risks downplaying women’s intersectional heterogeneity, within-group privileging and marginalisation, as well as erasing ideological differences. The standard for women’s inclusion associated with first-generation theorists (even if unfairly) allows for a claim that all women are well represented in institutions populated by unrepresentative women. Such conclusions belie the essence of representative politics and power: the core democratic question of who gets what, when and how in large and complex societies where there is no agreement about political ends and where resources are finite. It is, then, but a ‘hop, skip and jump’ from women’s inclusion to presence and to a descriptive representation that privileges this dimension and reinforces a disaggregated approach to representation, even when it is linked to substantive representation. There are substantial risks that overly optimistic conclusions are drawn from women’s inclusion: first, that with descriptive representation, all women are well represented, both substantively and symbolically; and, second, that all women are well represented where women legislators are predominantly situated on one side of the ideological spectrum, are homogeneous and/or are privileged. The represented might not, however, feel well represented because of who the elected representatives are, how they are and/or how they act and speak (Skeggs and Wood, 2012: 136; Kantola and Lombardo, 2017; Kantola, 2018; see also Siow and Talukder, this issue). Equally, they might feel represented when their interests are being harmed, precisely because of who the representative is and how they act and speak (Clayton et al, 2018). In contrast to a disaggregated approach, it is in the intertwining of its dimensions that good representation for women is achieved. This is not to say that the first generation failed to explore the concept of representation and representative democracy in sophisticated ways. Yet, what materialised was the principle of inclusion enacted by – and thereby reduced to – the presence of women elected representatives in existing representative institutions in the absence of any additional institutional redesign. The unfortunate consequence, as Phillips (2012) later made clear, was that representation effectively dropped out of the picture, creating a disconnect between the principle and its enactment. A (re)reading of the original 1990s’ works reminds us of an ideal of representative politics characterised by greater deliberation, advocacy and publicity, and that is more exploratory and connected. Existing representative institutions were falling far short of realising women’s (and men’s) good representation; decision making based on aggregation – most votes wins – was criticised for failing to appreciate how this reinforces and replicates existing power relations, including gender relations (Williams, 1998; Young, 2002). To discover the best argument, and thus decisions made on that basis, more deliberative decision making was preferred (Williams, 1998; Young, 2002: 23). As Phillips (1995: 149) rather nicely put it, deliberative decision-making Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC From women’s presence to feminist representation 363 is an exploratory politics that discovers ‘new areas of common interests facilitated by the possibility to formulate new positions in the course of the discussion with others’. At its simplest, better decisions are forthcoming because representatives inhabit settings of greater information and because deliberative decision making allows for – if not expects – a transformation of interests (Phillips, 1991; 1995; Young, 2002: 26). Through deliberation, the range of interests and potential solutions are greater and more appropriate to the issue at hand because they reflect the interests and needs of all those affected (Phillips, 1991; 1995; Young, 2002; Mansbridge et al, 2010). Even as consensus and agreement are aimed for, differences and conflicts are not swept aside (Young, 2002: 7). Deliberating participants form a ‘public’, speaking in ways accountable to ‘plural others’ (Young, 2002: 25). To persuade the represented ‘of the rightness of her judgement’, appeals shift from ‘self-regard to appeals of justice’ (Young, 2002: 115). Advocacy has a continuing critical role to play because it reduces the risk of deliberation giving rise to a consensus that is misrepresented as ‘in the interest of all’ (Young, 2002: 23). Young was particularly detailed in her design work, and in many ways, her ideas have aged remarkably well. She was adamant that in modern societies, individuals simply cannot be where all the decisions are made and thus representative politics was necessary (Young, 2002: 125), and she was sure that ‘all existing representative democracies could be improved by additional procedures and fora’ (Young, 2002: 134). Young wished to link the institutions of and in civil society and formal electoral politics (Young, 2002: 8; 132–3), talking of ‘many avenues and institutions’. By connecting public debate and accountability mechanisms ‘to institutional or policy outcomes’, democratic processes could address some of the ‘injustices’ of unequal societies (Young, 2002: 36). Finally, Young’s assertion that legitimacy is linked to political processes characterised by publicity, inclusiveness and procedural regularity (Young, 2002: 3) speaks to the notion that one does not have to have ‘won’ on a particular issue to be and/or feel well represented. The second generation: feminist democratic representation Unfortunately, too much of what first-generation theorists had to say about representation and representative democracy failed to define what came to be the gender and politics ‘acquis’. The sophistication of their critique was lost. We aim to show how these ideas can be updated and translated into more concrete and implementable forms. First, we update – represent – the principle of inclusion in a manner that embraces and foregrounds contemporary accounts of women’s heterogeneity. Refashioned, the principle of inclusion demands the presence of diverse women’s voices in a constitutive politics of identifying and forming what is in the interests of women. Understood ideologically and intersectionally, our approach recognises not only differences among women, but also the structural power relations that position them unequally. Relative privilege and marginalisation can create differences of experiences, perspectives and interests; each is not only multiple, but also at times in competition and oppositional (see also Norris, this issue). Where there is no agreement about ends, politically representing women well must attend to which women get what, when and how. Updating the ‘all affected’ principle, fair and just decision making requires the inclusion not only of women, but also of what we term ‘differently affected women’. In our intersectional incarnation, this is a claim Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC Karen Celis and Sarah Childs 364 for differently affected women being included in decision making such that no policy is made nor judged fair when, as for the first generation, the representative process ‘excluded a marginalized group that is affected by it’ (Williams, 1998: 172, 242; see also Urbinati, 2006: 2; Montanaro, 2012: 1099). Our second response is to supplement the first-generation advocacy of quota. While these have brought about unprecedented re-gendering to representative politics (see Phillips, 1995; Krook, 2009; Franceshet et al, 2012), they add women to existing representative institutions – parties and parliaments – without: intervening in ways that incentivise diverse women’s good representation by all representatives; holding political institutions and elected representatives collectively to account; and/ or sanctioning poor representation.4 Putting our critique more starkly still: when quota are adopted, nothing else is automatically put in place to ensure that diverse women elected representatives gain the institutional power to represent women or that women in society have sufficient means by which to judge the quality of their political representation. Our final response connects the revised principle of women’s group representation with its enactment (Saward, 2020), specifying how best to realise the inclusion of differently affected women in particular contexts. Interlocking three feminist principles5 – inclusiveness, responsiveness and egalitarianism – with the ideal representation process described by first-generation presence theorists and contemporary democratic theorists generates a feminist democratic process of representation (see Figure 1). Figure 1: The process of feminist democratic representation Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC From women’s presence to feminist representation 365 The advocacy moment enacts: • inclusiveness when the interests, opinions and perspectives of all relevant groups of women are voiced and heard, ensuring that women’s partial and subjective views are forcefully articulated; • responsiveness when representatives of women can act as passionate and partial advocates, speaking in their own voices and registers, and articulating the subjective conceptions of women’s interests of those experientially close to the issue; and • egalitarianism when the representatives of women are treated, and are seen to be treated, with equal respect and consideration, and no a priori assumptions are made about which women and which interests should be privileged. The deliberation moment enacts: • inclusiveness when all the interests, opinions and perspectives articulated in the advocacy moment are taken, and are seen to be taken, into account as representatives’debate and decide upon what is the fairest and most just decision; • responsiveness when representatives – who must be open to transforming their views on what is in the interests of women, rather than holding onto pre-existing positions that might very well be partial and gender unequal – examine and take into account the relationship between the representation of subjective and partial interests and what constitutes just and fair decisions; and • egalitarianism when all women’s interests are considered and have the potential to affect the decision under consideration, irrespective of political, socio-economic or cultural power hierarchies. The accountability moment enacts: • inclusiveness when elected representatives’ explanations and justifications are addressed to. and are received by, women in their diversity; • responsiveness when representatives engage with women’s approval, contestation and/or rejection of decisions, as only in this way will all women witness and experience reciprocity in the representative relationship and regard the institution as accountable to them; and • egalitarianism when representatives give accounts in ways that give equal weight and consideration to the multiple and, at times, competing women’s interests articulated during the earlier advocacy moment, as well as to the potential objections of various groups of women, as women in their diversity should see that their views and interests were taken seriously, irrespective of the substantive outcome. To bring our second-generation design to life, we call for the formal, institutionalised political presence within existing legislatures of a new set of political actors: the affected representatives of women. Legislatures are now required by design to bring in the representatives of differently affected women, including the most marginalised women who will rarely find themselves elected representatives under the current rules of the political recruitment game, even with quota. The naming of our new representatives as affected representatives captures a number of aspects of who these representatives are and how they represent. First, the prefix Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC Karen Celis and Sarah Childs 366 refers to the differently affected principle, which we put forward as an ‘intersectional update’ of the all-affected principle. The latter states that democratic decision making requires that all participate when they are affected by the matter (Williams, 1998). Our update consists of the specification that women differently affected due to their intersectional or ideological positionality merit representation. Second, we wanted to highlight that affected representatives are epistemologically and experientially, but importantly also affectively, close to those they represent. They are thus better able to know and present factual and affective knowledge (for example, how an issue is experienced and felt by the represented). Here, our concept of ‘affected representatives’ marries up with Dovi’s ‘preferable descriptive representatives’, as factual and affective knowledge is produced through ‘strong mutual relationships with dispossessed subgroups of historically disadvantaged groups’, reciprocal recognition and linked fates (Dovi, 2002: 729). Third, our new concept reflects the ‘affective turn’ in politics (Ahmed, 2014), acknowledging how affects – such emotions as recognition, trust and pride – are co-constitutive of the representative relationship. Turning to the noun, affected representatives are not merely witnesses or informants to parliamentary proceedings undertaken by elected politicians (for example, witnesses to committees or spokespeople in legislative hearings); rather, they are representatives of a constituency of women. Granting them the status of representatives and giving them an institutionalised role in the representative process makes affected representatives ‘equal of sorts’ with elected ones. Elected representatives undisputedly retain their primacy, reflecting their electoral mandate, but the affected representatives of women play highly visible, high-status, formal roles within legislatures. The presence of affected representatives is not a one-off, compensatory intervention, but a permanent institutional provision.6 It is triggered when a legislature discusses women’s issues and/or where there is discrepancy between the political/institutional agenda and civil-societal debates about women’s issues. It has, in other words, become an institutional responsibility to reach out to, and crucially bring in, affected representatives of women.7 It is for the represented – women in civil society – to determine who is the best representative of their interests.8 Since women must ‘own’ not only how they are represented, but also the process of identifying their representatives (Dovi, 2007: 155–9), we do not specify how many affected representatives there should be or the (s)election process or the societal spheres that they would come from (these might include organised civil society organisations, ad hoc groups, artists and social media influencers, for example). Affected representatives have bespoke representative responsibilities during group advocacy and account giving – the institutional input and output phases of the representative process, respectively. In group advocacy, their representative work ensures that elected representatives hear from, and listen to, the voices of differently affected women, increasing the available ‘store of knowledge’ (Young, 2002: 83). An exhaustive account of what is at stake for women is realised, with affected representatives speaking about their experiences, knowledge, preferences and interests, and doing so in their own voice, both factual and affective. Women’s interests are thus shown to be multiple, revealing competition and, at times, conflict over what is in the interests of women. This is especially the case regarding the differing interests of privileged and marginalised women, something that can all to easily be absent or hidden today (Young, 2002: 7; Urbinati, 2006). Due to group advocacy, some elected representatives might change their policy positions. Nor can there be pretence Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC From women’s presence to feminist representation 367 on behalf of elected representatives (or wider society for that matter) that an issue is not gendered, or assumptions among elected representatives that there is a universal women’s interest. Account giving is where affected representatives hold elected representatives to account – it is systemic recursiveness and reflexivity in practice (Disch, 2011; Mansbridge, 2019). Elected representatives explain and justify the content, course and conclusions of their deliberations to the affected representatives of women. As a highprofile, public moment, media coverage enables women beyond parliament to see and learn about what is going on within it, permitting autonomous, considered, reflective and robust judgment (Runciman, 2007; Mansbridge, 2009: 391; Warren, 2019: 40, 45). Occurring under conditions of publicity (Young, 2002), and being a collective affair, elected representatives are incentivised to deliberate and take decisions in ways that are inclusive, responsive and egalitarian, with elected representatives appealing to principles higher than self-interest (Williams, 1998: 145, 222, 227; Young, 2002: 115; Dovi, 2007). Affected representatives have power over elected representatives in terms of judging the quality of representation.9 They are institutionally positioned to question, probe and seek justifications, providing for Disch’s (2011: 8; 2012: 219) ‘disidentification’ or a ‘not in our name’ judgement (following Pitkin, 1967), or Dovi’s (2015) ‘naysaying’.10 If not for genuine reasons of wanting to do good by women, elected representatives are incentivised to avoid ‘looking bad’ for strategic or electoral reasons. Complementing each other, our twin augmentations together create and embed conducive contexts to make the throughput phase – the deliberation and decisions by elected representatives – better meet the representational interests of women and produce just and fair outcomes. With a new set of actors, a diversity of women’s voices is spoken, heard and responded to in our legislatures. The good representation of women is now an institutionalised obligation of elected representatives, indeed, of institutions qua institutions. The intended representational effects affect both elected representatives and the represented, and are both direct and indirect. Overall, the representative process is characterised by improved relationships between the represented and the elected representatives, and with new representative relations also created between the represented and affected representatives.11 Direct representational effects on elected representatives: knowing, caring and connected Five design features incentivise the transformation in the quality of women’s representation12 achieved by elected representatives, both male and female: (1) exposure via affected representatives to the direct and lived experiences of the represented; (2) the constitution of affected representatives as representatives, equal of sorts with elected representatives; (3) the formal and public character of account giving; (4) the institutionalisation of group advocacy and account giving as part of the routine and iterative practices of parliaments; and (5) the collective responsibility of elected representatives. By design, our new democratic practices ensure elected representatives are institutionally required to hear from affected representatives. In this way, elected representatives give formal recognition to women’s views, symbolising and legitimising women as a representable constituency. Group advocacy and account giving intentionally provide for elected representatives to know more about the representational issues and interests of differently affected women (see also Bonish, Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC Karen Celis and Sarah Childs 368 this issue). Our twin practices maximise the available knowledge critical for elected representatives to engage in an exploratory, recursive and reflexive politics about what is just and fair for women (Phillips, 1995; Disch, 2011; Mansbridge, 2019). Competition among diverse women regarding a particular women’s issue, policy or legislative intervention – and the strength of the feeling about them held by different women – is revealed, as affected representatives advocate for the women they represent. When elected representatives later deliberate, they will be better appraised of the cacophony of views (Dodson, 2006), with better appreciation of why particular issues and interests are advanced. During the representative process, elected representatives are active in (re)constituting women’s interests. Since our new democratic practices are normalised as part of everyday parliamentary processes, elected representatives appreciate and accept that representing women is a collective responsibility, with individual, institutional and systemic costs if done poorly. We go so far as to suggest that as elected representatives accept the democratic responsibility to represent diverse women, they would become more confident in their deliberations, emboldened in making their decisions and trusting in their individual and collective judgements. Our augmentations do not only educate; they also make elected representatives care more about representing women. Group advocacy and account giving are ‘close encounters’ between elected and affected representatives. Passionate and partial advocacy starkly contrasts with the witnessing of disembodied and dry knowledge. The represented is now a ‘concrete other’ (Benhabib, 1992). In the minds of elected representatives, differently affected women are made ‘conversationally’ and ‘imaginatively present’, expanding elected representatives’knowledge and sensibilities (Goodin, 2000: 83, 95, 98). Affective knowledge makes it harder for elected representatives to summarily ignore or dismiss claims (Kantola, 2018), or depict affected representatives and those they represent as unworthy of representation. Furthermore, even when elected representatives refute claims or choose some over others, as in some instances they must, affected representatives and their representative claims will still have been formally aired and acknowledged within the institution (Disch, 2011). Changes in the content of elected representatives’deliberations – the consequence of elected representatives knowing and caring more about diverse women’s interests – are matched by changes in how elected representatives deliberate and communicate within parliaments and extra-institutionally. Since they know that they will be held to account, elected representatives are incentivised to communicate with affected representatives on the latter’s terms. By speaking in ways that resonate with those they seek to persuade in the account-giving moment, elected representatives’ style shifts away from dominant political forms – adversarial, detached, formal and elite. These new modes engender institutional and societal recognition of the legitimacy and validity of (diverse) women’s speech. Direct representative effects on the represented women: recognised and legitimised, more knowledgeable, and interested and mobilised The success of our second-generation feminist design lies centrally in the transformation of the attitudes and behaviour of elected representatives. Yet, it is the views of the represented – what they think about the quality of their representation – that we value most. Five design features incentivise representational effects regarding the Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC From women’s presence to feminist representation 369 represented: (1) the formal and institutionalised presence of affected representatives; (2) the constitution of affected representatives as representatives, equal of sorts with elected representatives; (3) the right and practice of affected representatives advocating partially and speaking in one’s own voice and for one’s own interests; (4) ‘ownership’ by the represented over how they are represented by affected representatives; and (5) affected representatives’active power over elected representatives during account giving. First, the represented feel recognised and legitimised (Dovi, 2007: 155–6). Responsive to shifting and evolving societal debates, and built around concrete political issues and events, over time, a wide variety of women engage with formal politics; previously absent groups of women are formally included as active participants in the ‘public speech for the nation’and see themselves reflected among the affected representatives (Urbinati, 2006: 35). As elected representatives collectively respond to diverse women, and as affected and elected representatives adopt new styles of language and tones in their interactions, parliamentary politics becomes less exclusive13 and the gap between elected representatives, the legislature and the represented is lessened. Women should come to acknowledge that the long antipathy and indifference to their representation has ended and that parliaments are amenable sites for the redress of gender inequality. Second, women in society become more knowledgeable. Through repeated encounters between elected and affected representatives, women in society become more aware of different and, at times, oppositional views. Different groups of women and their affected representatives may: reflect upon the particularity of their views (Young, 2002: 113, 116); ‘recalibrate’ their thoughts and emotions (Mansbridge, 2019: 316); ‘transcend the immediacy of their biographical experience and social and cultural belongings and interests’(Urbinati, 2006: 5); and better appreciate how their ‘situation looks to others’ (Young, 2002: 116). This might alter or transform how some women conceive of their interests, even if for others, original conceptions of these will be reconfirmed. Either way, interactions that lay out the structure of any conflict open up the potential for mutual appreciation. The saliency of individual women’s issues may change over time too. This is not because all women suddenly agree, but, rather, because with additional factual and affective knowledge, initial preferences might be considered partial and new solutions and alliances become imaginable. Contestation, in an agonistic sense, allows citizens to understand the nature of their struggle and to identify the terms on which citizens might align or oppose (Mouffe, 2000: 13–20; Disch, 2019: 179). For some or all of these reasons, there may be recognition that subgroups of women are part of something bigger; new alliances and mobilisations, perhaps even the temporary identification of a collective women’s agenda, is possible. Third, a wide diversity of women will be interested in and mobilised for electoral politics. Seeing their affected representatives face to face with elected representatives, and witnessing a different form of politics, women should feel: content that their affected representatives have contributed to better understandings of the issue at hand; pride that their efforts have led to their interests being acknowledged and responded to; and positive about their contribution to the education of representatives and the improvement in the quality of the overall representative process. Such inclusive, responsive and egalitarian presence should, in turn, generate greater feelings of worth, efficacy and affinity with the actors and institutions of representative democracy (Rosanvallon, 2011). This should give rise to the greater self-organisation of women, Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC Karen Celis and Sarah Childs 370 with diverse women constituting themselves as representational constituencies (Saward, 2010), putting forward affected representatives and seeking direct participation as representatives, both elected and affected. Indirect representational effects: role models and the appreciation of diversity If the institutional presence of affected representatives improves women’s descriptive representation in straightforward numerical terms, as more women participate in the legislature, and qualitatively in terms of which women are now participating in formal politics,14 it might also boost descriptive representation in more indirect ways. Experiences gained may influence individual affected representatives’ ambition and resources, prompting them to seek (s)election as elected representatives. They will have acquired – and be seen to – the experiences, skills and resources for formal politics. As time passes, affected representatives have wider role-model effects outside formal politics; seeing ‘women like them’ in politics can increase the numbers wishing to participate in formal politics, whether as elected or affected representatives (Piscopo and Kenny, 2020; Hinojosa and Kittilson, 2020). The contrast between who comprises a parliament’s elected and affected representatives should throw additional light on the problematic homogeneity of so many institutions. The presence of affected representatives has the potential to reeducate parties about the value of diverse representation and may challenge leader and selectorate perceptions of women’s credentials and capacities for elected office. Rather than the artificial demand for women candidates created by gender quota, changes in gatekeeper attitudes towards women as candidates should engender ‘genuine’ demand for more and, importantly, diverse women in politics. Were this to happen, we would witness a profound change in the demand side of recruitment (Norris and Lovenduski, 1995), fundamentally overturning ideas about gender and merit. As mentioned earlier, this has proven singularly impossible to achieve (Murray, 2014; Annesley et al, 2019). Conclusion In the face of women’s ongoing poverty of representation, we were emboldened to undertake what we came to regard as second-generational feminist democratic design. We reflected once again on the 1990s’ politics of presence literature, and we reviewed contemporary democratic theory for what it might offer women. We were confident that the case for women’s group representation could be remade and that classic ideas regarding women’s political inclusion could be updated to address what it might mean for women in their diversity to be well represented (following Phillips, 2012). Our design thinking identified three feminist principles, reflecting a full appreciation of women’s intersectional and ideological differences, which we would infuse with newer democratic ideas regarding deliberation, advocacy and accountability. Feminist democratic representation establishes new institutional practices and introduces new political actors – the affected representatives of women – incentivising transformations in the relationship between the represented and elected representatives, and engendering new representational outcomes. Affected representatives have roles distinct from elected representatives. However, while our Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC From women’s presence to feminist representation 371 design maintains the latter as the key actors of representative democracy, it nevertheless disrupts their established ways of working and, in party democracies, the norms of party politics. Affected representatives are critical to the new input and output phases of parliamentary representation, that is, group advocacy and account giving. Reinforcing each other, these augmentations incentivise elected representatives to better meet the representational needs of women, notably, when they later deliberate and take decisions. Crudely, elected representatives can no longer claim ignorance of the diversity of women’s interests (they know more) and they are affected by, and responsive to, what they have heard (they care more). There is a reputational risk, both individual and institutional, in turning their backs on representing women: inviting criticism from the affected representatives within the legislature during account giving and, more generally, from women outside. Our design importantly moves the responsibility to realise women’s good representation from the personal preference of (mostly) descriptive representatives operating in highly constrained masculinised contexts to the collective interest of elected representatives, both male and female, and the responsibility of the institution overall. The institutionalisation of affected representatives means that our designedin incentives – and hence the potential to effect substantial representative change – deepens and broadens over time. Parliamentary politics becomes more conducive to women’s representation. In ongoing moments of advocacy, deliberation, decision making and account giving, the affected representatives’judgement of whether elected representatives have deliberated and decided in a just and fair manner feeds into subsequent consideration of the next women’s issues and interests to be decided upon. With its two new democratic practices and a new set of political actors, a virtuous circle is formed: affected representatives put particular interests on the parliamentary table, are treated responsively and in an egalitarian fashion, and hold elected representatives to account; in consequence, women’s motivation to participate is reinforced. In turn, greater participation by women in electoral politics – as both affected and elected representatives – opens up the possibility that representative democracy becomes an everyday practice of ordinary women. We would suggest that these stronger representative relationships encourage greater support for the procedures, institutions and substantive outputs of representative politics on the ground, and, at a higher level, for the idea of representative democracy. Feminist democratic representation, moreover, allows for the possibility that women who fail to have their interests (as they would define them) met by elected representatives can nonetheless judge the overall representative process as fair and just. The classic dimensions of representation are now recognised as thoroughly entwined: being well represented encompasses how women feel about their formal, elected representative relationships, the workings of democratic institutions and processes, and how those who stand and act for them speak, act and decide. Whether women feel and experience good representations is wrapped up with ideas and feelings of affinity, trust, legitimacy, symbolism and affect. We cannot guarantee such feminist outcomes, just like first-generation designers could not guarantee women’s substantive representation; rather, we have spoken of conducive contexts, talked in terms of incentives and outlined intended and hopedfor representational effects. Nor do we think that building our design will be easy or quick – there is a lot more to institutional (re)building (Lowndes and Roberts, 2013). Indeed, we are too cognisant of feminist-institutionalist scholarship to imagine such Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC Karen Celis and Sarah Childs 372 a rosy scenario, and there should be a feminist building process to inform bespoke institutional blueprints (Lowndes and Paxton, 2018). Furthermore, what we are suggesting is hugely demanding of political institutions, elected representatives and their parties, and at least in the first instance, it will slow down politics. Even so, we have some confidence that the remade case for women’s group representation should have appeal. Representative democracy is not in the best of health. Making our political institutions feminist and thus more democratic – and extending this design for other currently under-represented groups, including marginalised men – might just be one, very good, way of underpinning what at present look like rather shaky political institutions. Notes 1 Gender quota can take different forms but are mechanism to increase the number of women candidates and/or elected representatives.For example,a quota may determine the proportion of men and women on electoral lists, hence securing a minimum number of not only women, but also men, candidates.The norm is to use the term ‘gender quota’, even when formally a sex quota.Where quota include trans women, ‘gender quota’ is the more accurate nomenclature. 2 See: www.ipu.org 3 This contribution limits itself to the first two phases of democratic design:design-thinking and designing (Saward,2020).We refrain from discussing the implementation of feminist democratic representation in varying real-world contexts (that is, in parliamentary or presidential democracies, multi- or two-party systems, or newer or established democracies).The latter would:(1) require a third‘building’phase,that is,a‘translation’ to specific contexts,which requires more than a simple‘transfer’of practices from one context to another (Saward, 2020); (2) involve ‘local design coalitions’ mobilising the ‘local knowledge and creativity of multiple dispersed institutional entrepreneurs’,as well as the critical engagement of a pluralistic and diverse group of citizens (Lowndes and Roberts,2013:187);and (3) necessitate‘joining up’with other democratic innovations (Saward, 2020). 4 We cannot do justice to the literature that documents the women (and some men) who see their roles,at least in part,as about representing women and have undertaken political acts to those ends (for an overview, see Paxton et al, 2020). Our point is not to discredit their labour or existing scholarship. 5 Galligan (2012: 3) similarly writes of inclusion, accountability and recognition as the requisites for a gender democracy, and Walsh (2011) refers to access, voice and contestation capacity. 6 To be clear,the new processes advocated in feminist democratic representation do not replace either gender quota or gender mainstreaming, but augment these democratic innovations. 7 The actors (for example, academic experts or women’s policy agencies) and processes involved (for example, research or open calls) in mapping the differently affected groups of women is part of the third phase of democratic design, which we refrain from discussing in this article (see note 3). 8 We recognise the difficulties of civil society participation and note that some refuse engagement with formal politics. We trust that our design will engender women’s civil society mobilisation – a claim we return to when we discuss representational effects. Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC From women’s presence to feminist representation 373 9 As asserted by feminist institutionalists (for example,Krook and Mackay,2011;Mackay and Kenny, 2007), we acknowledge that the inclusion of affected representatives will not change institutional gendered power relations overnight. 10 The affected representatives do not have the right to veto elected representatives’ decisions (Young, 1990a; 1990b), which would render them akin to decision makers. 11 This ensures some feminist substance remains in play (Dodson,2006;Saward,2016:9). 12 Arguably, feminist democratic representation would also incentivise the establishment of gender-sensitive parliaments (Palmieri, 2019). 13 When elected representatives deliberate among themselves, they may switch back to their preferred mode of communication (Urbinati, 2006: 43–6). 14 We assume that most affected representatives will be women, that is, Dovi’s (2002) ‘preferable descriptive representatives’. Funding The authors received no financial support for the research,authorship,and/or publication of this article. Authors biographies Karen Celis is a full professor affiliated with the Department of Political Sciences of Vrije Universitiet Brussel, Belgium. She is co-director of the RHEA Research Centre on Gender, Diversity and Intersectionality and academic advisor on inclusion policy. She conducts theoretical and empirical research on the democratic quality of political representation from an intersectional perspective. Sarah Childs is Professor of Politics and Gender at the University of Edinburgh,UK.She researches women’s political representation,political parties and gender/diversity-sensitive parliaments (GSPs/DSPs).An impactful academic, she has undertaken GSP work with the UK Parliament,the Inter-Parliamentary Union,the Commonwealth Parliamentarian Association and UN Women. Conflict of interest The authors declare that there is no conflict of interest. References Ahmed, S. (2014) The Cultural Politics of Emotion, Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Annesley, C., Beckwith, K. and Franceschet, S. (2019) Cabinets, Ministers, and Gender, NewYork: Oxford University Press. Benhabib, S. (1992) The generalized and the concrete other: the Kohlberg–Gilligan controversy and feminist theory, in Situating the Self: Gender, Community, and Postmodernism in Contemporary Ethics, NewYork: Routledge, pp 402–24. Celis, K. and Mügge, L.M. (2018)Whose equality? Measuring group representation, Politics, 38(2): 197–213  Childs, S. and Krook, L.M. (2008) Critical mass theory and women’s political representation, Political Studies, 56(3): 725–36. doi: 10.1111/j.1467- 9248.2007.00712.x Childs,S.and Lovenduski,J.(2013) Representation,in G. Waylen,K. Celis,J. Kantola and L.S. Weldon (eds) Oxford Handbook of Gender and Politics, Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp 489–513. Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC Karen Celis and Sarah Childs 374 Clayton,A., O’Brien, D.Z. and Piscopo, J.M. (2018) All male panels? representation and democratic legitimacy, American Journal of Political Science, 63(1): 113–29. doi: 10.1111/ajps.12391 Dahlerup, D. (1988) From a small to a large minority, Scandinavian Political Studies, 11(4): 275–98. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9477.1988.tb00372.x Dahlerup, D. (2017) Has Democracy FailedWomen?, Cambridge: Polity Press. Disch, L. (2011) Toward a mobilization conception of democratic representation, American Political Science Review,105(1):100–14.doi:10.1017/S0003055410000602 Disch,L.(2012)The impurity of representation and the vitality of democracy,Cultural Studies, 26(2–3): 207–22. doi: 10.1080/09502386.2011.636190 Disch, L. (2019) The silent partner in political representation’s constructivist turn, in D. Castiglione and J. Pollak (eds) Creating Political Presence.The New Politics of Democratic Representation, Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, pp 162–85. Dodson, D.L. (2006) The Impact ofWomen in Congress, NewYork: Oxford University Press. Dovi, S. (2002) Preferable descriptive representatives: will just any woman, Black, or Latino do?, American Political Science Review, 96(4): 729–43. doi: 10.1017/ S0003055402000412 Dovi, S. (2007) The Good Representative, Oxford: Blackwell Publishing Ltd. Dovi,S.(2015) Representing women:The importance of resistance,paper presented at the ECPG Conference in Uppsala, Sweden, 11–13 June. Franceschet, S., Krook, M.L. and Piscopo, J.M. (2012) The Impact of Gender Quotas, NewYork: Oxford University Press. Fukuyama,F.(2018) Identity:The Demand for Dignity and the Politics of Resentment,New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux. Galligan,Y.(2012) Deliberative Processes and Gender Democracy (Report EU 6th Framework Project). Case Studies from Europe, Oslo:ARENA. Goodin, R.E. (2000) Democratic deliberation within, Philosophy & Public Affairs, 29(1): 81–109. Hinojosa, M. and Kittilson, M.C. (2020) SeeingWomen, Strengthening Democracy: How Women in Politics Foster Connected Citizens, NewYork: Oxford University Press. Jónasdóttir, A.G. (1989) On the concept of interest, women’s interests, and the limitations of interest theory, in K.B. Jones and A.G. Jónasdóttir (eds) The Political Interests of Gender, London: Sage Publications, pp 33–65.  Kantola,J.(2018) Gender and the economic crisis:political parties as sites of feminist struggles,Social Politics:International Studies in Gender,State & Society,25(3):361–82. doi: 10.1093/sp/jxy008 Kantola, J. and Lombardo, E. (2017) Gender and the politics of the economic crisis in Europe, in J. Kantola and E. Lombardo (eds) Gender and the Economic Crisis in Europe.Politics,Institutions and Intersectionality,London:Palgrave Macmillan,pp 1–25. Krook,M.L.(2009) Quotas forWomen in Politics:Gender and Candidate Selection Reform Worldwide, NewYork: Oxford University Press. Krook, M.L. and Mackay, F. (2011) Introduction: gender, politics, and institutions, in M.L. Krook and F. Mackay (eds) Gender, Politics and Institutions, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp 1–20. Lovenduski, J. (2005) Feminizing Politics, Cambridge: Polity Press. Lovenduski,J.(2019) Feminist reflections on representative democracy,inA. Gamble andT. Wright (eds) Rethinking Democracy,Chichester:JohnWiley & Sons,pp 18–35. Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC From women’s presence to feminist representation 375 Lowndes,V.and Paxton,M.(2018) Can agonism be institutionalised? Can institutions be agonised? Prospects for democratic design, The British Journal of Politics and International Relations, 20(3): 693–710. doi: 10.1177/1369148118784756 Lowndes,V. and Roberts, M. (2013) Why Institutions Matter:The New Institutionalism in Political Science, London: Red Globe Press. Mackay, F. and Kenny, M. (2007) Women’s representation in the 2007 Scottish Parliament:temporary setback or return to the norm?,ScottishAffairs,60(1):80–93. doi: 10.3366/scot.2007.0037 Mansbridge, J. (1999) Should blacks represent blacks and women represent women? A contingent ‘Yes’, The Journal of Politics, 61(3): 628–57. doi: 10.2307/2647821 Mansbridge, J. (2002) Practice–thought–practice, in A. Fung and E.O. Wright (eds) Deepening Democracy: Institutional Innovations in Empowered Participatory Governance, NewYork:Verso, pp 175–99. Mansbridge, J. (2009) A ‘selection model’ of political representation, The Journal of Political Philosophy, 17(4): 369–98. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9760.2009.00337.x Mansbridge, J. (2019) Recursive representation, in D. Castiglione and J. Pollak (eds) Creating Political Presence.The New Politics of Democratic Representation, Chicago, IL, and London: University of Chicago Press, pp 298–338. Mansbridge, J., Bohman, J., Chambers, S., Estlund, D., Føllesdal,A., Fung,A., Lafont, C., Manin, B. and Martí, J.L. (2010) The place of Self-interest and the role of power in deliberative democracy, Journal of Political Philosophy, 18(1): 64–100. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9760.2009.00344.x Montanaro, L. (2012) The democratic legitimacy of Self-appointed representatives, The Journal of Politics, 74(4): 1094–107. doi: 10.1017/S0022381612000515 Mouffe, C. (2000) The Democratic Paradox, London and NewYork:Verso. Murray,R.(2014) Quotas for men:reframing gender quotas as a means of improving representation for all,American Political Science Review,108(3):520–32.doi:10.1017/ S0003055414000239 Newton, K. (2012) Curing the democratic malaise with democratic innovations, in B. Geissel and K. Newton (eds) Evaluating Democratic Innovations. Curing the Democratic Malaise?, NewYork: Routledge, pp 3–20. Norris, P. and Lovenduski, J. (1995) Political Recruitment: Gender, Race and Class in the British Parliament, NewYork: Cambridge University Press. Palmieri,S.(2019) Feminist institutionalism and gender-sensitive parliaments:relating theory and practice, in M. Sawer and K. Baker (eds) Gender Innovation in Political Science, New Norms, New Knowledge, London: Palgrave, pp 173–94.  Paxton,P.,Hughes,M.M.andTiffany,D.B.(2020) Women,Politics,and Power,Lanham, MD, Boulder, CO, NewYork and London: Rowman and Littlefield. Phillips, A. (1992) Must feminists give up on liberal democracy?, Political Studies, 68–82. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9248.1992.tb01813.x Phillips,A. (1991) Engendering Democracy, Cambridge: Polity Press. Phillips,A. (1995) The Politics of Presence, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Phillips,A. (2012) Representation and inclusion, Politics & Gender, 8(4): 512–18. Piscopo, J. and Kenny, M. (2020) Rethinking the ambition gap: gender and candidate emergence in comparative perspective,European Journal of Politics and Gender,34(1:special issue [ed J.Piscopo and M.Kenny]):3–10.doi:10.1332/251510819X15755447629661 Pitkin,H.F.(1967) The Concept of Representation,Berkeley,CA:University of California Press. Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC Karen Celis and Sarah Childs 376 Rosanvallon, P. (2011) Democratic Legitimacy: Impartiality, Reflexivity, Proximity, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Runciman, D. (2007) The paradox of political representation, Journal of Political Philosophy, 15(1): 93–114. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9760.2007.00266.x Saward, M. (2010) The Representative Claim, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Saward, M. (2016) Towards democratic design: a note on methods of theory, paper presented to APSA Annual Meeting, Philadelphia, 1–4 September. Saward, M. (2020) Democratic Design, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Schwindt-Bayer, L.A. and Taylor-Robinson, M.M. (2011) Critical perspectives on politics and gender: the meaning and measurement of women’s interests, Politics & Gender, 7(3): 417–18. Skeggs, B. andWood, H. (2012) Reacting to RealityTelevision: Performance,Audience and Value, London & NewYork: Routledge. Smooth, W. (2011) Standing for women? Which women? The substantive representation of women’s interests and the research imperative of intersectionality, Politics & Gender, 7(3): 436–41. Trimble, L. and Arscott, J. (2003) Still Counting Women in Politics across Canada, Peterborough: Broadview Press. Urbinati,N.(2006) Representative Democracy:Principles and Genealogy,Chicago,IL,and London: University of Chicago Press. Verloo, M. (2018) Varieties of Opposition to Gender Equality in Europe, Abingdon: Routledge. Walsh, D. (2011) Women’s Rights in Democratizing States: Just Debate and Gender Justice in the Public Sphere, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Warren, M. (2019) How representation enables democratic citizenship, in D. Castiglione and J. Pollak (eds) Creating Political Presence,Chicago,IL,and London: University of Chicago Press, pp 39–60. Williams, M. (1998) Voice, Trust, and Memory. The Failings of Liberal Representation, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Young, I.M. (1990a) Justice and the Politics of Difference, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Young, I.M. (1990b) Throwing Like a Girl and Other Essays in Feminist Philosophy and SocialTheory, Bloomington and Indianapolis, IN: Indiana University Press. Young, I.M. (2002) Inclusion and Democracy, NewYork: Oxford University Press. Authenticated hrbkova | Downloaded 10/16/23 09:44 AM UTC