Institute of Foreign and Comparative Law Personality rights: a comparative overview Author(s): Johann Neethling Source: The Comparative and International Law Journal of Southern Africa, Vol. 38, No. 2 (JULY 2005), pp. 210-245 Published by: Institute of Foreign and Comparative Law Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/23252295 Accessed: 25-02-2019 10:39 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Institute of Foreign and Comparative Law is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Comparative and International Law Journal of Southern Africa This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview Johann Neethling* Professor: School of Law, University of South Africa Abstract This contribution entails a comparative review or synopsis of the present state of the protection of personality rights. Realistically, this can only be a snapshot of the status quo in various legal systems and is not intended to give a detailed exposition. The aim is to summarise, systemise and to an extent critically reflect on the available literature, as well as to identify particular dogmatic and practical problems. The research results may also stimulate in-depth examination of particular aspects of personality protection. The topics dealt with are the recognition and basis of protection of personality rights, the scope of their protection, the relationship between the general right to personality and specific personality rights, the nature of personality rights and personality harm, the classification of specific personality rights, the distinction between personality rights and certain patrimonial rights, personality rights as human rights, post-mortem personality protection, and the personality rights of juristic persons. HISTORICAL BACKGROUND Personality rights, which recognise a person as a physical and s being1 and guarantee his enjoyment of his own sense of existen protected in various countries to a greater or lesser degree. Bu of personality rights is not new. In particular classical natural notion of innate, inalienable human rights which included va relating to personality, forms the background to the modern 1877 Gareis, and after him Gierke and Kohler, postulated the idea *BA LLB (UOFS); LLM (McGill); LLD (Unisa). 'WA Joubert Grondslae van die persoonlikheidsreg (1953) at 130-1; J N Potgieter & PJ Visser Neethling's law of personality (2005) at 24. 2C von Bar The common European law of torts vol 2 (2000) at 61. 3Joubert n 1 above at 13ff\ D Leuze Die Entwicklung des Personlichke Jahrhundert: zugleich ein Beitrag zum Verhaltnis allgemeine Persdnl Rechtsfahigkeit (1962) at l\ff 21ff H Hubmann Das Persdnlichkeits 85ff\ M Herrmann Der Schutz der Persdnlichkeit in der Rechtslehre Jahrhunderts (1968) at I9ff 29ff; M-T Frick Personlichkeitsrechte. Rechtsvergleichende Studie iiberden Stand des Persdnlichkeitsschutzes in Ostereich, Deutschland, der Schweiz und Liechtenstein (1991) at 44; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 6. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 211 right to personality4 from which particular rights or interests of personality may develop, such as (the rights to) physical integrity, freedom, and dignity.5 Gierke even enumerated the characteristics which distinguish personality rights from other rights, they are private rights, of a non-patrimonial nature and highly personal in the sense that they are connected to the personality of their holder and terminate with his death (in other words, they are non transferable and unhereditable).6 However, whereas Gareis and Gierke considered the products of the human mind as part of the general right of personality, Kohler distinguished between such intellectual property and personality rights,7 demonstrating that a person's intellectual creations exist independently of his personality, and form a separate category of legal objects, namely immaterial or intellectual property. Today the idea of personality rights as a separate group of private rights is firmly established on the European continent, and has also made its appearance elsewhere (for example, in South Africa and the USA). The different legal systems nevertheless do not share the same views on the recognition and scope of protection of these rights.8 RECOGNITION AND BASIS OF PROTECTION OF PERSONALITY RIGHTS Since as a rule individuals attach considerable significance to face personality — so much so that most personality rights have also been entrenched as human rights9 — and are accordingly sensitive to infringements thereof,10 it can as premise be accepted that all legal systems strive towards, and indeed have an obligation, because of their human rights connotation,11 to provide for comprehensive personality protection. In this regard a differentiated approach has been followed. First of all, there are those systems, of which German law is the best example, that recognise a general right to personality as a basis for comprehensive personality protection. Although such a basis existed in the common law of that country under the actio iniuriarum, it was not included in the BGB, mainly because the protection by criminal sanctions of dignity alone was considered sufficient. Specific personality rights were nevertheless statutorily recognised, namely the rights to a name, image, dignity, reputation, body, life, 4Leuze n 3 above at 93#; Joubert n 1 above at 18\ff\ S Stromholm Right of privacy and rights of the personality: a comparative survey (1967) at 29; R Nehmelman Het algemeen persoonlijkheidsrecht. Een rechtsvergelijkende studie naar het algemeen persoonlijkheidsrecht in Duitsland en Nederland (2002) at Iff Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 6-7; BS Markesinis & H Unberath The German law of torts: a comparative treatise (2002) at 74. 5Leuze n 3 above at 114-5; Joubert n 1 above at 20; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 8-9. 'Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 8. 'joubert n 1 above at 21ff Leuze n 3 above at 103#; Nehmelman n 4 above at 7-8. 8Von Bar n 2 above at 61. 'See below under Personality rights as human rights. '"Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 12. uVon Bar n 2 above at 61. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 212 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 freedom and health.12 However, the paramount significance attached to human dignity and the free development of personality in the Constitution brought about a radical change in 1954 when the BGH recognised a general right to personality — a development confirmed by the BverfG13 and considered by Larenz and Canaris14 to be the most important change in German tort law since the enactment of the BGB.15 The basis of the protection of personality is thus the general right to personality which comprises all aspects of personality and can be regarded as the fountain (Mutterrecht) from which all concrete or specific rights of personality flow.16 These rights are either embodied in legislation as indicated, or they may b recognised by the courts, for example, the rights to privacy and identity.1 The general right can thus be regarded as a general clause on which expansio of personality protection can be based.18 At the opposite pole are those systems which have and see no need for th recognition of a general right to personality because their law possesses a different foundation for comprehensive personality protection.19 French la provides a clear example. Here the courts developed an extensive protection of personality interests on the basis of the general delictual provisions of the 12J Helle Besondere Persdnlichkeitsrechte im Privatrecht (1991) at 3-5; Leuze n 3 above at 67#; E von Caemmerer 'Wandlungen des Deliktsrechts' in E von Caemmerer, E Friesenhahn & R Lange (eds) Hundert Jahre deutsches Rechtsleben vol 2 (1960) at 102\ff\ C von Bar Gemeineuropaisches Deliktsrecht vol 1 (1996) at 42-3; Markesinis & Unberath n 4 above at 26-7, 43, 74-5; W-S Son Schutz gegen Ebrverletzungen im deutschen und koreanischen Recht (1996) at 52\ff\ Nehmelman n 4 above at 10ff H Walter Actio Iniuriarum: der Scbutz der Persdnlicbkeit im siidafrikanischen Privatrecht (1996) at 24-6. "H Neumann-Duesberg 'Zum allgemeinen Personlichkeitsrecht und zu den besonderen Personlichkeitsrechten im Privatrecht' (1991) 42 VersR 957 at 957-8; Nehmelman n 4 above at 22'ff. 14K Larenz & C-W Canaris Lebrbuch des Schuldrechts vol II/2 (1994) at 491; W van Gerven et al Tort law (2000) at 142. 15Von Bar n 12 above at 583-4; Von Caemmerer n 12 above at 105-6; Helle n 12 above at 6-7; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 63# 142# 165-6; JM Smits 'Constitutionalisering van het vermogensrecht' in JM Smits et al (eds) Preadviezen uitgebracht voor de Nederlandse Vereniging voor Rectsvergelijking (2003) 121-3; Walter n 12 at 26-7; E Guldix & A Wylleman 'De positie en de handhaving van persoonlijkheidsrechten in het Belgisch privaatrecht' (1999) 36 TPR 1589 at 1620-1621; Nehmelman n 4 above at 16# Neumann-Duesberg n 13 above at 957. I6Helle n 12 above at 11. "Hubmann n 3 above at 220ff 27Iff, 52}ff H Hubmann 'Inhalt und Abgrenzung des zivilrechtlichen allgemeinen Personlichkeitsrechts' in W Waldner & R Kiinzl (eds) Erlangen Festschrift fur Karl Heinz Schwab (1990) at 4-5; O-F van Gamm Persdnlickheits- und Ebrverletzungen durcb Massenmedien (1969) at 28, 39-42; Son n 12 above at 32-5, 52-4; K Lemmens 'The protection of privacy between a rights based and a freedom-based approach: what the Swiss example can teach us' (2003) 10 MJ 381 at 385-387; Nehmelman n 4 above at 3Qff\ U Kerpcn Das Internationale Privatrecht der Persdnlichkeitsrechtsverletzungen (2003) at 5-8, 11; cf Helle n 12 above at 11#, 27% 45iff, 229# lsCf Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 518-9. l9Von Bar n 2 above at 94 n 508. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 213 CC, and especially by extending the concept of damage to personality harm.20 Some of these interests are physical integrity, dignity, good name, feelings {sentiments d'affectiori), privacy and identity (including name and image), and may be identified by the courts as objects of personality rights.21 A few of these interests have furthermore been granted legislative protection, the most prominent of which is the express recognition of privacy in the CC.22 As a result of the all-embracing protection of especially the principles of delict, there is no need for the recognition of a general right of personality — as in German law. Besides, the practical significance of such a right is questioned by French jurists since a concretisation of specific rights of personality is in any case still necessary.23 24South African law can also be mentioned here. Since the actio iniuriarum provides all-embracing protection of personality, there is no need for the recognition of a general right to personality. Separate personality rights are recognised and protected, including the rights to corpus (physical-mental integrity), libertas (physical freedom) andfama (reputation), as well as the rights relating to dignitas, which is regarded as a collective term tor all other personality rights, inter alia the rights to dignity, privacy and, to a lesser extent, feelings and identity. The concept of dignitas accordingly serves as a basis for the recognition of further rights of personality and therefore the extension of personality protection in so far as this may be necessary.25 Thirdly, there are those systems which, although they have another basis for comprehensive personality protection, nevertheless in addition also recognise a general right to personality. This is for instance the case in the Netherlands 20Kerpen n 17 above at 44/7; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 57/7; WVH Rogers (ed) el al Damages for non-pecuniary loss in a comparative perspective (2001) at 87-9; Hubmann n 3 above at 104-6; I Schmitz I Persdnlichkeitsrechte und zivilrechtliche Deliktshaftung imfranzdsischen und deutschen Recht (1967) at 4-6; Gutachten des Max-Planck-Instituts ffir auslandisches und internationales Privatrecht Der zivilrechtliche Persdnlichkeits- und Ehrenschutz in Franckreich, der Schweiz, England und den vereinigten Staaten (1960) at 34/7; L-J Constantinesco 'Die Persdnlichkeitsrechte und ihr Schutz im Franzosischen Recht' (1960) 159 AcP 320 at 320ff 21Kerpen n 17 above at 44, 46, 47ff, Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 110, 152, 166; Schmitz n 20 above at 30ff 39ff Hubmann n 3 above at 105; Max-Planck Gutachten n 20 above at 4:1ff, Joubert n 1 above at 53ff 22Kerpen n 17 above at 44, 52ff; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 53, 156-7; Lemmens n 17 above at 385. 23Kerpen n 17 above at 46; Hubmann n 3 above at 105; Schmitz n 20 above at 18\ff Smits n 15 above at 126. 24In Belgium the concept of personality rights was imported from France and is today still influenced by French literature (Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1589-94). Belgium therefore, also does not know or need a general right to personality, but recognises only separate personality rights which include the rights to privacy, image, life, body, name, dignity and good name (Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1620-1, 1624/7). 25Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 39-59; Joubert n 1 above at ISff, Walter n 12 above at 42\ff 64ff, 144-8; JM Burchell Personality rights and freedom of expression. The modern actio iniuriarum (1998) at 133, 327ff, JM Burchell 'The protection of personality rights' in R Zimmermann & D Visser (eds) Southern cross: civil law and common law in South Africa (1996) 639 at 639jff This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 214 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 and Austria. In Austria the basis for a comprehensive recognition and protection of personality rights is provided not only in the ABGB which expressly emphasises personality rights, but also in the general delictual provisions.26 However, for a long time the courts had an inhibiting influence on the realisation of the full potential of these provisions, 7 refusing {contra legem) to extend personality protection beyond cases expressly recognised by legislation;28 and this may perhaps be the reason why the general right to personality was recently adopted by the Austrian courts.29 Specific personality rights (such as the rights to life, physical integrity, image, privacy and dignity) are also recognised. In the Netherlands, in spite of the general delictual clause of the BW, and the provision catering for awarding non pecuniary loss in instances of infringement of the physical person, dignity, reputation, or any other infringement of the person, which entails, inter alia, non-physical personal injury (such as psychiatric illness), invasion of privacy and interference with freedom of movement,30 the Hoge Raad recognised the existence of the general right to personality in 1994. This right is said to underpin other fundamental rights such as the right to privacy, although its juridical nature remains uncertain.32 Although Dutch law recognises rights of personality (such as the rights to life, physical and psychological integrity, freedom of movement, dignity, good name, identity, autonomy, and privacy),33 the most striking difference between the German and Dutch concepts of the general right to personality is that the former gave rise to the creation of various specific personality rights, while the latter has been very slow to do so.34 35 26Frick n 3 above at 56. 27E Kamer & H Koziol Der Ersatz ideellen Scbadens im osterreichischen Recht und seine Reform: Verhandlungen des Fiinfzehnten Osterreichischen Juristentages Innsbruck 2003 vol II/l (2003) at 17-22; Frick n 3 above at 44-8. 28Frick n 3 above at 59-61. 29Von Bar n 2 above at 94 n 508; cf Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 17-22. ^SD Lindenbergh 'De positie en de handhaving van persoonlijkheidsrechten in het Nederlandse privaatrecht' (1999) 36 TPR 1665 at 1692-3; Rogers et al n 20 above at 155. 31 Cf Nehmelman n 4 above at 268. 32Smits n 15 above at 124; Nehmelmann n 4 above at 115; Lindenbergh n 30 above at 1672-3. 33Smits n 15 above at 124; Lindenbergh n 30 above at 1667-9,1673-5; cf Nehmelmam n 4 above at 165# 34Lemmens n 17 above at 387-8; Nehmelman n 4 above at 215-6. 35Italian law can also be mentioned under this group where, notwithstanding the fact that the provisions for delictual liability are similar to French law, a right to the free self-determination of personality development was recognised by the judicature, based on the constitution, followed by the acceptance of the rights to privacy and identity (including the right to a name) as separate personality rights. This also seems to be the position in Greece: a general right to personality (dignity and autonomy) was recognised as a legally protected interest within the meaning of its general delictual clause (see Von Bar n 2 above at 93; Von Bar n 12 above at 18-9, 22Jf, 584). Von Bar (n 12 above at 24) remarks that the Greek courts have indeed extended the application of the general right far beyond any length to which other European countries have gone. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 215 The fourth group lies between the French and Austrian models. Switzerlan was the first country in which the modern theory of personality rights w implemented, providing comprehensive statutory protection against any interference with legal subjectivity or the wrongful infringement of th personality (previously personal relations). This protection was made eve more comprehensive in 1983, particularly as far as the mass media were concerned.36 However, there is no concensus on the general right o personality. Some jurists accept Gierke's wide concept, which encompass not only true personality rights but also the legal personality itself, including freedom of economic activity,37 while others recognise only specific rights of personality.38 In order to facilitate the practical handling of the protectio of personality, the approach in practice is to recognise specific rights o personality (in addition to the general right). Personality rights recognised in this manner are the rights to life, physical integrity, freedom of movement, feelings (or sentiments), a good name, dignity, privacy and identity (including the name and image).39 However, like Gareis and Gierke, Swiss law al protects patrimonial (economic) interests such as the business enterprise (against unlawful competition), and immaterial property (trade marks and trade names) as aspects of personality.40 It may be concluded that notwithstanding the divergent approaches to th recognition of a general right of personality, in all of the above systems specific personality rights are recognised by either statute or the courts. They int alia include the rights to life, physical integrity, bodily freedom, reputation, dignity, privacy, identity (including name and image), and feelings (sentiment d 'affection). In contradistinction to the previous systems, in English law, as with mos common law countries, the doctrine and recognition of personality rights are virtually non-existent. As a result of historical development protection personality is based on tort law. A wide range of torts are applicable here inter alia, assault, battery, false imprisonment, defamation (libel, slander), malicious falsehood, malicious prosecution, intentional infliction of menta suffering, and breach of confidence.41 The personality interests protected by these torts, which can be identified as physical-psychological integrity, liberty 36Rogers et al n 20 above at 301-4; Frick n 3 above at 286; Hubmann n 3 above at 100-1; Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1621; Joubert n 1 above at biff 37Joubert n 1 above at 37-8; Frick n 3 above at 28, 209-14, 227-30, 285. 38A Bucher Naturliche Personen und Persdnlichkeitsschutz (1995) at 148^; Frick n above at 27-8. 39Frick n 3 above at 214ff\ Bucher n 38 above at 149ff, Joubert n 1 above at 42-3; Hubmann n 3 above at 100-1; Max-Planck Gutachten n 20 above at 4ff, Lemmens n 17 above at 399. ^Frick n 3 above at 227-30; Joubert n 1 above at 42, 43-4. 41RFV Hueston & RA Buckley Salmond and Hueston on the law of torts (1996) at 120ff 138ff, WVH Rogers Winfield & Jolowicz on tort (2002) at 68ff, 8lff 403ff, Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 44ff 90ff 159ff\ Kerpen n 3 above at 82\ff Walter n 12 above at 115^; Joubert n 1 above at 63; Hubmann n 3 above at 106-7; Max-Planck Gutachten n 20 above at 100#; JG Fleming The law of torts (1998) at 21ff 580ff as to Australia. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 216 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 reputation42 and to a lesser extent privacy43 and dignity, receive very little attention. However, none of these torts is suitable to serve as basis for a comprehensive protection of personality. Moreover, English common law manifestly lacks the ability to recognise and protect interests of personality which do not fall under one of the existing torts but are nevertheless worthy of protection. A clear example is the failure of English law to recognise the rights to privacy and identity, although (more and more expanded) incidental relief for certain instances of infringement of privacy (particularly for breach of confidence) is provided by other remedies.45 The argument that the right to privacy would be too uncertain and restrict freedom of the press too much, has not prevented most other countries from recognising this right.46 There is also only scant incidental protection of human dignity in England.47 48 Unlike in most other common law countries, for various reasons the idea of personality rights gained acceptance in the USA.49 A significant factor was the focus in jurisprudence50 on the different interests of personality,51 as well as the attention directed in theory and practice at the creation of a broader basis for the extention of personality protection. In this regard Warren and Brandeis52 laid the foundation for the recognition of the right to privacy as an aspect of the more general right to personality.53 However, the right to privacy in the USA does not only protect privacy but extends much wider, so much so that this right to be left alone portrays surprising similarities to the 42P Milmo & WVH Rogers (eds) Gatley on libel and slander (2004) at 17-21. 43C Herth Personlichkeitsschutz im englischen Recht (1989) at 29-53. "^Walter n 12 above at 28; Fleming n 41 above at 5-6, 664-6. 45Milmo & Rogers n 42 above at 606-9; Rogers n 41 above at 479#; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 159# 163-4, 166-7; Kerpen n 3 above at 142; Herth n 43 above at 29-92; Walter n 12 above at 28, 133#; R Youngs English, French and German comparative law (1998) at 275-6. ^"Von Bar n 12 above at 286. The recognition of the right to privacy in the Human Rights Act and under the European Convention of Human Rights may nevertheless provide a stimulus for a wider protection of privacy (Milmo & Rogers n 42 above at 609#; Rogers n 41 above at 484-6; Von Bar n 2 above at 95). 47Von Bar n 12 above at 285. 48In New Zealand there are indications that the courts may deviate from English common law by recognising the right to privacy (B Atkin, K Evans, G Mcloy & S Petersson Torts in New Zealand: cases and materials (2002) 111#; SMD Todd et al The law of torts in New Zealand (1991) 754#, 763-4; contra Fleming n 41 above at 664# as to Australia), and in Ireland, because of its written constitution, the common law may change in matters where constitutional (personality) rights are involved (Von Bar n 12 above at 304-6). Also in Scotland, where delictual liability is based on general principles and not nominate torts, extension of personality protection and recognition of, for example, the right to privacy, should be possible (Von Bar n 12 above at 307-10). 49Joubert n 1 above at 65ff. "'Especially by R Pound 'Interests of personality' (1915) 28 Harv LR 343, 445 at 343#, 445# 51SW Halpern The law of defamation, privacy, publicity, and moral right (2000) at vii-viii. «S Warren & L Brandeis 'The right to privacy' (1890) 4 Harv LR 193 at 193.# "Halpern n 51 above at 410-2; Joubert n 1 above at 64—5; Walter n 12 above at 134-5; Kerpen n 17 above at 109-11. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 217 general right of personality in Germany.5 But there is no certainty as to the personality interests involved. Prosser,55 whose viewpoint found genera support in the courts and with jurists, classifies the right to privacy into four distinct torts (intrusion, publication, false light and appropiation) invadin different interests {viz, a mental interest, reputation, and a patrimonial interest), while Bloustein56 considers human dignity to be the object of protection.57 The Supreme Court also protects autonomy under the right t privacy.58 GENERAL RIGHT TO PERSONALITY AND SPECIFIC PERSONALITY RIGHTS The concept of a general right to personality and its relation to sp personality rights require scrutiny. The object of the general right personality manifestly is the complete human being or personality. B concept is dogmatically flawed, mainly because the human being is functioning simutaneously as subject as well as object of a (subjective) right.59 However, this does not imply that particular facets of personality cannot function as legal objects. On the contrary, it is apparant from the above that even in countries which adopt the general right to personality, this approach is followed regarding bodily integrity, reputation, privacy and similar interests of personality,60 and this notwithstanding the view that the concept of the general right to personality does not really allow for the segmentation of the personality of the individual.61 Secondly, the concept of a general right to personality is too abstract to be of any practical value62 — a concretisation of specific rights of personality is therefore still necessary. The identification and delimitation of these rights facilitates their protection by rendering them dogmatically and practically manageable and promotes legal certainty.63 The precise description of those interests of personality which the law protects, is very important for, inter alia, the law of delict, since it increases the courts' (or the legislature's) ability to articulate, develop and apply principles of legal protection. This approach assists in determining how a personality interest, like privacy, differs from what has already been recognised or refused 54Stromholm n 4 above at 43-4; Joubert n 1 above at 69-70; Kerpen n 17 above at 139. 35WL Prosser 'Privacy' (1960) 48 Cal LR 383 at 383#; WP Keeton et al Prosser and Keeton on the law of torts (1984) at 852#; Fleming n 41 above at 664# as to Australia). 56EJ Bloustein 'Privacy as an aspect of human dignity: an answer to Dean Prosser' (1964) 39 NYULR 962 at 962ff. 57Halpern n 51 above at 412-3 58Keeton et al n 55 above at 866-7. "joubert n 1 above 124# Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 14-5; Lemmens n 17 above at 390. mCf Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1589-94. 61Von Bar n 2 above at 95. 62Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1621. 63Frick n 3 above at 24-5; S Ulrich Das Recht auf Identitdt im zivilrechtlichen Persdnlichkeitsscbutz (1995) 19-20; Helle n 12 above at 37-40. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 218 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 recognition under established legal theory, as well as which measures are necessary for its protection.64 Therefore one cannot agree with Larenz and Canaris63 where they doubt the usefulness of the recognition of specific rights of personality.66 Moreover, it would be a negation of the significance attached to the personality rights entrenched as human rights, to ignore their substantive existence in the private law of delict.67 Notwithstanding the above criticism, a general right to personality has a utilitarian function in some systems, that is, because it is not concrete it may provide the basis for the recognition of new personality rights when the need arises.68 Thus it may both complement and extend the protection which the particular legal system provides.69 However, this observation is valid only with regard to legal systems which have no general (delictual) basis for the comprehensive protection of personality rights in practice (such as German law). In other jurisdictions, like France, Belgium and South Africa, where this basis does exist in positive law, the recognition of a general right to personality is superfluous.70 It does not make sense to incorporate a general clause (the general right to personality) into another general clause (general delictual liability).71 SCOPE OF PROTECTION OF PERSONALITY RIGHTS Although the focus here is on the law of delict or tort law, crim particularly constitutional law (human rights)73 also play an im in the protection of personality rights in various legal systems. In many systems wrongfulness is the most important requirement liability in instances of personality harm.74 German law regards rights recognised by legislation, such as the rights to identity (n body, life, freedom, health, reputation and dignity, as absolute r seem to be best protected in the sense that any infringement indicative of wrongfulness or, in other words, is in the absence of a justification, wrongful.75 But this is not the case with the gene personality which is often in conflict with opposing rights of MJ Neethling 'Tort law in South Africa — the mixing of the gen particular' in J Smits (ed) The contribution of mixed legal systems t private law (2001) 81 at 86; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above a 65Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 519-20. Mcy Kerpen n 17 above at 12-3; Joubert n 1 above at 115ff. 67Von Bar n 2 above at 61. ^Frick n 3 above at 24-5; Ulrich n 63 above at 19-20. 69Von Bar n 2 above at 93 70Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 14-5; Karner & Koziol n 33-4; Lemmens n 17 above at Kerpen n 17 above at 139-40. 71Von Bar n 2 above at 94. 72Von Bar n 12 above at 597ff. 73See below under Personality rights as human rights. 74Von Bar n 2 above at 255ff 75Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 63; Von Bar n 2 above at 235-6; Von Bar n 12 above at 1-22; Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 373#, 500, 501, 518. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 219 example the right to privacy and the right to freedom of expression, so that wrongfulnes can be determined only by a weighing up or balancing of th conflicting rights.76 In this process the degree of fault of the perpetrator, th nature (seriousness), and intensity (expected consequences) of the infringement, and the motive of the perpetrator, play an important part.77 If the other right or interest is regarded as socially more important, the personality right will not be protected 78 In the Netherlands wrongfulness is also determined by a weighing up of opposing rights79 and the same factors as in Germany are taken into consideration.80 81 In Swiss law any infringement of a personality right is wrongful in the absence of a ground of justification. To ascertain whether such justification exists, apart from consent, the interest of the victim has to be weighed up against the opposing private or public interest. Where the perpetrator acted to maintain or further a legitimate interest, the wrongfulness of his act is excluded.82 Under South African law wrongfulness is also a general delictual requirement for the actionability of personality harm (iniuria). A factual infringement of a protected personality interest contra bonos mores is prima facie wrongful. The perpetrator may then prove justification, if any, for his conduct. Both stages of the wrongfulness inquiry involve a balancing of opposing interests.83 Although particular wrongs (such as seduction, adultery, defamation, insult, and malicious prosecution) have developed their own rules primarily to promote the practical utility of, inter alia, the wrongfulness requirement and legal certainty, each of these delicts remains a species of the general concept of iniuria.84 It may therefore be concluded that a similar approach is followed in these systems as wrongfulness is generally determined by weighing up conflicting rights or interests. In contradistinction to the previous systems, French law does not know the requirement of wrongfulness.85 If the general delictual requirements of fault (intention or negligence), damage (including personality harm or domage 76Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 498-9; Markesinis & Unberath n 4 above at 76-8, 81-2; Hubmann n 17 above at 5jff, Neumann-Duesberg n 13 above at 957. 77Neumann-Duesberg n 13 above at 958; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 142jff, 168; Smits n 15 above at 123; Rogers et al n 20 above at 120-2; Hubmann n 3 above at 159ff. 78Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 167. 79Lindenbergh n 30 above at 1677ff. 80Smits n 15 above at 123, 124ff, Lindenbergh n 30 above at 1694-5. 81The Austrian approach is similar to German law, making a distinction between so called absolute personality rights, such as the rights to life, physical integrity and freedom, which is considered to be the most valuable and where any infringement is indicative of wrongfulness, and other personality rights, such as those to image, privacy and dignity, where wrongfulness is established by weighing up the conflicting interests (Kamer & Koziol n 27 above at 34-5, 40ff). 82Bucher n 38 above at 162ff, Frick n 3 above at 232'ff, Hubmann n 3 above at 101. 83Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 54-6. 84Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 60-1; Walter n 12 above at 151. 85Von Bar n 2 above at 214. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 220 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 moral) and causation are present, delictual liability is established.86 However, where personality rights have been recognised by the courts (fo example, the right to bodily integrity) or the legislature (such as the right to pricacy in the CC) — elevating these rights to the status of autonomous rights in relation to the general law of delict — a presumption of fault and dama arises. The mere infringement of such a right, without in addition requirin prove of fault and damage, therefore founds liability.87 This is in contrast to German law where a claim for infringement of personality still has to comply with all the requirements for delictual liability.88 Belan law has a similar approach to French law, but this does not mean that the general delictua clause has become superfluous as infringement of personality rights may still be based on it.89 In English law, and in other common law countries such as the USA and Australia, the scope of protection of the personality interests (physical psychological integrity, liberty, reputation and to a lesser extent privacy and dignity) safeguarded by the relevant torts, inter alia, assault, battery, false imprisonment, libel, slander, malicious prosecution, intentional infliction of mental suffering, and breach of confidence, is entirely dependent upon the rules applicable to each specific tort.90 91This also applies in respect of the right to privacy in the USA where the act complained of has to comply with the requirements of, as the case may be, the tort of intrusion, publication, false light or appropriation.92 The legal consequences of a tortious personality infringement are to a large degree similar in different countries. First of all, in some systems the victim may approach the court to determine the (threatened) wrongfulness of a personality infringement.93 Secondly, since injunctive relief (prohibitory or mandatory) is often sought in instances of a threatened or continuous infringement of personality rights, such relief is provided for in all legal systems.94 Since the interdict is directed at the prevention of a wrongful act, 86Kerpen n 17 above at 47, 65-8; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 57ff 87Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 110ff, 140. 88Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 140, 153, 156-7. 89Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1625#", 1634# '"Hueston & Buckley n 41 above at 120#, 138I#; Rogers n 41 above at 68jff 81ff 403jf Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 45ff, 90ff 159ff-, Walter n 12 above atll5ff, Max Planck Gutachten n 20 above at 100#; Keeton et al n 55 above at 39ff, 771#; Kerpen n 17 above at 125, 130#; Fleming n 41 above at 21# 580#. 9>Eg, trespass to the person creates liability per se, placing the burden of proof of one of the recognised defences on the defendant (Rogers n 41 above at 69; Hueston & Buckley n 41 above at 120-3, 127ff, Youngs n 45 above at 224-5; Rogers et al n 20 above at 54#; Fleming n 41 above at 21ff, 41, 83# as to Australia). wKeeton et al n 55 above at 851# 93Eg Belgian, Dutch and Swiss law, in contrast to eg Germany and South Africa (Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1664-5; Lindenbergh n 30 above at 1683-5; Frick n 3 above at 238-9). MVan Gerven et al n 14 above at 168; Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1645#; Lindenbergh n 30 above at 1685-9; Frick n 3 above at 58-9, 237-8; Kerpen n 17 above at 33ff 68-70, 141; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 260-1. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 221 and not at retribution for wrongfulness already committed, it is generall accepted that fault is not a requirement.95 Apart from this remedy, whe relevant, other relief which may also be claimed includes a retraction or correction,96 publication of the court's decision, publication of an apology and the right to reply.97 Important is that these remedies are probably much more effective for natural restitution purposes — for example to restore vindicate a person's good name — than a sum of money.98 These forms relief — especially the right to reply — are, however, unknown in Ang American systems.99 There is for example no general power in England f a court to order the defendant to publish a correction or an apology eve though some relief is provided for by statute.100 Although a right to rep was recognised earlier in the USA, it has now been prohibited as it conflic with the freedom of the press.101 All systems, in a varying degree, also make provision for a monetary award (as compensation, satisfaction or even punitive damages) for personality harm where the infringement was accompanied by fault. In Germany satisfactio which is partially punitive,102 may be claimed for an intentional or negligent personality infringement provided that the disturbance was serious.103 Dutch law compensates serious104 immaterial damage in three instances: intentional infringement of personality, personal injuries, and, under certain conditions, defamation of a deceased person.105 In Austria the gener delictual clause provides for full compensation for personality infringeme accompanied by serious fault, but no satisfaction or punitive damages may claimed.106 Under Swiss law a sum of money (as satisfaction) for personali infringement may be claimed in instances warranted by the gravity of the harm "Kerpen n 17 above at 26; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 261. ''Of, eg, an untrue defamatory statement. ^Rogers et al n 20 above at 125-6, 281, 302-4; Kerpen n 17 above at 8-9, 37-8, 68f Lindenbergh n 39 above at 1685-9; Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1648-9, 1655-6; Frick n 3 above at 239jff, Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 44-5; Max-Planck Gutachten n 20 above at 24ff; Bucher n 38 above at 205ff. 98Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 at 171; contra Rogers (n 41 above at 472-3) who doubts the effectiveness of these remedies and opines that large sums of compensation, coupled with criminal sanctions, will be more effective to protect the personality interests involved. "Kerpen n 17 at 141; Rogers n 41 at 471-3. 100Milmo & Rogers n 42 above at 229; Hueston & Buckley n 41 above at 138iff, Youngs n 45 above at 265-8; Walter n 12 above at 119ff, 161ff\ Rogers n 41 above at 471-473; Rogers et al n 20 above at 73-4, 281; Max-Planck Gutachten n 20 above at 103# 101Kerpen n 17 above at 134. 102Kerpen n 17 above at 141-2. 103Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 375-6, 494-5, 497; Markesinis & Unberath n 4 above at 78; Neumann-Duesberg n 13 above at 958-9; Kerpen n 17 above at 24-5, 29-32; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 146-7, 203; Von Caemmerer n 12 above at 105-7; Walter n 12 above at 26-7. This also applies to personal injuries (Rogers et al n 20 above at 252). 104Lindenbergh n 30 above at 1693-4. 105Smits n 15 above at 135. 106Kamer & Koziol n 27 above at 24-7. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 222 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 and to the extent that the wrongdoer has not otherwise given satisfaction to the victim.107 If the general delictual requirements of fault (intention or negligence), damage, and causation are present, a claim for compensation for non-patrimonial {domage moral) loss will lie in France.108 In South Africa satisfaction (which has a punitive element) is awarded for an intentional infringement of a personality interest, while compensation may be claimed for personal injuries caused negligently.109 However, intention is not an absolute requirement for an iniuria. Negligence has been accepted as sufficient for liability for certain forms of defamation and malicious prosecution, while strict liability applies to wrongful deprivation of liberty and wrongful attachment of property.110 No monetary awards will be made for insignificant personality harm: de minimis non curat lex.111 Under English law compensation may be claimed for a tort causing non-patrimonial loss, the fault element depending on the requirements of the specific tort. In addition, in instances of, for example, trespass to the person and defamation, aggravated and even exemplary (punitive) damages may be awarded.112 In most European countries liability of personal injuries as a result of road accidents is strict.113114 From the above it can be concluded that in most countries the object of a monetary award for personality harm is compensation. Clear exceptions to this approach are Germany and South Africa where an award of satisfaction also has a penal function, as well as England where aggravated and exemplary damages may be claimed under certain circumstances. It has been argued that punitive damages are not justifiable in a modern system of law since the basic purpose of a civil action in delict is to compensate the victim for the actual harm done, and that it is for criminal law to punish and thereby discourage such conduct.115 On the other hand, punitive damages for intentional or grossly negligent violations of personality may act as a deterrent and thus promote the preventive function of tort law. In this regard there is indeed a 107Frick n 3 above at 239#; Rogers et al n 20 at 302-4; Karner & Koziol n 27 at 44-5; Max-Planck Gutachten n 20 above at 2Aff. 108Kerpen n 17 above at 47, 65-8; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 57ff This also applies to Belgian law but punitive or exemplary damages may not be awarded (Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1651-5). 109J Neethling, JM Potgieter & PJ Visser Law of delict (2002) at 5-6, 13ff, 17-8. noNeethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 49-58, 119-20, 166-8, 182,185; Burchell (1998) n 25 above at 133-5; Walter n 12 above at 144-8, 158-9. '"Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 85, 87, 93, 112, 113, 201. 112Von Bar n 12 above at 271-2, 283ff Milmo & Rogers n 42 above at 228ff-, Kerpen n 17 above at 102ff; Herth n 43 above at 125ff- The position in the USA and Australia is similar (Keeton et al n 55 above at 39ff 771#; Kerpen n 17 above at 125, 130ff Fleming n 41 above at 21ff, 580ff). 113Youngs n 45 above at 259ff Rogers et al n 40 above at 250-1. U4The assessment of the quantum of compensation or damages will not be discussed in this contribution (see Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 59-60; Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 119# as to the position in South Africa and Austria). See generally also BA Koch & H Koziol (eds) et al Compensation for personal injury in a comparative perspective (2003) passim. U5Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 58 n 218. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 223 tendency in Europe for courts to revive civil punishment for grave violations of the personality. This is particularly evident from decisions that profits mad by newspapers from scandalous publications should be taken into account assessing the quantum of damages.116 It is also clear from the above that not every instance of personality harm compensable. Many systems (such as Germany, The Netherlands and Sout Africa) require in addition that the infringement of the personality interests should be serious or have a particular gravity. On the other hand, there a systems (like Spain) which rebuttably presume personality harm if a personality interest like privacy or dignity has been violated. This means that such harm is compensable irrespective of its seriousness.117 However, the danger is that courts may then be swamped with trivial claims for personality harm, a situation that should be avoided. Finally, it should be noted that instances of personality infringement increasingly involve an international dimension. This is particularly so with mass-media publications, the Internet and inter-state freedom of movement for whatever purpose. Therefore, where transborder personality harm occurred and conflict of laws is present, it will have to be ascertained which legal system is applicable. Although international provision was made in 1999, its applicability is not without problems.118 NATURE OF PERSONALITY RIGHTS AND PERSONALITY HARM There is general consensus that personality rights are private law ( rights which are by nature non-patrimonial and highly personal in that they cannot exist independently of a person since they are i bound up with his personality.119 From the highly personal patrimonial nature of personality rights it is possible to deduce their characteristics: they are non-transferable; unhereditable; incapabl relinquished or attached; they cannot prescribe; and they come int with the birth and are terminated by the death of a human being.120 personality rights form a separate category of rights, distinguishable personal and immaterial property rights121 which are patrimonial rig can exist independently of the personality.122 In this regard Vo n6Von Bar n 12 above at 604ff Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 27'ff. U7Von Bar n 2 above at 20-1. Von Bar (n 2 above at 27-9) supports this propagates that every violation of a personality right should constitut compensable with non-patrimonial damages. u8Kerpen n 17 above passim. '"joubert n 1 above at 121, 129; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 ab Frick n 3 above at 28-30; Schmitz n 20 above at 10ff. 120Joubert n 1 above at 146-7; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above Gamm n 17 above at 39; Frick n 3 above at 28'ff-, Bucher n 38 above at 1 & Wylleman n 15 above at 1594-5; Lindenbergh n 30 above at 1667-9, 1 mGuldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1594-5; Lindenbergh n 30 above 1675. 122Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 13. 123Von Bar n 2 above at 94. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 224 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 remark that the supporters of specific personality rights hold the view that they are 'simply an aspect of life protected by the law of delict', does not deny the unique character of these rights. But the fact that Swiss law also protects patrimonial (economic) interests, such as the business enterprise (against unlawful competition), and immaterial property (trade marks and trade names), as aspects of personality,124 is unacceptable. The concept of personality rights as subjective rights has been criticised, especially by Belgian and French jurists. According to them personality rights are merely private freedoms, especially freedom of privacy, of which the law takes note only where a person enters into relations with others or where conflict arises.123 However, this criticism lacks dogmatic support and has had no impact on the protection of personality rights by the courts in Belgium and France.126 From this it follows that the infringement of a personality right primarily results in personality harm, non-pecuniary (non-patrimonial) loss or ideal damage, which is any damage or harm to (that is, any diminution in the quality of) a personality (non-patrimonial) interest that does not affect (lead to a diminution of) a person's patrimony per se and which can therefore not be rationally calculated in money by reference to a market value.127 It has been propagated128 that although the infringement of a personality right may also result in patrimonial loss, the personality right concerned does not thereby acquire a patrimonial character. This view raises theoretical problems. If a right to personality only has a specified (non-patrimonial) personality interest as its object, then, logically speaking, only non-patrimonial loss (personality harm) can be present if an impairment of a personality interest has occurred. Instances where infringement of personality also results in patrimonial loss, can accordingly only mean that apart from such infringement, a (as yet unidentified) patrimonial interest connected to the personality has also been damaged. It is an enigma how patrimonial loss can exist without an element of patrimony being involved. This premise can be based on the acceptance of the theory that personality interests may include certain patrimonial elements.129 or that130 there are oatrimonial riehts containing asoects of personality which fall outside the sphere of personality rights stricto sensu.m The recognition of a patrimonial right related to the human body where personal injuries result in medical expenses, should, for example, be 124Frick n 3 above at 227-30; Joubert n 1 above at 42, 43-4. 125Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1595ff. l26Id at 1603-4. 127Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 11, 119-20; Rogers et al n 20 above at 246; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 109 above at 242. mInter alia by Joubert n 1 above at 121; Frick n 3 above at 30; Bucher n 38 above at 160; Schmitz n 20 above at 13. 129As is accepted in Germany with regard to the post-mortem right to identity (see below under Right to publicity or advertising (market) value of personality interests). 130As in the case of the right to personal immaterial property or copyright (see below under Personality rights to creditworthiness and earning capacity and Author's personality right). 131Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 64. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 225 considered in this regard. Whether the object of the patrimonial right with regard to the body should be regarded as personal immaterial property (like earning capacity), or even as personal material (patrimonial) property, is controversial.132 A question with important theoretical and practical implications is the role of human consciousness with regard to personality harm. In this regard a distinction must be made between the objective and subjective elements of such harm.133 The objective element refers to the external, generally recognisable and concrete manifestation of personality harm of which the victim need not be aware, and is possible in instances of assault, deprivation of liberty, defamation, violation of privacy and identity, loss of the amenities of life, shortened life expectancy and disfigurement. In such cases consciousness is thus not a requirement for the existence of harm. On the other hand, the subjective element of harm exists only in a person's consciousness. Such harm is usually formed by his reaction to a concrete infringement of his personality (for example, physical pain in the case of assault or affective suffering after defamation), but it can also constitute the complete personality harm (as with insult). In these cases personality harm can naturally not exist in the absence of affective loss.134 The distinction between the objective and subjective elements of harm is of practical importance in cases of comatose victims,135 juristic persons136 and even infants where harm may concretely exist even in the absence of any affective loss or suffering, and the question as to the compensability of the harm is raised. As far as infantes and small children are concerned, damages should be awarded for concrete personality harm although the child may not have undergone any mental suffering.137 In such cases the objective function of satisfaction under German and Swiss law138 makes sense, meaning a symbolic redress of the harm by effecting retribution for the injustice the child-victim has suffered. This view is supported by Roman law where infantes could succeed with the actio iniuriarum even though they were unaware that their personality had been violated.139 SPECIFIC PERSONALITY RIGHTS The classification of personality rights is an issue on which there are (sometimes vast) differences of opinion in jurisprudence and practice. It is indeed a topic where everything has possibly already been said but not everyone has said it. So this is an addition to this clamour of voices. This 132Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 13 133Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 109 above at 242-3; Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 122-3. 134Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 51-3 135See below under Right to physical-psychological integrity. 136See below under Personality rights of juristic persons. l31Cf Von Bar n 2 above at 22. 138Frick n 3 above at 31-2. I39Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 52 n 161. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 226 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 classification takes account of factual reality,140 the personality rights or interests identified and delimited by jurists, the courts and legislatures, as well as typical examples of infringements of personality sanctioned by different legal systems.141 Right to life It is clear that every natural person has a right to life, his most valuable asset.142 Life is protected by law in all countries. If a person's life is threat ened he may, for example, ward off the threat in defence or necessity, or, if needs be, he may apply for injunctive relief to prevent the threat from being carried out. Also, a tortious reduction of a person's life expectancy through personal injuries (infringement of his right to physical integrity), is in many countries considered to be a form of harm for which damages may be awarded.143 Furthermore, in the case of the birth of a deformed child, his mere existence or life is not regarded as damage — no person has a right to non-existence (not to live).144 The right to life may be classified as a personality right, closely connected to the right to physical integrity — in the sense of a person's right to keep his body alive — because it displays most of the characteristics of that right.145 But it appears that the right to life differs in certain respects from personality rights: first, the object of this right, human life, is a conditio sine aua non for all other personality rights; and second, an infringement of the right to life (that is death)146 does not bring about any legally recognised personality harm for the deceased, and can therefore not found a claim for satisfaction or compensation — his legal capacity ends at his death and he may therefore nootlaim on own behalf.147 However, seen in the light of the fact that comatose victims are awarded damages,148 the question arises whether the tortious infringement of the right to life (death), should not be regarded as harm for which damages should be awarded. As Karner and Koziol150 argue, death is the most serious personality infringement a person can suffer and should therefore be subject to tortious liability. Although the victim cannot be compensated, the objective function of satisfaction (meaning a symbolic redress of the death by effecting retribution for the injustice the victim has suffered), should, as in the case of 140Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 24. 141 Von Bar n 2 above at 95. 142Von Bar n 2 above at 63. 143Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 16; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 165; Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 63; Rogers et al n 20 above at 11, 97, 114, 161, 202. 144Von Bar n 2 aboye at 64. 145Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 15-6, 26; Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 60. l46Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 377; Markesinis & Unberath n 4 above at 44-5. 147Von Bar n 2 above at 62. 148See below under Right to physical-psychological integrity. 149As is the case in Portugal (Von Bar n 2 above at 62). 150Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 61ff. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 227 comatose victims, also be employed here.131 The preventive function of delictual damages also play a role in promoting such damages. Right to physical-psychological integrity This personality right concerns the human body which comprehends physical and a mental element (although an attempt to divide these elemen into watertight compartments, would be forced and artificial) and include both physical and mental well-being and health.132 All legal systems giv prominent status to the protection of psyco-physical integrity. Accordingl generally any conduct which has a detrimental effect on the physique, psyche or even sensory feelings153 can be regarded as an infringement of bodi integrity.154 Specific forms of physical-psychological harm include pain an (affective) suffering, emotional shock or other psychological lesions,155 disfigurement or physical lesions, loss of amenities of life and shortened li expectancy, but neither pain nor disfigurement appears to be a requiremen for infringement. In most systems only medically recognisable psychologic injury or illness qualify as harm and not mere sorrow, sadness, grief, fright o anxiety.156 157 In England the intentional torts of battery (direct application of force) an assault (reasonable apprehension of battery), as well as the tort of negligently inflicted injury (including recognisable psychiatric illness in certain cases protect the physical-psychological integrity.158 The so-called right to sexu 151See again below under Right to physical-psychological integrity. 152Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 25-6. 153By, eg, noise, smoke, smells and telephone calls — so-called 'Belastigung' Germany or nuisance (and harassment) in England and South Africa (Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 516-7; Rogers n 41 above at 101-2, 503#; H Ehmann 'D allgemeine Personlichkeitsrecht' in CW Canaris & A Heldrich (eds) 50 Jahre Bundesgerichtshofi Festgabe aus der Wissenschaft vol 1 (2000) 669# W Timm 'Das "Allgemeine Personlichkeitsrecht" im Wettbewerbs- und Markenrecht'in U-H Erichsen, H Kollhosser & J Welp (eds) Recht der Persdnlichkeit (1996) 358 at 360# Von Bar n 2 above at 86-8 (noise); Youngs n 45 above at 245; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 25, 87). 154Von Bar n 2 above at 69-71; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 25-6. '"including (pre-death) fright or anxiety (Rogers et al n 20 above at 39# 97, 114, 161, 202, 261-2; Kamer & Koziol n 27 above at 64-7). 156Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 25-6, 90-3; Walter n 12 above at 151-5; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 109 above at 17-8, 245# 290# 332-5; J Neethling 'Troosgeld en kompensasie vir persoonlikheidsnadeel in Suid-Afrika' in G van Maanen (ed) De rol van bet aansprakelijkheidsrecht bij de verwerking van persoonlijk leed (2003) 163 at 165-6; Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 40-4, 48# 74# Rogers et al n 20 above at 1# 28# 39# 87# 109# 135# 155# 301# 260-6, 283-4; Frick n 3 above at 88-93, 214-5; Larenz & Canaris n 14 at 377# 516-7; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 78# 110# 140, 129-30, 136-9; Von Bar n 12 above at 571-7; Von Bar n 2 above at 69-71, 73-86; Markesinis & Unberath n 4 above at 45-8, 115# Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 89-91; Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1626; Koch & Koziol et al n 114 above at 424-6, 428-9. 157In Holland it is required that the psychological trauma must be serious enough to qualify as mental injury — a psychiatric illness in medical terms is not decisive (Rogers et al n 20 above at 155#. I58Rogers n 41 above at 68# 98-102, 176# 762# Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 90# This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 228 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 self-determination, which is for example infringed by sexual abuse, 9 is really not a separate personality right but fits comfortably under the right to bodily integrity. In this regard a person clearly has a power of self determination or autonomy over the inviolability of his body,160 which naturally applies to organ transplant, blood donation, abortion, medical operation, sexual intercourse, hair cut, and the like.161 The question arises whether the personality right to physical integrity continues to exist in regard to parts of the body which have been separated from the body itself, such as hair, a tooth, a transplanted kidney, a severed hand, or even sperm. One view is that the separated parts no longer form part of the body as an interest of personality, but exist independently as res (things) — albeit not things in the ordinary sense — outside the body.162 In the Netherlands, on the other hand, it is accepted that a personality right continues to exist with regard to the separated parts.163 In German law an acceptable midway is followed. A distinction is made between body parts permanently separated from the body where ordinary personal property rules apply, parts destined to be reintegrated which remain part of the body, and parts destined to perform a typical bodily function, such as sperm for procreation, which are also treated as part of body.164 The destruction of sperm is therefore regarded as interference with bodily integrity (or the general right to personality).165 A particular problem is whether comatose victims should be able to claim compensation or satisfaction for infringement of their physical-psychological integrity. This is in fact allowed in some countries,166 while in others,167 the position is unclear.168 Arguments against awarding damages are that the victim suffers no harm because he experiences no pain and (affective) suffering, that the money cannot be used for the benefit of the victim and also offers him no consolation — it merely provides a delayed inheritance to dependants. On the other hand it cannot be denied that, objectively viewed, concrete personality harm is not dependent on the consciousness of the 159Kamer & Koziol n 27 above at 92ff\ Frick n 3 above at 93-4; cf Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 515. 160Rogers n 41 above at 75. 161Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1604-7, 1626; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 26 n 278. 162i\"eethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 24 n 262, 86 n 37. 163Lindenbergh n 30 above at 1675-6. 164Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 137, 147-9; Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 111-2; Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 514-5. 165JTM Labuschagne 'Deliktuele aanspreeklikheid weens liggaamskending as gevo van spermavernietiging: 'n Verreikende uitspraak van die Duitse Bundesgerichtsh (1995) 58 THRHR I48ff. 166Eg, Germany, Austria, France, Italy, England, Belgium and Switzerland. l67Such as the Netherlands, Greece and South Africa. 168Rogers et al n 29 above at 257-9; Koch & Koziol el al n 114 above at 425; Karne & Koziol n 27 above at 58-60; Von Bar n 2 above at 22-3, cf 23-7; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 137-8; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 24Sff. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 229 victim. 9 However, from a comparative law analysis it is clear that no on believes that such personality harm suffered by a comatose victim can real be compensated. Accordingly, in such cases the objective function of satisfaction under German and Swiss law170 makes sense, meaning a symbolic redress of the harm by effecting retribution for the injustice the victim has suffered, thereby enabling the law to express society's symphathy for the victim and its sense of outrage at his grievous loss.171 Since the mid 1960s actions for wrongful conception (an action for damages by the parents of a normal child born as a result of a failed sterilization or abortion performed by a medical doctor), wrongful birth (an action by the parents on similar grounds but where the child is born handicapped), and wrongful life (an action by a deformed child who was born as a result of a negligent diagnosis or other act by a doctor) have troubled courts in various countries. The first two actions are mainly concerned with the patrimonial loss of the parents (cost of pregnancy, child-birth and of raising the child). It is generally accepted that the mere existence of a child cannot be regarded as harming the personality of the parents, although it is conceivable that the birth of a deformed child may, for example, cause a parent serious psychological harm.172 The question also arises whether the personality right to dignity of such a child is not (unfairly) infringed by the fact that the doctor, and not the parents, are paying for his upbringing. This question is controversial,173 but the fact that many countries allow such damages against the doctor, is perhaps a clear sign that the child's dignity does not play a decisive role in this regard. As regards the action for wrongful life, the following. If a foetus which is injured or deformed dies in utero, it has no legal personality, no right to physical integrity and therefore cannot claim non-patrimonial damages. Yet, if a deformed or injured child is born alive, although his mere existence is not regarded as damage — no person has a right to non-existence — he should be able to claim damages for the infringement of his physical integrity.174 Right to physical liberty This personality right is not concerned with the body itself, but with bodily freedom, and is infringed not only by total deprivation of liberty (such as detention or imprisonment), but also by any interference with an individual's liberty to move freely. Consciousness is not an element of the personality harm mEg, loss of amenities of life (see above under NATURE OF PERSONALITY RIGHTS AND PERSONALITY HARM) I70Frick n 3 above at 31-2. 171PQR Boberg The law of delict I: aquilian liability (1984) at 570; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 109 above at 248-53, 251 n 339. 172Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 116-9. 173Smits n 15 above at 130#". ™Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 138; E Engelhard, T Hartlief & G van Maanen (eds) et al Aansprakelijkheid in gezinsverband (2004) 21ff, 221ff\ Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 72-3; Von Bar n 12 above at 576ff\ Von Bar n 2 above at 71-3; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 109 above at 37, 281; Markesinis & Unberath n 4 above at 48-9, 144#, 156#. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 230 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 involved since a person can be deprived of liberty without being aware of it.175 The right to bodily freedom is protected in all legal systems.176 In England this protection is under the umbrella of the tort of false imprisonment, that is, the infliction of bodily restraint unauthorised by the law, as well as the tort of malicious prosecution where applicable.177 Bodily freedom should be distinguished from the general freedom to act (especially in the economic sphere) or the freedom to develop the personality.178 Freedom to act in this sense does not relate to a specific interest of personality, the infringement of which causes personality harm, but is rather an aspect of human self-determination in society and therefore of legal subjectivity itself.179 Right to dignity Dignity embraces a person's subjective feelings of dignity or self-respect: his personal sense of self-worth or innere Ehre.1S0 Infringing a person's dignity means insulting that person. It stands to reason that because of its complete subjectivity, a person cannot be protected against every insult. Therefore, in all systems where the right to dignity is recognised, protection is directed at serious insults only, which can be difficult to determine in borderline cases.181 In South Africa, for example, actionability requires not only that the victim feels insulted, but also that a reasonable person in his position would have felt insulted.182 The Austrian and English protection of dignity is unjustifiably scant.183 It should be noted that dignity is sometimes used in 175Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 26, 113; Von Bar n 2 above at 92; see also above under Nature of personality rights and personality harm. 176Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 16, 26, 111#; Walter n 12 above at 155-60; Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 97-8; Frick n 3 above at 94-8; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 78, 139; Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 385-6, 513; Von Bar n 2 above at 89-93; Von Bar n 12 above at 567-8; Rogers et al n 20 above at 122-3, 168, 284-5; Youngs n 45 above at 245; Markesinis & Unberath n 4 above at 49. "'Rogers n 41 above at 81/7; Heuston & Buckley n 41 above at 123-7; Von Bar n 2 above at 92; Youngs n 45 above at 245; Rogers et al n 20 above at 75-6; Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 90; Walter n 12 above at 118-9, 131-3; Fleming n 41 above at 33# as to Australia. 178This distinction is not always made in, eg, Austrian, German and Swiss law (Bucher n 38 above at 139#; Ehmann n 153 above at 613-4; Ulrich n 63 above at 29; Frick n 3 above at 94, 96-8, 259-60). 179Joubert n 1 above at 123, 127; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 15, 16; cf Von Bar n 2 above at 90. 180Kerpen n 17 above at 13, 47-8; Son n 12 above at 38-41; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 28. 181Youngs n 45 above at 270-1; Kerpen n 17 above at 13# 47-8; Guldix & Wyllem n 15 above at 1629-30; Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 500-1; Van Gamm n 17 above at 36; Son n 12 above at 75# In the USA serious insults are protected under the tort of intentional infliction of mental suffering (Keeton et al n 55 above at 57-60; Rogers n 41 above at 100). 182Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 28, 194-6. 183Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 98-101; Frick n 3 above at 99-100; Heuston & Buckley n 41 above at 120-1; Rogers n 41 above at 69; Von Bar n 12 above at 285. In Austria protection of dignity is dependent on the presence of patrimonial loss. Violation of dignity by the mass media, or by assaulting the victim, or by publishing his image, is nevertheless in principle wrongful (Karner & Koziol n 27 above at This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 231 the much broader sense of embracing the whole human personality. A clear example is the recognition of the general right to personality in Germany which primarily emanated from the significance attached to human dignity in the constitution.184 The right to dignity as a human right probably also connotes this broad context, which should be distinguised from dignity in the narrower sense of a substantive personality interest.183 Right to reputation A person's reputation or good name is the opinion, regard or esteem which he enjoys in society; his aussereEhre, in contradistinction to self-esteem in the case of dignity.186 Any words or conduct which tarnishes or lowers his reputation within the community infringes his good name.187 The right to reputation is protected in all European systems.188 Although true words may be defamatory, the truth is in principle a defence against an action for defamation.189 This is also the position in England.190 Whether the truth should in all circumstances be a defence is controversial — for instance, where facts about physical deformaties or long forgotten scandals are published merely to satisfy the salacious appetite of the public — and the law has been changed in a few common law countries191 to limit the defence to th publication of true facts which are also in the public interest.192 This also reflects the law in South Africa.193 In general a flexible weighing up of the rights to reputation and freedom of expression (of the mass media) must be undertaken by the courts.194 Under certain circumstances even the publication of untruth may be justified. In Germany, for example, although the intentional publication of untruth cannot be lawful, innocent or negligent untruth may be justified where the publication concerns a matter of publi 98-101; Frick n 3 above at 99-100). In England the right to dignity is not recognised or directly protected by any tort (cf however Fleming n 41 above at 41), but damages may be recovered for insults due to interference with the person that has done no physical harm at all (Heuston & Buckley n 41 at 120-1; Rogers n 41 above at 69). 184See above under Recognition and basis of protection of personality rights. mCf Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 28. 186Son n 12 above at 38-41; Kerpen n 17 above at 47-8. 187Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 27; Halpern n 51 above at vii-viii, 5; Milmo & Rogers n 42 above at 8; Rogers n 41 above at 404; Frick n 3 above at 225; Ehmann n 153 above at 636. Even true words may therefore be defamatory (Milmo & Rogers n 42 above at 8; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 38, 131). 188Von Bar n 1 above at 100-4; Rogers et al n 20 above at 150, 280-1; Van Gamm n 17 above at 37, 39; Youngs n 45 above at 271-4; Kerpen n 17 above at 48\ff Frick n 3 above at 102-3, 225-6. 189Van Gamm n 17 above at 37; Youngs n 45 above at 269-70; Kerpen n 17 above at 21-2, 24, 61-2. l90Milmo & Rogers n 42 above passim. mEg, Australia. 192Milmo & Rogers n 42 above at 267-8. 193Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 153-5; Burchell n 25 above at 272ff l94Von Bar n 1 above at 100-6; Von Bar n 12 above at 588-99; Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1629; Kerpen n 17 above at 20-1, 24, 63-4; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 129ff. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 232 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 interest and no insult is involved, 93 and in the Netherlands liability for a untrue statement was excluded where the reporters carried out diligent research.196 In this regard a defence of media privilege, that is the fair o reasonable publication of (even untrue) defamatory statements about matte of public interest (including political speech), has recently been accepted i common law countries (like England and Australia) and also in South Afric underlining modern conceptions of democracy as to freedom of expressio and the role of the media in this regard.197 The protection of reputation is of course the field of libel (as a rule writte defamation) and slander (generally oral defamation) in English common law and many other common law countries which remain close to the Englis model.198 The law of defamation in South Africa law has also benefitted from adopting much of the detail of English common law.199 The requirements for libel and slander, which is the outcome of the balancing process between reputation and freedom of expression, are the publication (disclosure to a third person) of defamatory matter (tendency to lower the victim in the estimation of right-thinking members of society) about the victim. The most important defences, apart from truth (justification), are privilege and fair comment.200 Except for a few instances where negligence is required for liability,201 liability is strict.202 In this regard the courts in the USA developed constitutional privilege as an additional defence that requires at least negligence,203 and in the case of public officials and figures, intent or actual malice204 for liability. The strict liability of English law for defamation generally was never imposed on innocent defamers.205 Since strict liability tilt the scale unfairly in favour of the victim,206 while vice versa, liability based on intent tends to benefit the defendant,207 liability basedT on negligence seems to position the scale in a proper and fair balance. Liability based on negligence has in fact long been established in many European systems and has also been accepted, for example, in South Africa, for liability of the mass media for defamation.208 195Kerpen n 17 above at 20-1, 24. 196Von Bar n 2 above at 103 197Milmo & Rogers n 42 above at 451-82; Rogers n 41 above at 459-63; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 155-7. 198Milmo & Rogers n 42 above at 4-7; Von Bar n 12 above at 283-4; Kerpen n 17 above at 112# '"Neethling n 64 above at 93 200Milmo & Rogers n 42 above passim; Kerpen n 17 above at 99ff, 123#. 201The press may, for example, prove absence of fault. 202Milmo & Rogers n 42 above at 8-10. 203Halpem n 51 above at 5. 2MThat is, defamatory falsehood published with knowledge of its falsity, or recklessly. 205Keeton et al n 55 above at 802#; Rogers n 41 above at 460. 206As generally in England and previously in South Africa with regard to the press. 207Especially the mass media, as in the USA. 208Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 167. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 233 Right to privacy Privacy is a personal condition of life characterised by seclusion from, and therefore absence of acquaintance by, the public. A person himself determines or controls the scope of his privacy.209 Seen thus, privacy can only be infringed by an unauthorised acquaintance by outsiders with a person or his private affairs, which acquaintance can occur in two ways. Firstly, by intrusion into the private sphere (that is, where an outsider himself becomes acquainted with a person or his personal affairs). Secondly, by disclosure or publication of private facts (that is, where a third party acquaints outsiders with a person or his personal affairs which, although known to that party, remain private).210 Examples of prima facie wrongful invasions of privacy are entering a private residence, observing a person in closed quarters, reading private documents, eavesdropping on private conversations, shadowing a person, taking blood tests, and the police interrogation of a person. Examples of violation of the right to privacy by disclosure, are the disclosure of private facts that have been acquired by a wrongful act of intrusion, the disclosure of private facts in breach of a confidential relationship (for example, between doctor-patient, legal advisor-client, bank-client, priest-penitant, police informant, etcetera), and the publication of private facts by the mass media.211 The fixing or recording of private facts (for example, by photography, photocopying and tape recording), whether by outsiders or insiders, should per se also be wrongful in principle because such an act, by exposing privacy to the danger or risk of intrusion or disclosure, constitutes a threat to the right to privacy.212 The right to privacy is recognised in numerous systems/13 the most notable exception being English common law,214 and other common law countries which follow the English model closely.215 As with other personality rights, the right to privacy is often in mCf Lemmers n 17 above at 383-4. 210Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 30-3- In the USA, the torts of 'intrusion upon the plaintiffs seclusion or solitude, or into his private affairs', and 'the public disclosure of embarrassing private facts about the plaintiff represent these two ways of infringing privacy (see above under Recognition and basis of protection of personality rights; Prosser n 55 above at 383ff, Keeton et al n 55 above at 852\ff). 2uNeethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 222-5, 226-36; Kamer & Koziol n 27 above at 101-3; W van Gerven et al Tort law (1998) 183-90; Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 503ff, 508ff; Van Bar n 2 above at 106-19. 212Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 236-40. This is the position in Germany with regard to the clandestine taking of photo's (Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 506-7; Youngs n 45 above at 278). 213Kamer & Koziol n 27 above at 101jff\ Rogers n 20 above at 17-18, 50, 74-5, 104, 120-122, 168, 183, 220, 281-283; Von Bar n 12 above at 28, 31, 43 n 157; Von Bar n 2 above at 94-5, 106-18; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 217-20; Halpern n 51 above at 410-2; Walter n 12 above at 134-5; Kerpen n 17 above at 109-11; Keeton et al n 55 above at 852\ff Van Gerven et al n 211 above at 171ff 201-2, 203; Lemmers n 17 above at 381ff Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1625-6; Lindenbergh n 30 above at 1674; BS Markesinis The German law of torts: a comparative introduction (1990) at 294ff; Youngs n 45 above at 277, 278; see also as to Germany, France, Belgium, South Africa, Austria, the Netherlands, Switzerland, and the USA, above under Recognition and basis of protection of personality rights. 214See above under Recognition and basis of protection of personality rights. mCf n 48 above. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 234 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 conflict with opposing private rights and the public interest, requiring a fair balancing outcome. The most important public interest, and simultaneously the most difficult to delimit vis-a-vis the right to privacy, is the public interest in (true) information about people (maintained especially by the freedom of expression of the mass media).216 Various kinds of conduct are often regarded as infringements of privacy while other personality interests and even patrimonial interests are at stake. They are physical-psychological integrity (including sensory feelings), dignity, identity, autonomy, self-realisation, and trade secrets.217 As has been argued,218 such an equation of dissimilar interests is unacceptable, and should, for purposes of conceptual clarity, dogmatic and practical manageability and legal certainty, be avoided. An important aspect of the right to privacy in most countries is data protection, which entails the protection of a person (data subject) with regard to the processing of his personal data by another person or the state.219 There is general agreement on the core data protection principles220 which should be embodied in any effective data protection regime,221 and many countries222 have adopted data protection legislation reflecting these principles.223 It is submitted that all countries will in future have to adopt such legislation to ensure adequate protection of privacy and the continuous free cross-border flow of personal information.224 Right to identity Identity as an interest of personality can be defined as a person's uniqueness or individuality which identifies or individualises him as a particular person and thus distinguishes him from others.225 Identity is manifested in various indicia by which a person can be recognised; in other words, facets of his personality which are characteristic of or unique to him, such as his name, 2l6Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 240/7", 245-9; see also idem 246 n 238, 247 n 239 as to Germany and the USA. 217Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 33-6. 2l8See above under General right to personality and particular personality rights. 219Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 267//; LA Bygrave Data protection law: approaching its rationale, logic amd limit (2002) passim; A Roos The law of data (privacy) protection: a comparative and theoretical study (2003) passim-, CJ Bennett Regulating privacy: data protection and public policy in Europe and the United States (1992) passim; Electronic Privacy Information Centre (EPIC) Privacy and human rights: an international survey of privacy laws and developments (2002) passim; Karner & Koziol n 27 above at 102. 220Cf Roos n 219 above at 650-2. 221Roos n 219 above at 480ff\ Bygrave n 219 above at 57//". 222More than forty by the end of 2002. 223Roos n 219 above at 480ff identifies the following principles: fair and lawful processing; purpose specification; minimality; data quality; disclosure limitation; data subject participation; openness; sensitivity; security and confidentiality; and accountability. 224Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 281. 225Hubmann n 3 above at 271; PPJ Coetser Die Reg op Identiteit (1986) 140-8; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 36; Ulrich n 63 above at 52, 131-2. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 235 physical image (or likeness), voice, life history, creditworthiness, handwriting, character, etcetera. A person's identity is infringed if any of these indicia are used in ways which cannot be reconciled with his true identity; in other words, where his identity has been falsified, or a wrong image of his personality has been communicated.226 Where a person's name, image or any other indicium, identifies him with true personal facts, they merely have an identification function and are relevant with regard to the protection of privacy, forming part of the private facts to which they relate.227 Indicia of identity may serve as the object of a specific right to personality. In various countries228 this has happened with regard to, for example, the right to a name and the right to image.229 The right to one's own voice is also recognised in a few systems.230 The right to identity has been recognised eo nomine in countries such as Italy, France, Swit2erland and South Africa.231 In the USA, the torts of putting a person in a false light in the public eye, and appropriation, for the defendant's advantage, of the plaintiffs name or likeness,232 are thus rather examples of protection of identity than of privacy.233 This naturally also applies to the German sanctioning of the falsification or distortion of the personality image, as well as the economic misappropriation of the name or image,234 but the right to identity still needs general recognition by the courts.235 In England identity is not directly protected but such protection may take place incidentally under other torts, for example, malicious falsehood and passing off.236 Although the publication of untruth is in principle wrongful, 226Hubmann n 3 above at 273-4; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 36-7; Ehmann n 153 above at 628, 643; Ulrich n 63 above at 29, 133#, 183#; Von Bar n 2 above at 105-6. 227Hubmann n 3 above at 272 n 10; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 37; Halpern n 51 above at 413-4; Frick n 3 above at 82# 105# 159# 228Such as Germany, France, Switzerland, Liechtenstein, Italy, Austria and Belgium. 22Von Bar n 12 above at 584; Von Bar n 2 above at 96-8, 107-8; Hubmann n 3 above at 271; Helle n 12 above at 21-2, 45# Van Gamm n 14 above at 39, 40-1; Coetser n 225 above at 26# 37# Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 36-8, 255# Rogers et al n 20 above at 150; Youngs n 45 above at 275-8; Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1625, 1627; Frick n 3 above at 62# 105# 230# 260# Bucher n 38 above at 243# mEg, Belgium, Austria, Germany and Liechtenstein (Guldix & Wylleman n 15 above at 1626; Frick n 3 above at 151# 264; Kerpen n 17 above at 17-8). 231Ulrich n 63 above at 129-30; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 255. 232But only in so far such use of the name or likeness creates the false impression that plaintiff has given consent to such conduct, or has received financial remuneration therefor, or supports the advertised product, service or business (Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 37). 233Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 37; cf Halpern n 51 above at 428-9; Ehmann n 153 above at 643; Ulrich n 63 above at 130; Kerpen n 17 above at 118# Keeton et al n 55 above at 852# 234Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 499-500, 502, 517; Van Gamm n 17 above at 39; Youngs n 45 above at 277-8; Ulrich n 63 above at 53# 150# Kerpen n 17 above at 17# cf Won Bar n 2 above at 98-100. 235Ulrich n 63 above at 104# 112# 236Rogers n 41 above at 476# 674# Herth n 43 above at 88-91; Von Bar n 2 above at 107. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 236 XXXVIII CILSA 2005 infringement of identity may be justified by freedom of expression, as with defamation.237 It should be noted that although, in for example Germany or France, the rights to a name, image, written and spoken word are regarded as separate personality rights,238 conduct which is considered to be infringements of these rights may also be relevant with regard to other interests of personality (such as identity, privacy and reputation) and even the so-called patrimonial components of personality.239 For the sake of jurisprudential clarity and legal certainty, it is suggested that those personality infringements should rather be accommodated and classified under the rights to identity (falsification), privacy (intrusion into the private sphere and the publication of private facts), reputation (lowering of esteem), and dignity (insult). Other personality rights Apart from feelings of dignity (Ehrgefuhl, which are the most prominent feelings protected by law),240 a person has a wide variety of other spiritual moral feelings or inherent perceptions on matters such as love, faith (religion), sentiment and chastity.241 Disregard for his or her feelings — where insult or infringement of dignity need not be present — causes (intense) moral suffering. However, as with insult, not every affective infliction can be actionable; the infringement should be of a serious nature. Under South African law the actio iniuriarum protects inter alia the right to feelings of engaged couples and spouses in instances of breach of promise and adultery, abduction, enticement and harbouring.242 Interference with parental care (for example, the abduction of a child) can probably also be accommodated under this right.243 A number of systems244 grant damages for bereavement (pretium affectionis) to certain relatives or to other persons having a firm relationship or ties of affection with a dead victim, but others245 reject such claims altogether. Although France — which has an almost overly generous approach in this regard246 — Belgium and Switzerland also award damages to others in the case of non-fatal injury of the victim, other countries have not 237See above under Right to reputation; Ehmann n 153 above at 645-6; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 261-2. 238Helle n 12 above passim. mCf Kerpen n 17 above at 140; see also below under Right to publicity or advertising (market) value of personality interests. 240See above under Right to dignity. 241Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 28-9, 199#; cf Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 516-7 as to feelings of chastity. ^Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 204# Von Bar n 2 above at 124-9 as to Europe; Frick n 3 above at 215-6. mCf Von Bar n 2 above at 121# Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 193, 200. luEg, England, France, Switzerland, Belgium, Spain, Greece and Italy. "'Such as Germany, the Netherlands and South Africa. 246Van Gerven et al n 14 above at 139. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 237 followed, probably because of substantial arguments the other way.247 In France feelings (sentiments d'affection) are even protected where an animal has been killed, and in Switzerland where an organ was transplanted without the consent of relatives.248 Belgium and France furthermore recognise a right to family memories.249 The rights to informational self-determination, self-realisation, freedom from utterances not made, concerning sexuality and marriage, and the right to resocialising are also identified as specific personality rights.250 However, it seems that the fields of application of these rights can quite comfortably be accommodated under legal subjectivity, as well as the rights to privacy, identity, reputation and dignity.251 In Germany a person's right to know his own descent or parentage has been deduced from the general right to personality, and it has also been imbedded in Dutch law, but it is controversial whether such a right is recognised in Switzerland.232 This right must of course be weighed against the parent's right to privacy not to have the information disclosed — a process in which various factors may play a role.253 However, it seems that the right to know one's own descent is not a specific independent right of personality, but rather an aspect of a person's right to privacy (in the sense of his right of access to and therefore control over his own personal information: his right to informational self-determination),254 or of his right to identity (which should include the power to know one's own real identity). Smits253 considers knowledge as to one's own descent as part of human dignity. PERSONALITY RIGHTS AND PATRIMONIAL RIGHTS Personality rights, with their highly personal and non-patrimonial nature f a separate category of rights, distinguishable from patrimonial rights that exist independently of the personality.256 This distinction is problemat the following instances: 247Rogers et al n 20 above at 87ff, 262-5; Koch & Koziol et al n 114 above at 25 64, 140, 203, 273-4, 349-50, 429-30; AJ Verheij 'Compensation of pretium affectionis — A constitutional necessity' (2004) 67 THRHR 394 at 394ff\ Smits n 15 above atl35ff, 266-71; Gregoritza n 261 above at 81ff 191 ff. 319Fischer n 266 above at 188^, 195-7. 320Halpern n 51 above at 639. 321Frick n 3 above at 170; Hubmann n 3 above at 342-3; Fisher n 266 above at 50-2; see also above under Author's right of personality. 322Von Bar n 2 above at 130. 323Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 68; Walter n 12 above at 149. 324See above under Nature of personality rights and personality harm. 325Hubmann n 3 above at 334; Von Bar n 2 above at 133. This viewpoint is endorsed by the South African Constitution (Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 68 n 334, 68ff Walter n 12 above at 149-50). 326Frick n 3 above at 40, cf 255-6; Hubmann n 3 above at 336-7; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 68ff. 327See above under Nature of personality rights and personality harm. 328Von Bar n 2 above at 132. 329Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 68\ff Frick n 3 above at 40; Hubmann n 3 above at 335. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms Personality rights: a comparative overview 245 Germany the name, dignity330 and privacy of juristic persons are protecte but they may not claim satisfaction331 since they cannot experienc satisfaction.332 This is also the position in England as regards the defamati of juristic persons.333 However, in various other countries334 the court allow a juristic person (and in Belgium even the state) to claim compensatio for non-patrimonial harm as a result of infringement of its reputation.3 Although a claim for non-patrimonial damages by juristic persons is not unknown in Austria, its field of application is very limited.336 330Probably in the sense of 'aussere Ehre' and not 'innere Ehre' which a juristic person cannot possess. 331Larenz & Canaris n 14 above at 520-1; Youngs n 45 above at 272; Nehmelman n 4 above at 51-2. 332Frick n 3 above at 41. 333Von Bar n 2 above at 132. 334Like Belgium, Italy, the Netherlands, France, Switzerland and South Africa. 335Von Bar n 2 above at 132 n 783; Youngs n 45 above at 267, 271; Frick n 3 abov at 41, 227; Neethling, Potgieter & Visser n 1 above at 68-9. 336Frick n 3 above at 42. This content downloaded from 147.251.160.150 on Mon, 25 Feb 2019 10:39:52 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms