Why I Am Not a Cognitive Psychologist Author(s): B. F. Skinner Source: Behaviorism, Vol. 5, No. 2 (Fall, 1977), pp. 1-10 Published by: Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27758892 . Accessed: 21/10/2011 13:42 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Cambridge Center for Behavioral Studies is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Behaviorism. http://www.jstor.org Why I am Not a Cognitive Psychologist B.F. Skinner Harvard University The variables of which human behavior is a function lie in the environment. We distinguish between (1) the selective action of that environment during the evolution of the species, (2) its effect in shaping and maintaining the repertoire of behavior which converts each member of the species into a person, and (3) its role as the occasion upon which behavior occurs. Cognitive psychologists study these relations between organism and environment, but they seldom deal with them directly. Instead they invent internal surrogates which become the subject matter of their science. Take, for example, the so-called process of association. In Pavlov's experiment a hungry dog hears a bell and is then fed. If this happens many times, the dog begins to salivate when it hears the bell. The standard mentalistic explanation is that the dog "associates" the bell with the food. But itwas Pavlov who associated them! "As sociate" means to join or unite. The dog merely begins to salivate upon hearing the bell. We have no evidence that itdoes so because of an internal surrogate of the contingencies. In the "association of ideas" the ideas are internal replicas of stimuli towhich I shall return. Ifwe have eaten lemons, we may taste lemon upon seeing a lemon or see a lemon upon tasting lemon juice, but we do not do this because we associate the flavor with the appearance. They are associated in the lemon. "Word associations" are at least correctly named. Ifwe say "home" when someone says "house," it is not because we associate the two words but because they are associated in daily English usage. Cognitive association is an invention. Even if itwere real, itwould go no further toward an explanation than the external contingencies upon which it ismodelled. Another example is abstraction. Consider a simple experiment. A hungry pigeon can peck any one of a number of panels bearing the names of colors?"white," "red," "blue,'' and so on, and thepecks are reinforced with small amounts of food. Any one of a number of objects?blocks, books, flowers, toy animals, and so on?can be seen in an adjacent space. The following contingencies are then arranged: whenever the object is white, no matter what its shape or size, pecking only the panel marked "white" is reinforced; whenever the object is red, pecking only the panel marked "red" is rein forced; and so on. Under these conditions the pigeon eventually pecks the panel marked "white" when the object iswhite, the panel marked "red" when the object is red, and so on. Children are taught to name colors with similar contingencies, and we all possess comparable repertoires sustained by the reinforcing practices of our verbal environ ments. But what is said tobe going on in themind? Karl Popper (1957) has put a classical issue thisway: "We can say either that (1) the universal term "white" is a label attached to a set 1 B. F. Skinner of things, or that (2) we collect the set because they share an intrinsic property of "whiteness." Popper says the distinction is important; natural scientists may take the firstposition but social sciencists must take the second. Must we say, then, that thepigeon is either attaching a universal term to a set of things or collecting a set of things because they share an intrinsic property? Clearly, it is the experimenter not the pigeon who "attaches" the white key to the white objects displayed and who collects the set of objects on which a single reinforcing event ismade contingent. Should we not simply attribute the behavior to the experimental contingencies? And ifso, why not for children or ourselves? Behavior comes under the control of stimuli under certain contingencies of reinforcement. Special contingencies maintained by verbal communities produce "abstractions." We do attach physical labels to physical things and we collect physical objects according to labels properties, but comparable cognitive processes are inven tions, which even if real, would be no closer to an explanation than the external contingencies. Another cognitive account of the same data would assert thata person, ifnot a pigeon, forms an abstract idea or develops a concept of color. The development of concepts is an especially popular cognitive field. (The horticultural metaphor minimizes contributions from the environment. We may hasten the growth of the mind but we are no more responsible for its final character than farmers for the character of the fruits and vegetables they so carefully nourish.) Color vision is part of the genetic endowment of most people, and itdevelops or grows in a physiological sense, possibly to some extent after birth, Nevertheless, most stimuli acquire control because of their place in con tingencies of reinforcement. As the contingencies become more complex, they shape and maintain more complex behavior. It is the envirionment that develops, not a mental or cognitive possession. A passage from a recent discussion of the development of sexual identity in a child might be translated as follows: "The child forms a concept based upon what it has observed and been told of what itmeans to be a boy or girl." (A child's behavior is affected by what ithas observed and been told about being a boy or girl.)' 'This concept is oversimplified, exaggerated, and stereotyped." (The contingencies affecting the be havior are simplified and exaggerated and involve stereotyped behavior on the part of parents and others.) "As the child develops cognitively, itsconcepts, and consequently its activities, become more sophisticated and realistic." (As the child grows older, the contingencies become more subtle and more closely related to the actual sex of the child.) Children do not go around forming concepts of their sexual identity and "consequently" behaving in special ways; they slowly change theirbehavior as people change theways in which they treat them because of their sex. Behavior changes because the contingencies change, not because a mental entity called a concept develops. Many mentalistic or cognitive terms refer not only to contingencies but to the behavior they generate. Terms like "mind," "will," and "thought" are often simply synonyms of "behavior." An historian writes: "what may be called a stagnation of thought prevailed, as though themind, exhausted after building up the spiritual fabric of theMiddle Ages, had sunk into inertia." Exhaustion is a plausible metaphor when a 2 Why I AmNot a CognitivePsychologist quiet period follows an active one, but itwas behavior that became stagnant and inert, presumably because the contingencies changed. Certain social conditions ("the spiritual fabric of theMiddle Ages") made people active. A second set of conditions, possibly produced by the very behavior generated by the first,made them much less so. To understand what actually happened, we should have to discover why the contingencies changed, not why thought became stagnant or inert. Behavior is internalized as mental life when it is too slight to be observed by others?when, as we say, it is covert. A writer has pointed out that "the conductor of an orchestra maintains a certain even beat according to an internal rhythm, and he can divide that beat in half again and again with an accuracy rivaling any mechanical instrument." But is there an internal rhythm? Beating time isbehavior. Parts of the body often serve as pendulums useful indetermining speed, as when the amateur musician beats time with a foot or the rock player with the whole body, but other well-timed behavior must be learned. The conductor beats time steadily because he has learned to do so under rather exacting contingencies of reinforcement. The behavior may be reduced in scale until it is no longer visible to others. It is still sensed by the conductor, but it is a sense of behavior not of time. The history of "man's development of a sense of time" over the centuries is not a matter of cognitive growth but of the invention of clocks, calendars, and ways of keeping records?in other words, of an environment that "keeps time." When an historian reports that in a given period "a wealthy, brilliant, and traditional governing class lost itswill,'' he is reporting simply that itstopped acting like a wealthy, brilliant, and traditional governing class. Deeper changes are suggested by the term "will" but they are not identified. They could not have been changes in particular people, since the period lasted more than one lifetime. What changed were presumably the conditions affecting the behavior of members of the class. Perhaps they lost their money; perhaps competing classes became more powerful. Feelings, or the bodily conditions we feel, are commonly taken as the causes of behavior. We go for a walk "because we feel like going." It is surprising how often the futility of such an explanation is recognized. A distinguished biologist, C. H. Wad dington (1974), reviewing a book by Tinbergen, writes as follows: It is not clear how far he (Tinbergen) would go along with the argument of one of themost perceptive critical discussions of ethology by Suzanne Langer, who argues thateach step ina complex structure of behavior iscontrolled, not by a hierarchical set of neural centers, but by the immediate feelings of the animal. The animal, she claims, does the next thing in the sequence, not to bring about a useful goal, or even as amove toward an enjoyable consummation, but because it actually feels like doing itat themoment. Evidently Waddington himself goes along part way with this "perceptive view." But suppose Langer is right. Suppose animals simply do what they feel like doing? What is the next step inexplaining their behavior? Clearly, a science of animal behavior must be replaced or supplemented by a science of animal feelings. It would be as extensive as the science of behavior because therewould presumably be a feeling for each act. But feelings are harder to identify and describe than the behavior attributed to them, and we should have abandoned an objective subject matter in favor of one of dubious status, accessible only through necessarily defective channels of introspection. The 3 B,F. Skinner contingencies would be the same. The feelings and the behavior would have the same causes. A British statesman recently asserted that the key to crime in the streets was "frustration." Young people mug and rob because they feel frustrated. But why do they feel frustrated? One reason may be thatmany of them are unemployed, either because they do not have the education needed to get jobs or because jobs are not available. To solve the problem of street crime, therefore, we must change the schools and the economy. But what role is played in all this by frustration? Is it the case thatwhen one cannot get a job one feels frustrated and thatwhen one feels frustrated one mugs and robs, or is it simply the case thatwhen one cannot earn money, one ismore likely to steal it?and possibly to experience a bodily condition called frustration? Since many of the events which must be taken into account inexplaining behavior are associated with bodily states that can be felt, what is felt may serve as a clue to the contingencies. But the feelings are not the contingencies and cannot replace them as causes. By itsvery nature operant behavior encourages the invention of mental or cognitive processes said to initiate action. In a reflex, conditioned or unconditioned, there is conspicuous prior cause. Something triggers the response. But behavior that has been positively reinforced occurs upon occasions which, though predisposing, are never compelling. The behavior seems to start up suddenly, without advance notice, as if spontaneously generated. Hence the invention of such cognitive entities as intention, purpose, or will. The same issues were debated with respect to the theory of evolution and for the same reason: selection is a special causal mode not easily observed. Because controlling circumstances which lie in an organism's history of reinforcement are obscure, themental surrogate gets itschance. Under positive reinforcement we do, as we say,what we are free todo; hence the notion of freewill as an initiating condition. (I think itwas Jonathan Edwards who said thatwe believe infreewill because we know about our behavior but not about its causes.) When we do not know why people do one thing rather than another, we say that they "choose" or "make decisions." Choosing originally meant examining, scrutinizing, or testing. Etymologically, deciding means cutting off other possibilities, moving in a direction from which there is no return. Choosing and deciding are thus conspicuous forms of behavior, but cognitive psychologists have nevertheless invented internal surrogates. Anatole Rapaport (1973) puts it this way: "A subject in a psychological experiment is offered a choice among alternatives and selects one alternative over others." When this happens, he says, "common sense suggests that he is guided by a preference." Common sense does indeed suggest it,and so do cognitive psychologists, but where and what is a preference? Is itanything more than a tendency to do one thing rather than another? When we cannot tellwhence thewind cometh and wither itgoeth, we say that it"bloweth where it listeth," and common sense, ifnot cognitive psychology, thus credits itwith a preference. (List, by the way, is an example of a term with a physical referent used to refer to a mental process. Itmeans, of course, to lean?as in the listof a ship. And since things usually fall in the direction inwhich they are leaning, we 4 Why I AmNot a CognitivePsychologist say that people lean toward a candidate in an election as a rough way of predicting how theywill vote. The same metaphor is found in"inclincation"; we are "inclined" to vote forX. But itdoes not follow thatwe have internal leanings and inclinations which affect our behavior.) "Intention" is a rather similar term which once meant stretching. The cognitive version is a critical issue incurrent linguistics. Must the intention of the speaker be taken into account? In an operant analysis verbal behavior is determined by the consequences which follow in a given verbal environment, and consequences are what cognitive psychologists are really talking about when they speak of intentions. All operant behavior "stretches forward" a future even though the only consequences responsible for its strength have already occurred. I go to a drinking fountain "with the intention of getting a drink ofwater'' in the sense that Igo because in thepast I have got a drink when I have done so. (I may go for the first time, following directions, but that is not an exception; it is an example of rule-governed behavior, of which more later.) So much for the cognitive internalization of contingencies of reinforcement and the invention of cognitive causes of behavior. Far more damaging to an effective analysis is the internalization of the environment. The Greeks invented themind to explain how the real world could be known. For them, toknow meant tobe acquainted with, tobe intimate with. The term cognition itself is related to coitus, as in theBiblical sense inwhich aman is said to know a woman. Having no adequate physics of light and sound nor any chemistry of taste and odor, theGreeks could not understand how a world outside the body, possibly some distance away, could be known. There must be internal copies. Hence cognitive surrogates of the'real world. The distinction between reality and conscious experience has been made so often that itnow seems self-evident. Fred Attneave (1974) has recently written that "the statement that theworld as we know it isa representation is, I think, a truism?there is really no way inwhich itcan be wrong." But there are at least twoways, depending upon themeaning. If the statement means thatwe can know only representations of the outside world, it is a "truism" only ifwe are not our bodies but inhabitants located somewhere inside. Our bodies are incontact with the real world and can respond to itdirectly, but ifwe are tucked away up in the head, we must be content with representations. Another possible meaning is thatknowing is the very process of constructing mental copies of real things, but if that is the case how do we know the copies? Do we make copies of them! And is that regress infinite? Some cognitive psychologists recognize that knowing is action but try tomake the point by appealing to another mental surrogate. Knowledge is said to be "a system of propositions." According toone writer, "when we use theword 'see' we refer to a bridge between a pattern of sensory stimulation and knowledge which is propositional." But "propositional" is simply a laundered verion of "behavioral," and the "bridge" is between stimuli and behavior and was built when the stimuli were part of the contingen cies. Representational theories of knowledge are modeled on practical behavior. We do make copies of things.We construct representational works of art, because looking at 5 B. F. Skinner them is reinforced inmuch the same way as looking at what they represent. We make maps, because our behavior in following them is reinforced when we arrive at our destination in the mapped territory. But are there internal surrogates? When we day dream, do we first construct copies of reinforcing episodes which we thenwatch, or do we simply see things once again? And when we learn to get about ina given territory,do we construct cognitive maps which we then follow or do we follow the territory? Ifwe follow a cognitive map, must we learn to do so, and will that require a map of themap? There is no evidence of themental construction of images to be looked at or maps to be followed. The body responds to theworld, at the point of contact; making copies would be a waste of time. Knowledge isa key term incognitive theory, and itcovers a good deal of ground. It is often contrasted with perception. We are said tobe able to see that there are three dots on a card but only to know that there are thirteen after counting them, even though counting is a form of behavior. After noting that one spiral can be seen to be continuous but that another can be discovered to be so.only by tracing, Bela Julesz (1975) has said that"any visual task thatcannot be performed spontaneously, without effortor deliberation, can be regarded as a cognitive task rather than as a perceptual one," though all the steps in that example are also clearly behavioral. 44 Knowing how todo something" isan internal surrogate of behavior in itsrelation to contingencies. A child learns to ride a bicycle and is then said to possess knowledge of how to ride. The child's behavior has been changed by the contingencies of reinforce ment maintained by bicycles; the child has not taken possession of the contingencies. To speak of knowing about things is also to construct an internal surrogate of contingencies. We watch a football game and are then said topossess knowledge of what happened. We read a book and are said to know what it is about. The game and the book are somehow 4 4represented" inour minds: we are "in possession of certain facts." But the evidence is simply thatwe can describe what happened at the game and reportwhat the book was about. Our behavior has been changed, but there isno evidence thatwe have acquired knowledge. To be "in possession of the facts" isnot to contain the facts within ourselves but to have been affected by them. Possession of knowledge implies storage, a field inwhich cognitive psychologists have constructed a great many mental surrogates of behavior. The organism is said to take in and store the environment, possibly in some processed form. Let us suppose that a young girl saw a picture yesterday and when asked todescribe ittoday, does so.What has happened? A traditional answer would run something like this:when she saw the picture yesterday the girl formed a copy inhermind (which, infact,was really all she saw). She encoded it ina suitable form and stored it inhermemory, where itremained until today. When asked to describe the picture today, she searched her memory, retrieved the encoded copy, and converted it into something like the original picture, which she then looked at and described. The account ismodelled on the physical storage ofmemoranda. We make copies and other records, and respond to them. But do we do anything of the sort inour minds? 6 Why I Am Not a Cognitive Psychologist Ifanything is"stored," it isbehavior. We speak of the "acquisition" of behavior, but inwhat form is itpossessed? Where is behavior when an organism is not behaving? Where at the present moment, and inwhat form, is the behavior I exhibit when I am listening tomusic, eating my dinner, talking with a friend, taking an early morning walk, or scratching an itch?A cognitive psychologist has said that verbal behavior is stored as "lexical memories." Verbal behavior often leaves public records which can be stored in files and libraries, and themetaphor of the storage is therefore particularly plausible. But is the expression any more helpful than saying thatmy behavior in eating my dinner is stored as prandial memories, or scratching an itch as a prurient memory? The observed facts are simple enough: I have acquired a repertoire of behavior, parts of which Idisplay upon appropriate occasions. The metaphor of storage and retrieval goes well beyond those facts. The computer, together with information theory as designed to deal with physical systems, has made the metaphor of input-storage-retrieval-output fashionable. The struggle tomake machines that think like people has had the effect of supporting theories inwhich people think likemachines. Mind has recently been defined as "the system of organizations and structures ascribed to an individual that processess inputs ... and provides output to the various subsystems and the world." But organizations and structures of what? (The metaphor gains power from the way inwhich itdisposes of troublesome problems. By speaking of input one can forget all the travail of sensory psychology and physiology; by speaking of output one can forget all the problems of reporting and analyzing action; and by speaking of the storage and retrieval of informa tion one can avoid all the difficult problems of how organisms are indeed changed by contact with their environments and how those changes survive.) Sensory data are often said to be stored as images, much like the images said to represent the real world. Once inside, they are moved about for cognitive purposes. There is a familiar experiment on color generalization inwhich a pigeon pecks at a disk of, say, green light, the behavior being reinforced on a variable interval schedule. When a stable rate of responding develops, no further reinforcements are given, and the color of the disk is changed. The pigeon responds to another color at a ratewhich depends upon how much itdiffers from the original; rather similar colors evoke fairly high rates, very different colors low rates. A cognitive psychologist might explain thematter in thisway: The pigeon takes in a new color (as "input"), retrieves the original color frommemory, where ithas been stored in some processed form, puts the two colored images side by side so that theymay be easily compared, and after evaluating the difference, responds at the appropriate rate. But what advantage isgained by moving from a pigeon that responds to different colors on a disk to an inner pigeon that responds to colored images in itsmind? The simple fact is that because of a known history of reinforcement, different colors control different rates. The cognitive metaphor isbased upon behavior in the real world. We store samples of material and retrieve and compare them with other samples. We compare them in the literal sense of putting them side by side tomake differences more obvious. And we respond to different things in different ways. But that is all. The whole field of the processing of information can be reformulated as changes in the control exerted by stimuli. 7 B. F. Skinner The storage of factual knowledge raises another problem. When I learn, say, to take apart the rings of a puzzle, itseems unlikely that I storemy knowledge of how todo so as a copy of thepuzzle or of the contingencies thepuzzle maintains for those trying to solve it. Instead cognitive theory holds that I store a rule. Rules are widely used as mental surrogates of behavior, inpart because they can be memorized and hence "possessed," but there is an important difference between rules and the contingencies they describe. Rules can be internalized in the sense thatwe can say them to ourselves, but indoing so we do not internalize the contingencies. Imay learn to solve the puzzle ineither of twoways. Imay move the rings about until I hit upon a response that separates them. The behavior will be strengthened, and if I do the same thing a number of times, Iwill eventually be able to take the rings apart quickly. My behavior has been shaped and maintained by its effects on the rings. Imay, on the other hand, simply follow printed directions supplied with the puzzle. The directions describe behavior that separates the rings, and if I have already learned to follow directions, I can avoid the possibly long process of having my behavior shaped by the contingencies. Directions are rules. Like advice, warnings, maxims, proverbs, and governmental and scientific laws, they are extremely important parts of a culture, enabling people to profit from the experience of others. Those who have acquired behavior through expo sure to contingencies describe the contingencies, and others then circumvent exposure by behaving in theways described. But cognitive psychologists contend that something of the same sort happens internallywhen people learn directly from the contingencies. They are said to discover rules which they themselves then follow. But rules are not in the contingencies, normust they be "known'' by those who acquire behavior under exposure to them. (We are lucky that this could be so, since rules are verbal products which arose very late in the evolution of the species.) The distinction between rules and contingencies is currently important in the field of verbal behavior. Children learn to speak through contact with verbal communities, possibly without instruction. Some verbal responses are effective and others not, and over a period of time more and more effective behavior is shaped and maintained. The contingencies having this effect can be analyzed. A verbal response "means" something in the sense that the speaker is under the control of particular circumstances; a verbal stimulus "means" something in the sense that the listener responds to it in particular ways. The verbal community maintains contingencies of such a nature that responses made upon particular occasions serve as useful stimuli to listeners who then behave appropriately to the occasions. More complex relations among the behaviors of speaker and listener fall within the fields of syntax and grammar. Until the time of theGreeks, no one seems to have known that therewere rules of grammar, although people spoke grammatically in the sense that they behaved effectively under the contingencies maintained by verbal communities, as children today learn to talk without being given rules to follow. But cognitive psychologists insist that speakers and listeners must discover rules for themselves. One authority, indeed, has defined speaking as "engaging in a rule-governed form of inten tional behavior." But there is no evidence that rules play any part in the behavior of the ordinary speaker. By using a dictionary and a grammar we may compose acceptable 8 Why I AmNot a CognitivePsychologist sentences in a language we do not otherwise speak, and we may occasionally consult a dictionary or a grammar in speaking our own language, but even so we seldom speak by applying rules. We speak because our behavior is shaped and maintained by the practices of a verbal community. Having moved the environment inside the head in the form of conscious experience and behavior in the form of intention, will, and choice, and having stored the effects of contingencies of reinforcement as knowledge and rules, cognitive psychologists put them all together to compose an internal simulacrum of the organism, a kind of Doppleganger, not unlike the classical homunculus, whose behavior is the subject of what Piaget and others have called "subjective behaviorism." The mental apparatus studied by cognitive psychology is simply a rather crude version of contingencies of reinforcement and their effects. Every so-called cognitive process has a physical model. We associate things by putting them together.We store memoranda and retrieve them for later use. We compare things by putting them side by side to emphasize differences. We discriminate things one from another by separating them and treating them indifferent ways. We identify objects by isolating them from confusing surroundings. We abstract sets of items from complex arrays. We describe contingencies of reinforcement inrules. These are the actions of real persons. It is only in the fanciful world of an inner person that they become mental processes. The very speed with which cognitive processes are invented to explain behavior should arouse our suspicions. Moliere made a joke of amedical example more than three hundred years ago: "I am asked by the learned doctors for the cause and reason why opium puts one to sleep, towhich I reply that there is in ita soporific virtue the nature of which is to lull the senses." Moliere's candidate could have cited evidence from introspection, invoking a collateral effect of the drug, by saying: "To which I reply that opium makes one feel sleepy.'' But the soporific virtue itself is a sheer invention, and it is not without current parallels. A conference was recently held inEurope on the subject of scientific creativity. A report published inScience (1974) begins by pointing out thatmore than ninety percent of scientific innovation has been accomplished by fewer than ten percent of all scientists. The next sentence might be paraphrased in thisway: "I am asked by the learned doctors for the cause and reason why this should be so, towhich I reply that it is because only a few scientists possess creativity." Similarly, "I am asked by the learned doctors for the cause and reason why children learn to talk with great speed, towhich I reply that it is because they possess linguistic competence." Moliere's audiences laughed. Cognitive psychologists have two answers to the charge that themental apparatus is ametaphor or construct. One is thatcognitive processes are known through introspection. Do not all thinking persons know that they think?And ifbehaviorists say they do not, are they not either confessing a low order of mentality or acting inbad faith for the sake of their position? No one doubts that behavior involves internal processes; the question is 9 B. F. Skinner how well they can be known through introspection. As I have argued elsewhere, self-knowledge, consciousness, or awareness became possible only when the species acquired verbal behavior, and thatwas very late in itshistory. The only nervous systems then available had evolved for other purposes and did not make contact with themore important physiological activities. Those who see themselves thinking see littlemore than theirperceptual and motor behavior, overt and covert. They could be said toobserve the results of "cognitive processes'' but not the processes themselves?a "stream of consciousness" but not what causes the streaming, the "image of a lemon" but not the act of associating appearance with flavor, their use of an abstract termbut not the process of abstraction, a name recalled but not its retrieval frommemory, and so on. We do not, through introspection, observe the physiological processes through which behavior is shaped and maintained by contingencies of reinforcement. But physiologists observe them and cognitive psychologists point to resemblances which suggest that they and the physiologists are talking about the same things. The very fact thatcognitive processes are going on inside the organism suggests that the cognitive account is closer to physiology than the contingencies of reinforcement studied by those who analyze behavior. But ifcognitive processes are simply modelled upon the environ mental contingencies, the fact that they are assigned to space inside the skin does not bring them closer to a physiological account. On the contrary, the fascination with an imagined inner life has led to a neglect of the observed facts. The cognitive constructs give physiologists a misleading account of what theywill find inside. In summary, then, I am not a cognitive psychologist for several reasons. I see no evidence of an innerworld of mental life relative either to an analysis of behavior as a function of environmental forces or to the physiology of the nervous system. The respective sciences of behavior and physiology will move forward most rapidly if their domains are correctly defined and analyzed. I am equally concerned with practical consequences. The appeal to cognitive states and processes is a diversion which could well be responsible formuch of our failure to solve our problems. We need to change our behavior and we can do so only by changing our physical and social environments. We choose thewrong path at the very startwhen we suppose thatour goal is to change the "minds and hearts of men and women" rather than theworld inwhich they live. REFERENCES Attneave, Fred, American Psychologist, July, 1974. Julesz, Bela, Scientific American, April, 1975. Popper, Karl, Poverty of Historicism, London, 1957. Rapaport, Anatol, Experimental Games and their Uses in Psychology, General Learning Press, 1973, Science, June 21, 1974. Waddington, C. H., New York Review, February 3, 1974. 10