mm THREE The Textual Structure of Performance islliiiii.. W;^' -yry: I /'■■^■^■^•■vr-* The work of art aims at revealing essential or important elements, or important ideas, in a clearer and more concrete way than real objects are capable of revealing them. It succeeds in this by employing a set of interconnected parts, systematically changing the relationships between these parts. Hippolyte Tame, The Philosophy of Art Signification occurs when we submit the data of the world to a "coherent deformation." Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Signs 3.1, MULTIPLE SYSTEMS AND SINGLE SYSTEMS In the last chapter I reviewed some of the important characteristics of the performance text ("ephemeral" presence, lack of persistence, heterogeneity- of expressive media, multiplicity of codes, mmticUmenSionality) by virtue of which it is now perhaps possible to locate the performance text within the general category of semiotic texts. Up to this poult I have concentrated on the physical, visible level of performance, and will now shift my attention to the formal-systemic level, where We can locate series of theoretical entities "constructed" by the analytical-interpretive process. The most important of these entities is the textual structure of performance, a system which emerges from the combination of the various codes of the performance text, and which assures the coherence Of the code^ relations.1 My conception of the textual structure of performance Coin-cides substantially with the concept of the "textual system" elaborated by Metz in the context of the cinematic text. It is expressed in the following definition: The system has no physical existence; it is nothing more than a logic, a prin- - ■■■ ;i/;;myym^y y:\mmy,. .ASM 't fag- 84 The Semiotics of Performance dple of coherence. It is the intelligibility of the text: that which must be presupposed if the text is to be comprehensible.2 (Metz 1971: ET 75-76) Thus the basic characteristic feature of the textual structure of performance is its systematic quality. As we shall see, the performance code also belongs to the systematic level but it cannot be confused with the textual structure of performance, of which it is merely a component, because it does not possess the second characteristic of the textual structure: uniqueness. To claim that the textual structure of a given performance is "unique" is to maintain that as a particular combination of codes, it belongs, by definition, only to that performance and to that performance alone, thus guaranteeing the individuality/unrepeatability of the performance on the structural level. However,, the same cannot be said of the codes that make up the textual structure of performance: a code is, by definition, "a system which is valid for several texts/' that is, a multiple system (Metz 1971: ET 76). As we shall see in chapter 4, a particular gestural, in-tonational, or mime code may appear in different performance texts (as well as in extra-theatrica] texts). This means it can enter into different combinations with different codes. On the contrary, the textual structure of a performance such as, for example, the complete network of code relations underlying Luca Ronconi's Oresteia (1972), or, more precisely, the network underlying a single performance of the Ronconi production, belongs to this performance alone (if one concedes that it is indeed possible to "reconstitute" it), and cannot be found—in the same may, or in its entirety—in any other performance.3 According to Metz, who has the merit of having developed the distinction between "singular systems" (textual structures, in the present case) and "multiple systems" (codes), this cUstinction not only holds true for the field of performance but may constitute a general semiotic principle of great importance. [This distinction] seems to us to be of great importance for any structural analysis. ... It comes down to saying that it is the peculiarity of certain structures that they underlie entire series of events while concerning none of these events in particular (thus the code of a language is present in every sentence, narrative codes in every narrative, the typographical code in every printed page, etc.), while other structures are linked from the very beginning to unique events which they characterize and which are so to speak by definition unfit to be used again, at least not in exactly the same way. Such is the structure of a sonnet (not the sonnet form) or of a sonata (not the sonata form). (ET 76) Two further characteristics of the textual structure of performance must be kept in mind. The first is the fact that the textual structure of performance performs a single, unique combination, i.e., it combines in an unrepeatable way codes that are variously specific and codes that are variously nonspecific at the same time (Metz uses the word mixite in this The Textual Structure of Performance 85 context). Obviously, this characteristic is also common to the performance text as a concrete discursive event. Finally, we must consider the dynamic quality of the textual structure of performance, which almost never limits itself to assembling the codes in a static manner, but combines them instead in an original way, and in the process of relating them to each other ■"restructures"' and "transforms" them. 3.2. DEGREES OF DYNAMISM IN THE TEXTUAL STRUCTURE OF PERFORMANCE The textual structure of a performance is therefore something more than simply the sum of the codes that create it. This "something more" is actually the result of the process of restructuring, or deplacement (Metz), that it exerts on the codes.4 The distinction that I will draw in 4.6. between "performance codes" in the strict sense and "theatrical conventions," as well as my definition of the role played by the conventions, will enable me to confirm my current assertion regarding the dynamic quality of the textual structure of performance. It will also allow me to define Metz's rather ineffable deplacement of the codes within a given performance in more concrete terms as a deviation from their extra-theatrical usage, as the consequences of the action of the "theatrical conventions" of that performance.5 Leaving out the kinds of conventions that are dominant in a particular performance text, and hence their effect on the extra-theatrical codes (see 4.7.), we can already see that the degree to which the performance codes in the performance text in question deviate from their extra-theatrical use depends, quite predictably, on the extent to which the textual structure is capable of dynamically integrating these performance codes. Let us consider, for example, the theatrical productions of the historical avant-garde, and especially the movement generally known as "director's theater." From about the middle of the last century when the director's role began to assert itself as an aesthetic principle rather than simply as empirical practice, directors have explicitly aimed at creating a mise-en-scene understood as a unified work of art, created from the fusion of various expressive media (words, music, dance, painting) to form an indivisible, homogeneous whole, where the basic elements undergo a more or less radical transformation. Wagner's Gesamtkunstxoerk constitutes the most explicit and extreme theorization in this direction. As for examples of the same phenomenon on the level of praxis, I should at least mention (apart from the work of Craig and Appia, both theorists rather than practitioners) the outstanding period in Russian theater during and after the revolution (Mejerchol'd, Tairov, Evreinov, Vachtangov), the productions of Piscator and Brecht, the experiments of Gropius, Schlemmer, and Moholy-Nagy at the Bauhaus, the important theatrical innovators in France (Copeau, Dullin, Artaud, Bar- 86 The Semiotics of Performance rault), right down to the current (but rarely exciting) practice of director's theater.6 In other cases, however, the disparity between the performance code and the extra-theatrical code may be very slight, and sometimes may not even seem to exist. Apart from the (fundamental) role played by the type of theatrical conventions used, this situation is generally linked to a (significant) reduction in the dynamic power proper to the textual structure of performance. This reduction means that a diagram of the code relations would take on the shape of a simple juxtaposition rather than a hierarchical interrelationship. Even in this case there are many examples. To begin, we could consider the widely independent status enjoyed paratactically by the partial texts that form the basis of a large number of festivals in the Western tradition, festivals that range from aristocratic and courtly celebrations of the Renaissance and baroque periods, to folk festivals past and present. Instrumental music, songs, poetry, dances, costumes, emblems, and images are blended together in the festivals. These elements originate before and continue after the festival itself, and are to a great extent autonomous and independent. In such cases, the degree of integration and restructuring of the codes in the performance tends to approach zero (without ever quite reaching zero, as we shall see later). The Renaissance festival provides an example of this phenomenon, and is described by the most up-to-date theatrical historiography as a "set of autonomous forms of expression in their highest state of development" (Cruciani 1972: 9), or as a form of "architecture in time, catalyzing the diverse elements that appear within it, elements that are among the most distinguished in various art forms, customs, and activities" (Cruciani and Taviani 1980: 35). One of these forms of expression, or highly distinguished elements (in fact, the most important of them), is comedy, which maintains a relationship of mutual legitimation with the festival: Classical comedy appears in the context of the festival not because it is particularly entertaining (indeed it is often experienced by witnesses as one of the most boring moments), but because it is an outstanding example of the new culture's rediscovery of antiquity. Thus on the one hand the festival, as a form of architecture in time, gives meaning to the presence of the comedy, while on the other hand the comedy gives its "blessing" to the festival, by representing a link with a body of artistic work based in an era that transcends the contemporary. (1980: 35)7 In Renaissance productions of ancient and contemporary comedy, various partial texts with their relative codes are often endowed with considerable autonomy, and are not intended to function as an illustration of the content of the texts. This can be seen, for example, in the costumes, and especially in the stage scenery, which was' allowed a very narrow range of rigidly preestablished possibilities (comic, tragic, and satirical scenes). The aim of the scenery was not to visualize the locations of the dramatic action, The Textual Structure of Performance 87 but rather to offer an image of a more or less idealized city (Ruffini 1978a: 164).8 In our own times we can find very obvious examples of performances where the partial texts and codes are integrated with scarcely any dynamic intensity (with a consequently insignificant diplacement of the codes) in the many-faceted movement of experimental theater which began with "happenings" and pop art in the 1950s and 1960s, evolved through the 1968 experiences of street theater and improvisation, and continues today with the most recent offerings of the so-called post-avant-garde and trans-avant-garde (performance art, conceptual theater, and the like). Despite the great diversity of their poetics and techniques, all of these phenomena have two features in common. First, they all create a conglomeration of different "elements/' where incoherence and (perhaps only superficial) discontinuity are frequently emphasized in a provocative way9 (for example, the already mentioned "compartmental structure" of "happenings" and environmental performances by Kaprow, Oldenburg, and Whitman, but also the "pieces" created by Robert Wilson and subsequently rearranged in different ways for his new performances). Following the example of Duch-amp's technique of the "ready-made," the second feature that the avant-garde experiments have in common is the use of objects, images, gestures, and forms of behavior taken "as they are" from daily life and assigned new communicative intentionalities, as well as strong "aesthetic" connotations, thanks to the distancing procedure of decontextualization/ recontextualization with which they are presented. The aesthetic process of display and staging constitutes them as signifiers available for numerous new sign-correlations. To give just two examples, I will mention Rauschen-berg's assemblages in the late 1950s and Oldenburg's sensational Autobodys in 1963. Regarding the distinctions I articulated on the dynamic quality of the textual structure of performance, it is useful to recall the opposition that Ruffini (1978a) observes between "mise-en-scene" and "placing on stage," based on the binary opposition of functionaHty/nonfunctionality. According to Ruffini, we can speak of "placing something on stage" when "the text transferred simply ends up juxtaposed with other partial texts without significant amounts of reciprocal interference" (1978a: 130). Ruifini cites the following as examples of "placing on stage": the newscast, the ceremonial, and some Renaissance comedies. On the other hand, he perceives the presence of "mise-en-scene" when "the transcriptive codes are functional-ized to serve the content of the text," as in "director's theater," or in "public speaking." Ruffini's hypothesis also makes the already mentioned connection between the extent to which the codes of the textual structure of performance are integrated and the extent to which they deviate from extra-theatrical usage. "While adherence to different norms is the basis of -placing something on stage, in the case of mise-en-scene, by contrast, there is a sense of breaking all cliches" (131-32). Obviously, the contrast that Ruffini draws is meant to be understood and used only as a theoretical polar- 88 The Semiotics of Performance ity, and concrete examples must be located along the intermediate points of an infiriite continuum. In fact I believe that no real examples of "zero-degree" integration-deviation can be found. Even in the extreme cases of "happenings" and performance art there is usually a new context to "modify" the real, everyday element I have mentioned, preventing it from being perceived in a completely automatic way. The act of ostension always makes some of the concrete traits pertinent at the expense of others, by constituting the object as a functive capable of becoming the vehicle of new meanings.10 We should also bear in mind that the Renaissance festival {another of Ruffinf s examples of "placing on stage") assembles the autonomous expressive forms that come together within it into a "different," "detached" time-space, which is the ideál time-space of celebration, thus modifying the semantic valences (and in particular the ideological valences) of the elements used with a kind of Metziah déplace-ment: What qualifies and unifies the various forms of the festival's expression is their being positioned as celebration. This celebration is not only the superficial occasion, the honoring of some person or some moment of the year; it has instead the much weightier value that I have mentioned: it is the ideal time for the society to take a look at itself in its "eternal" dimension, it projects itself into its own Utopia . . .: it is the "well-regulated city." (Cruciani 1972:11) Although Cruciani also insists a great deal on the autonomy of the different forms of expression that converge in the festive event as a whole, he mentions the festival several times as a "complex system" or as a "structuring'' and "formalizing" unit which does not limit itself to the paratactic assembly of elements from different sources but which—within limits-reorganizes these elements, redefining their function and meaning as they are brought together.11 3.3. PARTIAL STRUCTURES AND MACROSTRUCTURES Up to this point I have alluded to the textual structure of performance in the singular, as if each performance has only one structure. There are nevertheless two kinds of completely different though compatible considerations that lead me to postulate a (limited) multiplicity of the textual structures of every performance text. The first consideration is of an objective nature and concerns the already mentioned macro-textual character of the performance text, the fact that it really consists of the interweaving or juxtaposition of various partial texts, each one of which can be in turn endowed (and generally is endowed) with an already complex system of codes; and hence with a textual structure (i.e., a partial textual structure). For example, one can easily suppose that the scenographic text of a stage set in a baroque theater was organized by a perspective code, an iconographic code, a proxemic The Textual Structure of Performance 89 code, as well as by various conventions of genre (see 4.6.2.). The homology between the performance text and the textual structure of performance is perfect in this case also. Just as the performance text is in reality a macro-text (as we have seen), the entity that I called the textual structure of performance represents in fact a structure of structures, a macrostruc-ture (naturally not in van Dijk's semantic application), i.e., "a complex system made of reciprocal mterweavings, interrelations, and inscriptions of specific systems which are in themselves already complex" (Bettetini 1977: 26). There is nevertheless a problem with the hypothesis that several partial textual structures are manifest within the performance text and organized into a complex macrostructure. If the textual structure of a performance is "unique" as I have claimed, that is, if it actually belongs to one performance text and only to one, what is the situation of the partial textual structures that constitute it? Are these similarly unique or not? And, if they are not, can they be considered textual structures in the proper sense, since they lack a characteristic that we have seen to be constitutive of textual structures? The dilemma is not easily resolved, and perhaps cannot be resolved once and for all. Only several concrete analyses carried out according to the theoretical framework that I am in the process of delineating will succeed in resolving this and other problems that remain open at the moment. However, in a hypothetical and purely provisional way, let us imagine the possibility superficially suggested by several factors that "uniqueness" or "singularity" is not one of the properties of partial textual structures. This is equivalent to supposing, for example, that the multi-coded system underlying the gestural text of a given performance can appear basically unchanged in the gestural texts of other performances. It means, in other words, that two or more performances can present identical partial texts (in the obvious sense of being structurally identical).12 This assumption seems easy to verify in performances belonging to genres that are strongly coded and hence highly standardized. Let us take, for example, the gestural codes in Sicilian puppet theater (Pasqualino's 3978 study distinguishes four types of movement made by these puppets), noting that the gestures remain almost unchanged from one performance to the next, at least within the various schools and traditions (it is widely known that the movements of puppets in the Palermo tradition are not the same as the movements of puppets in Naples or Catania). Or we could consider various forms of repertory theater, also rigidly defined, from tnudra to Indian classical dance, and from the over-coded kinesis of nineteenth