Journal of Philosophy of Education, Vol. 53, No. 2, 2019 Mindfulness In, As and Of Education: Three Roles of Mindfulness in Education OREN ERGAS Following the exponential rise in publications on mindfulness in education and the emergence of some critical perspectives on this field, this paper articulates three roles of mindfulness practice in education: Mindfulness in, as and of education. The three are developed based on an examination of the practice as it is shaped by two different socio-historical narratives, which in turn manifest in different modalities of implementation and aims in the contemporary educational field. While much of the field is governed by ‘mindfulness in education’ within economic-therapeutic interventions, equal attention is given to ‘mindfulness as education’ as reflected in a whole school approach and to ‘mindfulness of education’ in which the practice radicalises the ethos of critical pedagogy. Describing these three roles, the paper introduces readers to the practice itself, offers a framework for understanding its associations with a variety of educational aims, and critically discusses these associations as well as the diverse pedagogical possibilities that this practice brings to contemporary and future education. INTRODUCTION In the past decades, mindfulness practice has been increasingly incorporated across educational settings. Broad reviews and meta-analyses point to hundreds of thousands of students and thousands of teachers who have been learning to practice mindfulness within school programmes of various lengths and intensities (Carsley et al., 2018; Lomas et al., 2017; Semple et al., 2017; Zenner et al., 2014). Great Britain-based Mindfulness in Schools Project (MiSP) reports having trained over 4,500 teachers, many of whom implement mindfulness in primary and secondary educational settings.1 Research of mindfulness in education has now expanded to huge state-funded projects, such as MYRIAD, which includes 84 UK schools (approx. 6,000 students).2 Examining publications that discuss/study mindfulness in educational settings, however, one finds that they hardly constitute a uniform phenomenon (Ergas and Hadar, 2019). A practice that bears one name is framed C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Published by John Wiley & Sons Ltd, 9600 Garsington Road, Oxford OX4 2DQ, UK and 350 Main Street, Malden, MA 02148, USA. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 Three Roles of Mindfulness in Education 341 and implemented in a variety of ways, and toward an array of aims, such as reduction of teacher burnout and stress (Flook et al., 2013), enhancement of social-emotional competencies (Jennings et al., 2017), improved cognitive functions and well-being in students (Zenner et al., 2014), transformative teaching and learning processes (Owen-Smith, 2017), enhanced scientific criticality (Roth, 2006), cultivation of spirituality (Wong, 2004), and critical pedagogy (Magee, 2016). Modalities of implementations are also diverse, spanning short term school mindfulness-based interventions (MBIs) (Zenner et al., 2014) of 4 to 12 sessions, to whole-school approaches incorporating mindfulness across the curriculum (Tarrasch, 2017), and integrations of mindfulness in higher education courses across disciplines, such as social work, communication, law and psychology (Komjathy, 2018). Witnessing such variety, one is bound to question how can one practice be associated with so many aims, how ‘educational’ are these aims, and how seriously ought we to take this multifaceted phenomenon? Indeed, many have been posing challenging questions in regards to the development of this discourse. Eppert (2013), Hyland (2017) and Purser and Loy (2013) pointed to ‘McMindfulness’—the commodification of mindfulness, its uprooting from Buddhist ethics and its presentation as a panacea. Forbes (2019) and Reveley (2015) critiqued its shallow and self-indulging implementations that result as serving neoliberal agendas. Others warned us to ‘mind the hype’ around mindfulness, for research in this field is still in its infancy and suffers from various methodological flaws (Van Dam et al., 2018). That said, implementations of mindfulness in educational institutions across ages are clearly spreading. The number of peer-reviewed publications in this particular field had risen exponentially from 2 in 2002 to 101 in 2017, amounting to 447 overall. Half of them were published between 2014 and 2017, 294 (66 percent) of which involve actual implementations (Ergas and Hadar, 2019). In the face of this growth, these diverse manifestations, and considering critical perspectives, this paper proposes a framework for understanding different roles of mindfulness in contemporary education. The framework is developed based on depicting the encounter between the core facets of the practice and its socio-historical framings on the one hand, and education on the other hand. Based on this encounter three strands of implementations of the practice in education are depicted to explain the diversity described above: a socialisation-oriented mindfulness in education, a holistic mindfulness as education, and a radical-critical mindfulness of education. Each of these reflects different modalities of implementation, aims and roles of the practice in education. The paper includes two parts. The first part of the paper deals with the practice in isolation and prior to its implementations within education. It renders its core facets and presents two narratives that contextualise it as a path or as a tool. These narratives are then explored in relation to parallel conceptions of education. The second part describes the three roles of mindfulness in education in light of this exposition. Mindfulness in, as and of education are explained, discussed critically, and grounded in publications in the field. The three strands are given relatively equal attention despite the fact that currently mindfulness in education predominates the C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 342 O. Ergas field. The intention behind this is to offer a broader orientation to the practice and to shed light on some of its less known emerging potentials for education. MINDFULNESS PRACTICE Three Core Facets of Mindfulness Practice Understanding the variety within the discourse of mindfulness in education requires a definition of the practice; however, there are various definitions of mindfulness in the discourse (Bishop et al., 2004; Cullen, 2011; Gethin, 2011; Kabat-Zinn, 2005; Shapiro et al., 2012; Yates et al., 2015). I hence refer to the following as a description of the practice’s core facets. The description aims to draw boundaries that are loose enough to include a variety of contemporary implementations, yet are sufficiently rigid to enable distinguishing mindfulness practice from other practices. Mindfulness is often considered as a set of meditative practices that involve three distinct yet intertwined components: attention, intention and attitude (Bishop et al., 2004; Kabat-Zinn, 2005; Shapiro et al., 2012). One common way to practice mindfulness requires bringing attention to the sensation of the breath in the abdomen and sustaining it there. An untrained mind, however, will quickly succumb to mind-wandering; that is, one will unwittingly transition into reflecting/ruminating on past events or planning the future (Petitmengin et al., 2017). This transition represents the forgetting of the object of attention and the intention to practice (Wallace, 1999). Wandering goes on until the practitioner realises his/her forgetfulness upon which s/he is to bring back attention to the breath. The recurrence of this scenario can yield irritation, frustration and reprimanding oneself for the inability to sustain attention. In the face of this inner antagonism the practitioner practices attitude, which means mentally fostering an acceptance of any experience within the practice, including the inability to sustain attention. Attitude is often elaborated based on terms, including non-judgementalism, non-striving, compassion and kindness (Cullen, 2011; Kabat-Zinn, 2005). The third component—intention—undergirds the entire process. It consists of the recurrent re-establishment of the intention to practice attention and attitude rather than succumb to rumination, mind-wandering or deliberate planning (Yates et al., 2015). The core facets of mindfulness practice hence include attention, attitude and intention. If any one of these elements is missing from the instructions, then in this paper it is not considered to be mindfulness practice. Notwithstanding, there are diverse ways to practice mindfulness, which are introduced in contemporary programmes, e.g. body scan, focused attention, open awareness, mindful walking, mindful yoga, and there are various adaptations of these practices to suit diverse ages and populations (Cullen, 2011; Roeser, 2014). The above allows for distinguishing mindfulness from other practices, such as reflection. Though diversely implemented, reflection in education is often based in and/or aims at drawing conclusions, conceptualisation, improving performance, and decision making (Owen-Smith, 2017). C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 Three Roles of Mindfulness in Education 343 Conversely, mindfulness is grounded in attending to the present moment as it is, stepping away from interpretation, elaboration and deliberate meaning-making processes. If the latter emerge spontaneously within the practice one is to shift from them back to the breath/bodily sensations (Yates et al., 2015). Volitional control is exercised here over attention but not over the unfolding of experience nor over the content of thoughts (Webster-Wright, 2013). It is hence a practice in which one examines pre-reflective content, grounded in ‘how’ one attends and refraining from becoming absorbed in ‘what’ one attends to (Petitmengin et al., 2017, p. 173). Further details on the implications of these core facets and these distinctions will be offered in subsequent parts of the paper. Beyond depicting the boundaries of mindfulness practice as the phenomenon under study, the articulation of these core facets serves an additional purpose, which concerns the task of this paper. It strategically separates the internal mental activities within practice from the external cultural-social-historical context within which it is practiced. It is proposed here that with some variations and remaining within the boundaries of the core facets described, the same practice can have different aims and be framed differently depending on when and where it is offered. The following section turns to depict the external context that shapes these framings and aims. Mindfulness Practice: Two Narratives at the Gateway of Education One way to understand the variety in contemporary discourse is by depicting two different narratives within which the above core facets of the practice are embedded. These two reflect different historical-social contexts and human interests. They can be viewed as providing mindfulness with different IDs and biographies that frame the practice differently as it stands at the ‘gateway’ of education. When mindfulness goes through this gateway it moulds and is moulded by contemporary educational settings, forking into diverse modalities of implementation and aims. The following presents these two narratives very briefly to position mindfulness at this gateway. The first narrative depicts mindfulness practice as having been ‘born’ around the 5th century BCE under the Pali name sati (also meaning ‘remembering’) (Yates et al., 2015). Sati connotes with a set of practices elaborated by the Buddha orally and later transcribed in texts, such as the Satipatthana Suta. Some of these practices correspond with the core facets of the practice described above (Gethin, 2011; Repetti, 2016). When mindfulness practice is presented based on this narrative it is both a practice and a component within a broad Buddhist path toward liberation from suffering. The practice is thus embedded in a robust ethical worldview, that stresses the socio-ethical dispositions of compassion and wisdom (Hyland, 2013). The second narrative depicts mindfulness as having been adopted and adapted in 1979 by Jon Kabat-Zinn. Kabat-Zinn, a doctor of molecular biology, who practiced Zen meditation, realised the potential of the practice C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 344 O. Ergas to reduce the suffering of a variety of chronic physical and mental problems (Kabat-Zinn, 2005). However, he also acknowledged that a Buddhist framing is likely to prevent the possibility of offering it to those who may be aided by it. He hence developed ‘mindfulness-based stress-reduction’ (MBSR)— an 8 week structured intervention in which patients learned to practice mindfulness (Kabat-Zinn, 2011). His rendition provided the practice with an alternative framing; not necessarily Buddhist, but rather secular-clinical. When mindfulness practice is presented based on this narrative it is not part of a Buddhist path, but more of a way to cope with day-to-day stress. These two different narratives appeal to different populations. In fact, recontextualising the appeal of the practice was the very intention behind the formation of the second narrative. As Kabat-Zinn (2005) described, the patients to whom it was offered were not interested in Buddhism. They sought a solution to health problems. The existence of these two narratives in contemporary times reveals the phenomenon of two people interpreting their engagement with mindfulness practice in significantly different ways. One might be drawn to it as an inquiry into the nature of (non)self and as a path toward cultivating wisdom and compassion (the first narrative). Another might view it as a way to cope with stress or ameliorate burnout (the second narrative). Very roughly the first narrative is about ‘solving the problem of life’; the second, is about ‘solving a problem that gets in the way of life’. Shifts between these perspectives may occur as some examples suggest (Kabat-Zinn, 2005). However, for the purposes of this paper the distinction here, which seems to cut through contemporary implementations of mindfulness in general, and in education, is between mindfulness as a path versus mindfulness as a tool. Mindfulness as a path nests the practice within a broad framework in which it is embraced as a life-long ethicalexistential undertaking (Hyland, 2016). Mindfulness as a tool means that it is a particular technique applied toward solving a particular big/small problem. In such a case, the practice has a functional role. It is valued if it solves the problem; however, if other tools solve it more efficiently/costeffectively, then mindfulness might be traded for them. To be sure, each of the narratives continued to evolve since its beginnings. The Buddhist narrative has been developing through interpretations that had led to a variety of Buddhist schools of thought-practice (Gethin, 2011; Wallace, 1999). The secular-clinical narrative was added the context of therapy with the development of ‘mindfulness-based cognitive therapy’ (MBCT) (Segal et al., 2018). It then further expanded into the context of economy as its potential to contribute to occupational health, performativity and productivity began to manifest, and implementation disseminated into business, technological apps, sports, the police force, and the US army (Forbes, 2019; Purser and Loy, 2013). In the course of four decades, the second narrative has become a conglomerate that fuses secular-clinicaltherapeutic-economic framings and implications. A heated debate exists as to the relationships between the two narratives. Some view the second narrative, in its worthy manifestations as a clear extension of the first (Kabat-Zinn, 2005; Repetti, 2016). Others construe the progression of the second narrative as leading to ‘McMindfulness’; the C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 Three Roles of Mindfulness in Education 345 commodification of the practice and its complete separation from the first narrative (Forbes, 2019; Hyland, 2017; Purser and Loy, 2013). Mindfulness stands at the gateway of education with both narratives and this latter debate following it as a trail wherever it goes. Yet, prior to examining the encounter between the practice and education, it is crucial to point out that the path/tool distinction has its parallel within a broad perspective on educational theory and practice. Education as a path appears in Plato’s cave allegory (the Republic), which depicts it as a journey toward and reflecting moral living based on inquiry into the Good, True and Beautiful. Education for tools and qualifications is found in the very same text, for the above educational journey was saved for the elite. The education of others had a functionalist-economic socialisation role aimed at preparing citizens for a productive life. Both educational orientations have continued to manifest in our times. Education as a path can be found in theory and practice (Aloni, 2007; Owen-Smith, 2017; Peters, 1973), and the economic-functional orientation can be seen clearly in our times. As Gilead (2015) described, over the passing decades a process of ‘economic imperialism’ has taken place. Phenomena, such as accountability, highstakes testing, ‘best practices’, tools for teaching, and what Biesta (2009) called ‘the learnification of education’, reflect education as a vehicle of economic progress that stands for values of functionality, efficiency, costeffectiveness and productivity. For some, like Peters (1973), this path versus tools distinction would mark a boundary between what education is and what it is not. For Peters an activity would be considered educational only if it leads to educational aims and is intrinsically worthwhile. Hence some contemporary activities in school might not necessarily qualify as ‘education’. In light of these distinctions between the two narratives of mindfulness practice and their encounter with parallel conceptions of education, and in light of Peters, we can turn to explore three roles of mindfulness practice in education. The three are presented beginning with the most common and conformist to the less common and radical. THREE ROLES OF MINDFULNESS IN EDUCATION Mindfulness in Education ‘Mindfulness in education’ embeds the practice in the second narrative. It reflects the most common form of contemporary implementations of the practice in educational settings (Ergas and Hadar, 2019; Roeser, 2014). When analysing the role of the practice here, both an external perspective (focusing on the facets of the practice) and the internal perspectives (focusing on the social-historical narrative) are required because each sheds a different light on this phenomenon. The former clearly reveals mindfulness as a tool in this case, whereas the latter raises questions on whether something more profound is occurring here. The external perspective shows mindfulness in education as conforming with ‘the system’, supporting its functioning and improving performance and well-being within it. I refer to this as ‘in education’, thinking of C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 346 O. Ergas ‘education’ metaphorically as a box made of certain ways of thinking and practice, rules, regulations, timetables and so forth. Mindfulness in education implies finding ways to take a practice that comes from radical places (the first narrative) and fitting it in to the box. This involves molding it in various ways and developing a language that appeals to policy-makers. One can detect these processes in the ways in which the practice is framed throughout publications in this domain. As Ergas and Hadar (2019) demonstrate, they will generally ground it in Kabat-Zinn’s work and either refrain from mentioning the first narrative (e.g., Bakosh et al., 2016), or mention it in passing yet shift to scientific-secular language: ‘Mindfulness, which is derived from centuries-old meditative traditions and taught in a secular way, has been linked to heightened activation in brain regions . . . ’ (Flook et al., 2013, p. 183, emphasis added). Framing the practice as a tool manifests in two fundamental conceptual frameworks from the second narrative—therapy and economy. These shape the modalities of implementation and affect the aims. Publications of mindfulness in education usually structure their argument in one of two ways. The first depicts MBIs as targeting the problem of stress—a therapeuticclinical concept, thereby indirectly contributing to schooling outcomes (e.g. academic achievements, cognitive functions). MBIs address the adverse effects of stress on teachers’ and/or students’ ability to function and thus contribute to coping with school tasks (e.g. Crain et al., 2017; Flook et al., 2013). The second kind of argument depicts MBIs as directly contributing to cognitive functions, readiness to learn and academic performance (e.g. Bakosh et al., 2016; Mrazek et al., 2013), and/or to social-emotional skills and classroom climate (e.g. Jennings et al., 2017). The economic framing emerges in a variety of ways. It begins with the modality of implementation framed as mindfulness-based interventions (MBIs). The term ‘intervention’ is borrowed from the medical world and has an economic logic built into it. It is a short-term implementation that has a particular aim and is tested for efficacy and cost-effectiveness. This logic is clearly captured in broad projects, such as the above-mentioned MYRIAD titled: ‘The effectiveness and cost-effectiveness of a mindfulness training program in schools compared with normal school provision (MYRIAD)’,3 and in studies that make claims, such as, ‘[I]n the long run, reducing teacher stress and burnout may reduce costs associated with teacher absenteeism, turnover, and health care . . . ’ (Jennings et al., 2017, p. 17), ‘[T]he personal, societal, and financial costs associated with burnout are too high to ignore’ (Flook et al., 2013, p. 182). The economic orientation further manifests in seeking the ‘right dosage’ of practice (Davidson et al., 2012) and in MBIs designed to minimise practice time and expenses and maximise outcomes, such as a ten-minute CD-delivered intervention that does not depend on teachers and is aimed at improving academic achievements (Bakosh et al., 2016). The logic behind MBIs is clearly understandable from an external perspective; however, when considering them in light of Peters’ (1973) criteria, mindfulness here may be in education but it wouldn’t qualify as education. Its function here is to support other processes and ends that are understood C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 Three Roles of Mindfulness in Education 347 as educational, but the educational merit of the actual practice; namely the engagement with its core facets, remains outside of the discussion. The very term ‘intervention’ embodies the seed of alienating the practice from education. There’s a not-too-hidden curriculum in the message of the medium: that which intervenes, is not the thing in which it intervenes. By comparison, we don’t tend to view the learning of maths or literature or learning to read as interventions in education, but rather as educational activities. A further concern here is that some of the aims that mindfulness practice addresses are not easily framed as educational. When they are framed within occupational health (e.g. reduced absenteeism and burnout) it is clearly not the case. This has little to do with the merit, logic and desirable outcomes of addressing these matters; however, the aim here is to sustain the system more than it is to engage in mindfulness as a worthwhile activity. If this is about occupational health, then maybe jogging or listening to music are preferable. An educational justification for mindfulness, construing it as (not merely in) education, would need to highlight the intrinsic educational value of the practice itself. That is, how and why do the core features of the practice reflect an educational process and bring about educational aims? Additional critique emerges when pointing to a paradoxical logic at work here. Economic-driven policies, such as accountability and high-stakes testing are often the source of the stress that MBIs are to address (Roeser and Peck, 2009). Some have thus critiqued MBIs for normalising a sick system in fact ‘adding lemon juice to poison’ (Sellman and Buttarazzi, 2019). They enhance teacher and student resilience, ‘pathology-proofing’ them so that they can feel ‘good’ within an oppressive system (Reveley, 2015). From such perspective a practice originally aimed at liberation is devoured by neoliberal agendas (Forbes, 2019), making one wonder whether this is Marx’s ‘false consciousness’ returned with a vengeance. However, there is a need for balancing the external perspective with internal perspectives. For example, it is crucial to note that some leading scientists and leaders in this field describe quite remarkable personal stories of transformation, which have led them to the practice (Jennings, 2015), many are clearly grounded in the Buddhist path (Burnett, 2011) and some collaborate with world-renowned Buddhist leaders (Hanh and Weare, 2018). When looking at mindfulness in education from this perspective, its serious manifestations parallel Kabat-Zinn’s (2011) very Buddhist motivation—to address suffering in the world. The ‘tool’ seems to be studied/offered by those who see it as a path within the Buddhist concept of skillful means (upaya). Their work is one of crafting a language that appeals to a system that would not tolerate Buddhist terms but is well-versed in the language of market-economy. What makes mindfulness into a tool is often not those who seriously study/implement it. It is the educational system within which this takes place. The former might be interested in liberation and the reduction of suffering; the latter is more interested in a lubricant that oils its engine. An additional aspect to be noted is that MBIs are increasingly associated with the enhancement of social-emotional skills/competencies (Jennings et al., 2017). On the one hand skills/competencies reflect an economic discourse (Biesta, 2009). On the other hand, these are not the early 20th century C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 348 O. Ergas three Rs (reading, writing, arithmetic), but rather the attitudinal components of mindfulness practice—compassion and kindness. Mindfulness in education here is about creating prosocial classrooms and developing healthy teacher–student relationships (Davidson et al., 2012). The potential for construing these within education as a path toward moral living is clearly there; however, currently the justification for mindfulness in education is mostly confined to quantitative research. This tends to exacerbate the erosion of the educational status of mindfulness for quantitative measures of mindfulness and its outcomes fail to convey the phenomenology of first-person experience (Petitmengin et al., 2017). Behind improvements in occupational health, there may be a teacher who has become more attentive and feels more joy and fulfillment in her job. Behind MBIs, such as Mindfulness in Schools Project (UK) or Peace in Schools (US) there are children and teenagers who learned to cope with anxiety revealing remarkable stories of personal transformation.4 These need to be explored from qualitative perspectives in order to bring forth a fuller educational justification for the practice (e.g. Tarrasch, 2015). The role of mindfulness in education suggests a variety of contributions to students’ and teachers’ well-being, cognitive functions and social-emotional competencies (Zenner et al., 2014). From an external view, however, the medium of implementation, and the justifications provided for it within quantitative studies, often deprive mindfulness from being fully considered within the scope of Education. Paradoxically, this deprivation stems from the ethos of the educational system itself. Its functional-economic ethos is understandable from an external perspective, yet it erodes the educational worthwhileness of the practice. Mindfulness as Education The conception of ‘mindfulness as education’ takes its cue from the first narrative of mindfulness and from the broader horizons of education as a path. It positions the practice as both serving educational aims and as an inherently worthwhile activity (Peters, 1973) and gives it a far more robust presence in the curriculum (O’Donnell, 2015). Such conception implies a shift away from education that is narrowed down by ‘economic imperialism’ (Gilead, 2015); conversely, it grounds it in ancient and contemporary conceptions of education as a path and as a holistic endeavour that concerns character, virtue, self-knowledge and social-engagement (Aloni, 2007). However, there is a clear issue at stake here for ideally speaking, this would imply that the incorporation of mindfulness as education would necessitate bringing its Buddhist roots along with it. This unlikely progression is one reason why current discourse around mindfulness as education is mostly theoretical and revolves around critique of mindfulness in education (Ergas and Hadar, 2019). Critics argue against a two-layered economic imperialism that frames education in these terms and then frames mindfulness in this very way to serve education-framed in economical terms (Lewin, 2017; O’Donnell, 2015). This process itself is part of the broader ‘McMindfulness’ phenomenon described as ‘divorcing technique from underpinning C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 Three Roles of Mindfulness in Education 349 value foundations’ (Hyland, 2016, p. 14). Eppert (2013) hence claimed that mindfulness and contemplative practices in general ‘are in danger of being “used and abused”, diluted and commodified, packaged and made “easy”, designed to fit into society rather than rigorously question and re-imagine it’ (p. 339). She called for engaging the ancestries of these practices as an antidote to these trends. Some attempts have been made in this direction. Hyland (2013) proposed Buddhist mindfulness as a ‘more suitable vehicle than religious or faith-based strategies for fostering spirituality or other-regarding values’ (p. 10). O’Donnell (2015) suggested deploying ‘more heterodox methods inspired by mindfulness practices rooted in the Buddhist tradition, that are both integrated into the curriculum and school experience’ (p. 197). These proposals are laudable, yet they may still raise concerns of proselytising a religion to students within some Western industrialised countries (Jennings, 2016). As the following proposes, a possibly more effective way to render mindfulness as education, can be articulated based on certain interpretations of the core facets of the practice itself. This may offer a narrative that is not Buddhist, nor therapeutic-economic, but rather educational. Demonstrating the inherent educational worthwhileness of mindfulness practice can begin with an often-cited passage from William James: ‘The faculty of voluntarily bringing back a wandering attention, over and over again, is the very root of judgment, character, and will . . . An education which should improve this faculty would be the education par excellence’ (1981[1890], p. 401, emphasis added). Bear in mind that the italicised words can pass for the attentional and intentional core facets of mindfulness practice as depicted earlier. But why did James make such claim? Explaining this requires engaging a little more deeply with his perspective on attention, experience and the mind. James argued that ‘for the moment what we attend to is reality’ (1981 [1890], p. 322). Minds select what to attend to and ‘make’ reality in two ways: actively, as one wills attention to an object, and passively, as attention is lured involuntarily to objects of interest (James, 1962). Our lives amount to a concatenation of moments of reality shaped by these two processes. However, James observed that we have very poor ability to sustain attention voluntarily (p. 234). This lack is an expression of lacking will, for willing something implies being able to sustain it before our minds by the faculty of attention (ibid.). Such lack prevents us from pursuing long-term goals, for we are constantly lured and side-tracked by a mind that keeps presenting us with alternative possibilities. These lure our judgement, resulting in weakness of character. It follows then that improving our ability to bring attention to an object of choice, we will become more capable of holding ideas in mind until they are pursued. Hence if mindfulness practice indeed enhances attention as some evidence suggests (Davidson et al., 2012; Tarrasch, 2017), according to James it would reflect education par excellence. Yet there is still a question about the nature of things we would want to pursue with this trained attention, for sustained attention is an ‘ethicallyneutral quality’ (Conze, 1956, p. 19). One can apply it toward committing a crime as much as one can apply it toward an altruistic deed. This is why the C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 350 O. Ergas attitudinal facet of the practice is crucial. It includes non-judgmentalism, kindness, curiosity, non-striving and in some modalities of MBIs these are extended to practices of loving-kindness, friendliness, compassion and gratitude (Cullen, 2011; Roeser, 2014). I suggest that these practices can be seen as bringing attitude to the foreground and casting attention to the background remaining within the bounds of what has been described as the core facets of mindfulness practice. Within mindfulness practice one does not merely bring back a wandering mind to the object; one cultivates an ability to live within one’s body, accepting everything experienced throughout the practice with kindness. These are hence ethical commitments built into the practice that undergird the neutrality of attention. When framed this way this is not about Buddhism; it is about virtues. Aristotle claimed that one cultivates virtue by engaging in virtuous deeds. The question is whether one becomes kinder or more compassionate by practicing these qualities mentally on one’s own? This is a basic assumption that undergirds mindfulness as education. Evidence from research of MBIs and from neuroscience proposes that this is indeed the case (Condon et al., 2013; Davidson et al., 2012; Shapiro et al., 2012). Namely, habits are formed both by acting and by mentally acting upon ourselves through practices such as mindfulness. When looking at mindfulness as an educational practice in this way the distinction between mindfulness in education and as education has far more to do with modalities of implementation than with a full investment in the first narrative of mindfulness. This is about showing how the means embody the ends and the intrinsic value of the activity itself. Lewin (2017) in fact suggested that: ‘There is something about the delicate nature of attention that yields to intrinsic reward, where the mindful subject is not oriented to anything, but to being present’ (p. 114). On this view, the very act of halting our doings and attending kindly to the breath reflects a sense of gratitude and appreciation of being. Treating the practice thus, must imply implementing it in a way that respects this activity and not only its outcomes. Though rarer, there are some actual implementations of this approach in contemporary literature. Tarrasch (2017) studied a primary public school with a student population of low socio-economic status that in the past fifteen years has integrated ‘the mindfulness language’ into school life. This included, weekly sessions dedicated to mindfulness practices, as well as practices interweaved throughout the school day within disciplinary lessons. The school principal introduced this curricular reform after experiencing extreme violence and behavioural issues in the school. The curricular reform began with setting aside academic achievements completely and highlighting emotional engagement and relationships among teachers, among students, and between teachers and students (Frankel, 2008). The implementation of this ‘mindfulness language’ in this case, reflects the antithesis of a ‘mindfulness intervention’. It is not a compartmentalised tool, but rather a language that undergirds all human interactions and permeates school life. It is not surprising that such cases are rare. Such reforms require a huge commitment and deep understanding of the practice on behalf of the C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 Three Roles of Mindfulness in Education 351 principal and school staff. Furthermore, recruiting a community to prioritise social-emotional aspects of school life in an age of accountability and highstakes testing is no simple matter. Interestingly, in the course of a decade this reform has led the school from the bottom of the country’s rankings to the top on both school climate and academic achievements (Tarrasch, 2017). At least in this case implementing mindfulness as education, yielded the benefits sought within mindfulness in education. One case is certainly not enough for theory-building. It does, however, provide a concrete example of potential. Importantly, this is not an alternative school (e.g. Waldorf, Montessori). It is a public urban school that had to work within the realms of the autonomy given to it by a ministry of education. This implies that mindfulness as education can take place within the bounds of public education. It does not seem to compromise the economic-functional role of socialisation concerned with the need for engineers, lawyers, nurses, teachers. It rather opens the possibility for highlighting the education of kind and compassionate engineers, lawyers, nurses, teachers, etc. What emerges from the analysis is that the transition from mindfulness in to as education does not necessarily involve Buddhist liberation as much as it involves liberating education from economic imperialism. This enables a more creative approach to the integration of mindfulness into curricularpedagogical practice by adopting not a ‘Buddhist language’, but rather a ‘mindfulness language’. I would still argue, however, that just as many of the scientists and leaders within mindfulness in education are versed in the first narrative, those teaching mindfulness in or as education need to be grounded in the practice and its ancestries. However, the actual words they use when teaching can rely safely on very basic human faculties of attention, attitude and intention, which can at one and the same time be viewed as core facets of both mindfulness practice and the practice of Education. Mindfulness of Education There is a third possibility that is conceptualised here as ‘mindfulness of education’ conceived as engaging in mindfulness for the purpose of critiquing education. It is far less obvious and only beginning to emerge in the discourse (Ergas, 2017; Forbes, 2019; Kaufman, 2017; Magee, 2016). However, it holds significant potential for introducing radical dimensions of critique that can inform education and critical pedagogy. To develop this, I begin by associating the act of critique with a further description of the core facets of mindfulness. Then I tie it to educational possibilities. Critique can occur in diverse contexts, involve various methods, and be expressed in a variety of ways. Some examples include, Socratic elenchus in which argument and counterargument are exchanged through dialogue, self-reflection as in Descartes’ Meditations, and Freire’s dialectical analysis of social injustice. These examples differ significantly in terms of the aims of critique and the themes discussed, yet one thing they all share, is the media they are all based in—thinking processes, reasoning and language. I am well aware that pointing to what is missing from them, I will be applying the very same media, hence it should be clear that the merit of all of them is C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 352 O. Ergas completely beyond questioning here. I do, however, point to a modality of critique that mindfulness (and other body-based contemplative practices) can introduce, which can substantially inform critical thinking. Scholars in the field of contemplative studies refer to this as ‘contemplative inquiry’ (Zajonc, 2009), and speak of ‘critical first-person perspective’ (Komjathy, 2018; Roth, 2006). Yet, unlike Descartes’ critical first-person philosophy, the critical stance that mindfulness practice introduces, steps away from an ‘I’ that reflects on ‘his’ thoughts. Practicing mindfulness, one is instructed to return to the moment-to-moment experience of embodied sensations whenever one finds oneself engaging in thinking, reasoning and interpreting. To some degree this can be interpreted as reversing Descartes’ mistrust of the body and adopting it as the point from which the mind itself is critiqued (Ergas, 2013). Shifting away from the content of thoughts stands in sharp contrast to conventional philosophical and day-to-day meaningmaking processes. As such, I argue, it reflects scepticism applied toward the mind of the sceptic him/herself. It is a critical stance that moves away from the thoughts one has, the schemes that bring them about, and the power that these have on our formation, views, and ways of critique. This process opens us to novel perspectives and can lead to insights into the nature of experience (Zajonc, 2009). Practicing mindfulness of ‘something’ means invoking the attitude of curiosity and inquisitiveness, applying them to the content of experience, while being the one who ‘has’ the experience. The expression ‘mindfulness of’ appears in the Satipatthana Suta—the fundamental text in which the Buddha explains the practice of sati. In this text it appears, for example, as practicing ‘mindfulness of the breath’ or ‘of bodily sensations’. This means bringing attention to their natural appearance without attempting to change them. This leads to growing discernment as to the nature of the phenomenon as it breaks down into finer elements (Young, 2016). As attention and awareness are enhanced, the breath is noted with far more detail unraveling more of its subtleties (Yates et al., 2015). As I argue, we can practice mindfulness of the breath, but we can also practice ‘mindfulness of education’ in a variety of ways to which the following serves only as a primer. Since mindfulness of education is a radical form of critique it can willingly engage the first narrative if this informs the critical endeavour. Consider, for example, the first verse of The Dhammapada, a compilation of the Buddha’s words: ‘All phenomena are preceded by the mind, issue forth from the mind, and consist of the mind’ (in Wallace, 1999, fn. 1). Fast-forward to our times and compare this with Eisner’s (1993) claim, ‘what schools allow children to think about shapes, in ways perhaps more significant than we realize, the kind of minds they come to own . . . education is a mind-making process’ (p. 5). Looking at these two very different sources, the tautological nature of education comes into view. All phenomena are preceded by the mind; ‘education’ is itself a phenomenon. It is a process that begins with minds and makes minds. Would it not then be a good idea to explore the mind that makes education? (Ergas, 2017). C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 Three Roles of Mindfulness in Education 353 To make this more concrete, I briefly present a practice that I introduce in undergraduate courses to ignite mindfulness of education. The reader is invited to try the following instructions I give to students, to enable for a clearer understanding of what follows: For the next two minutes, your intention is to just be a witness to experience. Make a list of all things you attend to when you’re not trying to do anything special. Whatever it is, a thought, a sound, an itch, just write it down. I’m not going to make you read it out loud, so you don’t have to be politically correct either. The first thing to establish is that these instructions embody the core facets of mindfulness practice. The difference is that here, mindfulness is practiced in writing and not only mentally: intention is set at the beginning and attitude of non-judgementalism is encouraged. Attention is practiced here within a mindfulness practice known as ‘choiceless awareness’, which requires one to note whatever attention selects and to let go of it without getting stuck on anything in particular (Yates et al., 2015). A typical list following the above instructions can look like this: sound of a cough thought: ‘who was that?’ sight of other students engaged in practice numb sensation in the left hip sound of pens writing thought: ‘it’s so quiet in the classroom’ hum of the projector . . . Broadly, such lists reflect what a mind does when it is not asked to attend to anything in particular. Based on our lists we uncover the phenomenology of this experience. Three fundamental observations emerge: 1. All experiences are based on the faculty of attention. 2. All represent the present moments attended to. 3. All emerge from one of two fields in space: in—private, embodied experiences (e.g. thoughts, inner sensations) or out—stimuli like sights, sounds, smells, which are perceived in the public sphere that is available to everyone. On the face of it, these do not seem to hold much, until we start to consider how the above possibilities feature in education. For example, we may consider a basic definition of teaching as ‘orienting students’ attention to worthwhile content’ (Ergas, 2017). In every moment there are only two options for teachers: either ask students to attend in to their own minds or out. In contemporary education, the former is quite rare. The public curriculum seems very rich with disciplines, but the mind, which ‘precedes all phenomena’, is mostly what Eisner (1994) called a ‘null’ curriculum. Minds created education that makes minds in a way that sends those minds to attend to everything but to the source of the endeavour. C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 354 O. Ergas A further implication of the above practice is that it is imprecise to claim that minds are ‘made’ by education, curriculum, schooling or teaching. They are made by what they attend to wittingly and/or unwittingly. Sometimes minds attend to the planned/taught curriculum; at others, they attend to a myriad other things, many of them in fact, produced by the wandering mind itself. Neuroscientists have become very interested in the latter domain, which in schools manifests in sitting in the classroom yet floating in thoughts to other places. Studies suggest that we spend close to half of our waking hours wandering and this affects our moods, behaviours and thought processes (Killingsworth and Gilbert, 2010; Segal et al., 2018). Perhaps we should consider then, whether educational research should not start turning its flashlight to something that minds do about half of the time including in school and university and seems to affect who we are in significant ways? As I developed elsewhere (Ergas, 2018), education may be an external mind-making process determined by society, but we are also schooled in and shaped from within our own minds as we become absorbed in the content they produce constantly. These ideas open additional strands of critique that emerge at the intersection of mindfulness of education and critical pedagogy. As Magee (2016) writes: ‘each of us teaching in traditional educational settings almost inevitably reenacts and re-inscribes prevailing cultural norms and imperatives’ (p. 11). In other words, when education makes minds through its contemporary functional-economic role this may well imply social reproduction, because minds are made to project socio-cultural norms to the next generation. Forbes (2019) and Magee (2016) hence describe a variety of ways in which mindfulness and other contemplative practices extend critical pedagogy to engage directly with the mind that has been made by education. It is this mind that reads reality through and enacts prejudice, bias and privilege. Forbes (2019) calls for re-grounding the practice in its Buddhist socially-engaged civic ethics in his critique of mindfulness in education as encouraging self-indulgence. Relevant implementations to this domain, which are still rare, begin to demonstrate such potential. Mindfulness practice implemented within the context of the Israeli-Palestinian conflict led to increased support for political compromise in adults (Alkoby et al., 2017) and to reduced affective prejudice and other group stereotyping in fourth and fifth grade students (Berger et al., 2018). These varieties of mindfulness of education present its role as an inherently worthwhile educational activity that opens new possibilities for critique. They grant us the possibility of engaging in a radical act of stepping away from thoughts and reasoning to inform our ways of individual and social critique and engagement. They connect with the first narrative for they bring forth an ethos of liberation, which is mutual to the Buddha’s teachings and to critical pedagogy. Critically considering mindfulness of education, however, the more libertarian and critical it gets, the more resistance it will face from the very systems that it seeks to change. Its implementations are thus likely to exist only in educational settings that are willing to face radical challenges to their foundations. Socrates paid with his life for such deeds. Are we willing to go there two and a half millennia later? C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 Three Roles of Mindfulness in Education 355 CONCLUSION Mindfulness practice can be depicted based on three core facets, which can be grounded within the therapeutic-economic narrative (as a tool) or within the Buddhist narrative (as a path). Education meets the former as an economic-functionalist process of socialisation characterising contemporary times. In this more common case it enables mindfulness in education—a limited modality that is critiqued for addressing problems that the system itself creates, yet a glance from within may reveal that it is more transformative than realised. Education meets mindfulness as a path when it is itself construed as a path and enables for mindfulness as education—an approach that reflects the inherent worthwhileness of the practice itself. For this to be applicable in contemporary public education it needs a narrative that is not Buddhist but rather Educational. Such possibility emerges given certain interpretations of the core facets of the practice. Mindfulness of education brings forth the most radical possibility in which mindfulness is embraced as a practice that radicalises the act of critique. From this perspective, the mind that has been made by education becomes the object of the critique seeking individual and social liberation. The three roles proposed for mindfulness advance from relative conformity to radicality. They reflect different potentials that are there to be explored. Mindfulness in education is the most common, however, the other two hold the more transformative and radical potential inherent in the practice. Yet the seeds of radicality are there present in the core facets of the practice. In that sense, mindfulness in education may be more radical than we realise. Is it sustaining the box of contemporary education or reconstructing education from within? It may be worth remembering that the fact that we are getting more used to the idea that students and/or teachers spend time in schools and universities attending to their breaths and examining their interiority, even within an intervention, is quite radical. Twenty years ago, this would have been unheard of. Correspondence: Dr. Oren Ergas, Faculty of Education, Beit Berl College, Kfar Sava, 44905, Israel. Email: orenergas1@gmail.com NOTES 1. https://mindfulnessinschools.org/about/about-us/ 2. http://myriadproject.org/schools/ 3. https://trialsjournal.biomedcentral.com/articles/10.1186/s13063-017-1917-4 4. https://www.peaceinschools.org/videos/, https://mindfulnessinschools.org/ REFERENCES Alkoby, A., Halperin, E., Tarrasch, R. and Levit-Binnun, N. (2017). Increased Support for Political Compromise in the Israeli-Palestinian Conflict Following an 8-Week Mindfulness Workshop. Mindfulness, 8.5, pp. 1345–1353. Aloni, N. (2007). Enhancing Humanity: The Philosophical Foundations of Humanistic Education Vol. 9 (Dordrecht, Springer). C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 356 O. Ergas Bakosh, L. S., Snow, R. M., Tobias, J. M., Houlihan, J. L and Barbosa-Leiker, C. (2016). Maximizing Mindful Learning: Mindful Awareness Intervention Improves Elementary School Students’ Quarterly Grades. Mindfulness, 7.1, pp. 59–67. Berger, R., Brenick, A. and Tarrasch, R. (2018). Reducing Israeli-Jewish Pupils’ Outgroup Prejudice with a Mindfulness and Compassion-Based Social-Emotional Program. Mindfulness, 9.6, pp. 1768–1779. Biesta, G. (2009). Good Education in an Age of Measurement: On the Need to Reconnect with the Question of Purpose in Education. Educational Assessment, Evaluation and Accountability (formerly: Journal of Personnel Evaluation in Education), 21.1, pp. 33–46. Bishop, S. R., Lau, M., Shapiro, S., Carlson, L., Anderson, N. D., Carmody, J., . . . and Devins, G. (2004). Mindfulness: A Proposed Operational Definition. Clinical Psychology: Science and Practice, 11.3, pp. 230–241. Burnett, R. (2011). Mindfulness in Schools: Learning Lessons from the Adults, Secular and Buddhist. Buddhist Studies Review, 28, pp. 79–120. Carsley, D., Khoury, B. and Heath, N. L. (2018). Effectiveness of Mindfulness Interventions for Mental Health in Schools: a Comprehensive Meta-analysis. Mindfulness, 9.3, pp. 693–707. Condon, P., Desbordes, G., Miller, W. B. and DeSteno, D. (2013). Meditation Increases Compassionate Responses To Suffering. Psychological Science, 24.10, pp. 2125–2127. Conze, E. (1956). Buddhist Meditation (London, George Allen and Unwin). Crain, T. L., Schonert-Reichl, K. A. and Roeser, R. W. (2017). Cultivating Teacher Mindfulness: Effects of a Randomized Controlled Trial on Work, Home, and Sleep Outcomes. Journal of Occupational Health Psychology, 22.2, pp. 138–152. Cullen, M. (2011). Mindfulness-based Interventions: An Emerging Phenomenon. Mindfulness, 2.3, pp. 186–193. Davidson, R.J., Dunne, J., Eccles, J.S., Engle, A., Greenberg, M., Jennings, P., Jha, A., Jinpa, T., Lantieri, L., Meyer, D., Roeser, R.W. and Vago, D. (2012) Contemplative Practices and Mental Training: Prospects for American Education. Child Development Perspectives, 6.2, pp. 146–153. Eisner, E. W. (1993). Forms of Understanding and the Future of Educational Research. Educational Researcher, 22.7, pp. 5–11. Eisner, E. W. (1994). The Educational Imagination: On the Design and Evaluation of School Programs 3rd ed. (New York, Macmillan). Eppert, C. (2013). Awakening Education: Toward a Rich Tapestry of Mindful and Contemplative Engagement for Social/Environmental Transformation, in: J. Lin, R. Oxford and S. Brantmeier (eds) Re-envisioning Higher Education (Charlotte, NC, Information Age Publishing), pp. 337– 352. Ergas, O. (2013). Descartes in a ‘Headstand’: Introducing ‘Body-Oriented Pedagogy’, Philosophical Inquiry in Education (formerly Paideusis), 21.1, pp. 4–12. Ergas, O. (2017). Reconstructing’Education’Through Mindful Attention: Positioning the Mind at the center of curriculum and Pedagogy (London, Palgrave Macmillan). Ergas, O. (2018). Schooled in our Own Minds: Mind-wandering and Mindfulness in the Makings of the Curriculum. Journal of Curriculum Studies, 50.1, pp. 77–95. Ergas, O. and Hadar, L. L. (2019). Mindfulness In and As Education: A Map of a Developing Academic Discourse from 2002 to 2017. Review of Education. https://doi.org/10.1002/rev3.3169 Flook, L., Goldberg, S. B., Pinger, L., Bonus, K. and Davidson, R. J. (2013). Mindfulness for Teachers: A Pilot Study to Assess Effects on Stress, Burnout, and Teaching Efficacy. Mind, Brain, and Education, 7.3, pp. 182–195. Forbes, D., (2019). Mindfulness and its Discontents (New York, Fernwood Publishing). Frankel, I. (2008). Attention without Disorder. Hed Hachinuch, 93, pp. 96–99 (in Hebrew). Gethin, R. (2011). On Some Definitions of Mindfulness. Contemporary Buddhism, 12.01, pp. 263– 279. Gilead, T. (2015). Economics Imperialism and the Role of Educational Philosophy. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 7.47, pp. 715–733. Hanh, T. N. and Weare, K. (2017). Happy Teachers Change The World: A Guide for Cultivating Mindfulness in Education (London, Parallax Press). Hyland, T. (2013). Buddhist Practice and Educational Endeavour: In Search of a Secular Spirituality for State-funded Education in England. Ethics and Education, 8.3, pp. 241–252. C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 Three Roles of Mindfulness in Education 357 Hyland, T. (2016). The Limits of Mindfulness: Emerging Issues for Education. British Journal of Educational Studies, 64.1, pp. 97–117. Hyland, T. (2017). McDonaldizing Spirituality: Mindfulness, Education, and Consumerism. Journal of Transformative Education, 15.4, pp. 1–20. James, W. (1981[1890]). The Principles of Psychology (Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press). James, W. (1962). Psychology the Briefer Course (New York, Collier Books). Jennings, P. A. (2015). Mindfulness for Teachers (New York, WW Norton & Company). Jennings, P. A. (2016). Mindfulness-based Programs and the American Public School System: Recommendations for Best Practices To Ensure Secularity. Mindfulness, 7.1, pp. 176–178. Jennings, P. A., Brown, J. L., Frank, J. L., Doyle, S., Oh, Y., Davis, R., . . . and Greenberg, M. T. (2017). Impacts of the CARE for Teachers Program on Teachers’ Social and Emotional Competence and Classroom Interactions. Journal of Educational Psychology, 109.7, p. 1010. Kabat-Zinn, J. (2005). Full Catastrophe Living (New York, Delta Trade Paperbacks). Kabat-Zinn, J. (2011). Some Reflections on the Origins of MBSR, Skillful Means, and the Trouble with Maps. Contemporary Buddhism, 12.01, pp. 281–306. Kaufman, P. (2017). Critical Contemplative Pedagogy. Radical Pedagogy, 14.1, pp. 1–20. Killingsworth, M. A. and Gilbert, D. T. (2010). A Wandering Mind is an Unhappy Mind. Science, 330.6006, pp. 932–932. Komjathy, L. (2018). Introducing Contemplative Studies (Oxford, UK, John Wiley & Sons). Lewin, D. (2017). Educational Philosophy for a Post-secular Age (London, Routledge). Lomas, T., Medina, J. C., Ivtzan, I., Rupprecht, S. and Eiroa-Orosa, F. J. (2017). The Impact of Mindfulness on the Wellbeing and Performance of Educators: A Systematic Review of the Empirical Literature. Teaching and Teacher Education, 61, pp. 132–141. Magee, R. V. (2016). The Way of ColorInsight: Understanding Race and Law Effectively through Mindfulness-based ColorInsight Practices. Georgetown Journal of Law & Modern Critical Race Perspectives, 8, pp. 251–302. Mrazek, M. D., Franklin, M. S., Phillips, D. T., Baird, B. and Schooler, J. W. (2013). Mindfulness Training Improves Working Memory Capacity and GRE Performance While Reducing Mind Wandering. Psychological Science, 24.5, pp. 776–781. O’Donnell, A. (2015). Contemplative Pedagogy and Mindfulness: Developing Creative Attention in an Age of Distraction. Journal of Philosophy of Education, 49.2, pp. 187–202. Owen-Smith, P. (2017). The Contemplative Mind in the Scholarship of Teaching and Learning (Indianapolis, IN, Indiana University Press). Peters, R. S. (ed.) (1973). The Philosophy of Education (Oxford, Oxford University Press). Purser, R. and Loy, D. (2013). Beyond McMindfulness. Huffington Post, 1.7, p. 13. Petitmengin, C., Van Beek, M., Bitbol, M. and Nissou, J. M. (2017). What is it Like to Meditate? Methods and Issues for a Micro-phenomenological Description of Meditative Experience. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 24.5-6, pp. 170–198. Repetti, R. (2016). Meditation Matters: Replies to the Anti-McMindfulness Bandwagon! In: R. Purses, D. Forbes and A. Burke (eds), Handbook of Mindfulness (Dordrecht, Springer), pp. 473–493. Reveley, J. (2015). School-based Mindfulness Training and the Economisation of Attention: A Stieglerian View. Educational Philosophy and Theory, 47.8, pp. 804–821. Roeser, R. W. (2014). The Emergence of Mindfulness-based Interventions in Educational Settings, in: S. A. Karabenick and T. C Urdan, Motivational Interventions (New York, Emerald Group Publishing Limited), pp. 379–419. Roeser, R. W. and Peck, S. C. (2009). An Education in Awareness: Self, Motivation, and SelfRegulated Learning in Contemplative Perspective. Educational Psychologist, 44.2, pp. 119–136. Roth, H. D. (2006). Contemplative Studies: Prospects for a New Field. Teacher’s College Record, 108.6, pp. 1787–1815. Segal, Z. V., Williams, M. and Teasdale, J. (2018). Mindfulness-based Cognitive Therapy for Depression (New York, Guilford Publications). Sellman, E. M. and Buttarazzi, G. F. (2019). Adding Lemon Juice to Poison – Raising Critical Questions about the Oxymoronic Nature of Mindfulness in Education and its Future Direction. British Journal of Educational Studies. https://doi.org/10.1080/00071005.2019.1581128 Semple, R. J., Droutman, V. and Reid, B. A. (2017). Mindfulness Goes To School: Things Learned (So Far) from Research and Real-World Experiences. Psychology in the Schools, 54.1, pp. 29–52. C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024 358 O. Ergas Shapiro, S. L., Jazaieri, H. and Goldin, P. R. (2012). Mindfulness-based Stress Reduction Effects on Moral Reasoning and Decision Making. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 7.6, pp. 504–515. Tarrasch, R. (2015). Mindfulness Meditation Training for Graduate Students in Educational Counseling and Special Education: A Qualitative Analysis. Journal of Child and Family Studies, 24.5, pp. 1322–1333. Tarrasch, R. (2017). Mindful Schooling: Better Attention Regulation among Elementary School Children who Practice Mindfulness as Part of their School Policy. Journal of Cognitive Enhancement, 1.2, pp. 84–95. Van Dam, N. T., van Vugt, M. K., Vago, D. R., Schmalzl, L., Saron, C. D., Olendzki, A., . . . and Fox, K. C. (2018). Mind the Hype: A Critical Evaluation and Prescriptive Agenda for Research on Mindfulness and Meditation. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 13.1, pp. 36–61. Wallace, B. A. (1999). The Buddhist Tradition of Samatha: Methods for Refining and Examining Consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6.2-3, pp. 175–187. Webster-Wright, A. (2013). The Eye of the Storm: A Mindful Inquiry into Reflective Practices in Higher Education. Reflective Practice, 14.4, pp. 556–567. Wong, Y. L. R. (2004). Knowing Through Discomfort: A Mindfulness-based Critical Social Work Pedagogy. Critical Social Work, 5.1, pp. 1–9. Yates, J., Immergut, M. and Graves, J. (2017). The Mind Illuminated (Prescot, AZ, Simon and Schuster). Young, S. (2016). What is Mindfulness? A Contemplative Perspective, in: K. Schonert-Reichl and R. Roeser (eds), Handbook of Mindfulness in Education (New York, NY, Springer), pp. 29–45. Zajonc, A. (2009). Meditation as Contemplative Inquiry (Great Barrington, MA, Lindisfarne Books). Zenner, C., Herrnleben-Kurz, S. and Walach, H. (2014). Mindfulness-based Interventions in Schools—A Systematic Review and Meta-analysis. Frontiers in Psychology, 5, pp. 1–16. C 2019 The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain. Downloadedfromhttps://academic.oup.com/jope/article/53/2/340/6821499byMasarykovaUniverzitauseron11November2024