Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Sewanee Review. http://www.jstor.org The Intentional Fallacy Author(s): W. K. Wimsatt Jr. and M. C. Beardsley Source: The Sewanee Review, Vol. 54, No. 3 (Jul. - Sep., 1946), pp. 468-488 Published by: Johns Hopkins University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/27537676 Accessed: 22-02-2016 06:25 UTC Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/ info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY By W. K. WIMSATT, JR. and M. C. BEARDSLEY He owns with toil he wrote the following scenes; But, if they're naught, ne'er spare him for his pains: Damn him the more; have no commiseration For dullness on mature deliberation. William Congreve, Prologue to The Way of the World THE claim of the author's "intention" upon the critic's judgment has been challenged in a number of recent dis cussions, notably in the debate entitled The Personal Heresy, between Professors Lewis and Tillyard, and at least im plicitly in periodical essays like those in the "Symposiums" of 1940 in the Southern and Kenyon Reviews.1 But it seems doubt ful if this claim and most of its romantic corollaries are as yet subject to any widespread questioning. The present writers, in a short article entitled "Intention" for a Dictionary2 of literary criticism, raised the issue but were unable to pursue its implica tions at any length. We argued that the design or intention of the author is neither available nor desirable as a standard for judging the success of a work of literary art, and it seems to us that this is a principle which goes deep into some differences in the history of critical attitudes. It is a principle which accepted or rejected points to the polar opposites of classical "imitation" and romantic expression. It entails many specific truths about inspiration, authenticity, biography, literary history and scholar ship, and about some trends of contemporary poetry, especially its allusiveness. There is hardly a problem of literary criticism inwhich the critic's approach will not be qualified by his view of "intention." "Intention," as we shall use the term, corresponds to what he intended in a formula which more or less explicitly has had wide acceptance. "In order to judge the poet's performance, we must This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 469 know what he intended." Intention is design or plan in the au thor's mind. Intention has obvious affinities for the author's at titude toward his work, the way he felt, what made him write. We begin our discussion with a series of propositions sum marized and abstracted to a degree where they seem to us axio matic, if not truistic. 1. A poem does not come into existence by accident. The words of a poem, as Professor Stoll has remarked, come out of a head, not out of a hat. Yet to insist on the designing intellect as a cause of a poem is not to grant the design or intention as a standard. 2. One must ask how a critic expects to get an answer to the question about intention. How is he to find out what the poet tried to do? If the poet succeeded indoing it, then the poem itself shows what he was trying to do. And if the poet did not succeed, then the poem is not adequate evidence, and the critic must go outside the poem?for evidence of an intention that did not be come effective in the poem. "Only one caveat must be borne in mind," says an eminent intentionalist3 in a moment when his the ory repudiates itself; "the poet's aim must be judged at the mo ment of the creative act, that is to say, by the art of the poem itself." 3. Judging a poem is like judging a pudding or a machine. One demands that it work. It is only because an artifact works that we infer the intention of an artificer. "A poem should not mean but be." A poem can be only through its meaning?since itsmedium iswords?yet it isy simply is, in the sense that we have no excuse for inquiring what part is intended or meant.4 Poetry is a feat of style by which a complex of meaning is handled all at once. Poetry succeeds because all or most of what is said or implied is relevant; what is irrelevant has been excluded, like lumps from pudding and "bugs" from machinery. In this re spect poetry differs from practical messages, which are success This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 470 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY ful if and only if we correctly infer the intention. They are more abstract than poetry. 4. The meaning of a poem may certainly be a personal one, in the sense that a poem expresses a personality or state of soul rather than, a physical object like an apple. But even a short lyric poem is dramatic, the response of a speaker (no matter how abstractly conceived) to a situation (no matter how universal ized). We ought to impute the thoughts and attitudes of the poem immediately to the dramatic speaker, and if to the author at all, only by a biographical act of inference. 5. If there is any sense in which an author, by revision, has better achieved his original intention, it is only the very abstract, tautological, sense that he intended to write a better work and now has done it. (In this sense every author's intention is the same.) His former specific intention was not his intention. "He's the man we were in search of, that's true"; says Hardy's rustic constable, "and yet he's not the man we were in search of. For the man we were in search of was not the man we wanted."5 "Is not a critic," asks Professor Stoll, "... a judge, who does not explore his own consciousness, but determines the author's meaning or intention, as if the poem were a will, a contract, or the constitution? The poem is not the critic's own."8 He has diagnosed very accurately two forms of irresponsibility, one which he prefers. Our view is yet different. The poem is not the critic's own and not the author's (it is detached from the author at birth and goes about the world beyond his power to intend about it or control it). The poem belongs to the public. It is embodied in language, the peculiar possession of the public, and it is about the human being, an object of public knowledge. What is said about the poem is subject to the same scrutiny as any statement in linguistics or in the general science of psychology or morals. Mr. Richards has aptly called the poem a class? "a class of experiences which do not differ in any character more This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 471 than a certain amount . . . from a standard experience." And he adds, "We may take as this standard experience the relevant experience of the poet when contemplating the completed com position." Professor Wellek in a fine essay on the problem has preferred to call the poem "a system of norms," "extracted from every individual experience," and he objects to Mr. Richards' deference to the poet as reader. We side with Professor Wellek in not wishing to make the poet (outside the poem) an authority. A critic of our Dictionary article, Mr. Ananda K. Coomara swamy, has argued7 that there are two kinds of enquiry about a wrork of art: (1) whether the artist achieved his intentions; (2) whether the work of art "ought ever to have been undertaken at all" and so "whether it is worth preserving." Number (2), Mr. Coomaraswamy maintains, is not "criticism of any work of art qua work of art," but is rather moral criticism; number (1) is artistic criticism. But we maintain that (2) need not be moral criticism: that there is another way of deciding whether works of art are worth preserving and whether, in a sense, they "ought" to have been undertaken, and this is the way of objective criticism of works of art as such, the way which enables us to distinguish between a skilful murder and a skilful poem. A skilful murder is an example which Mr. Coomaraswamy uses, and in his system the difference between the murder and the poem is simply a "moral" one, not an "artistic" one, since each if carried out ac cording to plan is "artistically" successful. We maintain that (2) is an enquiry of more worth than (1), and since (2), and not (1) is capable of distinguishing poetry from murder, the name "artistic criticism" is properly given to (2). II It is not so much an empirical as an analytic judgment, not a historical statement, but a definition, to say that the intentional fallacy is a romantic one. When a rhetorician, presumably of the first century A.D., writes: "Sublimity is the echo of a great soul," This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 472 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY or tells us that "Homer enters into the sublime actions of his heroes" and "shares the full inspiration of the combat," we shall not be surprised to find this rhetorician considered as a distant harbinger of romanticism and greeted in the warmest terms by so romantic a critic as Saintsbury. One may wish to argue whether Longinus should be called romantic,8 but there can hardly be a doubt that in one important way he is. Goethe's three questions for "'constructive criticism" are "What did the author set out to do? Was his plan reasonable and sensi ble, and how far did he succeed in carrying it out?" If one leaves out the middle question, one has in effect the system of Croce? the culmination and crowning philosophic expression of roman ticism. The beautiful is the successful intuition-expression, and the ugly is the unsuccessful; the intuition or private part of art it the aesthetic fact, and the medium or public part in not the subject of aesthetic at all. Yet aesthetic reproduction takes place only "if all the other conditions remain equal." Oil-paintings grow dark, frescoes fade, statues lose noses . . . the text of a poem is corrupted by bad copyists or bad print ing. The Madonna of Cimabue is still in the Church of Santa Maria Novella; but does she speak to the visitor of to-day as to the Florentines of the thirteenth century? Historical interpretation labours ... to reintegrate in us the psychological conditions which have changed in the course of history. It . . . enables us to see a work of art (a physical object) as its author saw it in the moment of production.9 The first italics are Croce's, the second ours. The upshot of Croce's system is an ambiguous emphasis on history. With such passages as a point of departure a critic may write a close analysis of the meaning or "spirit" of a play of Shakespeare or Corneille ?a process that involves close historical study but remains aes This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 473 thetic criticism?or he may write sociology, biography, or other kinds of non-aesthetic history. The Crocean system seems to have given more of a boost to the latter way of writing. "What has the poet tried to do," asks Spingarn in his 1910 Columbia Lecture from which we have already quoted, "and how has he fulfilled his intention?" The place to look for "in superable" ugliness, says Bosanquet, in his third Lecture of 1914, is the "region of insincere and affected art." The seepage of the theory into a non-philosophic place may be seen in such a book as Marguerite Wilkinson's inspirational New Voices, about the poetry of 1919 to 1931?where symbols "as old as the ages . . . retain their strength and freshness" through "Realization." We close this section with two examples from quarters where one might least expect a taint of the Crocean. Mr. I. A. Richards' fourfold distinction of meaning into "sense," "feeling," "tone," "intention" has been probably the most influential statement of intentionalism in the past fifteen years, though it contains a hint of self-repudiation: "This function [intention]," says Mr. Rich ards, "is not on all fours with the others." In an essay on "Three Types of Poetry" Mr. Allen T?te writes as follows: We must understand that the lines Life like a dome of many-colored glass Stains the white radiance of eternity are not poetry; they express the frustrated will trying to compete with science. The will asserts a rhetorical proposition about the whole of life, but the imagination has not seized upon the mater ials of the poem and made them into a whole. Shel ley's simile is imposed upon the material from above; it does not grow out of the material. The last sentence contains a promise of objective analysis which is not fulfilled. The reason why the essay relies so heavily throughout on the terms "will" and "imagination" is that Mr. T?te is accusing the romantic poets of a kind of insincerity (ro This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 474 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY manticism in reverse) and at the same time is trying to describe something mysterious and perhaps indescribable, an "imaginative whole of life," a "wholeness of vision at a particular moment of experience," something which "yields us the quality of the experience." If a poet had a toothache at the moment of con ceiving a poem, that would be part of the experience, but Mr. T?te of course does not mean anything like that. He is think ing about some kind of "whole" which in this essay at least he does not describe, but which doubtless it is the prime need of criticism to describe?in terms that may be publicly tested. Ill I went to the poets; tragic, dithyrambic, and all sorts. . . . I took them some of the most elaborate passages in their own writings, and asked what was the meaning of them. . . . Will you believe me? . . . there is hardly a person present who would not have talked better about their poetry than they did themselves. Then I knew that not by wisdom do poets write poetry, but by a sort of genius and inspiration. That reiterated mistrust of the poets which we hear from Socrates mav have been part of a rigorously ascetic view in which we hardly wish to participate, yet Plato's Socrates saw a truth about the poetic mind which the world no longer commonly sees? so much criticism, and that the most inspirational and most affec tionately remembered, has proceeded from the poets themselves. Certainly the poets have had something to say that the ana lyst and professor could not say; their message has been more exciting: that poetry should come as naturally as leaves to a tree, that poetry is the lava of the imagination, or that it is emotion recollected in tranquillity. But it is necessary that we realize the character and authority of such testimony. There is only a fine shade between those romantic expressions and a kind of earnest advice that authors often give. Thus Edward Young, Carlyle, Walter Pater: This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 475 I know two golden rules from ethicsy which are no less golden in Composition, than in life. 1. Know thyself; 2dly, Reverence thyself. This is the grand secret for finding readers and retaining them: let him who would move and convince others, be first moved and convinced himself. Horace's rule, Si vis me flerey is applicable in a wider sense than the literal one. To every poet, to every writer, we might say: Be true, if you would be believed. Truth! there can be no merit, no craft at all, without that. And further, all beauty is in the long run only fineness of truth, or what we call expression, the finer accommodation of speech to that vision within. And Housman's little handbook to the poetic mind yields the following illustration: Having drunk a pint of beer at luncheon?beer is a sedative to the brain, and my afternoons are the least intellectual portion of my life?I would go out for a walk of two or three hours. As I went along, thinking of nothing in par ticular, only looking at things around me and following the progress of the seasons, there would flow into my mind, writh sudden and unaccountable emotion, sometimes a line or two of verse, sometimes a whole stanza at once. . . . This is the logical terminus of the series already quoted. Here is a confession of how poems were written which would do as a definition of poetry just as well as "emotion recollected in tranquillity"?and which the young poet might equally well take to heart as a practical rule. Drink a pint of beer, relax, go walking, think on nothing in particular, look at things, surrender yourself to yourself, search for the truth in your own soul, listen to the sound of your own inside voice, discover and express the vraie v?rit?. 2 This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 476 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY It is probably true that all this is excellent advice for poets. The young imagination fired by Wordsworth and Carlyle is probably closer to the verge of producing a poem than the mind of the student who has been sobered by Aristotle or Richards. The art of inspiring poets, or at least of inciting something like poetry in young persons, has probably gone further in our day than ever before. Books of creative writing such as those issued from the Lincoln School are interesting evidence of what a child can do if taught how to manage himself honestly.10 All this, however, would appear to belong to an art separate from criticism, or to a discipline which one might call the psychology of com position, valid and useful, an individual and private culture, yoga, or system of self-development which the young poet would do well to notice, but different from the public science of evaluating poems, Coleridge and Arnold were better critics than most poets have been, and if the critical tendency dried up the poetry in Arnold and perhaps in Coleridge, it is not inconsistent with our argu ment, which is that judgment of poems is different from the art of producing them. Coleridge has given us the classic "anodyne" story, and tells what he can about the genesis of a poem which he calls a "psychological curiosity," but his definitions of poetry and of the poetic quality "imagination" are to be found else where and in quite other terms. The day may arrive when the psychology of composition is unified with the science of objective evaluation, but so far they are separate. It would be convenient if the passwords of the intentional school, "sincerity," "fidelity," "spontaneity," "au thenticity," "genuineness," "originality," could be equated with terms of analysis such as "integrity," "relevance," "unity," "func tion"; with "maturity," "subtlety," and "adequacy," and other more precise axiological terms?in short, if "expression" always meant aesthetic communication. But this is not so. "Aesthetic" art, says Professor Curt Ducasse, an ingenious This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 477 theorist of expression, is the conscious objectification of feelings, in which an intrinsic part is the critical moment. The artist cor rects the objectification when it is not adequate, but this may mean that the earlier attempt was not successful in objectifying the self, or "it may also mean that it was a successful objectification of a self which, when it confronted us clearly, we disowned and repudiated in favor of another."11 What is the standard by which we disown or accept the self? Professor Ducasse does not say. Whatever itmay be, however, this standard is an element in the definition of art which will not reduce to terms of objectification. The evaluation of the work of art remains public; the work is measured against something outside the author. IV There is criticism of poetry and there is, as we have seen, author psychology, which when applied to the present or future takes the form of inspirational promotion; but author psychology can be historical too, and then we have literary biography, a legitimate and attractive study in itself, one approach, as Mr. Tillyard would argue, to personality, the poem being only a parallel approach. Certainly it need not be with a derogatory purpose that one points out personal studies, as distinct from poetic studies, in the realm of literary scholarship. Yet there is danger of confusing personal and poetic studies; and there is the fault of writing the personal as if it were poetic. There is a difference between internal and external evidence for the meaning of a poem. And the paradox is only verbal and superficial that what is (1) internal is also public: it is dis covered through the semantics and syntax of a poem, through our habitual knowledge of the language, through grammars, dictionaries, and all the literature which is the source of diction aries, in general through all that makes a language and culture; while what is (2) external is private or idiosyncratic; not a part of the work as a linguistic fact: it consists of revelations (in This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 478 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY journals, for example, or letters or reported conversations) about how or why the poet wrote the poem?to what lady, while sitting on what lawn, or at the death of what friend or brother. There is (3) an intermediate kind of evidence about the character of the author or about private or semi-private meanings attached to words or topics by an author or by a coterie of which he is a member. The meaning of words is the history of words, and the biography of an author, his use of a word, and the associations which the word had for him, are part of the word's history and meaning.12 But the three types of evidence, especially (2) and (3), shade into one another so subtly that it is not always easy to draw a line between examples, and hence arises the difficulty for criticism. The use of biographical evidence need not involve intentionalism, because while it may be evidence of what the author intended, it may also be evidence of the meaning of his words and the dramatic character of his utterance. On the other hand, itmay not be all this. And a critic who is concerned with evidence of type (1) and moderately with that of type (3) will in the long run produce a different sort of comment from that of the criticwho is concerned with type (2) and with (3) where it shades into (2). The whole glittering parade of Professor Lowes' Road to Xanadu, for instance, runs along the border between types (2) and (3) or boldly traverses the romantic region of (2). " cKubla Khan'," says Professor Lowes, "is the fabric of a vision, but every image that rose up in its weaving had passed that way before. And it would seem that there is nothing haphazard or fortuitous in their return." This is not quite clear?not even when Professor Lowes explains that there were clusters of associations, like hooked atoms, which were drawn into complex relation with other clus ters in the deep well of Coleridge's memory, and which then coalesced and issued forth as poems. If there was nothing "hap hazard or fortuitous" in the way the images returned to the sur face, that may mean ( 1) that Coleridge could not produce what This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 479 he did not have, that he was limited in his creation by what he had read or otherwise experienced, or (2) that having received certain clusters of associations, he was bound to return them in just the way he did, and that the value of the poem may be described in terms of the experiences on which he had to draw. The latter pair of propositions (a sort of Hartleyan associationism which Coleridge himself repudiated in the Biographia) may not be assented to. There were certainly other combinations, other poems, worse or better, that might have been written by men who had read Bartram and Purchas and Bruce and Milton. And this will be true no matter how many times we are able to add to the brilliant complex of Coleridge's reading. In certain flourishes (such as the sentence we have quoted) and in chapter headings like "The Shaping Spirit," "The Magical Synthesis," "Imagina tion Creatrix," it may be that Professor Lowes pretends to say more about the actual poems than he does. There is a certain deceptive variation in these fancy chapter titles; one expects to pass on to a new stage in the argument, and one finds?more and more sources, more about "the streamy nature of associa ?,1,-3 tion." "Wohin der Weg?" quotes Professor Lowes for the motto of his book. "Kein Weg! Ins Unbetretene." Precisely because the way is unbetreten ywe should say, it leads away from the poem. Bartram's Travels contains a good deal of the history of certain words and romantic Floridan conceptions that appear in "Kubla Khan." And a good deal of that history has passed and was then passing into the very stuff of our language. Per haps a person who has read Bartram appreciates the poem more than one who has not. Or, by looking up the vocabulary of "Kubla Khan" in the Oxford English Dictionary y or by reading some of the other books there quoted, a person may know the poem better. But it would seem to pertain little to the poem to know that Coleridge had read Bartram. There is a gross body of ll?c, ?>f sensory and mental experience, which lies behind and This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 480 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY in some sense causes every poem, but can never be and need not be known in the verbal and hence intellectual composition which is the poem. For all the objects of our manifold experience, especially for the intellectual objects, for every unity, there is an action of the mind which cuts off roots, melts away context? or indeed we should never have objects or ideas or anything to talk about. It is probable that there is nothing in Professor Lowes' vast book which could detract from anyone's appreciation of either The Ancient Mariner or Kubla Khan. We next present a case where preoccupation with evidence of type (3) has gone so far as to distort a critic's view of a poem (yet a case not so obvious as those that abound in our critical journals). In a well-known poem by John Donne appears the following quatrain: Moving of th' earth brings harmes and feares, Men reckon what it did and meant, But trepidation of the spheares, Though greater farre, is innocent. A recent critic in an elaborate treatment of Donne's learning has written of this quatrain as follows: ... he touches the emotional pulse of the situation by a skillful allusion to the new and the old astronomy. ... Of the new astronomy, the "moving of the earth" is the most radical principle; of the old, the "trepidation of the spheres" is the motion of the greatest complexity. ... As the poem is a valediction forbidding mourning, the poet must exhort his love to quietness and calm upon his departure; and for this purpose the figure based upon the latter motion (trepi dation), long absorbed into the traditional astronomy, fit tingly suggests the tension of the moment without arousing the "harmes and feares" implicit in the figure of the mov ing earth.1* This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 481 The argument is plausible and rests on a well-substantiated thesis that Donne was deeply interested in the new astronomy and its repercussions in the theological realm. In various works Donne shows his familiarity with Kepler's De Stella Novay with Gali leo's Siderius NunciuSy with William Gilbert's De Magnetey and with Clavius's commentary on the De Sphaera of Sacrobosco. He refers to the newT science in his Sermon at Paul's Cross and in a letter to Sir Henry Goodyer. In The First Anniversary he says the "new philosophy calls all in doubt." In the Elegy on Prince Henry he says that the "least moving of the center" makes "the world to shake." It is difficult to answer argument like this, and impossible to answer it with evidence of like nature. There is no reason why Donne might not have written a stanza in which the two kinds of celestial motion stood for two sorts of emotion at parting. And if we become full of astronomical ideas and see Donne only against the background of the new science, we may believe that he did. But the text itself remains to be dealt with, the analyz able vehicle of a complicated metaphor. And one may observe: ( 1) that the movement of the earth according to the Copernican theory is a celestial motion, smooth and regular, and while it might cause religious or philosophic fears, it could not be associ ated with the crudity and earthiness of the kind of commotion which the speaker in the poem wishes to discourage; (2) that there is another moving of the earth, an earthquake, which has just these qualities and is to be associated with the tear-floods and sigh-tempests of the second stanza of the poem; (3) that "trepi dation" is an appropriate opposite of earthquake, because each is a shaking or vibratory motion; and "trepidation of the spheres" is "greater far" than an earthquake, but not much greater (if two such motions can be compared as to greatness) than the annual motion of the earth; (4) that reckoning what it "did andmeant" shows that the event has passed, like an earthquake, not like the incessant celestial movement of the earth. Perhaps a knowl This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 482 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY edge of Donne's interest in the new science may add another shade of meaning, an overtone to the stanza in question, though to say even this runs against the words. To make the geo-centric and helio-centric antithesis the core of the metaphor is to disre gard the English language, to prefer private evidence to public, external to internal. V If the distinction between kinds of evidence has implications for the historical critic, it has them no less for the contemporary poet and his critic. Or, since every rule for a poet is but another side of a judgment by a critic, and since the past is the realm of the scholar and critic, and the future and present that of the poet and the critical leaders of taste, we may say that the problems arising in literary scholarship from the intentional fallacy are matched by others which arise in the world of progressive ex periment. The question of "allusiveness," for example, as acutely posed by the poetry of Eliot, is certainly one where a false judgment is likely to involve the intentional fallacy. The frequency and depth of literary allusion in the poetry of Eliot and others has driven so many in pursuit of full meanings to the Golden Bough and the Elizabethan drama that it has become a kind of common place to suppose that we do not know what a poet means unless we have traced him in his reading?a supposition redolent with intentional implications. The stand taken by Mr. F. O. Mat thiessen is a sound one and partially forestalls the difficulty. If one reads these lines with an attentive ear and is sensitive to their sudden shifts inmovement, the contrast between the actual Thames and the idealized vision of it during an age before it flowed through a megalopolis is sharply conveyed by that movement itself, whether or not one recognizes the refrain to be from Spenser. This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 483 Eliot's allusions work when we know them?and to a great extent even when we do not know them, through their suggestive power. But sometimes we find allusions supported by notes, and it is a very nice question whether the notes function more as guides to send us where we may be educated, or more as indications in themselves about the character of the allusions. "Nearly every thing of importance . . . that is apposite to an appreciation of 'The Waste Land'," writes Mr. Matthiessen of Miss Weston's book, "has been incorporated into the structure of the poem it self, or into Eliot's Notes." And with such an admission it may begin to appear that it would not much matter if Eliot invented his sources (as Sir Walter Scott invented chapter epigraphs from "old plays" and "anonymous" authors, or as Coleridge wrote marginal glosses for "The Ancient Mariner"). Allusions to Dante, Webster, Marvell, or Baudelaire, doubtless gain something because these writers existed, but it is doubtful whether the same can be said for an allusion to an obscure Elizabethan: The sound of horns and motors, which shall bring Sweeney to Mrs. Porter in the spring. "Cf. Day, Parliament of Bees:" says Eliot, When of a sudden, listening, you shall hear, A noise of horns and hunting, which shall bring Actaeon to Diana in the spring, Where all shall see her naked skin. . . . The irony is completed by the quotation itself; had Eliot, as is quite concenceivable, composed these lines to furnish his own background, there would be no loss of validity. The conviction may grow as one reads Eliot's next note: "I do not know the origin of the ballad from which these lines are taken: it was reported to me from Sydney, Australia." The important word in this note?on Mrs. Porter and her daughter who washed their This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 484 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY feet in soda water?is "ballad." And if one should feel from the lines themselves their "ballad" quality, there would be little need for the note. Ultimately, the inquiry must focus on the integrity of such notes as parts of the poem, for where they con stitute special information about the meaning of phrases in the poem, they ought to be subject to the same scrutiny as any of the other words in which it is written. Mr. Matthiessen believes the notes were the price Eliot "had to pay in order to avoid what he would have considered muffling the energy of his poem by ex tended connecting links in the text itself." But it may be ques tioned whether the notes and the need for them are not equally muffling. The omission from poems of the explanatory stratum on which is built the dramatic or poetic stuff is a dangerous responsibility. Mr. F. W. Bateson has plausibly argued that Tennyson's "The Sailor Boy" would be better if half the stanzas were omitted, and the best versions of ballads like "Sir Patrick Spens" owe their power to the very audacity with which the minstrel has taken for granted the story upon which he comments. What then if a poet finds he cannot take so much for granted in a more recondite context and rather than write informatively, supplies notes? It can be said in favor of this plan that at least the notes do not pretend to be dramatic, as they would if written in verse. On the other hand, the notes may look like unas similated material lying loose beside the poem, necessary for the meaning of the verbal symbol, but not integrated, so that the symbol stancis incomplete. We mean to suggest by the above analysis that whereas notes tend to seem to justify themselves as external indexes to the author's intention, yet they ought to be judged like any other parts of a composition (verbal arrangement special to a particular context), and when so judged their reality as parts of the poem, or their imaginative integration with the rest of the poem, may come into question. Mr. Matthiessen, for instance, sees that Eliot's titles for poems and his epigraphs are informative appara This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 485 tus, like the notes. But while he is worried by some of the notes and thinks that Eliot "appears to be mocking himself for writing the note at the same time that he wants to convey something by it," Mr. Matthiessen believes that the "device" of epigraphs "is not at all open to the objection of not being sufficiently struc tural." "The intention" he says, "is to enable the poet to secure a condensed expression in the poem itself." "In each case the epigraph is designed to form an integral part of the effect of the poem." And Eliot himself, in his notes, has justified his poetic practice in terms of intention. The Hanged Man, a member of the traditional pack, fits my purpose in two ways: because he is associated inmv mind with the Hanged God of Frazer, and because I associate him with the hooded figure in the passage of the disciples to Emmaus in Part V. . . . The man with Three Staves (an authentic member of the Tarot pack) I associate, quite ar bitrarily, with the Fisher King himself. And perhaps he is to be taken more seriously here, when off guard in a note, than when in his Norton Lectures he comments on the difficulty of saying what a poem means and adds playfully that he thinks of prefixing to a second edition of Ash Wednesday some lines from Don Juan: I don't pretend that I quite understand My own meaning when I would be very fine; But the fact is that I have nothing planned Unless it were to be a moment merry. If Eliot and other contemporary poets have any characteristic fault, itmay be in planning too much.1" Allusiveness in poetry is one of several critical issues by which we have illustrated the more abstract issue of intentionalism, but it may be for today the most important illustration. As a poetic practice allusiveness would appear to be in some recent poems an This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 486 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY extreme corollary of the romantic intentionalist assumption, and as a critical issue it challenges and brings to light in a special way the basic premise of intentionalism. The following instance from the poetry of Eliot may serve to epitomize the practical implica tions of what we have been saying. In Eliot's "Love Song of J. Alfred Pr?f rock," towards the end, occurs the line: "I have heard the mermaids singing, each to each," and this bears a certain re semblance to a line in a Song by John Donne, "Teach me to heare Mermaides singing," so that for the reader acquainted to a cer tain degree with Donne's poetry, the critical question arises: Is Eliot's line an allusion to Donne's? Is Pr?f rock thinking about Donne? Is Eliot thinking about Donne? We suggest that there are two radically different ways of looking for an answer to this question. There is ( 1) the way of poetic analysis and exegesis, which inquires whether it makes any sense if Eliot-Prufrock is thinking about Donne. In an earlier part of the poem, when Prufrock asks, "Would it have been worth while, . . .To have squeezed the universe into a ball," his words take half their sadness and irony from certain energetic and passionate lines of Marvel "To His Coy Mistress." But the exegetical inquirer may wonder whether mermaids considered as "strange sights" (To hear them is in Donne's poem analogous to getting with child a mandrake root) have much to do with Pr?f rock's mer maids, which seem to be symbols of romance and dynamism, and which incidentally have literary authentication, if they need it, in a line of a sonnet by G?rard de Nerval. This method of in quiry may lead to the conclusion that the given resemblance be tween Eliot and Donne is without significance and is better not thought of, or the method may have the disadvantage of pro viding no certain conclusion. Nevertheless, we submit that this is the true and objective way of criticism, as contrasted to what the very uncertainty of exegesis might tempt a second kind of critic to undertake: (2) the way of biographical or genetic in quiry, in which, taking advantage of the fact that Eliot is still This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions WIMSATT AND BEARDSLEY 487 alive, and in the spirit of a man who would settle a bet, the critic writes to Eliot and asks what he meant, or if he had Donne in mind. We shall not here weigh the probabilities?whether Eliot would answer that he meant nothing at all, had nothing at all in mind?a sufficiently good answer to such a question?or in an unguarded moment might furnish a clear and, within its limit, irrefutable answer. Our point is that such an answer to such an inquiry would have nothing to do with the poem "Pru frock;" it would not be a critical inquiry. Critical inquiries, un like bets, are not settled in this way. Critical inquiries are not settled by consulting the oracle. FOOTNOTES ^f. Louis Teeter, "Scholarship and the Art of Criticism," ELE, V (Sept. 1938), 173-94; Rene Wellek, review of Geoffrey Tillotson's Essays in Criticism and Research, Modem Philology, XLI (May, 1944), 262; G. Wilson Knight, Shakespeare' and Tol stoy, English Association Pamphlet No. 88 (April, 1934), p. 10; Bernard C. Heyl, New Bearings in Esthetics and Art Criticism (New Haven, 1943), pp. 66, 113, 149. 2Dictionary of World Literature, ed. Joseph T. Shipley (New York, 1924), pp. 326-39. 3J. E. Spingarn, "The New Criticism," in Criticism and America (New York, 1924), pp. 24-25. 4As critics and teachers constantly do. "We have here a deliberate blurring. . . ." "Should this be regarded as ironic or as unplanned?" ". . . is the literal meaning in tended. . .?" "... a paradox of religious faith which is intended to exult. . . ." It seems to me that Herbert intends. . ." These examples are chosen from three pages of an issue of The Explicator (Fredericksburg, Va.), vol. II, no. 1 (Oct., 1943). Au thors often judge their own works in the same way. See This is My Best, ed. Whit Burnett (New York, 1942), e.g., pp. 539-40. 5A close relative of the intentional fallacy is that of talking about "means" and "end" in poetry instead of "part" and "whole." We have treated this relation con cisely in our dictionary article. 6E. E. Stoll, 'The Tempest," PMLA, XLIV (Sept. 1932), 703. 7Ananda K. Coomaraswamy, "Intention," The American Bookman, I (Winter, 1944), 41-48. 8For the relation of Longinus to modern romanticism, see R. S. Crane, review of Samuel Monk's The Sublime, Philological Quarterly, XV (April, 1936), 165-66. 9It is true that Croce himself in his Ariosto, Shakespeare, and Corneille, trans. Doug las Ainslie (London, 1920), Chapter VII, "The Practical Personality and the Poetical Personality," and in his Defence of Poetry, trans. E. F. Carritt (Oxford, 1933). p. 24, has delivered a telling attack on initentionalism, but the prevailing drift of such pas sages in the Aesthetic as we quote is in the opposite direction. 10See Hughes Mearns, Creative Youth (Garden City, 1925), esp. pp. 10, 27-29. The technique of inspiring poems keeps pace today with a parallel analysis of the pro cess of inspiration in successful artists. See Rosamond E. M. Harding, An Anatomy of This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions 488 THE INTENTIONAL FALLACY Inspiration, Cambridge, 1940; Julius Portnoy, A Psychology of Art Creation, Philadel phia, 1942. nCurt Ducasse, The Philosophy of Art (New York, 1929), p. 116. 12And the history of words after a poem is written may contribute meanings which if relevant to the original pattern should not be ruled out by a scruple about intention, cf. C. S. Lewis and E. M. W. Tillyard, The Personal Heresy, (Oxford, 1939), p. 16; Teeter, loc cit., pp. 183, 192: review of Tillotson's Essays, TLS, XLI (April, 1942), 174. "Chapters VIII, "The Pattern," and XVI, "The Known and Familiar Landscape," will be found of most help to the student of the poem. For an extreme example of intentionalistic criticism, see Kenneth Burke's analysis of The Ancient Mariner in The Philosophy of Literary Form (Louisiana State Uni versity Press, 1941), pp. 22-23, 93-102. Mr. Burke must be credited with realizing very clearly what he is up to. "Charles M. Coffin, John Donne and the New Philosophy (New York, 1827), pp. 97-98. 15In his critical writings Eliot has expressed the right view of author psychology' (See The Use of Poetry and the Use of Criticism, Cambridge, 1933, p. 139 and "Tra dition and the Individual Talent" in Selected Essays, New York, 1932), though his record is not entirely consistent (See A Choice of Kipling's Verse, London, 1941, pp. 10-11, 20-21). This content downloaded from 91.228.45.168 on Mon, 22 Feb 2016 06:25:56 UTC All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions