30 Four Constitutional Revolutions with 161 cases, most of which were of crucial constitutional significance. Bill of Rights cases account for 53 percent (85 of 161) of all reported SACC cases; landmark federalism and separation of powers judgments make up an additional 25 percent (40 of 161) of the SACC caseload. From the Court's critical appraisal of the new constitution to its outlawing of the death penalty, in present-day South Africa there have been very few salient political controversies not contemplated by the Court. In sum, the adoption of constitutional catalogues of rights in Canada, New Zealand, Israel, and South Africa ushered in a new constitutional era in these countries. In each case, the constitutionalization of rights and the fortification of judicial review marked a shift from traditional principles of parliamentary sovereignty toward a new regime of constitutional supremacy and active judicial review. Judicial empowerment through the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review may shed light on an often-overlooked aspect of constitutional politics: the political origins of constitutionalization. Although the adoption of a constitutional catalogue of rights provides the necessary institutional framework for the judicialization of politics, it is certainly insufficient in and of itself to generate the high level of judicialized politics seen in present-day Canada, New Zealand, Israel, and South Africa. How then can the increasingly common transfer of power from majoritarian policy-making arenas to national high courts through constitutionalization be explained? The following chapters address this frequently overlooked puzzle of the political origins of constitutionalization. CHAPTER 2 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization The very purpose oi the Bill of Rights was to withdraw certain subjects from the vicissitudes of political controversy, to place them beyond the reach of majorities and officials and to establish them as legal principles to be applied by the courts. U.S. Supreme Court Justice Robert H. Jackson, West Virginia State Board of Education v. Bamette {1943) Conventional Theories of Constitutional Transformation Extant theories of constitutional transformation may be grouped into three major categories: evolutionist theories, functionalist explanations, and institutional economics models. Most scholars of constitutional politics agree that there is a strong correlation between the recent worldwide expansion of democracy and the contemporaneous global expansion of judicial power. Indeed, with a few notable exceptions (such as Egypt and Pakistan, which maintain relatively autonomous and influential national high courts), the expansion of judicial power has taken place primarily in democratic polities. Over the past three decades, three major waves that established and consolidated democracy took place: in Southern Europe in the late 1970s; in Latin America in the 1980s; and in Central and Eastern Europe in the early 1990s. These movements brought with them an expansion of judicial power in most of these new democracies, primarily through the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of relatively autonomous judiciaries and supreme courts armed with judicial review practices. Indeed, by its very nature, the existence of a democratic regime implies the presence of a set of procedural governing rules and decision-making processes to which all political actors are required to adhere. The persistence 32 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization The Political Origins of Constitutionalization 33 and stability of such a system in turn requires at least a semiautonomous, supposedly apolitical judiciary to serve as an impartial umpire in disputes concerning the scope and nature of the fundamental rules of the political game. Similarly, judicial review is a prerequisite of viable democratic governance in multilayered federalist countries (for example, the United States, Germany, Canada, India, and Australia), and in emerging supranational polities (for example, the European Union). Moreover, the transition to and consolidation of democracy entails the establishment of some form of separation of powers between the major branches of government, and between the central and provincial or regional legislatures. In short, the existence of an independent and active judiciary appears to be a necessary condition for, and an inevitable by-product of, the proliferation of democracy during the second half of the twentieth century. The expansion of judicial power has indeed been associated with political and economic liberalization in postaufhoritarian or quasi-democratic polities. However, the democratic proliferation thesis has certain shortcomings. The widespread transition to democracy cannot provide a coherent explanation for the significant variations in judicial power among new democracies. What is more, the expansion-of-democracy thesis fails to account for the significant variations in the timing, scope, and nature of the expansion of judicial power among established democracies. evolutionist theories. The evolutionist approach to legal change stresses the inevitability of judicial progress and the importance of invisible and endogenous macrofactors in explaining the expansion of judicial power through constitutional reform. Some evolutionist theories suggest that legal development is linked to a polity's passage from one socioeconomic stage to another. Early legal transformation theorists, such as Adam Smith, argued that development of genuine contract and property concepts could only occur alongside the consolidation of agriculture. More recent evolutionist theories of legal transformation emphasize cultural variations among societies as a determinant of legal development.' Other theories positing inevitable judicial progress and legal development by stages have also emerged within more general theories of economic and political development.2 The most widely held thesis associated with this approach defines the trend toward the constitutionalization of rights and the fortification of judicial review as an inevitable by-product of a new and near-universal prioritization of human rights in the wake of World War II.3 According to this view, the presence ol an effective, written bill of rights is the crowning proof of constitutional development. The greatest proof of democracy's triumph in our times, it is argued, stems from the increasing acceptance and enforcement of the idea that democracy is not equivalent to majority rule; in a real democracy, minorities should possess legal protections in the form of a written constitution unchangeable even by parliament. According to this view, a constitutional bill of rights is part of fundamental law. Judges, who are removed from the pressures of panisan politics, are responsible for enforcing such rights through active judicial review. The conception of constitutional transformation that stems from the social contract school of thought views constitutions and judicial review as procedural devices that free and equal people agree to voluntarily impose upon themselves to protect their equal, basic rights.4 Realizing the occasional temptation of popular majorities to adopt measures that infringe on the basic rights of some members of the polity while not having an a priori indication of whose rights might be restricted by such potential measures, members of a polity might rationally choose to entrench the fundamental rules of the political game and the basic rights of its participants by granting a nonlegislative body that is insulated from majoritarian politics the power to review legislation. In so doing, members of the polity (or its constituent assembly) provide themselves with precautions, or precommitments, against their own imperfections or harmful future desires, and tie themselves into their initial agreement on the basic rules and rights that specify their sovereignty.5 Proponents of this approach often regard the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review as reflecting polities' and politicians' genuine "maturity" and deep commitment to a universal notion of human rights. In its more empirically grounded variant, the evolutionist approach regards the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review as fortifying the separation of powers among the executive, the legislature, and the judiciary. According to this view, confidence in technocratic government and planning has waned, and from this has grown a consequent desire to restrict the discretionary powers of the state. The result has been a diffusion of judicial power over the past several decades.6 In its countermajoritarian guise, this approach stresses that by increasing "access" for special interest groups, the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of active judicial review promote the diffusion of political power, add veto mechanisms, restrict the maneuvering of policymakers, and 34 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization The Political Origins of Constitutionalization 35 limit the power of majorities in legislatures.7 According to this view, independent courts, especially those armed with judicial review practices, not only monitor untrustworthy executive and legislature bodies but also facilitate the political representation of diffuse but well-organized minorities. This representation creates opportunities for certain groups to participate in policy-making that might otherwise be closed to them in majoritarian parliamentary politics.6 Proponents of this approach therefore regard the constitutionalization of rights and the fortification of judicial review as the outcome of successful efforts by well-organized minority groups to protect themselves against the systematic threat of majoritarian political whims and to increase their impact on public policy outcomes. functionalist explanations. Like the evolutionist approach, functionalist (or systemic need-based) explanations cast constitutional transformation as an organic response to pressures within the political system itself. These explanations emphasize the absence of human agency and the ineluctability embedded in any legal progress. They also recognize particular ways in which legal innovations can follow from demonstrations of social need. The best-known functionalist explanations for legal change focus on increases in systemic efficiency as the end products of such change. Some institutional economists, for example, posit a systemic efficiency-driven process of legal transformation, in which inefficient legal rules would more likely be litigated while new, efficient rules would persist once established.9 Equivalent arguments have been made for legal changes in tort law and contract law, and even in the legal organization of a society to allow for modes of production that increase the rate of return on capital. Douglass North and Robert Thomas's analysis of the demise of feudalism in Europe illustrates the logic of this argument. During the Middle Ages, feudalism remained stable as long as land remained the scarce resource. Although lords could offer more rights to laboring serfs, it was not in their interest to do so. Following the Black Death, however, labor became the scarce resource. Lords facing competition for labor for the first time attempted to lure workers by offering them more attractive working conditions. This in turn stimulated labor force mobility, thus destroying feudalism in Western Europe.10 In its most common version, the functionalist approach suggests that the : expansion of judicial power derives from a structural, organic political problem such as a weak, decentralized, or chronically deadlocked political system. The less functional the political system is in a given democracy, the; ■--■ nnwer in that nolity.11 Constituv tionalization is seen as the best possible way of overcoming political ungovernability and ensuring the unity and "normal" functioning of such polities.12 In its "consociational" variant, the needs-based explanation of constitutional transformation emphasizes political necessity in the development of mechanisms such as mutual veto and proportional representation, characterizing them as inevitable constitutional solutions that allow fragmented polities to function. According to this logic, expansion of judicial power in polities facing political polarization is the only institutional mechanism that enables opposition groups to monitor distrusted politicians and decisionmakers. The explanation commonly given for the unprecedented judicialization of Israeli politics in recent years provides a perfect illustration of the idea that systemic needs are the main cause of judicial empowerment. In a marked change from the norms of Israel's early decades of independence, the judiciary, in particular the Israeli Supreme Court, has recently become one of the most significant actors in Israel's political arena. From the early 1990s onward, the Court has increasingly exercised its power at the expense of politicians and administrators. The Court has gained the authority to review primary legislation, political agreements, and administrative acts; it monitors almost every aspect of public life in Israel. Israeli society is characterized by deep social and cultural cleavages13 as well as by a political deadlock between the two major electoral blocs dating back to the late 1970s. According to the systemic needs explanation of judicial empowerment, this structural inability to deal with the social and cultural rifts besetting Israeli society and the stalemate faced by Israel's majoritarian politics corroded the authority of the Knesset and the government. This in turn led to the systemic dependency of the Israeli polity on a dominant, seemingly apolitical body of professional decision-makers: the Supreme Court judges.14 Another functionalist (or systemic needs-based) explanation emphasizes the general proliferation in levels of government and the corresponding emergence of a wide variety of semiautonomous administrative and regulatory state agencies as the main driving forces behind the expansion of judicial power over the past few decades. According to this thesis, independent and active judiciaries armed with judicial review practices are necessary for efficient monitoring of the ever-expanding administrative state. Moreover, the modern administrative state embodies notions of government as an active policy-maker, rather than a passive adjudicator of conflicts. The state therefore requires an active, policy-making judiciary.15 Along the same lines, scholars of judicial politics view the rapid growth 36 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization of supranational judicial review in Europe as an inevitable institutional response to complex coordination problems deriving from the systemic need to adopt standardized legal norms and administrative regulations across member-states in an era of converging economic markets."5 A similar standardization rationale may explain what may be called the incorporation scenario of constitutional reform. In this view, the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review in member-states of supranational economic and political regimes (the European Union, for example), as well as signatory states to transnational trade and monetary treaties, occurred througii the incorporation of international and trans- or supranational legal standards into domestic law. Recent examples of this scenario of constitutionalization include the incorporation of the European Convention on Human Rights provisions into Danish law in 1993, into Swedish law in 1995, and into British law through the enactment in. Britain of the Human Rights Act 1998—the first rights legislation introduced in the United Kingdom in three hundred years. While the constitutional evolution and functionalist theories just outlined account for some factors involved in the development of juristocracy, none analyzes the specific political vectors behind any of the constitutional revolutions of the past several years in a comparative, systematic, and detailed way. Moreover, none of these theories accounts for the precise timing of constitutional reform. If we apply these theories to a concrete example, they consistently fail to explain why a specific polity reached its most advanced stage of judicial progress at a specific moment and not, say, a decade earlier. Like the democratic proliferation thesis, both the constitutionalization in the wake of World War II thesis and its corresponding constitutionalization as precommitment argument fail to account for the significant variations in the timing, scope, and nature of constitutionalization. It is hard to sec, , for example, why members of the Canadian polity in 1982, or members of . the Israeli polity .a decade later, chose to take steps against their own imperfections in the year they did and not earlier or later. What is more, the constitutionalization as precommitment argument is based on a set of hypothetical and speculative presuppositions concerning the origin of constitu-: tions and judicial review that at the very best provide an ex post facto normative justification for their adoption. Moreover, if a given polity is indeed structurally ungovernable, it is difficult to see how the successful entrench-m»"t of a bill of rights and the establishment of judicial review in that polity The Political Origins of Constitutionalization 37 can be explained, given the failed earlier attempts to enact a constitutional catalogue of rights. Furthermore, both legal evolution and systemic needs-based theories of judicial transformation tend to ignore human agency and the fact that legal innovations require legal innovators—people who make choices as to the timing, scope, and extent of legal reforms. Both explanations overlook the crucial self-interested intervention by political power-holders who are committed to judicial expansion in an attempt to shape the institutional setting to serve their own agendas. institutional economics models. Another utilitarian approach—the institutional economics-derived theory of constitutional transformation—sees the development of constitutions and judicial review as mechanisms to mitigate systemic collective-action concerns such as commitment, enforcement, and information problems. One such explanation sees the development of constitutions and independent judiciaries as an efficient institutional answer to the problem of "credible commitments."17 Political leaders of any independent unit want to promote sustainable long-term economic growth and encourage investment that will facilitate the prosperity of their polity. Two critical preconditions for economic development are the existence of predictable laws governing the marketplace and a legal regime that protects capital formation and ensures property rights. The entrenchment of constitutional rights and the establishment of independent judicial monitoring of the legislative and executive branches are seen as ways of increasing a given regime's credibility and enhancing the ability of its bureaucracy to enforce contracts, thereby securing investors' trust and enhancing their incentive to invest, innovate, and develop. Indeed, as Max Weber noted, the fundamental building block of every successful capitalist market is a secure "predictability interest."18 Without this, potential investors lack the incentive to invest. Scholars have shown how entrenched legal rights that enhance investors' trust have led to economic growth in various historical contexts. Douglass North and Barry Weingast, for example, have illustrated how limitations on rulers' power in early capitalist Europe increased legal security and predictability, thereby allowing certain polities to borrow capital from external lenders, who were protected by law from the seizure of their capital.19 More recent empirical studies have established a statistical link between the existence of institutional limitations on government action (rigid constitutional provisions and judicial review, for example) and rapid economic growth.-20 38 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization The Political Origins of Constitutionalization 39 A second institutional economics explanation suggests that judicial review may constitute an efficient "tire alarm" mechanism for monitoring the bureaucracy.21 Legislators routinely delegate discretion over public policy programs to bureaucrats but must try to ensure that these bureaucrats implement the programs as they were intended. Investments in measures that enhance judicial independence are accordingly interpreted as efforts by executive branch leaders to avoid the high costs of constant central supervision of bureaucratic agencies (or a "police patrol" mechanism). Adopting a decentralized "fire alarm" monitoring model allows those who feel they have been treated unfairly to sue through the courts. In a similar vein, recent studies have emphasized the utility of judicial review as a mechanism for conveying information to legislatures about judicial policy preferences vis-a-vis legislative policy preferences as well as information concerning the actual effects of legislation.22 The information-conveying function of judicial review is likely to increase in cases of a priori, abstract judicial "preview" such as that exercised by the French Comál Constitutionnel or by the Canadian Supreme Court in the reference procedure.^3 Even if the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review do indeed mitigate problems of information, commitment, and enforcement, as suggested by these institutionsl-economjcs-driven explanations for judicial empowerment through constitutionalization, however, these explanations fail to explain how prosperous democratic polities managed to successfully address commitment and enforcement problems prior to the establishment of judicial review. Nor do they demonstrate why a certain polity would choose to adopt such efficient mechanisms at a particular point in time. Thinking Critically about the Political Origins of Constitutionalization: The Strategic Approach and the Hegemonic Preservation Thesis A realist, strategic approach to judicial empowerment focuses on various power-holders' self-interested incentives for deference to the judiciary. It: makes four preliminary assumptions. First, legislative deference to the judiciary and judicial empowerment through constitutionalization do not develop separately from the concrete social, political, and economic struggles that shape a given political system. Indeed, the expansion oi judicial power.. is an integral part and an important manifestation of those struggles and cannot be understood in isolation from them. Second, when studying the political origins of constitutionalization (as well as the political origins of other institutional reforms), it is important to take into account events that did not occur and the motivation of political power-holders for not behaving in certain ways. In other words, the political origins of constitutional reform cannot be studied in isolation from the political origins of constitutional stalemate and stagnation. Third, political and legal institutions produce differential distributive effects: they privilege some groups and individuals over others. Other variables being equal, prominent political, economic, and judicial actors are therefore likely to favor the establishment of institutional structures most beneficial to them. And fourth, because constitutions and judicial review hold no purse strings and have no independent enforcement power but nonetheless limit the institutional flexibility of political decisionmakers, the voluntary self-limitation through the transfer of policy-making authority from majoritarian decision-making arenas to courts seems, prima facie, to run counter to the interests of power-holders in legislatures and executives. Unless proven otherwise, the most plausible explanation for voluntary, self-imposed judicial empowerment is therefore that political, economic, and legal power-holders who either initiate or refrain, from blocking such reforms estimate that it will serve their interests to abide by the limits imposed by increased judicial intervention in the political sphere. Political power-holders may profit from an expansion of judicial power in a number of ways. First, from the politicians' point of view, delegating policy-making authority to the courts may be an effective means of reducing decision-making costs as well as shifting responsibility, thereby reducing the risks to themselves and to the institutional apparatus within which they operate, ff delegation of powers can increase credit and/or reduce blame attributed to the politician as a result of the policy decision of the delegated body, such delegation can be beneficial to the politician.24 The removal of policymaking power from legislatures and executives and its investiture in courts may become attractive for political power-holders when disputes arise that they consider undesirable as open public debates, primarily because they present no-win political dilemmas (such as the dispute over abortion policy in the United States, the debate over same-sex marriage in Canada, or the question of "who is a Jew" in Israel). As Mark Graber and others have shown, ruling national coalitions in the United States have been inclined to defer to the U.S. Supreme Court primarily when they have reached a political deadlock, faced a no-win decision, or have been unwilling or unable to 40 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization settle contentious public disputes in the political sphere. Deference to the judiciary, in other words, is derivative of political, not judicial, factors.25 Second, when politicians seek to gain public support for contentious views by relying on national high courts' public image as professional and apolitical decision-making bodies, or when they regard public disputes in majoritarian decision-making arenas as likely to put their own policy preferences at risk, diverting responsibility to the courts may become an attractive option. The threat of losing grip on pertinent policy-making processes and outcomes may be a strong driving force behind attempts to transfer power to courts. Accordingly, a strategic, political-power-oriented explanation for voluntary, self-imposed judicial empowerment through the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review suggests that political power-holders who either initiate or refrain from blocking such reforms estimate that it enhances their absolute or relative political power vis-a-vis rival political actors. Political actors who voluntarily establish institutions that appear to limit their institutional flexibility (such as constitutions and judicial review) may assume that the clipping of their wings under the new institutional structure will be compensated for by the limits it might impose on rival political elements. In short, those who are eager to pay the price of judicial empowerment must assume that their position (absolute or relative) would be improved under a juristocracy. Such an understanding of judicial empowerment through constitutionalization as driven primarily by strategic political considerations may take a "thin" or a "thick" form. The thin version employs party-based "electoral market" logic to explain judicial empowerment. In their seminal work of 1975, William Landes and Richard Posner argued that, other variables being equal, legislators favor the interest groups from which they can elicit the greatest investment through lobbying activities. A key element in maximizing such investment is the ability of legislators to signal credible long-term commitments to certain policy preferences. An independent judiciary's role in this regard is complementary to parliamentary procedural rules—it increases the durability of.; laws by making changes in legislation more difficult and costly. A judi-;. ciary that is overtly subservient to a current legislature (or expressly biased against it) can nullify legislation enacted in a previous session (or in current Legislation), thereby creating considerable instability in legal regimes. In such legally unstable settings, selling legislation to powerful interest groups may prove difficult from the politicians' point of view. The potential threat The Political Origins of Constitutionalization 41 of instability or loss of mutual profits and power may therefore result in support for judicial empowerment vis-a-vis legislatures.26 Observing variations in the degree of judicial independence among industrial democracies, Mark Ramseyer develops Landes and Posner's argument into an "electoral market" model, which suggests that judicial independence correlates to the competitiveness of a polity's party system.v When a ruling party expects to win elections repeatedly, the likelihood of judicial empowerment is low. Since rational politicians want long-term bargains with their constituents, they lack the incentive to support an independent judiciary when their prospects of remaining in power are high. However, when a ruling party has a low expectation of remaining in power, it is more likely to support an independent judiciary to ensure that the next ruling party cannot use the judiciary to achieve its policy goals. In other words, under conditions of electoral uncertainty, the more independent courts (or other semiautonomous regulatory agencies) are, the harder it will be for the successive government to reverse the policies of the incumbent government.28 Therefore, in Japan, for example (where a single party ruled almost uninterruptedly for more than four decades following World War II), judicial independence is weaker than it is in countries where there is an acknowledged risk that the party in power might lose control of the legislature in each election. The electoral market thesis is quite insightful when it is used to analyze the politics of constitution-making processes during periods of regime change and political transition. Judicial review, argues Tom Ginsburg, is a solution to the problem of uncertainty in constitutional design. By providing "insurance" to prospective electoral losers, judicial review can facilitate transition to democracy.29 As Pedro Magalhaes notes, "When the political actors that dominate the constitution-making process expect to lack control over legislatures in the future, judicial review of legislation may emerge as an institution designed to protect their interests."30 The transition to democracy in Spain and Portugal in the mid-1970s, for example, was characterized by lack of a single core of postautlioritarian political power, thereby leading to the rapid adoption of strong constitutiona! review mechanisms. In Greece, by contrast, the postauthoritarian constituent process was dominated by a single party (Constantine Karamanlis's New Democracy), which enjoyed over 70 percent of the seats in the assembly and did not have to worry about elections following the approval of the new constitution. "The result," notes Magalhaes, "was that Greece, with similar authoritarian and 40 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization settle contentious public disputes in the political sphere. Deference to the judiciary, in other words, is derivative of political, not judicial, factors.25 Second, when politicians seek to gain public support for contentious views by relying on national high courts' public image as professional and apolitical decision-making bodies, or when they regard public disputes in majoritarian decision-making arenas as likely to put their own policy preferences at risk, diverting responsibility to the courts may become an attractive option. The threat of losing grip on pertinent policy-making processes and outcomes may be a strong driving force behind attempts to transfer power to courts. Accordingly, a strategic, political-power-oriented explanation for voluntary, self-imposed judicial empowerment through the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review suggests that political power-holders who either initiate or refrain from blocking such reforms estimate that it enhances their absolute or relative political power vis-a-vis rival political actors. Political actors who voluntarily establish institutions that appear to limit their institutional flexibility (such as constitutions and judicial review) may assume that the clipping oi their wings under the new institutional structure will be compensated for by the limits it might impose on rival political elements. In short, those who are eager to pay the price of judicial empowerment must assume that their position (absolute or relative) would be improved under a juristocracy. Such an understanding of judicial empowerment through constitutionalization as driven primarily by strategic political considerations may take a "thin" or a "thick" form. The thin version employs party-based "electoral market" logic to explain judicial empowerment. In their seminal work of 1975, William Landes and Richard Posner argued that, other variables being equal, legislators favor the interest groups from which they can elicit the greatest investment through lobbying activities. A key element in maximizing such investment is the ability of legislators to signal credible long-term commitments to certain policy preferences. An independent judiciary's role in this regard is complementary to parliamentary procedural rules—it increases the durability of ; laws by making changes in legislation more difficult and costly. A judi-:: ciary that is overtly subservient to a current legislature (or expressly biased against it) can nullify legislation enacted, in a previous session (or in cur-; rent legislation), thereby creating considerable instability in legal regimes. In;: such legally unstable settings, selling legislation to powerful interest groups; mav prove difficult from the politicians' point of view. The potential threat. The Political Origins of Constitutionalization 41 of instability or loss of mutual profits and power may therefore result in support for judicial empowerment vis-á-vis legislatures.26 Observing variations in the degree of judicial independence among industrial democracies, Mark Ramseyer develops Landes and Posner's argument into an "electoral market" model, which suggests that judicial independence correlates to the competitiveness of a polity's party system.27 When a ruling party expects to win elections repeatedly, the likelihood of judicial empowerment is low. Since rational politicians want long-term bargains with their constituents, they lack the incentive to support an independent judiciary when their prospects of remaining in power are high. However, when a ruling party has a low expectation of remaining in power, it is more likely to support an independent judiciary to ensure that the next ruling party cannot use the judiciary to achieve its policy goals. In other words, under conditions of electoral uncertainty, the more independent courts (or other semiautonomous regulatory agencies) are, the harder it will be for the successive government to reverse the policies of the incumbent government.28 Therefore, in Japan, for example (where a single party ruled almost uninterruptedly for more than four decades following World War II), judicial independence is weaker than it is in countries where there is an acknowledged risk that the party in power might lose control of the legislature in each election. The electoral market thesis is quite insightful when it is used to analyze the politics of constitution-making processes during periods of regime change and political transition. Judicial review, argues Tom Ginsburg, is a solution to the problem of uncertainty izt constitutional design. By providing "insurance" to prospective electoral losers, judicial review can facilitate transition to democracy.29 As Pedro Magalhaes notes, "When the political actors that dominate the constitution-making process expect to lack control over legislatures in the future, judicial review of legislation may emerge as an institution designed to protect their interests."30 The transition to democracy in Spain and Portugal in the mid-1970s, for example, was characterized by lack of a singte core of postauthoritarian political power, thereby leading to the rapid adoption oi strong constitutional review mechanisms. In Greece, by contrast, the postauthoritarian constituent process was dominated by a single party (Constantine Karamanlis's New Democracy), which enjoyed over 70 percent of the seats in the assembly and did not have to worry about elections following the approval of the new constitution. "The result," notes Magalhaes, "was that Greece, with similar authoritarian and 42 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization civil law legacies as Spain and Portugal, and involved in an almost simultaneous democratic transition, remained the only southern European democracy without constitutional review of legislation."31 The same rationale may explain the substantial increase in the power and autonomy of the Supreme Court of Mexico in 1994 as a calculated attempt by the then ruling party (Partido Revoludonario Institutional, or PRI) to lock in its historic influence over Mexico's political sphere before the PRI's increasingly popular political rivals (and eventually winners of the 2000 presidential election) were able to gain control over the country's crucial policy-making arenas.32 In a similar vein, the literature on the political origins of other relatively autonomous agencies (such as central banks, for example) suggests that the autonomy of these agencies in advanced industrial countries is simply a function of government politicians' time horizons. The longer the horizon of their time in power, the more government politicians will desire the greatest possible control over economic policy. This implies a consequent loss of independence for the agency in question. By this logic, short horizons or forthcoming elections can lead politicians who fear losing their office to increase central bank independence in order to limit the future options of their political opponents.33 While the electoral market ("thin") strategic explanation contributes significantly to an understanding of the conditions under which judicial empowerment is more likely to occur, especially at times of political transition, it still does not provide a lull understanding of constitutionalization and the accompanying emergence of judicial review. For one, this model does not provide a full explanation for the rise of judicial power in the premier case . of modern constitutionalization—the pre-ekctoral market, late-eighteenth-century United States. More importantly, this model is based on a somewhat simplistic perception of politics as limited to the partisan electoral market. Such a minimalist understanding of politics does not capture the full picture of constitutional politics in ethnically or culturally divided "'new constitu-. tionalism" polities (e.g., Canada or South Africa), or in countries such as Israel, India, Egypt, or Turkey (to name but a few examples) where the fun-; damental tension between secularist, cosmopolitan values and religious par- : ticularism has been at the forefront of political struggle for decades. The political hegemony and cultural propensities of ruling elites and the urban ■ intelligentsia in these and other fragmented polities have been constantly\ challenged by alternative worldviews, belief systems, and policy preferences. These nuanced and complex political struggles cannot be easily re-, -..^vt-a nrviitirians oper- The Political Origins of Constitutionalization 43 ating under conditions of political uncertainty at times of regime change. Third, the electoral market model ignores influential economic stakeholders' and judicial elites' own contribution to the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review. As will be discussed in more detail in the next chapter, the 1992 constitutional reform in Israel was initiated and carried out by an ad hoc cross-party coalition of leading Knesset members. Those supporting this reform included not only long-standing rivals from, the country's two largest political parties—the Likud (Unity) party, which was in power in 1992, and the Labor party, which was the main opposition party in 1992—but also representatives of the leftist opposition party Meretz and parliament members who represented the policy preferences of the secular bourgeoisie. Clearly, this example demonstrates that the reductive partisan competition model fails to account for certain social and cultural forces. A more nuanced explanation of the political origins of constitutionalization is necessary if we are to fully understand judicial empowerment in countries where it has occurred. Our explanation must ignore neither agency nor the role of economic and judicial elites, and it must reflect the political reality in internally fragmented, rute-of-law polities in a "thick" way that captures a broader picture than the mere electoral market aspect of politics. Such a "thick" strategic explanation, which I term the hegemonic preservation thesis, suggests that judicial empowerment through constitutionalization is best understood.as the by-product of a strategic interplay between three key groups: threatened political elites who seek to preserve or enhance their political hegemony by insulating policy-making processes from the vicissitudes of democratic politics; economic elites who may view the constitutionalization of certain economic liberties as a means of promoting a neoliberal agenda of open markets, economic deregulation, anti-statism, and anticollectivism; and judicial elites and national high courts that seek to enhance their political influence and international reputation. In other words, strategic legal innovators—political elites in association with economic and judicial elites who have compatible interests—determine the timing, extent, and nature of constitutional reform. To be sure, demands for constitutional change often emanate from various groups within the body politic. However, unless hegemonic political and economic elites, their parliamentary representatives, and the judicial elite envisage absolute or relative gain from a proposed change, the demand for that change is likely to be blocked or quashed. When facine nossible threats to their nolirv nrefprpnrp'; in m-aim-bai-ian 44 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization decision-making arenas (such as a growing influence on the part of historically disenfranchised or underrepresented groups and interests in democratically elected policy-making bodies), elites who possess disproportionate access to, and influence over, the legal arena may initiate a constitutional entrenchment of rights in order to transfer power to supreme or constitutional courts. Typically, such proconstitutionalization elites are made up of the urban intelligentsia, the legal profession, and the managerial class. They often represent historically hegemonic enclaves of political and economic power-holders, who tend to adhere to an agenda of relative cosmopolitanism, open markets, formal equality, and Lockean-style individual autonomy. Based on the essential tendency of classic civil liberties to protect individual freedoms, as well as on the courts' record of adjudication and justices' ideological preferences, these elites can safely assume that their policy preferences will be less effectively contested. This type of hegemonic preservation through the constitutionalization of rights or an interest-based judicial empowerment is likely to occur when the judiciary's public reputation for professionalism, political impartiality, and rectitude is relatively high; when judicial appointment processes are controlled to a large extent by hegemonic political elites; and when the courts' constitutional jurisprudence predictably mirrors the cultural propensities and policy preferences of these hegemonic elites. Under such conditions, judicial empowerment through the constitutionalization of rights and the es- . tablishment of judicial review may provide an efficient institutional means by which political elites can insulate their increasingly challenged policy preferences against popular political pressure, especially when majoritarian decision-making processes are not operating to their advantage. This counterintuitive argument has striking parallels in works concerning . the political origins of empowerment of other semiautonomous institutions,.. such as central banks, environmental regulatory bodies, and supranational : treaties and tribunals. Variances in the capacities of early central banking ; institutions in developing countries, for example, were shaped by the ■ changing financial interests of those in a position to voluntarily delegate au- v thority to central banks; government politicians and private banks.34 Simi-:; larly varying degrees of support by existing firms toward proposed environ-; mental regulatory policies can be explained by the different limits and costs: such policies impose upon new firms. Because environmental regulation typically imposes more stringent controls on new firms, it restricts entry into; m^Vptnlare and potentially enhances the competitive position of exist- The Political Origins of Constitutionalization 45 A similar rationale for judicial empowerment at the supranational level is put forward by the "intergovernmentalist" thesis concerning the evolution of the European Court of Justice (ECJ).36 According to this thesis, member states choose to create (and selectively abide by the limits imposed by) supranational institutions primarily because these institutions help them surmount problems arising out of the need for collective action and also help them overcome domestic political problems. National governments of the EU member-states have not been passive, unwilling victims of the process of European legal integration; they consciously transferred power to the Court, and they have supported the Court when it has taken a proactive stance. Moreover, the selective implementation of ECJ rulings by member-stases derives from domestic political considerations by national governments (such as a greater willingness to implement ECJ judgments that favor certain constituencies whose political support is essential for governments and ruling coalitions). Other works have similarly suggested that in newly established democracies in post-World War II Europe, governments committed to international human rights regimes (the European Court of Human Rights, for example) as a means of locking in fundamental democratic practices in order to protect against future antidemocratic threats to domestic governance.37 Governments resorted to this tactic when the benefits of reducing future political uncertainty outweighed the "sovereignty costs" associated with membership in such supranational human rights enforcement mechanisms. The same logic may explain the voluntary incorporation of major international treaties and covenants protecting fundamental human rights and civil liberties into embattled democracies' constitutional law (as happened in Argentina in 1994); or the constitutionalization of rights and the corresponding establishment of full-scale constitutional review following years of political instability and recurring military coups d'etat (as happened in Thailand in 1997),3s Likewise, Miles Kahler has suggested that the precision of the North American Free Trade Agreement (NAFTA), for example, was "part of the Mexican government's strategy to bind successor governments to its policies of economic openness."59 Hence, Andrew Moravcsik notes, "governments may turn to international enforcement when an international commitment effectively enforces the policy preferences of a particular government at a particular point in time against future domestic political alternatives."40 In other words, self-interested political incentives—rather than the altruistic considerations of political leaders or universal commitment to a morally elevated conception of human rights—provided the major impetus for the 46 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization commitment by various countries to binding supranational human rights and free trade regimes. Under specific circumstances, then, political power-holders may choose to enhance their position by voluntarily tying their own hands. Such a strategic, counterintuitive self-limitation may be beneficial from the point of view of political power-holders when the limits imposed on rival elements within the body politic outweigh the limits imposed on themselves. Influential proconstitutionalization political elites in rule-of-law polities, however, do not operate in a political or institutional vacuum. To effectively promote their judicial empowerment interests, they roust secure the cooper- | ation of economic and judicial elites with compatible interests. Indeed, judicial empowerment through the constitutionalization of rights may serve the interests of influential coalitions of domestic economic elites—powerful in- J dustrialists and corporations—who gain added impetus toward less government regulatioYt and reduced social spending by global economic trends. Most constitutional catalogues of rights place boundaries on government action and protect the private sphere (human and economic) from unjustified state intervention. Historically, the rights of landowners, big business, and economic investors were secured long before the rights of workers or women, let alone the poor. Moreover, the modern history of constitutional rights jurisprudence suggests that national high courts also tend to conceptualize the purpose of rights as protecting the private sphere from interference by the "collective," often understood as the state and its regulatory institutions. Economic elites may therefore view the constitutionalization of rights, especially property, mobility, and occupational rights, as a means of removing market rigidities (such as trade barriers and collective bargaining), promoting privatization and economic deregulation, or simply as a way of fighting what their members often perceive to be the harmful large-government policies of an encroaching state. Under specific circumstances, international political economy factors ■ may also push domestic economic elites to advocate constitutionalization as a means of placing economic liberties and rules allowing for free move-.; ment of transnational capital beyond the reach of majoritarian control.41 For : example, the protection of the economic sphere, through the constitu- ■• tionabzation of mobility, property, occupational, and trade rights as well as the establishment of independent judiciaries that function as checks on,, (often "unpredictable") domestic politics and (often "arbitrary") state ac-,; ti«n has long been viewed by transnational economic bodies such as the; The Political Origins of Constitutionalization 47 tary Fund as a primary indicator of successful markets and sustained economic growth.42 The incorporation into domestic law of these and other le-gal norms endorsed by transnational trade and monetary regimes is often a j prerequisite imposed on countries striving to become members. New de- li mocracies (such as those in the former Eastern Bloc) that rely heavily on 1 foreign aid and investment are likely to bow to pressure from leading west- ern democracies, economic corporations, or transnational governing bodies to promote the rule of law by emulating the constitutional fundamentals of liberal democracies. Adopting a constitutional catalogue of rights and establishing judicial review may therefore serve as a means to demonstrate a willingness to accept the required legal standards for joining supranational economic regimes. The restriction of legislative power through the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review may also enhance a given regime's international economic credibility. In short, the global trend towards constitutionalization concerns more than preservation of increasingly threatened values of core social groups. As Stephen Gill observes, "[n]ew constitutionalism is a macro-political dimension of the process whereby the nature and purpose of the public sphere has been redefined in a more privatized and commodifred way ... it can be defined as the political project of attempting to make trans-national liberalism, and if possible liberal democratic capitalism, the sole model for future development. It is therefore intimately related to the rise of market civilization."43 The transfer of power to the courts may also serve the interests of a supreme court seeking to enhance its political influence and international profile. As the recent strategic revolution in the study of judicial decisionmaking has established, judges may be precedent followers, framers of legal policies, or ideology-driven decision-makers, but they are also sophisticated strategic decision-makers who realize that their range of choices is constrained by the preferences and anticipated reaction of the surrounding political sphere.44 Justices tend to vote strategically to minimize the chances that their decisions will be overridden; if the interpretation that the justices most prefer is likely to elicit reversal by other branches, they will compromise by adopting the interpretation closest to their preferences that could be predicted to withstand reversal.45 Accordingly, quite a few landmark decisions of the U.S. Supreme Court have not been merely acts of professional, apolitical jurisprudence (as doctrinal legalistic explanations of court rulings often suggest) or reflections of its justices' ideological preferences and vafues (as "attitudinal" models of judicial behavior might suggest), but also a re-flection of their strategic choices. 48 The Political Origins of Constitutionalization The Political Origins of Constitutionalization 49 Short-term policy considerations represent merely one possible motivation for strategic behavior by courts. Supreme Court judges may also be viewed as strategic actors to the extent that they seek to maintain or enhance the Court's institutional position vis-a-vis other major national decision-making bodies.46 Courts may realize when the changing fates or preferences of other influential political actors, as well as gaps in the institutional context within which they operate, might allow them to strengthen their own position by extending the ambit of their jurisprudence and fortifying their status as crucial national policy-making bodies.47 As recent studies have shown, the establishment of an international rule of law in Europe was driven in no small part by national judges' attempts to enhance their independence, influence, and authority vis-a-vis other courts and political actors.48 Expansion of judicial power through the constitutionalization of rights and judicial review may also support the interests of a supreme court seeking to increase its symbolic power and international prestige by fostering its alignment with a growing community of liberal democratic nations engaged in judicial review and rights-based discourse. In this respect, note that the past several decades have seen an accelerating trend toward intercourr borrowing and the establishment of a globalized, non-U.S.-centered judicial discourse. This trend has been described by Mary Ann Glendon as "a brisk international traffic in ideas about rights" carried on through advanced information technologies by high court judges from different countries.*9 In its first landmark rights decision {Makwanyane, 1995—determining the unconstitutionality of the death penalty), the South African Constitutional Court examined in detail landmark rulings from Botswana, Canada, the European Court of Human .Rights, Germany, Hong Kong, Hungary, India, Jamaica, Tanzania, the United Nations Committee on Human Rights, the United States, and Zimbabwe. As one commentator recently noted: "Constitution interpretation across the globe is taking on an increasingly cosmopoli- . tan character, as comparative jurisprudence comes to assume a central place in constitutional adjudication."50 In short, according to Anne-Marie Slaughter, "Courts are talking to one another all over the world."51 Similarly, judi- v cial empowerment through constitutionalization may elevate the symbolic status of a fairly cohesive professional stratum of judges, law professors,; human rights organizations, litigation-oriented nongovernmental organizations (NGOs), top lawyers, and law firms. Not surprisingly, the legal profession has been one of the major advocates of judicial empowerment. The support of influential political elites remains the key factor in judicial empowerment through constitutionalization. Supreme courts in relatively open, rule-of-law polities would prefer to have an enhanced political influence and international profile. Likewise, economic elites have a near-permanent interest in extended protection of the private sphere and entrenchment of economic freedoms. It is political power-holders who are least likely to provide constant support for constitutionalization and the corresponding expansion of judicial power, because these changes are likely to lessen their room tor political maneuvering. Thus, political power-holders—not economic or judicial elites—are the primary catalyst and driving force behind constitutionalization. Judicial power does not fall from the sky; it is politically constructed. I believe that the constitutionalization of rights and the fortification of judicial review result from a strategic pact led by hegemonic yet increasingly threatened political elites, who seek to insulate their policy preferences against the changing fortunes of democratic politics, in association with economic and judicial elites who have compatible interests. The changes that emerge reflect a combination of the policy preferences and professional interests of these groups. Given that there are at least three distinct groups whose ability to gain ■ power and influence is contingent on judicial empowerment through the constitutionalization of rights, it becomes evident that the hegemonic preservation explanation does not depend on the existence of any systemic social need. Nor does it assume any necessary evolution in a progressive direction. This explanation is not deterministic, but actor-oriented; and, unlike extant microfoundational theories of judicial independence, it does not depend on the competitiveness of the party system. While most existing theories of constitutional transformation focus on universal or organic macro-explanations for this increasingly common phenomenon, a realist approach to constitutionalization emphasizes human agency and specific political incentives as the major determinants of judicial empowerment. Such an approach suggests that the expansion of judicial power through the constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review reflects appropriation of the rhetoric of social justice by threatened elites to bolster their own position in the ongoing political struggles of a specific polity. In the next chapter, I illustrate the hegemonic preservation thesis in action in four new constitutionalism polities—Israel Canada, New Zealand, and South Africa. Hegemonic Preservation in Action 51 ;HAPTER 3 Hegemonic Preservation in Action "When I use a word," Humpty Dumpty said in a rather scornful tone, "it means just what I choose it to mean—neither more nor less." "The question is," said Alice, "whether you can make words mean so many different things." "The question is," said Humpty Dumpty, "who is to be master— that's all." Lewis Carroll, Through the Looking Glass and What Alice Found There The 1992 Constitutional Revolution in Israel The recent history of constitutional politics in Israel presents a near-ideal illustration of my explanation of judicial empowerment. The hands that guided the 1992 constitutionalization of rights and the establishment of judicial review in Israel were entirely visible; the process was steered by an ad hoc. cross-party coalition of politicians representing Israel's historically hege- . monk (albeit increasingly challenged) secular Ashkenazi elite in associa- ,: tion with economic and judicial elites who had compatible interests. This . triadic strategic alliance, of which the political component was the most ;j active, determined the timing, scope, and nature of the 1992 constitutional revolution. It has also been the major coalition opposing the constitutionalization of subsistence welfare rights and the creation of a more demo- ■:. cratically representative Supreme Court. It was driven primarily by a self- ; interested agenda—not by its members' subordination to some invisible evolutionist or structural forces nor by their devotion to some elevated vi-.: sion of human rights or national unity. The 1992 constitutional entrenchment of rights and the establishment of. "^viai review in Israel were initiated and supported by politicians repre- senting Israel's secular Ashkenazi bourgeoisie, whose historic political hegemony in crucial majoritarian policy-making arenas (such as the Knesset) had become increasingly threatened. The political representatives of this group found the delegation of policy-making authority to the Court an efficient way to overcome the growing popular backlash against its ideological hegemony and, perhaps more important, an effective short-term means of avoiding the potentially negative political consequences of its steadily declining control over the majoritarian decision-making arena. A brief survey of the key events that have shaped Israel's constitutional history since the establishment of the state is necessary in order to understand this claim. The state of Israel was founded on May 14, 1948, as a "Jewish and Democratic" state. As we have seen in earlier chapters, the major constitutional challenge Israel has faced since its foundation has been the creation of an ideologically plausible and politically feasible synthesis between these two seemingly contradictory terms (especially given that approximately one-fifth of Israel's citizenry consists of non-Jews).1 And as we have seen in Chapter 1, even within the Jewish population itself, the exact meaning of Israel as a Jewish state has been highly contested with a secular, relatively cosmopolitan lifestyle and ideological preferences striving to maintain their hegemony vis-a-vis embedded symbols of Jewish tradition, religiosity, and exceptionalism. While historically the Orthodox stream of the Jewish religion has long enjoyed the status of being the sole branch of Judaism formally recognized by the state, a series of landmark Supreme Court of Israel (SCI) rulings over the past several years have altered the long-standing status quo.2 Throughout its existence, Israel has also struggled with social divisions based on ethnicity and national origin. There are the fissures between Mizrahi or Sephardi Jews (mostly Jews of North African and Mediterranean origin) and the generally better-off Ashkenazi Jews (mostly Jews of European descent). Further social heterogeneity comes from Israel's vibrant immigrant community, with approximately one million immigrants who arrived from the former Soviet Union during the 1990s forming the majority. A sizable minority of Jewish immigrants also came from Ethiopia. Their reception opened the polity up to charges of skin-based racism for the first time. The final twist of variety in this divided polity is the growing community of non-Jewish foreign workers residing in Israel (estimated at 300,000 or more), approximately two-thirds of whom have entered the country illegally. 52 Hegemonic Preservation in Action The 1948 Declaration of Independence of the State of Israel created temporary governmental institutions. A Constituent Assembly was simultaneously formed and invested with the power to draft a constitution that would eventually establish permanent governing institutions. In 1949, the Constituent Assembly changed its name to the Knesset and established itself as the legislative body of the state of Israel. After a year of debates over the merits of a constitution, it became apparent that the religious parties were opposed to the idea of an entrenched constitution because it would invest the ultimate source of sovereignty in the citizenry rather than in God or Jewish law. Mapai—the primary component of today's Labor Party and the unchallenged secular ruling party at the time—was also unwilling to proceed with drafting a constitution, partly to avoid jeopardizing the tenuous secular/religious coalition government, but primarily because Mapai leaders, notably David Ben-Gurion, had no political incentive to transfer policymaking authority to the judiciary and no desire to impose any limitations on their own power. Thus, to preserve political power while simultaneously pursuing a constitutional dialogue, in 1950 the first Knesset adopted a compromise known as the Harari Resolution. This enabled the Knesset both to evade its obligation to compose a written constitution and to preserve its power to enact one through the adoption of a series of Basic Laws. The resolution stated: "The constitution shall be composed of individual chapters in such a manner that each of them shall constitute a basic law in itself. The individual chapters shall be brought before the Knesset... and all the chapters together will form the State Constitution."3 In the years leading up to 1992, the Knesset passed nine Basic Laws, concerning primarily the powers vested in the various branches of government.4 None of these laws provided any entrenched constitutional protection of basic rights and liberties, just as none formally established any type of . judicial review. In the absence of a civil rights tradition and the necessary.: constitutional framework for actively reviewing primary legislation, the Supreme Court was limited in the pre-1992 era to judicial interpretation of administrative acts, informed by an "implied bill of rights" doctrine.5 Beginning in the late 1950s, numerous attempts were made by civil libertarian politicians and interest groups to pass a bill of rights. Until 1992, all of these attempts failed. Standard explanations for Israel's repeated failure to ; enact a bill of rights before 1992 include the British colonial legacy of parlia-: mentary sovereignty, steady opposition from the religious parties, and the; lark of consensus among Israel's Jewish secular and religious populations re- Hegemonic Preservation in Action 53 garding Israel's definition as a Jewish and democratic state (terms that many believe to be mutually exclusive and that therefore deity, prima facie, any meaningful protection of religious minority rights by a constitutional bill of rights). While these explanations are persuasive, they reveal only part of the picture. The British tradition was far more pervasive in India than in Israel, yet at the same historical moment of Israel's founding, the new Indian Congress was enacting a detailed and wide-reaching constitution. Moreover, every country that has adopted substantive judicial review, from eighteenth-century America to twentieth-century South Africa, has done so in opposition to a prior tradition—including, most recently, Canada in 1982, New Zealand in 1990, many former Eastern Bloc countries in the early 1990s, and the United Kingdom in 1998. In Israel, the religious parties' opposition to the constitutional entrenchment of rights was certainly not insurmountable. At least until the mid-1980s, they were a minority, whose opposition could have been overcome by combining several factions of the majority secular forces. The difficulty in defining Israel as both Jewish and democratic proved not to be a major stumbling block to a bill of rights; this dual definition has not changed since the state's foundation, and in fact was reentrenched by the Basic Laws adopted in 1992. The most plausible explanation for the failure to enact a bill of rights in Israel before 1992 is that political power-holders in the pre-1990s legislature were disinclined to delegate power to the judiciary as long as their political hegemony and control of parliament remained almost unchallenged. That constitutional reforms have taken place since 1992 in spite of the continued presence of the long-standing obstacles just mentioned suggests that the political incentives driving the parliamentary representatives of the primarily Ashkenazi secular elite were what changed. During the first three decades of Israel's independence, when its control of Israeli politics was virtually undisturbed, Ben-Gurion's Mapai opposed the adoption of a bill of rights and repeatedly championed the democratic character of parliamentary sovereignty and majority rule. Highly critical of the constitutional role of the Supreme Court in the United States, Ben-Gurion said in a frequently cited speech: "Do we need a Constitution like the Americans? By all means let us profit from the experience of others and borrow laws and procedures from them, provided they match our needs . . . [I]n a free state like ... Israel there is no need for a bill of rights. . . we need a bill of duties... duties to the homeland, to the people, to aliyah, to building the 54 Hegemonic Preservation in Action Hegemonic Preservation in Action 55 land, to the security of others, to the weak."6 In a debate about due process and emergency regulations, Ben-Garion went on to say: "Every jurist knows how easy it is to weave juridical cobwebs to prove anything and refute anything ... as a law student I know that no one can distort any text and invent far-fetched assumptions and confusing interpretation like the jurist."7 As Gary Jacobsohn notes, "for historians and legal scholars, even those inclined to resist cynicism, it is relatively easy to accept the allegations of Menachem Begin, then the leader of the minority Herut movement, that Ben-Gurion's opposition to a constitution was fundamentally attributable to his fear of losing all or some of his power." As Begin pointed out in a debate in the First Knesset, "if the Constituent Assembly legislates a constitution, then the government will not be free to do as it likes."s In short, as Song as Israel's secular Ashkenazi elite remained virtually unchallenged in their control of parliament, they had no reason to undermine their position by delegating power to the judiciary through the entrenchment of rights and the establishment of judicial review. This led to a constitutional stalemate, which persisted from the early 1950s until the late 1980s. But as Israel's secular Ashkenazi bourgeoisie and its political representatives increasingly lost their grip on Israeli politics, their attitude toward judicial review changed. In the early 1990s, a group of Knesset members, representing a primarily secular, neolibeTal ideological agenda, reacted to the continuous decline of their popular support by forming an ad hoc cross-party parliamentary coalition that initiated and carried out an institutional empowerment of the judiciary. Draft legislation was submitted to the Knesset by Knesset Member (MK) and law professor Amnon Rubinstein (of the liberal, left-wing Meretz party, then in the parliamentary opposition) in the summer of 1991, with the tacit assent of the Justice Minister Dan Meridor (of the right-wing Likud party). This initiative culminated in the. 1992 enactment of two basic civil rights and liberties laws—Basic Law: Human Dignity and Liberty, and Basic Law: Freedom of Occupation.—as well as : the amendment of Basic Law: The Government.9 These enactments paved the way for active judicial review in Israel by awarding the Supreme Court. the authority both to monitor closely Israel's political arena and to rescind any "unconstitutional" primary legislation enacted by the Knesset. A comprehensive survey of parliamentary records reveals that of the leading group of 32 MKs who consistently advocated and supported the new. lflws in the Knesset pre-enactment debates (from the preliminary debates in April-May 1991 to their official enactment in March 1992), 18 were Labor MKs, 8 were Likud MKs, and 6 were Meretz MKs {a rare cross-party coalition)—all of whom supported a clear secular, neoliberal agenda and many of whom held legal qualifications.10 Of the original 32 supporters, 28 voted consistently against increasing state funding for various religious and ultra-Orthodox educational institutions, 25 voted consistently for the privatization of various public services (including the commodification of Israel's electronic media, health, telecommunication, and banking services), and 26 were professionals (lawyers, doctors, managers, and so on). The 21 MKs who consistently opposed the adoption of the new Basic Laws in the pre-enactment parliamentary debates were all representatives of either the orthodox religious parties, the extreme right-wing parties, the communist party, or the Arab-Israeli population.11 What, were the political origins of this historic constitutional breakthrough and the astonishing change of heart among the major political representatives of Israel's secular bourgeoisie? Whereas Israel's historically hegemonic secular Ashkenazi bourgeoisie has faced a continuous decline in its political representation since the early 1980s, marginalized groups, such as residents of peripheral development towns and poor urban neighborhoods (mainly Mizrahi Jews and blue-collar immigrants from the former Soviet Union), Israeli-Arabs from ethnically mixed towns, and lower-income religious groups, have steadily gained political power during this period (see Table 3.1). The constant exclusion of these marginalized groups from privileged localities, networks, resources, and opportunities has reinforced their opposition to the historically dominant Ashkenazi bourgeoisie. In addition, Israel experienced an unprecedented 20 percent population increase between the mid-1980s and the early 1990s, with the absorption of more than 800,000 immigrants, most of them from the former Soviet Union.12 Over the period 1989-1991 alone, and in accordance with Israel's Law of Return, more than 450,000 newly arrived immigrants became members of the Israeli citizenry, thus gaining rights to vote and fully participate in Israel's public life. Not surprisingly, these new immigrants have gradually begun to take part in Israel's political life, establishing new political parties that represent their particular interests (for example, in the fields of employment, education, and housing). In the late 1980s and early 1990s, the levels of segregation and inequality in Israeli society rose to unprecedented heights, further alienating these marginalized groups from the (largely) Ashkenazi establishment. Israel's 56 Hegemonic Preservation in Action Gini Index (0 = perfect equal income distribution) worsened, from 0,222 in 1982 to 0.298 in 1991 to 0.314 in 1994 and to a record high of 0.356 in 2000, making Israel's wealth distribution one of the three most unequal among western countries (third only to New Zealand and the United States).13 The demographic distribution of poverty has also remained unchanged since Israel's establishment: the cities with the largest populations of ultra-Orthodox Jews, Arab-Israelis, new immigrants from the former Soviet Union, and Mizrahi Jews (not to mention undocumented foreign workers) remain those with the highest levels of poverty. In some Arab-Israeli villages and townships, ultra-Orthodox communities, and in so-called development towns (whose residents are almost exclusively Mizrahi Jews and blue-collar immigrants from the former Soviet Union), the level of poverty has grown to over 40 percent. The unemployment rate in these towns has risen sharply, to about 20 percent, twice Israel's average, as many textile and manufacturing factories in peripheral areas have closed their doors. In 1991, unemployment among the second-generation Ashkenazi population stood at 4.9 percent, but it was 13.2 percent among the second-generation Mizrahi population. In that year, 72 percent of the second-generation Ashkenazi population worked in white-collar occupations, while among the second-generation Mizrahi population, this figure was 46 percent. In 1975, 25 percent of the Israeli-born Ashkenazi population were college graduates, compared to 6 percent of the Mizrahi population; in 1992, the ratio was almost the same, although levels were higher: 41 percent and 11 percent respectively.14 These and other socioeconomic and demographic developments have brought about a growing antagonism among peripheral groups toward the : core elites. Some Mizrahi Orthodox rabbis have garnered wide popular support in poor neighborhoods, becoming political spokesmen who publicly challenge Israel's relationship with the non-Orthodox diaspora Jewry . worldwide and, more important, the rule of (secular) state law. A clear man- : jfestation of this trend was reflected in the 1995 assassination of Prime Minister Yitzhak Rabin (a representative and symbol of the Ashkenazi secular bourgeoisie) by a young religious Mizrahi Jew from a poor neighborhood.:: The assassin was backed by a Halakhic verdict issued by Orthodox rabbis who opposed the peace process led by Rabin—a process that had enjoyed wide support among the secular bourgeoisie.15 Antagonism toward the core values and policy preferences of the Ashkenazi secular high-income elite rapidly found its way into the Knesset. This.; Hegemonic Preservation in Action 57 can be seen in the number of seats won by parties that represent, by and large, the policy preferences of marginalized minority groups in Israeli society, as compared to seats won by Knesset members who represent the policy agenda of the secular bourgeoisie (Labor, Meretz, the Liberal Party's section of Likud, and others). As Table 3.1 indicates, the bloc of Knesset members representing the secular bourgeoisie's policy preferences consists mainly of the Labor Party (identified mainly with the secular Ashkenazi establishment), Meretz (identified, mainly with the secular urban intelligentsia and the Kibbutzim), and the segment of the Likud party identified with populist secularism and a deregu-latory economic policy. This bloc lost more than one-third of its relative combined electoral power between 1981 and 1999 (from 95 MKs in 1981 to 62 in 1996 and 58 in 1999).16 This continuous decline of the secular bourgeois power base has been accompanied by a dramatic increase in the electoral power of parties representing disadvantaged minorities in Israeli society. Together, parties representing marginalized groups in Israel more than doubled their combined electoral power between 1981 and 1999 (from 25 MKs in 1981 to 58 in 1996 and 62 in 1999). The Shas party alone (representing Orthodox religious Mizrahi residents of development towns and poor urban neighborhoods) increased its power impressively, from 4 Knesset seats in 1984 (63,600 votes) to 10 in 1996 (260,000 votes) and 17 in 1999 (430,000 votes), making it the third largest party in the fifteenth Knesset and leaving it only two seats shy of the Likud's 19 seats.17 Shas's impressive electoral success was quickly translated into powerful policy-making positions in the government and the public service. For over a decade (from 1988 to May 1999), Shas had control over both the Ministry of Labor and Social Affairs and the strategically powerful Ministry of Interior (responsible for local government, budgetary allocations for Israel's municipalities, and the population administration that controls the registration of new immigrants). Shas was the second largest partner (after the Labor Party) in the new governing coalition established by Ehud Barak following the 1999 election, and its ministers held four crucial policy-making portfolios, including National Infrastructure, Labor and Social Affairs, and the Ministry of Health. Drawing on its increasing political power, Shas has been able to secure government funding for its increasingly popular semiautonomous education network. The results of Israel's 1996 and 1999 elections clearly illustrate that parties representing the Arab-Israeli population, immigrants from the former Soviet Union, Orthodox religious voters, and Mizrahi resi- 58 Hegemonic Preservation in Action Hegemonic Preservation in Action 59 -----^T^T^MS!** 1996 Number of seats 120) 33 Labor3 Likud Knesset members representing a secular bourgeois policy agenda1' CRM/Shinui/Meretz Other Knesset members representing a secular bourgeois policy agenda* Total 47 43 3 2 95 44 35 10 89 82 44 24 12 80 34 15 louu Religious parttese ^ 7 n 4 62 23 10 58 1999 21" 15 16 6 58 27 4 10 10 11 62 Religious parties' Right-wing parties' Arab and Communist lists Ex-Soviet immigrants listss Likud, Labor, and other Knesset members identified primarily with Mizrabi Jews' policy agenda11 Total Total Source: Adapted from the official results of Israel's 1981, 1984, 1988, 1992, 1996, and 1999 national elections. ;