C h a p t e r O v e r v i e w Social scientific inquiry is an interplay of theory and research, logic and observation, induction and deduction—and of the fundamental frames of reference known as paradigms. Introduction Some Social Science Paradigms Macrotheory and Microtheory Early Positivism Social Darwinism Conflict Paradigm Symbolic Interactionism Ethnomethodology Structural Functionalism Feminist Paradigms Critical Race Theory Rational Objectivity Reconsidered Elements of Social Theory Two Logical Systems Revisited The Traditional Model of Science Deductive and Inductive Reasoning: A Case Illustration A Graphic Contrast Deductive Theory Construction Getting Started Constructing Your Theory An Example of Deductive Theory: Distributive Justice Inductive Theory Construction An Example of Inductive Theory: Why Do People Smoke Marijuana? The Links between Theory and Research Research Ethics and Theory C h a p t e r 2 Paradigms,Theory, and Social Research Introduction Certain restaurants in the United States are fond of conducting political polls among their diners whenever an election is in the offing. Some take these polls very seriously because of their uncanny history of predicting winners. Some movie theaters have achieved similar success by offering popcorn in bags picturing either donkeys or elephants. Years ago, granaries in the Midwest offered farmers a chance to indicate their political preferences through the bags of grain they selected. Such idiosyncratic ways of determining trends, though interesting, all follow the same pattern over time: They work for a while, and then they fail. Moreover, we can’t predict when or why they will fail. These unusual polling techniques point to a significant shortcoming of “research findings” that are based only on the observation of patterns. Unless we can offer logical explanations for such patterns, the regularities we’ve observed may be mere flukes, chance occurrences. If you flip coins long enough, you’ll get ten heads in a row. Scientists might adapt a street expression to describe this situation: “Patterns happen.” Logical explanations are what theories seek to provide. Theories function in three ways in research. First, they prevent our being taken in by flukes. If we can’t explain why Ma’s Diner has so successfully predicted elections, we run the risk of supporting a fluke. If we know why it has happened, we can anticipate whether or not it will work in the future. Second, theories make sense of observed patterns in a way that can suggest other possibilities. If we understand the reasons why broken homes produce more juvenile delinquency than intact homes do—lack of supervision, for example—we can take effective action, such as establishing after-school youth programs. Third, theories shape and direct research efforts, pointing toward likely discoveries through empirical observation. If you were looking for your lost keys on a dark street, you could whip your flashlight around randomly, hoping to chance upon the errant keys—or you could use your memory of where you had been and limit your search to more-likely areas. Theories, by analogy, direct researchers’ flashlights where they will most likely observe interesting patterns of social life. This is not to say that all social science research is tightly intertwined with social theory. Sometimes social scientists undertake investigations simply to discover the state of affairs, such as an evaluation of whether an innovative social program is working or a poll to determine which candidate is winning a political race. Similarly, descriptive ethnographies, such as anthropological accounts of preliterate societies, produce valuable information and insights in and of themselves. However, even studies such as these often go beyond pure description to ask “why.” Theory relates directly to “why” questions. This chapter explores some specific ways theory and research work hand in hand during the adventure of inquiry into social life. We’ll begin by looking at some fundamental frames of reference, called paradigms, that underlie social theories and inquiry. Whereas theories seek to explain, paradigms provide ways of looking. In and of themselves, paradigms don’t explain anything; however, they provide logical frameworks within which theories are created. As you’ll see in this chapter, theories and paradigms intertwine in the search for meaning in social life. Some Social Science Paradigms There is usually more than one way to make sense of things. In daily life, for example, liberals and conservatives often explain the same phenomenon—teenagers using guns at school, for example—quite differently. So might the parents and teenagers themselves. But underlying these different explanations, or theories, are paradigms—the fundamental models or frames of reference we use to organize our observations and reasoning. paradigm  A model or frame of reference through which to observe and understand. Some Social Science Paradigms ■ 33 Paradigms are often difficult to recognize as such, because they are so implicit, assumed, taken for granted. They seem more like “the way things are” than like one possible point of view among many. Here’s an illustration of what I mean. Where do you stand on the issue of human rights? Do you feel that individual human beings are sacred? Are they “endowed by their creator with certain inalienable rights,” as asserted by the U.S. Declaration of Independence? Are there some things that no government should do to its citizens? Let’s get more concrete. In wartime, civilians are sometimes used as human shields to protect military targets. Sometimes they are impressed into slave labor or even used as mobile blood banks for military hospitals. How about organized programs of rape and murder in support of “ethnic cleansing”? Those of us who are horrified and incensed by such practices probably find it difficult to see our individualistic paradigm—represented in concepts like human rights, liberty, human dignity—as only one possible point of view among many. However, many cultures in today’s world regard the Western (and particularly U.S.) commitment to the sanctity of the individual as bizarre. Historically, it has decidedly been a minority viewpoint. Although many Asian countries, for example, now subscribe to some “rights” that belong to individuals, those are balanced against the “rights” of families, organizations, and the society at large. Criticized for violating human rights, Asian leaders often point to high crime rates and social disorganization in Western societies as the cost of what they see as our radical “cult of the individual.” I won’t try to change your point of view on individual human dignity, nor have I given up my own. It’s useful, however, to recognize that our views and feelings in this matter result from the paradigm we have been socialized into. The sanctity of the individual is not an objective fact of nature; it is a point of view, a paradigm. All of us operate within many such paradigms. When we recognize that we are operating within a paradigm, two benefits accrue. First, we can better understand the seemingly bizarre views and actions of others who are operating from a different paradigm. Second, at times we can profit from stepping outside our paradigm. Suddenly we can see new ways of seeing and explaining things. We can’t do that as long as we mistake our paradigm for reality. Paradigms play a fundamental role in science, just as they do in daily life. Thomas Kuhn (1970) draws attention to the role of paradigms in the history of the natural sciences. Kuhn’s classic book on this subject is titled, appropriately enough, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Major scientific paradigms have included such fundamental viewpoints as Copernicus’s conception of the earth moving around the sun (instead of the reverse), Darwin’s theory of evolution, Newtonian mechanics, and Einstein’s relativity. Which scientific theories “make sense” depends on which paradigm scientists are maintaining. Although we sometimes think of science as developing gradually over time, marked by important discoveries and inventions, Kuhn says that scientific paradigms typically become entrenched, resisting substantial change. Thus, theories and research alike tend to follow a given fundamental direction. Eventually, however, as the shortcomings of a particular paradigm become obvious, a new one emerges and supplants the old. The seemingly natural view that the rest of the universe revolves around the earth, for example, compelled astronomers to devise ever more elaborate ways to account for the motions of heavenly bodies that they actually observed. Eventually, however, the shortcomings of that paradigm would become obvious in the form of observation that violated the expectations suggested by the paradigm. These are often referred to as anomalies, events that fall outside expected or standard patterns. For a long time in American society, as elsewhere, a fundamental belief system regarding sex and gender held that only men were capable of higher learning. In that situation, every demonstrably learned woman was an “anomalous challenge” to the traditional view. When the old paradigm was sufficiently challenged, Kuhn suggested, a new paradigm would emerge and supplant the old one. Social scientists have developed several paradigms for understanding social behavior. The fate of supplanted paradigms in the social sciences, however, has differed from what Kuhn observed in the natural sciences. Natural 34 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research Some scholars have taken a more intimate view of social life. Microtheory deals with issues of social life at the level of individuals and small groups. Dating behavior, jury deliberations, and student–faculty interactions are apt subjects for a microtheoretical perspective. Such studies often come close to the realm of psychology, but whereas psychologists typically focus on what goes on inside humans, social scientists study what goes on between them. The basic distinction between macro- and microtheory cuts across the other paradigms we’ll examine. Some of them, such as symbolic interactionism and ethnomethodology, are often limited to the microlevel. Others, such as the conflict paradigm, can be pursued at either the micro- or the macrolevel. Early Positivism When the French philosopher Auguste Comte (1798–1857) coined the term sociologie in 1822, he launched an intellectual adventure that continues to unfold today. Most importantly, Comte identified society as a phenomenon that can be studied scientifically. (Initially, he wanted to label his enterprise social physics, but that term was taken over by another scholar.) Prior to Comte’s time, society simply was. To the extent that people recognized different kinds of societies or changes in society over time, religious paradigms generally predominated in explanations of such differences. People often saw the state of social affairs as a reflection of God’s will. Alternatively, people were challenged to create a “City of God” on Earth to replace sin and godlessness. Comte separated his inquiry from religion. He felt that religious belief could be replaced with scientific study and objectivity. His “positive philosophy” postulated three stages of history. A theological stage predominated throughout the world until about 1300 c.e. During the next 500 years, a metaphysical stage replaced God with philosophical ideas such as “nature” and “natural law.” Comte felt he was launching the third stage of history, in which science would replace religion and metaphysics by basing knowledge on observations through the five senses rather than on belief or logic alone. Comte felt that society could be observed and then explained logically scientists generally believe that the succession from one paradigm to another represents progress from a false view to a true one. For example, no modern astronomer believes that the sun revolves around the earth. In the social sciences, on the other hand, theoretical paradigms may gain or lose popularity, but they are seldom discarded altogether. The paradigms of the social sciences offer a variety of views, each of which offers insights the others lack and ignores aspects of social life that the others reveal. Ultimately, paradigms are neither true nor false; as ways of looking, they are only more or less useful. Each of the paradigms we are about to examine offers a different way of looking at human social life. Each makes its own assumptions about the nature of social reality. As we’ll see, each can open up new understandings, suggest different kinds of theories, and inspire different kinds of research. Macrotheory and Microtheory Let’s begin with a difference concerning focus, a difference that stretches across many of the paradigms we’ll discuss. Some social theorists focus their attention on society at large, or at least on large portions of it. Topics of study for such macrotheories include the struggle between economic classes in a society, international relations, or the interrelations among major institutions in society, such as government, religion, and family. Macrotheory deals with large, aggregate entities of society or even whole societies. (Note that some researchers prefer to limit the macrolevel to whole societies, using the term mesotheory for an intermediate level between macro and micro: studying organizations, communities, and perhaps social categories such as gender.) macrotheory  A theory aimed at understanding the “big picture” of institutions, whole societies, and the interactions among societies. Karl Marx’s examination of the class struggle is an example of macrotheory. microtheory  A theory aimed at understanding social life at the intimate level of individuals and their interactions. Examining how the play behavior of girls differs from that of boys would be an example of microtheory. Some Social Science Paradigms ■ 35 popular view in Spencer’s time, although it was not universally accepted. This excerpt from a social science methods textbook published in 1950 illustrates the longterm popularity of the notion that things are getting better and better. The use of atomic energy as an explosive offers most interesting prospects in the civil as in the military field. Atomic explosives may be used for transforming the landscape. They may be used for blasting great holes and trenches in the earth, which can be transformed into lakes and canals. In this way, it may become possible to produce lakes in the midst of deserts, and thus convert some of the worst places in the world into oases and fertile countries. It may also be possible to make the Arctic regions comfortable by providing immense and constant sources of heat. The North Pole might be converted into a holiday resort. (Gee 1950: 339–40) Quite aside from the widespread disenchantment with nuclear power, contemporary concerns over global warming and the threat of rising sea levels illustrate a growing consciousness that “progress” is often a two-edged sword. Clearly, most of us operate today from a different paradigm. Conflict Paradigm One of Spencer’s contemporaries took a sharply different view of the evolution of capitalism. Karl Marx (1818–1883) suggested that social behavior could best be seen as a process of conflict: the attempt to dominate others and to avoid being dominated. Marx’s conflict paradigm focused primarily on the struggle among economic classes. Specifically, he examined the way capitalism produced the oppression of workers by the owners of industry. Marx’s interest in this topic did not end with analytical study; he was also ideologically committed to restructuring economic relations to end the oppression he observed. and rationally and that sociology could be as scientific as biology or physics. Comte’s view came to form the foundation for subsequent development of the social sciences. In his optimism for the future, he coined the term positivism to describe this scientific approach, believing that scientific truths could be positively verified through empirical observations and the logical analysis of what was observed. In recent decades, the idea of positivism has come under serious challenge, as we’ll see later in this discussion. Social Darwinism Comte’s major work on his positivist philosophy was published between 1830 and 1842. One year after the publication of the first volume in that series, a young British naturalist set sail on HMS Beagle, beginning a cruise that would profoundly affect the way we think of ourselves and our place in the world. In 1859, when Charles Darwin published On the Origin of Species, he set forth the idea of evolution through natural selection. Simply put, the theory states that as a species coped with its environment, those individuals most suited to success would be the most likely to survive long enough to reproduce. Those less well suited would perish. Over time the traits of the survivor would come to dominate the species. As later Darwinians put it, species evolved into different forms through the “survival of the fittest.” As scholars began to study society analytically, it was perhaps inevitable that they would apply Darwin’s ideas to changes in the structure of human affairs. The journey from simple hunting-and-gathering tribes to large, industrial civilizations was easily seen as the evolution of progressively “fitter” forms of society. Among others, Herbert Spencer (1820–1903) concluded that society was getting better and better. Indeed, his native England had profited greatly from the development of industrial capitalism, and Spencer favored a system of free competition, which he felt would ensure continued progress and improvement. Spencer may even have coined the phrase “the survival of the fittest.” He certainly believed that this principle was a primary force shaping the nature of society. Social Darwinism or social evolution was a positivism  Introduced by Auguste Comte, this philosophical system is grounded on the rational proof/disproof of scientific assertions; assumes a knowable, objective reality. 36 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research The contrast between the views set forth by Spencer and Marx indicates the influence of paradigms on research. These fundamental viewpoints shape the kinds of observations we are likely to make, the sorts of facts we seek to discover, and the conclusions we draw from those facts. Paradigms also help determine which concepts we see as relevant and important. Whereas economic classes were essential to Marx’s analysis, for example, Spencer was more interested in the relationship between individuals and society—particularly the amount of freedom individuals had to surrender for society to function. The conflict paradigm proved to be fruitful outside the realm of purely economic analyses. Georg Simmel (1858–1918) was especially interested in small-scale conflict, in contrast to the class struggle that interested Marx. Simmel noted, for example, that conflicts among members of a tightly knit group tended to be more intense than those among people who did not share feelings of belonging and intimacy. In an interesting application of the conflict paradigm, when Michel Chossudovsky’s (1997) analysis of the International Monetary Fund (IMF) and World Bank suggested that these two international organizations were increasing global poverty rather than eradicating it, he directed his attention to the competing interests involved in the process. In theory, the chief interest being served should be that of the poor people of the world or perhaps the impoverished nations. The researcher’s inquiry, however, identified many other interested parties who benefited: the commercial lending institutions who made loans in conjunction with the IMF and World Bank, as well as multinational corporations seeking cheap labor and markets for their goods, for example. Chossudovsky concluded that the interests of the banks and corporations tended to take precedence over those of the poor people. Moreover, he found that many policies were weakening the economies in developing nations, as well as undermining democratic governments. Although the conflict paradigm often focuses on class, gender, and ethnic struggles, we could appropriately apply it whenever different groups have competing interests. For example, we could fruitfully apply it to understanding relations among different departments in an organization, fraternity and sorority rush weeks, or student– faculty–administrative relations, to name just a few. Symbolic Interactionism In his overall focus, Georg Simmel differed from both Spencer and Marx. Whereas they were chiefly concerned with macrotheoretical issues—large institutions and whole societies in their evolution through the course of history— Simmel was more interested in how individuals interacted with one another. In other words, his thinking and research took a “micro” turn, thus calling attention to aspects of social reality that are invisible in Marx’s or Spencer’s theory. For example, he began by examining dyads (groups of two people) and triads (groups of three). Similarly, he wrote about “the web of group affiliations” (Wolff 1950). Simmel was one of the first European sociologists to influence the development of U.S. sociology. His focus on the nature of interactions particularly influenced George Herbert Mead (1863–1931), Charles Horton Cooley (1864–1929), and others who took up the cause and developed it into a powerful paradigm for research. Cooley, for example, introduced the idea of the “primary group,” those intimate associates with whom we share a sense of belonging, such as our family and friends. Cooley also wrote of the “looking-glass self” we form by looking into the reactions of people around us. If everyone treats us as beautiful, for example, we conclude that we are. Notice how fundamentally the concepts and theoretical focus inspired by this paradigm differ from the society-level concerns of Spencer and Marx. Mead emphasized the importance of our human ability to “take the role of the other,” imagining how others feel and how they might behave in certain circumstances. As we gain an idea of how people in general see things, we develop a sense of what Mead called the “generalized other” (Strauss 1977). Mead also showed a special interest in the role of communications in human affairs. Most interactions, he felt, revolved around the process conflict paradigm  A paradigm that views human behavior as attempts to dominate others or avoid being dominated by others. Some Social Science Paradigms ■ 37 of individuals reaching common understanding through the use of language and other such systems, hence the term symbolic interactionism. This paradigm can lend insights into the nature of interactions in ordinary social life, but it can also help us understand unusual forms of interaction, as when researchers Robert Emerson, Kerry Ferris, and Carol Gardner (1998), in a study still relevant today, set out to understand the nature of “stalking.” Through interviews with numerous stalking victims, they came to identify different motivations among stalkers, stages in the development of a stalking scenario, how people can recognize if they are being stalked, and what they can do about it. Moving from the topic of stalking, here’s one way you might apply the symbolic interactionism paradigm to a less dramatic examination of your own life. The next time you meet someone new, pay attention to how you get to know each other. To begin, what assumptions do you make about the other person based merely on appearances, how he or she talks, and the circumstances under which you’ve met. (“What’s someone like you doing in a place like this?”) Then watch how your knowledge of each other unfolds through the process of interaction. Notice also any attempts you make to manage the image you are creating in the other person’s mind. Ethnomethodology Whereas some social scientific paradigms emphasize the impact of social structure on human behavior—that is, the effect of norms, values, control agents, and so forth—other paradigms do not. Harold Garfinkel, a contemporary sociologist, claims that people are continually creating social structure through their actions and interactions—that they are, in fact, creating their realities. Thus, when you and your instructor meet to discuss your term paper, even though there are myriad expectations about how you both should act, your conversation will differ somewhat from any of those that have occurred before, and how you each act will somewhat modify your expectations in the future. That is, discussing your term paper will impact the interactions each of you have with other professors and students in the future. Given the tentativeness of reality in this view, Garfinkel suggests that people are continuously trying to make sense of the life they experience. In a sense, he suggests that everyone is acting like a social scientist, hence the term ethnomethodology, or “methodology of the people.” How would you approach learning about people’s expectations and how they make sense out of their world? One technique ethnomethodologists use is to break the rules, to violate people’s expectations. Thus, if you try to talk to me about your term paper but I keep talking about football, this might reveal the expectations you had for my behavior might become apparent. We might also see how you make sense out of my behavior. (“Maybe he’s using football as an analogy for understanding social systems theory.”) In another example of ethnomethodology, Johen Heritage and David Greatbatch (1992) examined the role of applause in British political speeches: How did the speakers evoke applause, and what function did it serve? Research within the ethnomethodological paradigm has often focused on communications. There is no end to the opportunities you have for trying out the ethnomethodological paradigm. For instance, the next time you get on an elevator, don’t face front watching the floor numbers whip by; that’s the norm, or expected behavior. Just stand quietly facing the rear. See how others react to this behavior. Just as important, notice how you feel about it. If you do this experiment a few times, you should begin to develop a feel for the ethnomethodological paradigm.* We’ll return to ethnomethodology in Chapter 10, when we discuss field research. For now, let’s turn to a very different paradigm. symbolic interactionism  A paradigm that views human behavior as the creation of meaning through social interactions, with those meanings conditioning subsequent interactions. *I am grateful to my colleague, Bernard McGrane, for this experiment. Barney also has his students eat dinner with their hands, watch TV without turning it on, and engage in other strangely enlightening behavior (McGrane 1994). 38 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research Structural Functionalism Structural functionalism, sometimes also known as social systems theory, has grown out of a notion introduced by Comte and Spencer: A social entity, such as an organization or a whole society, can be viewed as an organism. Like other organisms, a social system is made up of parts, each of which contributes to the functioning of the whole. By analogy, consider the human body. Each component—such as the heart, lungs, kidneys, skin, and brain—has a particular job to do. The body as a whole cannot survive unless each of these parts does its job, and none of the parts can survive except as a part of the whole body. Or consider an automobile. It is composed of the tires, the steering wheel, the gas tank, the spark plugs, and so forth. Each of the parts serves a function for the whole; taken together, that system can get us across town. None of the individual parts would be very useful to us by itself, however. The view of society as a social system, then, looks for the “functions” served by its various components. Social scientists using the structural functional paradigm might note that the function of the police, for example, is to exercise social control—encouraging people to abide by the norms of society and bringing to justice those who do not. Notice, though, that the researchers could just as reasonably ask what functions criminals serve in society. Within the functionalist paradigm, we might say that criminals serve as job security for the police. In a related observation, Emile Durkheim (1858–1917) suggested that crimes and their punishment provide an opportunity to reaffirm society’s values. By catching and punishing thieves, we reaffirm our collective respect for private property. To get a sense of the structural functional paradigm, suppose you were interested in explaining how your college or university works. You might thumb through the institution’s catalog and begin assembling a list of the administrators and support staff (such as the president, deans, registrar, campus security staff, maintenance personnel). Then you might figure out what each of them does and relate their roles and activities to the chief functions of your college or university, such as teaching or research. This way of looking at an institution of higher learning would clearly suggest a different line of inquiry than, say, a conflict paradigm, which might emphasize the clash of interests between people who have power in the institution and those who don’t. People often discuss “functions” in everyday conversation. Typically, however, the alleged functions are seldom tested empirically. Some people argue, for example, that welfare, intended to help the poor, actually harms them in a variety of ways. It is sometimes alleged that welfare creates a deviant, violent subculture in society, at odds with the mainstream. From this viewpoint, welfare programs actually result in increased crime rates. Lance Hannon and James Defronzo (1998) decided to test this last assertion. Working with data drawn from 406 urban counties in the United States, they examined the relationship between welfare payments and crime rates. Contrary to the beliefs of some, their data indicated that higher welfare payments were associated with lower crime rates. In other words, welfare programs have the function of decreasing rather than increasing lawlessness. In applying the functionalist paradigm to everyday life, people sometimes make the mistake of thinking that “functionality,” stability, and integration are necessarily good, or that the functionalist paradigm makes that assumption. However, when social researchers look for the functions served by poverty, racial discrimination, or the oppression of women, they are not justifying them. Just the opposite: They seek to understand the functions such things play in the larger society, as a way of understanding why they persist and how they could be eliminated. Feminist Paradigms When Ralph Linton concluded his anthropological classic, The Study of Man (1937: 490), speaking of “a store of knowledge that promises to give man a better life than any he has known,” no one complained that he had left out women. Linton was using the linguistic conventions of structural functionalism  A paradigm that divides social phenomena into parts, each of which serves a function for the operation of the whole. Some Social Science Paradigms ■ 39 his time; he implicitly included women in all his references to men. Or did he? When feminists first began questioning the use of masculine pronouns and nouns whenever gender was ambiguous, their concerns were often viewed as petty, even silly. At most, many felt the issue was one of women having their feelings hurt, their egos bruised. But be honest: When you read Linton’s words, what did you picture? An amorphous, genderless human being, or . . . a man? In a similar way, researchers looking at the social world from a feminist paradigm have called attention to aspects of social life that other paradigms do not reveal. In part, feminist theory and research have focused on sex-role differences and how they relate to the rest of social organization. These lines of inquiry have drawn attention to the oppression of women in many societies, which in turn has shed light on oppression generally. Feminist paradigms not only reveal the treatment of women or the experience of oppression but often point to limitations in how other aspects of social life are examined and understood. Thus, feminist perspectives are often related to a concern for the environment, for example. As Greta Gard suggests, The way in which women and nature have been conceptualized historically in Western intellectual tradition has resulted in devaluing whatever is associated with women, emotion, animals, nature, and the body, while simultaneously elevating in value those things associated with men, reason, humans, culture, and the mind. One task of ecofeminism has been to expose these dualisms and the ways in which feminizing nature and naturalizing or animalizing women has served as justification for the domination of women, animals and the earth. (1993: 5; quoted in Rynbrandt and Deegan 2002: 60) Feminist paradigms have also challenged the prevailing notions concerning consensus in society. Most descriptions of the predominant beliefs, values, and norms of a society are written by people representing only portions of society. In the United States, for example, such analyses have typically been written by middle-class white men—not surprisingly, they have written about the beliefs, values, and norms they themselves share. Though George Herbert Mead spoke of the “generalized other” that each of us becomes aware of and can “take the role of,” feminist paradigms question whether such a generalized other even exists. Mead used the example of learning to play baseball to illustrate how we learn about the generalized other. As shown here, Janet Lever’s research suggests that understanding the experience of boys may tell us little about girls. Girls’ play and games are very different. They are mostly spontaneous, imaginative, and free of structure or rules. Turn-taking activities like jumprope may be played without setting explicit goals. Girls have far less experience with interpersonal competition. The style of their competition is indirect, rather than face to face, individual rather than team affiliated. Leadership roles are either missing or randomly filled. (Lever 1986: 86) Social researchers’ growing recognition of the intellectual differences between men and women led the psychologist Mary Field Belenky and her colleagues to speak of Women’s Ways of Knowing (1986). In-depth interviews with 45 women enabled the researchers to distinguish five perspectives on knowing that challenge the view of inquiry as obvious and straightforward: ●● Silence: Some women, especially early in life, feel themselves isolated from the world of knowledge, their lives largely determined by external authorities. ●● Received knowledge: From this perspective, women feel themselves capable of taking in and holding knowledge originating with external authorities. ●● Subjective knowledge: This perspective opens up the possibility of personal, subjective knowledge, including intuition. ●● Procedural knowledge: Some women feel they have learned the ways of gaining knowledge through objective procedures. feminist paradigms  Paradigms that (1) view and understand society through the experiences of women and/or (2) examine the generally deprived status of women in society. 40 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research ●● Constructed knowledge: The authors describe this perspective as “a position in which women view all knowledge as contextual, experience themselves as creators of knowledge, and value both subjective and objective strategies for knowing.” (Belenky et al. 1986: 15) “Constructed knowledge” is particularly interesting in the context of our previous discussions. The positivistic paradigm of Comte would have a place neither for “subjective knowledge” nor for the idea that truth might vary according to its context. The ethnomethodological paradigm, on the other hand, would accommodate these ideas. Feminist standpoint theory is a term often used in reference to the fact that women have knowledge about their status and experience that is not available to men. Introduced by Nancy Hartsock (1983), this viewpoint has evolved over time. For example, scholars have come to recognize that there is no single female experience, that different kinds of women (varying by wealth, ethnicity, or age, for example) have very different experiences of life in society, all the while sharing some things in common because of their gender. This sensitivity to variations in the female experience is also a main element in what is referred to as third-wave feminism, which began in the 1990s. To try out feminist paradigms, you might want to explore whether discrimination against women exists at your college or university. Are the top administrative positions held equally by men and women? How about secretarial and clerical positions? Are men’s and women’s sports supported equally? Read through the official history of your school; is it a history that includes men and women equally? (If you attend an all-male or all-female school, of course, some of these questions won’t apply.) As we just saw, feminist paradigms reflect not only a concern for the unequal treatment of women but also an epistemological recognition that men and women overall perceive and understand society differently. Social theories created solely by men, which has been the norm, run the risk of an unrecognized bias. A similar case can be made for theories created almost exclusively by white people. Critical Race Theory The roots of critical race theory are generally associated with the civil rights movement of the mid- 1950s and race-related legislation of the 1960s. By the mid-1970s, with fears that the strides toward equality were beginning to bog down, civil rights activists and social scientists began the codification of a paradigm based on race awareness and a commitment to racial justice. This was not the first time sociologists paid attention to the status of nonwhites in U.S. society. Perhaps the best known African American sociologist in the history of the discipline was W. E. B. DuBois, who published The Souls of Black Folk in 1903. Among other things, DuBois pointed out that African Americans lived their lives through a “dual consciousness”: as Americans and as black people. By contrast, white Americans have seldom reflected on being white. If you were American, white was simply assumed. If you were not white, you have been seen and made to feel like the exception. So imagine the difference between an African American sociologist and a white sociologist creating a theory of social identity. Their theories of identity would likely differ in some fundamental ways, even if they were not limiting their analyses to their own race. Much of the contemporary scholarship in critical race theory has to do with the role of race in politics and government, studies often undertaken by legal scholars as well as social scientists. Thus, for example, Derrick Bell (1980) critiqued the U.S. Supreme Court’s landmark Brown v. Board of Education decision, which struck down the “separate but equal” system of school segregation. He suggested that the Court was motivated by the economic and political interests of the white, not by the objective of educational equality for African American students. In his analysis, Ball introduced the concept of interest convergence, suggesting that laws will criticalracetheory  A paradigm grounded in race awareness and an intention to achieve racial justice. interest convergence  The thesis that majority group members will only support the interests of minorities when those actions also support the interests of the majority group. Some Social Science Paradigms ■ 41 only be changed to benefit African Americans if and when those changes are seen to further the interests of whites. Richard Delgado (2002) provides an excellent overview of how Bell’s reasoning has been pursued by subsequent critical race theory scholars. As a general rule, whenever you find the word critical in the name of a paradigm or theory, it will likely refer to a nontraditional view, one that may be at odds with the prevailing paradigms of an academic discipline and also at odds with the mainstream structure of society. Rational Objectivity Reconsidered We began this discussion of paradigms with Comte’s assertion that society can be studied rationally and objectively. Since his time, the growth of science and technology, together with the relative decline of superstition, have put rationality more and more at the center of social life. As fundamental as rationality is to most of us, however, some contemporary scholars have raised questions about it. For example, positivistic social scientists have sometimes erred in assuming that humans always act rationally. I’m sure your own experience offers ample evidence to the contrary. Yet many modern economic models fundamentally assume that people will make rational choices in the economic sector: They will choose the highest-paying job, pay the lowest price, and so forth. This assumption ignores the power of tradition, loyalty, image, and other factors that compete with reason and calculation in determining human behavior. A more sophisticated positivism would assert that we can rationally understand and predict even nonrational behavior. An example is the famous “Asch experiment” (Asch 1958). In this experiment, a group of subjects is presented with a set of lines on a screen and asked to identify the two lines that are equal in length. Imagine yourself a subject in such an experiment. You are sitting in the front row of a classroom among a group of six subjects. A set of lines is projected on the wall in front of you (see Figure 2-1). The experimenter asks each of you, one at a time, to identify the line on the right (A, B, or C) that matches the length of line X. The correct answer (B) is pretty obvious to you. To your surprise, however, you find that all the other subjects agree on a different answer! The experimenter announces that all but one of the group has gotten the correct answer. Because you are the only one who chose B, this amounts to saying that you’ve gotten it wrong. Then a new set of lines is presented, and you have the same experience. What seems to be the obviously correct answer is said by everyone else to be wrong. As it turns out, of course, you are the only real subject in this experiment—all the others are working with the experimenter. The purpose of the experiment is to see whether you will be swayed by public pressure to go along with the incorrect answer. In his initial experiments, all of which involved young men, Asch found that a little over one-third of his subjects did just that. Choosing an obviously wrong answer in a simple experiment is an example of nonrational behavior. But as Asch went on to show, experimenters can examine the circumstances that lead more or fewer subjects to go along with the incorrect answer. For example, in subsequent studies, Asch varied the size of one group and the number of “dissenters” who chose the “wrong” (that is, the correct) answer. Thus, it is possible to study nonrational behavior rationally and scientifically. More radically, we can question whether social life abides by rational principles at all. In the physical sciences, developments such as FIGURE 2-1 The Asch Experiment. Subjects in the Asch experiment have a seemingly easy task: to determine whether A, B, or C is the same length as X. But there’s more here than meets the eye. X A B C © Cengage Learning® 42 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research chaos theory, fuzzy logic, and complexity have suggested that we may need to rethink fundamentally the orderliness of events in the physical world. Certainly the social world might be no tidier than the world of physics. The contemporary challenge to positivism, however, goes beyond the question of whether people always behave rationally in their political, economic, and other areas of behavior. In part, the criticism of positivism challenges the idea that scientists can be as objective as the positivistic ideal assumes. Most scientists would agree that personal feelings can and do influence the problems scientists choose to study, what they choose to observe, and the conclusions they draw from their observations. There is an even more radical critique of the ideal of objectivity. As we glimpsed in the discussions of feminism and ethnomethodology, some contemporary researchers suggest that subjectivity might actually be preferable in some situations. Let’s take a moment to return to the dialectic of subjectivity and objectivity. To begin, all our experiences are inescapably subjective. There is no way out. We can see only through our own eyes, and anything peculiar to our eyes will shape what we see. We can hear things only the way our particular ears and brain transmit and interpret sound waves. You and I, to some extent, hear and see different realities. And both of us experience quite different physical “realities” than, say, do bats. In what to us is total darkness, a bat “sees” things such as flying insects by emitting a sound we humans can’t hear. Echolocation or the reflection of the bat’s sound creates a “sound picture” precise enough for the bat to home in on the moving insect and snatch it up in its teeth. In a similar vein, scientists on the planet Xandu might develop theories of the physical world based on a sensory apparatus that we humans can’t even imagine. Maybe they have X-ray vision or hear colors. Despite the inescapable subjectivity of our experience, we humans seem to be wired to seek an agreement on what is really real, what is objectively so. Objectivity is a conceptual attempt to get beyond our individual views. It is ultimately a matter of communication, as you and I attempt to find a common ground in our subjective experiences. Whenever we succeed in our search, we say we are dealing with objective reality. This is the agreement reality discussed in Chapter 1. To this point, perhaps the most significant studies in the history of social science were conducted in the 1930s by a Turkish American social psychologist, Muzafer Sherif (1935), who slyly said he wanted to study “auto-kinetic effects.” To do this, he put small groups in totally darkened rooms, save for a single point of light in the center of the wall in front of the participants. Sherif explained that the light would soon begin to move about, and the subjects were to determine how far it was moving—a difficult task with nothing else visible as a gauge of length or distance. Amazingly, each of the groups agreed on the distance the point of light moved about. Oddly, however, the different groups of subjects arrived at quite different conclusions as to how much the light was moving. Strangest of all, the point of light had remained stationary. If you stare at a fixed point of light long enough it will seem to move about (Sherif’s “auto-kinetic effect”). Notice, however, that each of the groups agreed on a specific delusion. The movement of the light was real to them, but it was a reality created out of nothing: a socially constructed reality. Whereas our subjectivity is individual, then, our search for objectivity is social. This is true in all aspects of life, not just in science. Whereas you and I prefer different foods, we must agree to some extent on what is fit to eat and what is not, or else there could be no restaurants or grocery stores. The same argument could be made regarding every other form of consumption. Without agreement reality, there could be no movies or television, no sports. Social scientists as well have found benefits in the concept of a socially agreed-on objective reality. As people seek to impose order on their experience of life, they find it useful to pursue this goal as a collective venture. What are the causes and cures of prejudice? Working together, social researchers have uncovered some answers that hold up to intersubjective scrutiny. Whatever your subjective experience of things, for example, you can discover for yourself that as education increases, prejudice generally tends to decrease. Because each of us can discover this independently, we say that it is objectively true. Some Social Science Paradigms ■ 43 From the seventeenth century through the middle of the twentieth, however, the belief in an objective reality that people could see and measure ever more clearly predominated in science. For the most part, it was not simply held as a useful paradigm but held as The Truth. The term positivism has generally represented the belief in a logically ordered, objective reality that we can come to know better and better through science. This is the view challenged today by postmodernists and others who suggest that perhaps only our perceptions and experiences are real. Some say that the ideal of objectivity conceals as much as it reveals. As we saw earlier, in years past much of what was regarded as objectivity in Western social science was actually an agreement primarily among white, middleclass European men. Equally real experiences common to women, to ethnic minorities, to non-Western cultures, or to the poor were not necessarily represented in that reality. Thus, early anthropologists are now criticized for often making modern, Westernized “sense” out of the beliefs and practices of nonliterate tribes around the world, sometimes by portraying their subjects as superstitious savages. We often call orally transmitted beliefs about the distant past “creation myth,” whereas we speak of our own beliefs as “history.” Increasingly today, there is a demand to find the native logic by which various peoples make sense out of life and to understand it on its own terms. Ultimately, we’ll never be able to completely distinguish between an objective reality and our subjective experience. We can’t know whether our concepts correspond to an objective reality or are simply useful in allowing us to predict and control our environment. So desperate is our need to know what is really real, however, that both positivists and postmodernists are sometimes drawn into the belief that their own view is real and true. There is a dual irony in this. On the one hand, the positivist’s belief that science precisely mirrors the objective world must ultimately be based on faith; this conviction cannot be proved by “objective” science, because that’s precisely what is at issue. And the postmodernists, who say nothing is objectively so and everything is ultimately subjective, do at least feel that that is really the way things are. Postmodernism is often portrayed as a denial of the possibility of social science, but that’s not the point I’m making. This textbook makes no assumption about the existence or absence of an objective reality. At the same time, human beings demonstrate an extensive and robust ability to establish agreements as to what is “real.” This appears in regard to rocks and trees, as well as ghosts and gods, and even more-elusive ideas such as loyalty and treason. Whether something like “prejudice” really exists, research into its nature can take place, because enough people agree that prejudice does exist, and researchers can use agreed-on techniques of inquiry to study it. Another social science paradigm, critical realism, suggests that we define “reality” as that which can be seen to have an effect. Since prejudice clearly has an observable effect in our lives, it must be judged “real” in terms of this point of view. This paradigm fits interestingly with an oft-quoted statement by early U.S. sociologist, W. I. Thomas: “If men define situations as real, they are real in their consequences” (1928: 571–72). This book will not require or even encourage you to choose among positivism, postmodernism, or any of the other paradigms discussed in this chapter. In fact, I invite you to look for value in any and all as you seek to understand the world that may or may not exist around you. Similarly, as social researchers, we are not forced to align ourselves entirely with either positivism or postmodernism. Instead, we can treat them as two distinct arrows in our quiver. Each approach compensates for the weaknesses of the other by suggesting complementary perspectives that can produce useful lines of inquiry. For example, the reknown British physicist Stephen Hawking has elegantly described the appealing simplicity of the positivistic model but tempers his remarks with a recognition of the way science is practiced. postmodernism  A paradigm that questions the assumptions of positivism and theories describing an “objective” reality. critical realism  A paradigm that holds things are real insofar as they produce effects. 44 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research According to this way of thinking, a scientific theory is a mathematical model that describes and codifies the observations we make. A good theory will describe a large range of phenomena on the basis of a few simple postulates and will make definite predictions that can be tested. If the predictions agree with the observations, the theory survives that test, though it can never be proved to be correct. On the other hand, if the observations disagree with the predictions, one has to discard or modify the theory. (At least, that is what is supposed to happen. In practice, people often question the accuracy of the observations and the reliability and moral character of those making the observations.) (2001: 31) In summary, a rich variety of theoretical paradigms can be brought to bear on the study of social life. With each of these fundamental frames of reference, useful theories can be constructed. We turn now to some of the issues involved in theory construction, which are of interest and use to all social researchers, from positivists to postmodernists—and all those in between. Elements of SocialTheory As we have seen, paradigms are general frameworks or viewpoints: literally “points from which to view.” They provide ways of looking at life and are grounded in sets of assumptions about the nature of reality. Where a paradigm offers a way of looking, a theory aims to explain what we see. Theories are systematic sets of interrelated statements intended to explain some aspect of social life. Thus, theories flesh out and specify paradigms. Recall from Chapter 1 that social scientists engage in both idiographic and nomothetic explanations. Idiographic explanations seek to explain a limited phenomenon as completely as possible— explaining why a particular woman voted as she did, for example—whereas nomothetic explanations attempt to explain a broad range of phenomena at least partially: identifying a few factors that account for much voting behavior in general. Let’s look a little more deliberately now at some of the elements of a theory. As I mentioned in Chapter 1, science is based on observation. In social research, observation typically refers to seeing, hearing, and (less commonly) touching. A corresponding idea is fact. Although for philosophers “fact” is as complex a notion as “reality,” social scientists generally use the term to refer to some phenomenon that has been observed. It is a fact, for example, that Barack Obama defeated Mitt Romney in the 2012 presidential election. Scientists aspire to organize many facts under “rules” called laws. Abraham Kaplan (1964: 91) defined laws as universal generalizations about classes of facts. The law of gravity is a classic example: Bodies are attracted to each other in proportion to their masses and in inverse proportion to the distance separating them. Laws must be truly universal, however, not merely accidental patterns found among a specific set of facts. It is a fact, Kaplan points out (1964: 92), that in each of the U.S. presidential elections from 1920 to 1960, the major candidate with the longest name won. That is not a law, however, as shown by elections since. The earlier pattern was a coincidence. Sometimes called principles, laws are important statements about what is so. We speak of them as being “discovered,” granting, of course, that our paradigms affect what we choose to look for and what we see. Laws in and of themselves do not explain anything. They just summarize the way things are. Explanation is a function of theory, as we’ll see shortly. There are no social science laws that claim the universal certainty of those of the natural sciences. Social scientists debate among themselves whether such laws will ever be discovered. Perhaps social life essentially does not abide by invariant laws. This does not mean that social life is so chaotic as to defy prediction and explanation. As we saw in Chapter 1, social behavior falls into patterns, and those patterns quite often make perfect sense, although we may have to look below the surface to find the logic. As I just indicated, laws should not be confused with theories. Whereas a law is an observed regularity, a theory is a systematic explanation for observations that relate to a particular aspect of life. For example, someone might offer Two Logical Systems Revisited ■ 45 a theory of juvenile delinquency, prejudice, or political revolution. Theories explain observations by means of concepts. Jonathan Turner (1989: 5) calls concepts the “basic building blocks of theory.” Concepts are abstract elements representing classes of phenomena within the field of study. The concepts relevant to a theory of juvenile delinquency, for example, include “juvenile” and “delinquency,” for starters. A “peer group”— the people you hang around with and identify with—is another relevant concept. “Social class” and “ethnicity” are undoubtedly relevant concepts in a theory of juvenile delinquency. “School performance” might also be relevant. A variable is a special kind of concept. Some of the concepts just mentioned refer to things, and others refer to sets of things. As we saw in Chapter 1, each variable comprises a set of attributes; thus, delinquency, in the simplest case, is made up of delinquent and not delinquent. A theory of delinquency would aim at explaining why some juveniles are delinquent and others are not. Axioms or postulates are fundamental assertions, taken to be true, on which a theory is grounded. In a theory of juvenile delinquency, we might begin with axioms such as “Everyone desires material comforts” and “The ability to obtain material comforts legally is greater for the wealthy than for the poor.” From these we might proceed to propositions: specific conclusions, derived from the axiomatic groundwork, about the relationships among concepts. From our beginning axioms about juvenile delinquency, for example, we might reasonably formulate the proposition that poor youths are more likely to break the law to gain material comforts than are rich youths. This proposition, incidentally, accords with Robert Merton’s classic attempt to account for deviance in society. Merton (1957: 139–57) spoke of the agreed-on means and ends of a society. In Merton’s model, nondeviants are those who share the societal agreement as to desired ends (such as a new car) and the means prescribed for achieving them (such as to buy it). One type of deviant—Merton called this type the “innovator”—agrees on the desired end but does not have access to the prescribed means for achieving it. Innovators find another method, such as crime, of attaining the desired end. From propositions, in turn, we can derive hypotheses. A hypothesis is a specified testable expectation about empirical reality that follows from a more general proposition. Thus, a researcher might formulate the hypothesis, “Poor youths have higher delinquency rates than do rich youths.” Research is designed to test hypotheses. In other words, research will support (or fail to support) a theory only indirectly—by testing specific hypotheses that are derived from theories and propositions. Let’s look more clearly at how theory and research come together. Two Logical Systems Revisited The Traditional Model of Science Most of us have a somewhat idealized picture of “the scientific method.” It is a view gained as a result of the physical-science education we’ve received ever since our elementary school days. Although this traditional model of science tells only a part of the story, it’s helpful to understand its logic. There are three main elements in the traditional model of science: theory, operationalization, and observation. At this point we’re already well acquainted with the idea of theory. Theory According to the traditional model of science, scientists begin with a thing, from which they derive testable hypotheses. For example, as social scientists we might have a theory about the causes of juvenile delinquency. Let’s assume that we have arrived at the hypothesis that delinquency is inversely related to social class. That is, as social class goes up, delinquency goes down. Operationalization To test any hypothesis, we must specify the meanings of all the variables involved in it, in hypothesis  A specified testable expectation about empirical reality that follows from a more general proposition; more generally, an expectation about the nature of things derived from a theory. It is a statement of something that ought to be observed in the real world if the theory is correct. 46 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research observational terms. In the present case, the variables are social class and delinquency. To give these terms specific meaning, we might define delinquency as “being arrested for a crime,” “being convicted of a crime,” or some other plausible phrase, whereas social class might be specified in terms of family income, for the purposes of this particular study. Once we have defined our variables, we need to specify how we’ll measure them. (Recall from Chapter 1 that science, in the classical ideal, depends on measurable observations.) Operationalization literally means specifying the exact operations involved in measuring a variable. There are many ways we can attempt to test our hypothesis, each of which allows for different ways of measuring our variables. For simplicity, let’s assume we’re planning to conduct a survey of high school students. We might operationalize delinquency in the form of the question “Have you ever stolen anything?” Those who answer “yes” will be classified as delinquents in our study; those who say “no” will be classified as nondelinquents. Similarly, we might operationalize social class by asking respondents, “What was your family’s income last year?” and providing them with a set of family income categories: under $10,000; $10,000– $24,999; $25,000–$49,999; $50,000–$99,999; $100,000 and above. At this point someone might object that delinquency can mean something more than or different from having stolen something at one time or another, or that social class isn’t necessarily the same as family income. Some parents might think body piercing is a sign of delinquency even if their children don’t steal, and to some, social class might include an element of prestige or community standing as well as how much money a family has. For the researcher testing a hypothesis, however, the meaning of variables is exactly and only what the operational definition specifies. In this respect, scientists are very much like Humpty Dumpty in Lewis Carroll’s Through the Looking Glass [1895] 2009. “When I use a word,” Humpty Dumpty tells Alice, “it means just what I choose it to mean—neither more nor less.” “The question is,” Alice replies, “whether you can make words mean so many different things.” To which Humpty Dumpty responds, “The question is, which is to be master—that’s all” ([1895] 2009: 190) Scientists have to be “masters” of their operational definitions for the sake of precision in observation, measurement, and communication. Otherwise, we would never know whether a study that contradicted ours did so only because it used a different set of procedures to measure one of the variables and thus changed the meaning of the hypothesis being tested. Of course, this also means that to evaluate a study’s conclusions about juvenile delinquency and social class, or any other variables, we need to know how those variables were operationalized. The way we have operationalized the variables in our imaginary study could be open to other problems, however. Perhaps some respondents will lie about having stolen anything, in which cases we’ll misclassify them as nondelinquent. Some respondents will not know their family incomes and will give mistaken answers; others may be embarrassed and lie. We’ll consider issues like these in detail in Part 2. Our operationalized hypothesis now is that the highest incidence of delinquents will be found among respondents who select the lowest family income category (under $10,000); a lower percentage of delinquents will be found in the $10,000–$24,999 category; still fewer delinquents will be found in the $25,000–$49,999 and $50,000–$99,999 categories; and the lowest percentage of delinquents will be found in the $100,000 and above categoriey. Now we’re ready for the final step in the traditional model of science—observation. Having developed theoretical clarity and specific expectations, and having created a strategy for looking, all that remains is to look at the way things actually are. operationalization  One step beyond conceptualization. Operationalization is the process of developing operational definitions, or specifying the exact operations involved in measuring a variable. operational definition  The concrete and specific definition of something in terms of the operations by which observations are to be categorized. The operational definition of “earning an A in this course” might be “correctly answering at least 90 percent of the final exam questions.” Two Logical Systems Revisited ■ 47 These findings would disconfirm our hypothesis regarding family income and delinquency. Disconfirmability, or the possibility of falsification, is an essential quality in any hypothesis. In other words, if there is no chance that our hypothesis will be disconfirmed, it hasn’t said anything meaningful. You cannot test whether a hypothesis is true unless your test contains the possibility of deciding it is false. For example, the hypothesis that juvenile delinquents commit more crimes than do nondelinquents cannot possibly be disconfirmed, because criminal behavior is intrinsic to the idea of delinquency. Even if we recognize that some young people commit crimes without being caught and labeled as delinquents, they couldn’t threaten our hypothesis, because our actual observations would lead us to conclude they were law-abiding nondelinquents. Figure 2-2 provides a schematic diagram of the traditional model of scientific inquiry. In it we see the researcher beginning with an interest in a phenomenon (such as juvenile delinquency). Next comes the development of a theoretical understanding, in this case that a single concept (such as social class) might explain others. The theoretical considerations result in an expectation about what should be observed if the theory is correct. The notation Y 5 f (X) is a conventional way of saying that Y (for example, delinquency) is a function of (depends on) X (for example, social class). At that level, however, X and Y still have rather general meanings that could give rise to quite different observations and measurements. Operationalization specifies the procedures that will be used to measure the variables. The lowercase y in Figure 2-2, for example, is a precisely measurable indicator of capital Y. This operationalization process results in the formation of a testable hypothesis: For example, self-reported theft is a function of family income. Observations aimed at finding out whether this statement accurately describes reality are part of what is typically called hypothesis testing. (See the Tips and Tools box, “Hints for Stating Hypotheses,” for more on the process of formulating hypotheses.) PercentDelinquent Under $10,000 20 $10,000–$24,999 15 $25,000–$49,999 10 $50,000–$99,999 5 $100,000 and above 2 PercentDelinquent Under $10,000 15 $10,000–$24,999 15 $25,000–$49,999 15 $50,000–$99,999 15 $100,000 and above 15 Observation The final step in the traditional model of science involves actual observation, looking at the world and making measurements of what is seen. Let’s suppose our survey produced the following data: Observations producing such data would confirm our hypothesis. But suppose our findings were as follows: FIGURE 2-2 TheTraditional Image of Science.The deductive model of scientific inquiry begins with a sometimes vague or general question, which is subjected to a process of specification, resulting in hypotheses that can be tested through empirical observations. X causes Y THEORETICAL UNDERSTANDING HYPOTHESIS Y = f(X ) Theoretical expectation Operationalization y = f(x) Testable hypothesis y = f(x) Observation (hypothesis testing) ? Idea/interest “What causes Y ? ” © 2016 Cengage Learning® 48 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research Hints for Stating Hypotheses Riley E. Dunlap Department of Sociology, Oklahoma State University Ahypothesisisthebasicstatementthatistestedinresearch.Typicallya hypothesisstatesarelationshipbetweentwovariables.(Althoughitis possibletousemorethantwovariables,youshouldsticktotwofornow.) Becauseahypothesismakesapredictionabouttherelationshipbetween thetwovariables,itmustbetestablesoyoucandetermineiftheprediction isrightorwrongwhenyouexaminetheresultsobtainedinyourstudy.A hypothesismustbestatedinanunambiguousmannertobeclearlytest- able.Whatfollowsaresuggestionsfordevelopingtestablehypotheses. Assume you have an interest in trying to predict some phenomenon such as“attitudes toward women’s liberation,”and that you can measure such attitudes on a continuum ranging from“opposed to women’s liberation”  to  “neutral”  to  “supportive of women’s liberation.”Also assume that, lacking a theory, you’ll rely on“hunches”to come up with variables that might be related to attitudes toward women’s liberation. In a sense, you can think of hypothesis construction as a case of filling in the blank:  “_____ is related to attitudes toward women’s liberation.”  Your job is to think of a variable that might plausibly be related to such attitudes, and then to word a hypothesis that states a relationship between the two variables (the one that fills in the“blank” and“attitudes toward women’s liberation”).You need to do so in a precise manner so that you can determine clearly whether the hypothesis is supported or not when you examine the results (in this case, most likely the results of a survey). Thekeyistowordthehypothesiscarefullysothattheprediction itmakesisquitecleartoyouaswellasothers.Ifyouuseage,notethat saying  “Ageisrelatedtoattitudestowardwomen’sliberation”doesnot saypreciselyhowyouthinkthetwoarerelated(infact,theonlywaythis hypothesiscouldbefalsifiedisifyoufailtofindastatisticallysignificant relationshipofanytypebetweenageandattitudestowardwomen’slib- eration).Inthiscaseacoupleofstepsarenecessary.Youhavetwooptions: 1. “Age is related to attitudes toward women’s liberation, with younger adults being more supportive than older adults.”(Or, you could state the opposite, if you believed older people are likely to be more supportive.) 2. “Age is negatively related to support for women’s liberation.”  Note here that I specify  “support”for women’s liberation (SWL) and then predict a negative relationship—that is, as age goes up, I predict that SWL will go down. In this hypothesis, note that both of the variables (age, the independent variable or likely“cause,”and SWL, the dependent variable or likely“effect”) range from low to high.This feature of the two variables is what allows you to use“negatively”(or“positively”) to describe the relationship. Notice what happens if you hypothesize a relationship between gender and SWL. Because gender is a nominal variable (as you’ll learn in Chapter 5), it does not range from low to high—people are either male or female (the two attributes of the variable gender). Consequently, you must be careful in stating the hypothesis unambiguously: 1. “Sex is positively (or negatively) related to SWL”  is not an adequate hypothesis, because it doesn’t specify how you expect sex to be related to SWL—that is, whether you think men or women will be more supportive of women’s liberation. 2. It’s tempting to say something like“Women are positively related to SWL,”but this really doesn’t work, because female is only an attribute, not a full variable (sex is the variable). 3. “Sex is related to SWL, with women being more supportive than men”would be my recommendation. Or, you could say,“with men being less supportive than women,”which makes the identical prediction. (Of course, you could also make the opposite prediction, that men are more supportive than women are, if you wished.) 4. Equally legitimate would be“Women are more likely to support women’s liberation than are men.”(Note the need for the second “are,”or you could be construed as hypothesizing that women support women’s liberation more than they support men—not quite the same idea.) The previous examples hypothesized relationships between a “characteristic”(age or sex) and an“orientation”(attitudes toward women’s liberation). Because the causal order is pretty clear (obviously age and sex come before attitudes, and are less alterable), we could state the hypotheses as I’ve done, and everyone would assume that we were stating causal hypotheses. Finally,youmayrunacrossreferencestothenull hypothesis, especially in statistics. Such a hypothesis predicts no relationship (technically, no statistically significant relationship) between the two variables, and it is always implicit in testing hypotheses. Basically, if you have hypothesized a positive (or negative) relationship, you are hoping that the results will allow you to reject the null hypothesis and verify your hypothesized relationship. Tips andTools Two Logical Systems Revisited ■ 49 Deductive and Inductive Reasoning: A Case Illustration In Chapter 1, I introduced deductive and inductive reasoning, with a promise that we would return to them later. It’s later. As you probably recognized, the traditional model of science just described is a nice example of deductive reasoning: From a general theoretical understanding, the researcher derives (deduces) an expectation and finally a testable hypothesis. This picture is tidy, but in reality, science uses inductive reasoning as well. Let’s consider a real research example as a vehicle for comparing the deductive and inductive linkages between theory and research. Years ago, Charles Glock, Benjamin Ringer, and I (1967) set out to discover what caused differing levels of church involvement among U.S. Episcopalians. Several theoretical or quasi-theoretical positions suggested possible answers. I’ll focus on only one here: what we came to call the “Comfort Hypothesis.” In part, we took our lead from the Christian injunction to care for “the halt, the lame, and the blind” and those who are “weary and heavy laden.” At the same time, ironically, we noted the Marxist assertion that religion is an “opiate for the masses.” Given both, it made sense to expect the following, which was our hypothesis: “Parishioners whose life situations most deprive them of satisfaction and fulfillment in the secular society turn to the church for comfort and substitute rewards” (Glock, Ringer, and Babbie 1967: 107–8). Having framed this general hypothesis, we set about testing it. Were those deprived of satisfaction in the secular society in fact more religious than those who received more satisfaction from the secular society? To answer this, we needed to distinguish who was deprived. The questionnaire, which was constructed for the purpose of testing the Comfort Hypothesis, included items that seemed to offer indicators of whether parishioners were relatively deprived or gratified in secular society. To start, we reasoned that men enjoy more status than women do in our generally maledominated society. Though hardly novel, this conclusion laid the groundwork for testing the Comfort Hypothesis. If we were correct in our hypothesis, women should appear more religious than men. Once the survey data had been collected and analyzed, our expectation about gender and religion was clearly confirmed. On three separate measures of religious involvement— ritual (such as church attendance), organizational (such as belonging to church organizations), and intellectual (such as reading church publications)—women were more religious than men. On our overall measure, women scored 50 percent higher than men. In another test of the Comfort Hypothesis, we reasoned that in a youth-oriented society, old people would be more deprived of secular gratification than the young would. Once again, the data confirmed our expectation. The oldest parishioners were more religious than the middle-aged, who were more religious than young adults. Social class—measured by education and income—afforded another test of the Comfort Hypothesis. Once again, the test succeeded. Those with low social status were more involved in the church than those with high social status were. The hypothesis was even confirmed in a test that went against everyone’s commonsense expectations. Despite church posters showing worshipful young families and bearing the slogan “The Family That Prays Together Stays Together,” the Comfort Hypothesis suggested that parishioners who were married and had children—the clear American ideal at that time—would enjoy secular gratification in that regard. As a consequence, they should be less religious than those who lacked one or both family components. Thus, we hypothesized that parishioners who were both single and childless should be the most religious; those with either spouse or child should be somewhat less religious; and those married with children— representing the ideal pictured on all those posters—should be the least religious of all. That’s exactly what we found. null hypothesis  In connection with hypothesis testing and tests of statistical significance, that hypothesis that suggests there is no relationship among the variables under study. You may conclude that the variables are related after having statistically rejected the null hypothesis. 50 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research Finally, the Comfort Hypothesis suggested that the various kinds of secular deprivation should be cumulative: Those with all the characteristics associated with deprivation should be the most religious; those with none should be the least. When we combined the four individual measures of deprivation into a composite measure, the theoretical expectation was exactly confirmed. Comparing the two extremes, we found that single, childless, elderly, lowerclass female parishioners scored more than three times as high on the measure of church involvement than did young, married, upperclass fathers. Thus was the Comfort Hypothesis confirmed. I like this research example because it so clearly illustrates the logic of the deductive model. Beginning with general, theoretical expectations about the impact of social deprivation on church involvement, one could derive concrete hypotheses linking specific measurable variables, such as age and church attendance. The actual empirical data could then be analyzed to determine whether empirical reality supported the deductive expectations. I say this example shows how it was possible to address the issue of religiosity deductively, but, alas, I’ve been fibbing. To tell the truth, although we began with an interest in discovering what caused variations in church involvement among Episcopalians, we didn’t actually begin with a Comfort Hypothesis, or any other hypothesis for that matter. The study is actually an example of the inductive model. (In the interest of further honesty, Glock and Ringer initiated the study, and I joined it years after the data had been collected.) A questionnaire was designed to collect information that might shed a bit of light on why some parishioners participated in the church more than others, but it was not guided by any precise, deductive theory. Once the data were collected, the task of explaining differences in religiosity began with an analysis of variables that have a wide impact on people’s lives, including gender, age, social class, and family status. Each of these four variables was found to relate strongly to church involvement, in the ways already described. Indeed, they had a cumulative effect, also already described. Rather than being good news, however, this presented a dilemma. Glock recalls discussing his findings with colleagues over lunch at the Columbia faculty club. Once he had displayed the tables illustrating the impact of each individual variable as well as their powerful composite effect, a colleague asked, “What does it all mean, Charlie?” Glock was at a loss. Why were those variables so strongly related to church involvement? That question launched a process of reasoning about what the several variables had in common, aside from their impact on religiosity. Eventually we saw that each of the four variables also reflected differential status in the secular society. He then had the thought that perhaps the issue of comfort was involved. Thus, the inductive process had moved from concrete observations to a general theoretical explanation. It seems easier to lay out the steps involved in deductive than inductive research. Deductive research begins with a theory, from which we may derive hypotheses—which are then tested through observations. Inductive research begins with observations and proceeds with a search for patterns in what we have observed. In a quantitative study, we can search for correlations or relationships between variables (discussed further in Chapter 16). Thus, once a relationship has been discovered between gender and religiosity, our attention turns to figuring out logical reasons why that is so. Most qualitative research is oriented toward the inductive rather than the deductive approach. However, qualitative research does not, by definition, allow us to use statistical tools to find correlations that point toward patterns in need of explanation (see Chapter 14). Although there are computer programs designed for recording and analyzing qualitative data, the qualitative inductive analyst needs a strong reserve of insight and reflection to tease important patterns out of a body of observations. A Graphic Contrast As the preceding case illustration shows, theory and research can usefully be done both inductively and deductively. Figure 2-3 shows a graphic comparison of the two approaches as applied to an inquiry into study habits and performance on exams. In both cases, we are interested in the relationship between the number of hours Two Logical Systems Revisited ■ 51 spent studying for an exam and the grade earned on that exam. Using the deductive method, we would begin by examining the matter logically. Doing well on an exam reflects a student’s ability to recall and manipulate information. Both of these abilities should be increased by exposure to the information before the exam. In this fashion, we would arrive at a hypothesis suggesting a positive relationship between the number of hours spent studying and the grade earned on the exam. We say “positive” because we expect grades to increase as the hours of studying increase. If increased hours produced decreased grades, that would be called a “negative,” or “inverse,” relationship. The hypothesis is represented by the graph line in part 1(a), representing the deductive model in Figure 2-3. In part (a) we see the expectation of a simple, positive, linear relationship between the two variables. Part (b) represents what we observe when we study the two variables. Finally, part (c) is the need to decide whether the observations are close enough to what was expected to justify accepting the hypothesis. FIGURE 2-3 Deductive and Inductive Methods. Both deduction and induction are legitimate and valuable approaches to understanding. Deduction begins with an expected pattern that is tested against observations, whereas induction begins with observations and seeks to find a pattern within them. 100 0 0 40302010 Grades Hours studying 50 1. Deductive Method a. Hypothesis 100 0 0 40302010 Grades Hours studying 50 b. Observations 100 0 0 40302010 Grades Hours studying 50 c. Accept or reject hypothesis? 100 0 0 40302010Grades Hours studying 50 2. Inductive Method a. Observations 100 0 0 40302010 Grades Hours studying 50 b. Finding a pattern 100 0 0 40302010 Grades Hours studying 50 c. Tentative conclusion © Cengage Learning® 52 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research Our next step would be to make observations relevant to testing our hypothesis. The shaded area in part 1(b) of the figure represents perhaps hundreds of observations of different students, specifically, how many hours they studied and what grades they received. Finally, in part 1(c), we compare the hypothesis and the observations. Because observations in the real world seldom, if ever, match our expectations perfectly, we must decide whether the match is close enough to consider the hypothesis confirmed. Stated differently, can we conclude that the hypothesis describes the general pattern that exists, granting some variations in real life? Sometimes, answering this question necessitates methods of statistical analysis, which will be discussed in Part 4 of this book. Now suppose we used the inductive method to address the same research question. In this case, we would begin with a set of observations, as in part 2(a) of Figure 2-3. Curious about the relationship between hours spent studying and grades earned, we might simply arrange to collect relevant data. Then we’d look for a pattern that best represented or summarized our observations. In part 2(b) of the figure, the pattern is shown as a curved line running through the center of our observations. The pattern found among the points in this case suggests that with 1 to 15 hours of studying, each additional hour generally produces a higher grade on the exam. With 15 to about 25 hours, however, more study seems to lower the grade slightly. Studying more than 25 hours, on the other hand, results in a return to the initial pattern: More hours produce higher grades. Using the inductive method, then, we end up with a tentative conclusion about the pattern of the relationship between the two variables. The conclusion is tentative because the observations we have made cannot be taken as a test of the pattern—those observations are the source of the pattern we’ve created. As I discussed in Chapter 1, in actual practice, theory and research interact through a never-ending alternation of deduction and induction. A good example is the classic work of Emile Durkheim on suicide ([1897] 1951). When Durkheim pored over table after table of official statistics on suicide rates in different areas, he was struck by the fact that Protestant countries consistently had higher suicide rates than Catholic ones did. Why should that be the case? His initial observations led him to create inductively a theory of religion, social integration, anomie, and suicide. His theoretical explanations in turn led deductively to further hypotheses and further observations. The suicide data analyzed by Durkheim pale in comparison with what is now referred to as big data, enormous data sets created through the automatic monitoring of ongoing processes. If you have purchased books, CDs, or anti-itch lotions from Amazon.com or a similar online seller, those purchases were recorded in a huge data set containing the online purchases of everyone else. Hence, you may find yourself looking at a message such as, “Other people who bought this book also bought . . .” Or your web surfing may be spiced with ads for products or services vaguely related to actions you have previously taken online. If you’ve ever contributed to a political campaign or signed an online petition, you’re very likely to have received related notifications and requests subsequently. Similarly, you have probably read about the controversial bulk data-collection programs of the National Security Administration (NSA), monitoring telephone calls and Internet communications for the purpose of identifying possible terrorist connections and activities. The rise in big data collection and processing by commercial, governmental, and other agencies raises serious debates over the prospects for privacy in modern society. In summary, the scientific norm of logical reasoning provides a two-way bridge between theory and research. Scientific inquiry in practice often alternates between deduction and induction. Both methods involve an interplay of logic and observation. And both are routes to the construction of social theories. Although both inductive and deductive methods are valid in scientific inquiry, individuals may feel more comfortable with one approach than the other. Consider this exchange big data  Extremely large data sets generated through the automatic monitoring of ongoing processes, such as Amazon monitoring purchases or the National Security Administration’s monitoring of telephone and Internet communications. Deductive Theory Construction ■ 53 in Sir Arthur Conan Doyle’s story “A Scandal in Bohemia,” as Sherlock Holmes answers Dr. Watson’s inquiry (Doyle [1891] 1892: 13): “What do you imagine that it means?” “I have no data yet. It is a capital mistake to theorise before one has data. Insensibly one begins to twist facts to suit theories, instead of theories to suit facts.” Some social scientists would more or less agree with this inductive position (see especially the discussion of grounded theory in Chapter 10), whereas others would take a more deductive stance. Most, however, concede the legitimacy of both approaches. With this understanding of the deductive and inductive links between theory and research in hand, let’s now delve more deeply into how theories are constructed using either of these two different approaches. DeductiveTheory Construction To see what’s involved in deductive theory construction and hypothesis testing, imagine that you’re going to construct a deductive theory. How would you go about it? Getting Started The first step in deductive theory construction is to pick a topic that interests you. The topic can be very broad, such as “What is the structure of society?” or it can be narrower, as in “Why do people support or oppose the idea of a woman’s right to an abortion?” Whatever the topic, it should be something you’re interested in understanding and explaining. Once you’ve picked your topic, the next step is to undertake an inventory of what’s already known or thought about it. In part, this means writing down your own observations and ideas. Beyond that, it means learning what other scholars have said about it. You can talk to other people, and you’ll want to read the scholarly literature on the topic. Appendix A provides guidelines for using the library—you’ll likely spend a lot of time there. Your preliminary research will probably uncover consistent patterns discovered by prior scholars. For example, religious and political variables will stand out as important determinants of attitudes about abortion. Findings such as these will be very useful to you in creating your own theory. We’ll return to techniques of the literature review in more detail as the book continues. In this process, don’t overlook the value of introspection. Whenever we can look at our own personal processes—including reactions, fears, and prejudices—we may gain important insights into human behavior in general. I don’t mean to say that everyone thinks like you or me, but introspection can provide a useful source of insights that can inform our inquiries. Constructing Your Theory Now that you’ve reviewed previous work on the topic, you’re ready to begin constructing your theory. Although theory construction is not a lockstep affair, the process generally involves something like the following steps. 1. Specify the topic. 2. Specify the range of phenomena your theory addresses. Will your theory apply to all of human social life, will it apply only to U.S. citizens, only to young people, or what? 3. Identify and specify your major concepts and variables. 4. Find out what is known (propositions) about the relationships among those variables. 5. Reason logically from those propositions to the specific topic you’re examining. We’ve already discussed items (1) through (3), so let’s focus now on (4) and (5). As you identify the relevant concepts and discover what’s already been learned about them, you can begin to create a propositional structure that explains the topic under study. Let’s look now at an example of how these building blocks fit together in deductive theory construction and empirical research. An Example of Deductive Theory: Distributive Justice A topic of interest to scholars is the concept of distributive justice, people’s perceptions of whether they are being treated fairly by 54 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research life, whether they are getting “their share.” Guillermina Jasso describes the theory of distributive justice more formally, as follows: The theory provides a mathematical description of the process whereby individuals, reflecting on their holdings of the goods they value (such as beauty, intelligence, or wealth), compare themselves to others, experiencing a fundamental instantaneous magnitude of the justice evaluation (J), which captures their sense of being fairly or unfairly treated in the distributions of natural and social goods. (Jasso 1988: 11) Notice that Jasso has assigned a symbolic representation for her key variable: J will stand for distributive justice. She does this to support her intention of stating her theory in mathematical formulas. Though theories are often expressed mathematically, we’ll not delve too deeply into that practice here. Jasso indicates that there are three kinds of postulates in her theory. “The first makes explicit the fundamental axiom which represents the substantive point of departure for the theory.” She elaborates as follows: “The theory begins with the received Axiom of Comparison, which formalizes the long-held view that a wide class of phenomena, including happiness, self-esteem, and the sense of distributive justice, may be understood as the product of a comparison process” (Jasso 1988: 11). Thus, your sense of whether you’re receiving a fair share of the good things of life comes from comparing yourself with others. If this seems obvious to you, that’s not a shortcoming of the axiom. Remember, axioms are the taken-forgranted beginnings of theory. Jasso continues to do the groundwork for her theory. First, she indicates that our sense of distributive justice is a function of “Actual Holdings (A)” and “Comparison Holdings (C)” of some good. Let’s consider money, for example. My sense of justice in this regard is a function of how much I actually have, compared with how much others have. By specifying the two components of the comparison, Jasso can use them as variables in her theory. Next, Jasso offers a “measurement rule” that further specifies how the two variables, A and C, will be conceptualized. This step is needed because some of the goods to be examined are concrete and commonly measured (such as money), whereas others are less tangible (such as respect). The former kind, she says, will be measured conventionally, whereas the latter will be measured “by the individual’s relative rank . . . within a specially selected comparison group.” The theory will provide a formula for making that measurement (Jasso 1988: 13). Jasso continues in this fashion to introduce additional elements, weaving them into mathematical formulas to be used in deriving predictions about the workings of distributive justice in a variety of social settings. Here is just a sampling of where her theorizing takes her (1988: 14–15). ●● Other things [being] the same, a person will prefer to steal from a fellow group member rather than from an outsider. ●● The preference to steal from a fellow group member is more pronounced in poor groups than in rich groups. ●● In the case of theft, informants arise only in cross-group theft, in which case they are members of the thief’s group. ●● Persons who arrive a week late at summer camp or for freshman year of college are more likely to become friends of persons who play games of chance than of persons who play games of skill. ●● A society becomes more vulnerable to deficit spending as its wealth increases. ●● Societies in which population growth is welcomed must be societies in which the set of valued goods includes at least one quantity-good, such as wealth. Jasso’s theory leads to many other propositions, but this sampling should provide a good sense of where deductive theorizing can take you. To get a feeling for how she reasons her way to these propositions, let’s look briefly at the logic involved in two of the propositions that relate to theft within and outside one’s group. ●● Other things [being] the same, a person will prefer to steal from a fellow group member rather than from an outsider. Beginning with the assumption that thieves want to maximize their relative wealth, ask Inductive Theory Construction ■ 55 yourself if that goal would be best served by stealing from those you compare yourself with or from outsiders. In each case, stealing will increase your Actual Holdings, but what about your Comparison Holdings? A moment’s thought should suggest that stealing from people in your comparison group will lower their holdings, further increasing your relative wealth. To simplify, imagine there are only two people in your comparison group: you and I. Suppose we each have $100. If you steal $50 from someone outside our group, you will have increased your relative wealth by 50 percent compared with me: $150 versus $100. But if you steal $50 from me, you will have increased your relative wealth 200 percent: $150 to my $50. Your goal is best served by stealing from within the comparison group. ●● In the case of theft, informants arise only in cross-group theft, in which case they are members of the thief’s group. Can you see why it would make sense for informants (1) to arise only in the case of crossgroup theft and (2) to come from the thief’s comparison group? This proposition again depends on the fundamental assumption that everyone wants to increase his or her relative standing. Suppose you and I are in the same comparison group, but this time the group contains additional people. If you steal from someone else within our comparison group, my relative standing in the group does not change. Although your wealth has increased, the average wealth in the group remains the same (because someone else’s wealth has decreased by the same amount). So my relative standing remains the same. I have no incentive to inform on you. If you steal from someone outside our comparison group, however, your nefarious income increases the total wealth in our group. Now my own wealth relative to that total is diminished. Because my relative wealth has suffered, I’m more likely to inform on you in order to bring an end to your stealing. Hence, informants arise only in cross-group theft. This last deduction also begins to explain why these informants come from the thief’s own comparison group. We’ve just seen how your theft decreased my relative standing. How about members of the other group (other than the individual you stole from)? Each of them actually profits from the theft, because you have reduced the total with which they compare themselves. Hence, they have no reason to inform on you. Thus, the theory of distributive justice predicts that informants arise from the thief’s own comparison group. This brief peek into Jasso’s derivations should give you some sense of the enterprise of deductive theory. Of course, the theory guarantees none of the given predictions. The role of research is to test each of them to determine whether what makes sense (logic) actually occurs in practice (observation). See the Tips and Tools box, “Generating a Hypothesis from a Theory,” for a look at creating hypotheses for deductive purposes. InductiveTheory Construction As we have seen, quite often social scientists begin constructing a theory through the inductive method by first observing aspects of social life and then seeking to discover patterns that may point to relatively universal principles. Barney Glaser and Anselm Strauss (1967) coined the term grounded theory in reference to this method. Field research—the direct observation of events in progress—is frequently used to develop theories through observation. In a long and rich tradition, anthropologists have used this method to good advantage. Among modern social scientists, no one has been more adept at seeing the patterns of human behavior through observation than Erving Goffman, in a research career that stretched from the 1950s to the 1970s: A game such as chess generates a habitable universe for those who can follow it, a plane of being, a cast of characters with a seemingly unlimited number of different situations and acts through which to realize their natures and destinies. Yet much of this is reducible to a small set of interdependent rules and practices. If the meaningfulness of everyday activity is similarly dependent on a closed, finite set of rules, then explication of them would give one a powerful means of analyzing social life. (1974: 5) 56 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research Generating a Hypothesis from a Theory As we have seen, the deductive method of research typically focuses on the testing of a hypothesis. Let’s take a minute to look at how to create a hypothesis for testing. Hypotheses state an expected causal relationship between two (or more) variables. Let’s suppose you’re interested in student political orientations, and your review of the literature and your own reasoning suggest to you that college major will play some part in determining students’political views. Already, we have two variables: collegemajor and political orientation. Moreover, politicalorientation is the dependent variable—you believe it depends on something else, on the independent variable, which in this case is collegemajor. Now we need to specify the attributes comprising each of these variables. For simplicity’s sake, let’s assume political orientation includes only liberal or conservative. And to simplify the matter of major, let’s suppose your research interests focus on the presumed differences between business students and those in the social sciences. Even with these simplifications, you would need to specify more concretely how you would recognize a liberal or a conservative when you came across them in your study.This process of specification will be discussed at length in Chapter 5. For now, let’s assume you will ask student-subjects whether they consider themselves liberals or conservatives, letting each student report on what the terms mean to them. (As we’ll see later, this simple dichotomy is unlikely to work in practice, as some students would want to identify themselves as independents or something else.) Identifying students’majors isn’t as straightforward as you might think. For example, what disciplines compose the social sciences in your study? Also, must students be declared majors or simply be planning to major in one of the relevant fields? Once these issues have been settled, you are ready to state your hypothesis. For example, it might be the following: “Students majoring in the social sciences will be more likely to identify themselves as liberals than are those majoring in business.” In addition to this basic expectation, you may wish to specify  “more likely”in terms of how much more likely. Chapter 16 will provide some options in this regard. Deductive theory construction and hypothesis testing offer a clear example of what philosopher Karl Popper (1934) described as the principle of falsifiability in science. No conclusion can be considered “scientific”unless it is possible to state observations that would contradict or disprove it.This is what distinguishes scientific conclusions from religious, political, or philosophical beliefs. A belief you hold dear may very well be true, but unless we can agree on circumstances that would disprove it, it cannot be considered proven. Tips andTools In a variety of research efforts, Goffman uncovered the rules of such diverse behaviors as living in a mental institution (1961) and managing the “spoiled identity” of being disfigured (1963). In each case, Goffman observed the phenomenon in depth and teased out the rules governing behavior. Goffman’s research provides an excellent example of qualitative field research as a source of grounded theory. Our earlier discussion of the Comfort Hypothesis and church involvement shows that qualitative field research is not the only method of observation appropriate to the development of inductive theory. Here’s another detailed example to illustrate further the construction of inductive theory using quantitative methods. An Example of Inductive Theory: Why Do People Smoke Marijuana? During the 1960s and 1970s, marijuana use on U.S. college campuses was a subject of considerable discussion in the popular press. Some people were troubled by marijuana’s popularity; others welcomed it. What interests us here is why some students smoked marijuana and others didn’t. A survey of students at the University of Hawaii by David Takeuchi (1974) provided the data to answer that question. While the reasons and practices regarding pot may have changed, the subtle redefinition of what needed explaining is still instructive. At the time of the study, a huge number of explanations were being offered for drug use. People who opposed drug use, for example, often suggested that marijuana smokers were academic failures trying to avoid the rigors of college life. Those in favor of marijuana, on the other hand, often spoke of the search for new values: Marijuana smokers, they said, were people who had seen through the hypocrisy of middle-class values. Takeuchi’s analysis of the data gathered from University of Hawaii students, however, did not The Links between Theory and Research ■ 57 support any of the explanations being offered. Those who reported smoking marijuana had essentially the same academic records as those who didn’t smoke it, and both groups were equally involved in traditional “school spirit” activities. Both groups seemed to feel equally well integrated into campus life. There were other differences between the groups, however: 1. Women were less likely than men to smoke marijuana. 2. Asian students (a large proportion of the student body) were less likely to smoke marijuana than non-Asians were. 3. Students living at home were less likely to smoke marijuana than those who were living in their own apartments. As in the case of religiosity, the three variables independently affected the likelihood of a student’s smoking marijuana. About 10 percent of the Asian women living at home had smoked marijuana, in contrast to about 80 percent of the non-Asian men living in apartments. And, as in the religiosity study, the researchers discovered a powerful pattern of drug use before they had an explanation for that pattern. In this instance, the explanation took a peculiar turn. Instead of explaining why some students smoked marijuana, the researchers explained why some didn’t. Assuming that all students had some motivation for trying drugs, the researchers suggested that students differed in the degree of “social constraints” preventing them from following through on that motivation. U.S. society is, on the whole, more permissive with men than with women when it comes to deviant behavior. Consider, for example, a group of men getting drunk and boisterous. We tend to dismiss such behavior with references to “camaraderie” and “having a good time,” whereas a group of women behaving similarly would probably be regarded with disapproval. We have an idiom, “Boys will be boys,” but no comparable idiom for girls. The researchers reasoned, therefore, that women would have more to lose by smoking marijuana than men would. In other words, being female provided a constraint against smoking marijuana. Students living at home had obvious constraints against smoking marijuana, compared with students living on their own. Quite aside from differences in opportunity, those living at home were seen as being more dependent on their parents—hence more vulnerable to additional punishment for breaking the law. Finally, the Asian subculture in Hawaii has traditionally placed a higher premium on obedience to the law than other subcultures have, so Asian students would have more to lose if they were caught violating the law by smoking marijuana. Overall, then, a “social constraints” theory was offered as the explanation for observed differences in the likelihood of smoking marijuana. The more constraints a student had, the less likely he or she would be to smoke marijuana. It bears repeating that the researchers had no thoughts about such a theory when their research began. The theory came from an examination of the data. The Links betweenTheory and Research Throughout this chapter, we have seen various aspects of the links between theory and research in social science inquiry. In the deductive model, research is used to test theories. In the inductive model, theories are developed from the analysis of research data. This final section looks more closely into the ways theory and research are related in actual social science inquiry. Whereas we have discussed two idealized logical models for linking theory and research, social science inquiries have developed a great many variations on these themes. Sometimes theoretical issues are introduced merely as a background for empirical analyses. Other studies cite selected empirical data to bolster theoretical arguments. In neither case do theory and research really interact for the purpose of developing new explanations. Some studies make no use of theory at all, aiming specifically, for example, at an ethnographic description of a particular social situation, such as an anthropological account of food and dress in a particular society. As you read social research reports, however, you’ll often find that the authors are conscious of the implications of their research for social theories and vice versa. 58 ■ Chapter 2: Paradigms, Theory, and Social Research Research Ethics andTheory In Chapter 1, I introduced the subject of research ethics and said we would return to that topic throughout the book. At this point, what ethical issues do you suppose theory engenders? In this chapter, we have seen how the paradigms and theories that guide research inevitably impact what is observed and how it is interpreted. Choosing a particular paradigm or theory does not guarantee a particular research conclusion, but it will affect what you look for and what you ignore. Whether you choose a functionalist or a conflict paradigm to organize your research on police–community relations, for example, will make a big difference. This is a difficult issue to resolve in practice. Choosing a theoretical orientation for the purpose of encouraging a particular conclusion would be regarded as unethical as a general matter, but when research is linked to an intention to bring about social change, the researcher will likely choose a theoretical orientation appropriate to that intention. Let’s say you’re concerned about the treatment of homeless people by the police in your community. You might organize your research in terms of interactionist or conflict paradigms and theories that would reveal any instances of mistreatment that may occur. Two factors counter the potential problem of bias from theoretical orientation. First, as we’ll see in the remainder of the book, social science research techniques—the various methods of observation and analysis—place a damper on our simply seeing what we expect. Even if you expect to find the police mistreating the homeless and use theories and methods that will reveal such mistreatment, you will not observe what isn’t there if you apply those theories and methods appropriately. Second, the collective nature of social research offers further protection. As we’ll discuss more in Chapter 17, peer review in which researchers evaluate each other’s efforts will point to instances of shoddy and/or biased research. Moreover, with several researchers studying the same phenomenon, perhaps using different paradigms, theories, and methods, the risk of biased research findings is further reduced. Main Points Introduction ●● Theories function in three ways in research: (1) helping to avoid flukes, (2) making sense of observed patterns, and (3) shaping and directing research efforts. Some Social Science Paradigms ●● Social scientists use a variety of paradigms to organize how they understand and inquire into social life. ●● A distinction between types of theories that cut across various paradigms is macrotheory (theories about large-scale features of society) versus microtheory (theories about smaller units or features of society). ●● The positivistic paradigm assumes that we can scientifically discover the rules governing social life. ●● The Social Darwinist paradigm sees a progressive evolution in social life. ●● The conflict paradigm focuses on the attempt of individuals and groups to dominate others and to avoid being dominated. ●● The symbolic interactionist paradigm examines how shared meanings and social patterns develop in the course of social interactions. ●● Ethnomethodology focuses on the ways people make sense out of social life in the process of living it, as though each were a researcher engaged in an inquiry. ●● The structural functionalist (or social systems) paradigm seeks to discover what functions the many elements of society perform for the whole system. ●● Feminist paradigms, in addition to drawing attention to the oppression of women in most societies, highlight how previous images of social reality have often come from, and reinforced, the experiences of men. ●● Like feminist paradigms, critical race theory both examines the disadvantaged position of a social group (African Americans) and offers a different vantage point from which to view and understand society. ●● Some contemporary theorists and researchers have challenged the long-standing belief in an objective reality that abides by rational rules. They point out that it is possible to agree on an “intersubjective” reality, a view that characterizes postmodernism. Elements of Social Theory ●● The elements of social theory include observations, facts, and laws (which relate to the reality being observed), as well as concepts, variables, axioms Review Questions and Exercises ■ 59 or postulates, propositions, and hypotheses (which are logical building blocks of the theory itself). Two Logical Systems Revisited ●● In the traditional image of science, scientists proceed from theory to operationalization to observation. But this image does not accurately depict how scientific research is actually done. ●● Social scientific theory and research are linked through the two logical methods of deduction (the derivation of expectations and hypotheses from theories) and induction (the development of generalizations from specific observations). ●● In practice, science is a process involving an alternation of deduction and induction. Deductive Theory Construction ●● Guillermina Jasso’s theory of distributive justice illustrates how formal reasoning can lead to a variety of theoretical expectations that can be tested by observation. Inductive Theory Construction ●● David Takeuchi’s study of factors influencing marijuana smoking among University of Hawaii students illustrates how collecting observations can lead to generalizations and an explanatory theory. The Links between Theory and Research ●● In practice, there are many possible links between theory and research and many ways of going about social inquiry. Research Ethics and Theory ●● Researchers should not use paradigm and theory selection as a means of achieving desired research results. ●● The collective nature of social research offers protection against biased research findings. Key Terms The following terms are defined in context in the chapter and at the bottom of the page where the term is introduced, as well as in the comprehensive glossary at the back of the book. Proposing Social Research: Theory As this chapter has indicated, social research can be pursued within numerous theoretical paradigms— each suggesting a somewhat different way to approach the research question. In this portion of your proposal, you should identify the paradigm(s) that will shape the design of your research. We have also seen that paradigms provide frameworks within which causal theories may be developed. Perhaps your research project will explore or test an existing theory. Or more ambitiously, you may propose a theory or hypothesis for testing. This is the section of the proposal in which to describe this aspect of your project. Not all research projects are formally organized around the creation and/or testing of theories and hypotheses. However, your research will involve theoretical concepts, which should be described in this section of the proposal. As we’ll see more fully in Chapter 17, this portion of your proposal will reflect the literature on previous theory and research that has shaped your own thinking and research plans. Review Questions and Exercises 1. Consider the possible relationship between education and prejudice that was mentioned in Chapter 1. Describe how you might examine that relationship through (a) deductive and (b) inductive methods. 2. Review the relationships between theory and research discussed in this chapter. Select a research article from an academic journal and classify the relationship between theory and research you find there. 3. Using one of the many search engines (such as Google, Bing, Yahoo, Chrome, or another of your choosing), find information on the web concerning at least three of the following paradigms: functionalism, symbolic interactionism, conflict paradigm, ethnomethodology, feminist paradigms, critical race theory, rational objectivity. Give the web locations and report on the theorists discussed in connection with the information you found. 4. See if you can locate Judith A. Howard (2000), “Social Psychology of Identities,” Annual Review of Sociology 26:367–93. doi: 10.1146. What paradigm does Howard find most useful for the study of social identities? Explain why she feels that it is the appropriate paradigm. Do you agree? Why or why not? big data conflict paradigm critical race theory critical realism feminist paradigms hypothesis interest convergence macrotheory microtheory null hypothesis operational definition operationalization paradigm positivism postmodernism structural functionalism symbolic interactionism