Chapter 1 Numerals and their kin Author Affiliation In this paper, I focus on the meaning of numerals, i.e., lexical items that express a relationship with numbers. I discuss different functions that cardinal numerals can have including their quantifying and arithmetical use and compare various attempts to capture the relationship between those functions. Furthermore, I examine several types of complex numerical expressions such as ordinals, collective and taxonomic numerals and multipliers in Slavic in comparison to other languages. Finally, I bring novel data concerning Slavic label numerals, i.e., expressions used to identify entities via association with a number and propose a morpho-semantic analysis of such expressions. The core of the proposal is that the arithmetical meaning is the numerals’ underlying semantic core from which both the quantifying and the label meaning are derived. Keywords: numerals, cardinals, numerical expressions, labels 1 Introduction Numerals are funny words. On the one hand, it seems they share some core component that justifies grouping them together as if they formed a single category, a practice common in both descriptive and theoretic approaches to language.1 On the other hand, though, morphologically and syntactically they form a very heterogeneous class of expressions with different items often exhibiting distinct properties. This is the case not only when one compares various subclasses of numerals, e.g., cardinals, ordinals and multiplicatives, but also often within the subclass of cardinals different items have adjectival, nominal, or both nominal 1This intuition dates back at least to the Neo-Latin grammarian tradition, which distinguished between three subclasses within the category nomen, i.e., nomen substantivum, nomen adjectivum and nomen numerale. Author. Numerals and their kin. To appear in: Change Volume Editor & in localcommands.tex Change volume title in localcommands.tex Berlin: Language Science Press. [preliminary page numbering] Author and adjectival features while in some languages they seem to behave as verbs (Donohue 2005; Ionin & Matushansky 2018). In generative linguistics, a lot of work has been focused on establishing the syntactic status of numerals with different approaches differing in whether they are lexical or functional categories or whether they are heads or maximal projections. These questions have been studied thoroughly with respect to Slavic numerals with their well-known idiosyncratic properties (e.g., Babby 1987; Pesetsky 1982; Franks 1994; Rutkowski 2002; Klockmann 2012). On the other hand, since the early days of analytic philosophy and formal semantics a lot of attention has been dedicated to the meaning of numerals. At least from Frege (1884), it has been recognized that capturing the semantics of cardinals is far from trivial. Intuitively, it seems straightforward that they are linguistic expressions that somehow describe a numeric quantity. However, beyond this vague characterization it is much less obvious how to state exactly what they actually are. In this paper, I will discuss the main formal approaches to the meaning of cardinal numerals. In doing so, I will also focus on examining two issues that only recently have attracted due attention in the semantic literature. Specifically, I will investigate different uses of cardinals as well as various derivationally complex quantifying expressions in Slavic. The two sets of data indicate that cardinals are typally flexibile and that numerals in general are semantically complex expressions. I will argue that a proper approach to the meaning of numerals should describe a compositional mechanism deriving different semantic flavors from the underlying arithmetical meaning. The paper is outlined as follows. In §2, I will discuss various functions of cardinal numerals. §3 will provide an overview of different semantic approaches to the quantifying function of cardinals, as in five cats. Next, §4 will explore the relationship between the quantifying meaning and the ability of cardinals to refer to abstract arithmetical concepts. In §5, I will review the literature on the morphosemantics of complex numerical expressions in Slavic which presents evidence calling for a compositional treatment. §6 is a case study in which I will explore the so-far neglected label use of numerals. Finally, §7 concludes the paper. 2 Cardinals and their various flavors Let us start with cardinal numerals. One of the challenges in accounting for their meaning is that they can be used in very different ways (Bultinck 2005; Geurts 2006). Consider, for instance, (1). It turns out that a simple word such as English ii Numerals and their kin five is in fact quite tricky. Of course, it can be used to quantify over entities denoted by the modified NP when it appears prenominally as in (1a) but that is surely not the only function it can have. For instance, when it combines with a measure word as in (1b), it designates a portion of a substance rather than a plurality of objects. It can also appear in a predicative context such as (1c) or as part of a measure phrase like in (1d). And that is not it since it can also be used to refer to an abstract arithmetical concept, see (1e), or to label an entity as in (1f). (1) a. Five cats meowed. b. Five liters of milk got spilled. c. These are five cats. d. That cat is five years old. e. Five is a Fibonacci number. f. Player number five twisted her ankle. Below, I will briefly discuss how the measure, predicative and arithmetical function of cardinal numerals relate to their most deeply studied quantifying use.2 A thorough investigation into properties of the label function will be undertaken in §6. 2.1 Quantifying vs. measure use For many years, the mainstream research has been primarily focused on the quantifying use of cardinals exemplified in (1a). This seems justified since counting objects is perhaps the first thing that comes to mind when we think about expressions such as five. However, when a numeral appears in a measure phrase such as (1b), it seems to be involved in measuring within a certain dimension, e.g., volume, rather than in counting objects. Intuitively, the difference between counting and measuring is that the former is about specifying how many discrete objects of a certain kind there are, whereas the latter determines some quantity in relevant measure units. Admittedly, some proposals attempt to reduce measuring to a particular type of counting based on the individuation in terms of quantity (Lyons 1977; Matushansky & Zwarts 2017). Consequently, measuring would simply be counting units determined by measure words. An opposing approach treats counting as a form of measuring, i.e., measuring a quantity of a plural individual in terms of natural or object units 2For an exhaustive discussion of numeral NPs interpreted as measure phrases in Slavic, see Matushansky & Ionin (this volume). iii Author (Krifka 1989; 1995). Yet, there is also the third account which views counting and measuring as two independent operations (Rothstein 2017). The contrast between the two functions becomes clear when one considers classifier constructions involving container nouns, see (2). Such expressions are ambiguous between a measure (content) and counting (container) interpretation (e.g., Landman 2004; Grimshaw 2007; Partee & Borschev 2012). On the measure reading of (2a), Tomek flushed wine to the quantity of two bottles. On the counting reading, on the other hand, he did something quite spectacular since two actual bottles containing wine went down. Moreover, derivational morphology seems to be sensitive to the distinction since the suffix -ful selects only for the measure sense of a container noun, compare (2b)–(2c) (Rothstein 2011). (2) a. Tomek flushed two bottles of wine through the toilet. b. Romek added two { glasses / glassfuls } of wine to the soup. c. Marek brought two { glasses / #glassfuls } of wine for our guests. Another argument for distinguishing counting and measuring as two distinct operations comes from distinct restrictions on the domain of quantification (Wągiel 2018). Though both measuring and counting quantify over entities that need to be disjoint (Landman 2016), only the latter requires objects individuated as coherent integrated wholes. To realize the contrast, imagine someone has spilled some wine on the table in such a way that there are two separate blobs a and b whose volume is exactly one and a half milliliters each. In such a scenario, (3a) is true despite the fact that one of the three milliliters must be split between a portion of a and a portion of b. On the other hand, (3b) is simply false. This contrast shows that measuring, unlike counting, ignores individuation in terms of integrity. (3) Scenario: There are exactly two 1.5 ml blobs of wine on the table. a. There are three milliliters of wine on the table. true b. There are three objects on the table. false Though monotonic systems of measurement track certain part-whole relations (Schwarzschild 2002), they do not seem to be sensitive to the spatial arrangement of parts making up a whole. This suggests that despite sharing a common core counting and measuring are two distinct things. 2.2 Quantifying vs. predicative use It is well known that cardinals used as quantifiers give rise to scalar implicatures. For instance, five cats in (4a) allows for an at least reading, as witnessed by the iv Numerals and their kin compatibility with the in fact clause. Similarly, (4b) is typically interpreted in a way that Tomek must take at least three cards. (4) a. Five cats live in the barn; in fact, six cats live there. b. Tomek must take three cards. However, numeral NPs in predicate position systematically lack a lower-bounded interpretation (Partee 1986; Landman 2003; Geurts 2006). For instance, (5a) can only get the exactly reading. This is further corroborated by the infelicity of sentences such as (5b). (5) a. These are five cats. b. # The guests are three filmmakers; in fact, they are four filmmakers. Furthermore, it has been observed that also bare cardinals can appear as predicates in predicate position, see (6a)–(6b) (Rothstein 2017). This resembles the behavior of adjectives rather than determiners. (6) a. The apostles are twelve. b. The planets are eight. Similarly to numeral NPs, bare cardinals in predicate position lack an at least reading. Thus both (6a) and (6b) are true if there are exactly twelve apostles and exactly eight planets, respectively. Furthermore, sentences such as (7) are infelic- itous. (7) # My reasons for saying this are four; in fact they are five. The contrasts discussed above indicate that meaning of the predicative use of cardinals differs from their semantics in the quantifying function. 2.3 Quantifying vs. arithmetical use It is not always the case that cardinals designate a plurality or measure. In (1e), five refers to an abstract number concept rather than to a collection of entities. In this use, cardinals have different properties than in their quantifying function (Bultinck 2005; Rothstein 2017; Wągiel & Caha 2020). Specifically, number concepts can have special properties such as being prime, see (8a), and they can occur in mathematical statements such as (8b) and dedicated grammatical construction as in (8c). When compared, the dimension of comparison is based on their relative ordering, see (8d). v Author (8) a. Five is prime. b. Ten divided by five equals two. c. Hanna can count up to five. d. Five is bigger than four. This behavior contrasts with cardinals in their quantifying function, which lack the properties mentioned above. (9a) is odd since being prime is not a property that can be attributed to a collection of things. Similarly, expressions denoting a plurality of entities are illicit in constructions calling for a numeric value such as (9b)–(9c). Finally, (9d) has different truth conditions than (8d), e.g., it would not be true if one compared five cherries with four watermelons. (9) a. # Five things are prime. b. # Ten things divided by five things equals two things. c. # Hanna can count up to five things. d. # Five things are bigger than four things. Furthermore, cardinals referring to number concepts are incompatible with numeral modifiers such as more than and at least, see (10a). Finally, the arithmetical function does not give rise to scalar implicatures and always get an exactly reading, as witnessed in (10b). (10) a. # More than five is prime. b. # Two multiplied by five equals ten, if not more. As we have seen, cardinal numerals can be used in various ways each of which has different semantic characteristics. In the next two sections, I will review major approaches to the meaning of cardinals and compare how they account for at least some aspects of the flexibility discussed above. 3 Theories of cardinals Given the variety of uses discussed in the previous section, any quest for ‘the’ meaning of cardinal numerals is probably a misunderstanding. Rather, a theory of cardinals should be able to capture the relationship between meanings of cardinals in their various functions. And yet, the mainstream research has been mainly focused on the quantifying use often ignoring how it relates to other uses (with Bylinina & Nouwen’s 2020 systematic inquiry being a notable exception). vi Numerals and their kin 3.1 Cardinals as determiners Let us start with the earliest and most prominent formal account of the meaning of cardinal numerals, namely the standard Generalized Quantifiers (GQ) approach (Barwise & Cooper 1981; though it can be traced back via Montague to Frege). The intuition behind this analysis is that a cardinal such as English five is in fact a determiner similar to some, most or all, as suggested by its occurrence in prenominal position as in (11). (11) { Some / Most / All / Five } cats meowed. In the GQ theory, a determiner expresses a particular relation holding between two sets (type ⟨⟨e,t⟩, ⟨⟨e,t⟩,t⟩⟩), i.e., a set denoted by the NP and a set denoted by the VP. For instance, in (11) some yields the truth value True if the intersection between the set of cats and the set of entities that meowed is non-empty, see (12a). Similarly, on the GQ analysis five returns True if the cardinality of the set of cats and the set of entities that meowed equals 5, see (12b). (12) a. some = λPλQ[P ∩ Q ] b. five = λPλQ[|P ∩ Q| = 5] A nice thing about the GQ approach is that it aims to develop a unified semantics of all quantified DPs. Furthermore, it can be enriched with a type-shifting mechanism which allows for systematic mapping between different semantic types (Partee 1986). Consequently, the theory can account for predicative uses of numeral NPs such as (1c) by lowering the type of a general quantifier (⟨⟨e,t⟩,t⟩) to the type of a predicate (⟨e,t⟩). However, for some time it has been realized that the GQ approach is most probably not a good way of capturing what cardinals are (e.g., Krifka 1999; Landman 2003). In the next sections, I will briefly discuss problematic data and alternative approaches. 3.2 Cardinals as predicates There are several problems with the GQ approach to cardinals. First of all, there is a well-known asymmetry between DPs with numerals and DPs with regular determiners in predicate position. For instance, DPs headed by every cannot be used predicatively, see (13a). Similarly, examples such as (13b) are infelicitous on a non-partitive interpretation. Given the felicity of sentences such as (1c) and others discussed in §2.2, this fact is puzzling (e.g., Landman 2003). vii Author (13) a. # Hanna is every filmmaker at the party. b. # The guests are { most / some } filmmakers. Furthermore, as witnessed in (14a) bare determiners also cannot be used predicatively. This contrasts with examples such as (6), in which cardinals pattern with adjectives, see (14b). Since there is no standard type-shifting rule allowing for mapping the type of determiners (⟨⟨e,t⟩, ⟨⟨e,t⟩,t⟩⟩) onto the type of predicates (⟨e,t⟩), the predicative use of bare cardinals is unaccounted for. But even if such a rule were postulated, it would still fail to explain the contrast between cardinals and determiners such most and all. (14) a. # My reasons for saying this are { most / all / every }. b. My reasons for saying this are { serious / personal / five }. The last problematic data point to be discussed here concerns the fact that cardinals can appear along with bona fide determiners within a single DP (e.g., Rothstein 2017). From the GQ perspective, the compatibility of five with the definite article in (15a) and with every in (15b) is unexpected and raises serious questions regarding the semantic contribution of each of the elements. (15) a. The five cats that I saw meowed. b. Every two students got to share a hotel room. The evidence discussed above motivated developing an alternative approach, which treats cardinals as predicates (Landman 2003; 2004). Within such a framework, cardinals get an interpretation very similar to that of intersective adjectives, specifically they express a cardinality property. For this approach to work, it is required to distinguish between two types of entities within the domain of individuals, namely atoms, i.e., singular entities, and pluralities (Link 1983). While atoms are minimal elements of a nominal denotation, pluralities are formed from atoms via a pluralization operation * which closes the predicate under sum, i.e., takes a set of atomic entities and returns that set extended with all the pluralities that can be formed by summing the atoms. In addition, the two types of individuals are associated with each other via a part-whole relation defined in terms of mereological parthood, e.g., an atomic entity a is part of a plurality a ⊕ b.3 According to the semantics provided in (16a), five denotes a set of pluralities each of which contains 5 atomic entities. Similarly to intersective adjectives, cardinals combine with NPs they modify via Predicate Modification (Heim & Kratzer 3For an introduction to mereological theories of plurality, see, e.g., Champollion & Krifka (2016). viii Numerals and their kin 1998). Therefore, when five is composed with cats, see (16b), the resulting phrase denotes the intersection of a set of pluralities of cats and a set of plural individuals that consist of five atomic entities, i.e., a set of sums of five cats. (16) a. five = λx[#(x) = 5] b. five cats = λx[*cat(x) ∧ #(x) = 5] The approach discussed above gives a straightforward explanation for the contrasts between cardinals and determiners such every and most in predicate position as well as the well-formedness and felicity of constructions such as those in (15). However, it faces some challenges as well. 3.3 Cardinals as predicate modifiers A problem with treating cardinals as cardinal properties is that cross-linguistically the use of bare cardinals in predicate position is very restricted (Ionin & Matushansky 2018: 33–34). For instance, in Russian (17) is ungrammatical. Similarly, Dutch (18) can only mean that the children are two years old and not that they are two in number. And even in English the predicative use of bare cardinals is heavily restrained, as witnessed by the fact that examples such as (19) are highly degraded. If cardinals are assigned type ⟨e,t⟩, then this is rather startling. (17) * Deti children byli were { dva two / dvoe }. two.gndr Intended: ‘The children were two in number.’ (Russian) (18) # De the kinderen children zijn are twee. two Intended: ‘The children are two in number.’ (Dutch) (19) ⁇ The chairs in this room are twelve. Another issue concerns the fact that what counts as ‘one’ seems to be highly dependent on the meaning of the NP the cardinal combines with. Arguably, atoms should be defined relative to a particular property rather than in absolute terms. To see why, let us consider partitive constructions such as those in (20) (see Chierchia 2010; Wągiel 2018). Example (20a) is weird since the numeral NP designates triples of body parts and cannot be understood as referring to three pluralities of boys. Yet, in (20b) quantification over subgroups of boys is possible. Importantly, neither parts of the boys nor parts of the group denote entities that are atomic in ix Author any absolute sense. The first is true of portions of matter whose parts are also parts of the boys. Similarly, the latter designates subgroups which themselves can also consist of subgroups of boys. This suggests that the cardinal determines what counts as ‘one’ relative to the denotation of the modified NP (and possibly some contextual hints, see Rothstein 2010) and it is not obvious how this fact could be captured if cardinals were interpreted simply as intersective predicates. (20) a. # Three parts of the boys were sleeping. b. Three parts of the group were sleeping. A prominent alternative to treating cardinals as cardinal properties is to analyze them as predicate modifiers (type ⟨⟨e,t⟩, ⟨e,t⟩⟩) equipped with a pluralization operation * and a measure function #(P) (Krifka 1989; 1995). In (21a), * closes the predicate under sum, i.e., takes a set of atomic entities and returns that set extended with all the pluralities one can form by summing atoms. On the other hand, the operation # returns for a property P a measure function that yields pluralities of five individuals having that property. In other words, five maps pluralities of entities onto the natural number 5.4 When the cardinal combines with an NP, after the predicate slot is saturated we obtain a set of relevant plural individuals (type ⟨e,t⟩). For instance, five cats denotes a set of pluralities of cats each of which consists of five cats, see (21b). Thus, what counts as ‘one’ in this system is relativized to the denotation of the NP. (21) a. five = λP⟨e,t ⟩λxe [*P(x) ∧ #(P)(x) = 5] b. five cats = λxe [*cat(x) ∧ #(cat)(x) = 5] Another possibility is to interpret cardinals as predicate modifiers providing the cardinality of a partition of a plural individual (Ionin & Matushansky 2006; 2018). A partition of a plurality x is a cover of x, i.e., a set of entities such that the sum of all those entities forms x; in addition, it is a cover whose cells do not overlap, i.e., do not share any parts (see Gillon 1987; Schwarzschild 1996). In (22a), S is a partition Π of an individual x and the cardinality of S equals 5. The cardinal combines with the NP via standard Function Application and the result is of type ⟨e,t⟩. For instance, five cats gets the meaning in (22b), i.e., it denotes a set of pluralities divisible into 5 non-overlapping entities each of which has a property 4This is a slight simplification since in fact Krifka (1989) postulates a special operation nu for measuring pluralities in terms of ‘natural units’ they consist of, whereas Krifka (1995) proposes ou for measuring the number of ‘object units’ realizing a particular kind. x Numerals and their kin of being a cat.5 (22) a. five = λP⟨e,t ⟩λxe ∃S⟨e,t ⟩[Π(S)(x) ∧ |S| = 5 ∧ ∀s ∈ S[P(s)]] b. five cats = λxe ∃S⟨e,t ⟩[Π(S)(x) ∧ |S| = 5 ∧ ∀s ∈ S[ cat (s)]] Notice, however, that both approaches discussed above require the denotation of NPs the cardinal combines with to be singular, i.e., to consist only of atoms. It is postulated that the source of plurality is the numeral and the plural marking on the noun is, e.g., due to agreement with no semantic interpretation. Supporting evidence comes from expressions such as those in (23) where the plural is not associated with a plurality (Krifka 1989; Bylinina & Nouwen 2018) as well as from languages such as Finnish and Turkish which display the singular/plural distinction but in which unlike in, say, English cardinals systematically require singular NPs, see (24). (23) a. zero students b. 1.0 students (24) üç three { çocuk child / *çocuklar } children ‘three children’ (Turkish) Finally, analyzing cardinals as predicate modifiers makes it easier to account for restrictions on bare cardinals in predicate position, see (18)–(19), by appealing to the well-described peculiarities of the copula which would allow for a type-shift only under particular circumstances (Ionin & Matushansky 2018: 33–34). 3.4 Cardinals as degree quantifiers The last approach to be discussed in this sections builds on two observations regarding the behavior of cardinals. The first observation is that sentences with existential modals such as those in (25) are ambiguous (Kennedy 2013; 2015). On the strong reading, (25a) means that Hanna is allowed to eat five cookies and she is not allowed to eat more. The strong reading is probably the most natural interpretation of (25a). There is, however, also a weak reading which merely states that eating five cookies by Hanna is allowed without saying anything about eating other quantities of cookies. This interpretation becomes more prominent in questions, see (25b). 5The system is devised this way in order to provide a unified analysis of both simple and complex numerals such as five hundred. For a more detailed discussion of the approach, see Matushansky & Ionin (this volume). xi Author (25) a. Hanna is allowed to eat five cookies. b. Is Hanna allowed to eat five cookies? The second observation is that numerals can take scope independently of the rest of the NP. The evidence comes from decimals in sentences such as (26a) (Kennedy & Stanley 2009). Crucially, it does not entail the existence of families with 2.1 cats. This contrasts with (26b) which is infelicitous due to such an entailment. (26) a. The average Polish family has 2.1 cats. b. # A normal Polish family has 2.1 cats. The data discussed above suggest that cardinal numerals are in fact quantifiers. We have already seen that the analysis of five as a determiner is most probably incorrect and obviously treating it as a generalized quantifier over individuals (type ⟨⟨e,t⟩,t⟩) would not make much sense. However, an interesting idea is to interpret cardinals as quantifiers over degrees, i.e., expressions of type ⟨⟨d,t⟩,t⟩ (Kennedy 2013; 2015). Degrees (type d) are objects similar to individuals (type e) with the crucial difference that the domain of degrees Dd , unlike the domain of individuals De , is ordered.6 Hence, on the degree quantifier analysis five denotes a set of degree properties whose maximal value equals 5, see (27a). A sentence with a numeral NP would be then interpreted as in (27b), e.g., the maximal number of entities that Hanna had and that are cats is 5. (27) a. five = λD⟨d,t ⟩[MAX(D) = 5] b. Hanna had five cats = = MAX{n | ∃x[had(x)(hanna) ∧ *cat(x) ∧ #(x) = n)} = 5 The analysis of cardinals as degree quantifiers provides a promising perspective to explain interactions between modals and both unmodified and modified cardinals such as more than five and at least five (Nouwen 2010). In the next section, I will discuss the arithmetical function of cardinals and how it relates to the theories described so far. 4 Relating cardinalities and number concepts The theories of cardinal numerals discussed so far focus on the quantifying function. However, as we have already seen in (1e) and §2.3, cardinals can also be used to refer to abstract numeric values. 6For more discussion on degrees and an introduction to degree semantics, see, e.g., Morzycki (2016: Ch. 3). xii Numerals and their kin 4.1 Cardinals as names of numbers On the arithmetical function, cardinals seem to behave as proper names of number concepts (type n) or, alternatively, degrees (type d).7 From this perspective, the arithmetical meaning of five is simply the number 5, see (28a). Expressions such as prime would then denote properties of numbers (type ⟨n,t⟩). For instance the extension of (28b) would be the set {2, 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, . . . }. On the other hand, expressions used to formulate mathematical statements such as plus, times, divided by and equals seem to describe relations between number concepts. For instance, (28c) is interpreted in terms of addition of two numeric values. (28) a. five = 5 b. prime = λnn[prime(n)] c. plus = λnnλmn[n + m] The key question is what the relationship between names of number concepts, i.e., the arithmetical use, and meanings of cardinals used in the quantifying function is. In the next sections, I will discuss two possible approaches to how to relate the two meanings. 4.2 Deriving number concepts from cardinalities The mainstream view is to take the quantifying meaning as basic, be it the predicate, predicate modifier or degree quantifier analysis, and to derive the arithmetical meaning from it. Let us discuss three variants of that view. As we have already seen in §3.2, on the predicate analysis cardinals are interpreted as denoting a cardinal property, see (29a). Rothstein (2017) assumes this semantics to be basic.8 The arithmetical meaning is then derived via a special type-shifting operation ∩ which when applied to a cardinal property yields a proper name, see (29b). (29) a. five ⟨e,t ⟩ = λxe [#(x) = 5] b. five n = ∩ five ⟨e,t ⟩ = 5 7Throughout the paper, I will assume there is no difference between the two notions and following the widespread convention in the literature on the arithmetical use of cardinals I will simply use the label n. 8In fact, this is a slight simplification since the theory distinguishes typally between lower numerals and ‘lexical powers’, i.e., multiplicands such as hundred in five hundred. xiii Author The proposal is seemingly motivated by an analogy with adjectival and nominal uses of expressions such as white. It builds on Chierchia’s (1985) theory of predication according to which every property has an entity correlate of type π derived by ∩. For instance, the predicate white can be turned into the name of the property of being white. Similarly, ∩ turns five into the name of the property of being five in number. However, as argued convincingly by Ionin & Matushansky (2018: 31–33) this analogy does not hold since arithmetical environments such as those discussed in §2.3 require the number 5 itself as an argument rather than the property of being five in number. Consequently, in order to derive the arithmetical function Ionin & Matushansky (2018: 26–27) propose a null suffix NOMNUM which is a nominalizer that when applied to a predicate modifier, turns it into a numeric singular term. More specifically, for any cardinal numeral it yields the corresponding cardinality. An argument for such an account comes from the fact that cardinal numerals as names of numbers display full morpho-syntactic uniformity suggesting they are derived expressions. On the other hand, cardinals in the quantifying function often show variation with respect to φ-features, e.g., grammatical gender. Another mode of relating the arithmetical and quantifying meaning is proposed by Kennedy (2015). The idea is to derive the first from the latter by the standard type-shifting operations BE and IOTA defined in (30a) and (30b), respectively (Partee 1986). BE takes a quantifier and returns a property. On the other hand, IOTA yields the unique entity of which the relevant property is true. (30) a. BE = λP⟨⟨e,t, ⟩,t ⟩λxe [P(λye [y = x])] b. IOTA = λP⟨e,t ⟩ιx[P(x)] Generalizing the type-shifts defined above so that they can also apply to quantifiers over degrees and properties of degrees (or numbers), respectively, allows to derive the arithmetical meaning by applying BE and IOTA consecutively to the degree quantifier semantics. Specifically, when BE applies to a set of degree properties whose maximal value equals 5, see (27a), the result in (31a) is the singleton set {5}. The subsequent application of IOTA yields the number 5, as shown in (31b). (31) a. BE( five ) = λnn[n = 5] b. IOTA(BE( five )) = IOTA(λnn[n = 5]) = 5 A nice feature of such an approach is that it allows to relate the quantifying and arithmetical functions using standard independently motivated type-shifting machinery. In the next section, I will discuss accounts that derive cardinalities from the arithmetical meaning. xiv Numerals and their kin 4.3 Deriving cardinalities from number concepts Though the view that the quantifying function of cardinals is the basic one seems to have become mainstream, there are a number of approaches that build on a contrary intuition, namely that underlyingly cardinal numerals are simply names of number concepts (e.g., Scha 1981; Krifka 1989; Scontras 2014; Wągiel 2018). According to that alternative view, cardinals in prenominal position are in fact syntactically and semantically complex expressions derived from the arithmetical meaning via various shifts. An early theory of cardinals postulating that they are derived from number concepts was developed by Scha (1981). This system distinguishes between numbers, numerals and numerical determiners. The first simply denote number concepts. On the other hand, the numeral head shifts an integer (typen) to a cardinal predicate while the numerical D head transforms such a cardinal predicate into a determiner with a GQ-style semantics, see (32).9 (32) [ d⟨⟨e,t ⟩, ⟨⟨e,t ⟩,t ⟩⟩ [ numeral⟨e,t ⟩ [ numbern five ] ] ] A related idea is the core of the system developed by Hackl (2000) who makes use of a covert quantificational operator MANY in order to turn a number concept into a determiner, see (33a). On this approach, the cardinal on its quantifying use is accompanied with an additional null element that ensures the shift, as depicted in (33b). The result combines with the denotation of the NP to form a generalized quantifier. (33) a. MANY = λnnλP⟨e,t ⟩λQ⟨e,t ⟩∃xe [#(x) = n ∧ P(x) ∧ Q(x)] b. five cats = [ [ 5 MANY ] cats ] Another proposal on how to derive the quantifying meaning from a name of a number concept dates back to Krifka (1995). On this view, all cardinals are assumed to underlyingly designate number concepts but they also involve an additional classifier element that depending on a language can be either overt or covert. There are several variants of this approach but what they all share is that such a classifier element takes an integer and returns a counting device equipped with an appropriate measure function, see (34a) (Scontras 2014; Wągiel 2018). For instance, in the derivation of the phrase five cats the name of a number concept 9The exact denotation of the numerical determiner depends on whether the whole sentence gets a collective, distributive or cover reading. In other words, there are three distinct Ds each of which deriving a different interpretation. xv Author is first turned into a quantifying predicate modifier which then combines with the noun to yield the meaning in (34b). (34) a. CL = λnnλP⟨e,t ⟩λxe [*P(x) ∧ #(P)(x) = n] b. five cats = [ [ 5 CL ] cats ] = λxe [*cat(x) ∧ #(x) = 5] In yet another variant of the discussed approach, the classifier semantics turns an arithmetical concept into a predicate (Sudo 2016). The classifier takes a numeric value and yields a cardinal property (type ⟨e,t⟩) rather than a predicate modifier. In addition, it can introduce a special presupposition concerning the nature of referents of the modified noun. The resulting expression then combines with the NP via Predicate Modification. From the theoretical perspective both types of the relationship between the arithmetical and quantifying function, i.e., the derivation from the quantifying meaning to the arithmetical meaning and vice versa, seem plausible. Thus, the question which one is correct appears to be an empirical issue. In §4.2, we have already seen that certain aspects of cardinals’ morphology have been argued to support the quantifying-function-is-basic view. In the next section, I will discuss a different type of evidence that can be useful in determining the direction of the derivation. 4.4 Morphological evidence It has been observed that many languages distinguish formally between so-called counting, i.e., arithmetical, and attributive, i.e., quantifying, numerals (Hurford 1998; 2001). For instance, in Mandarin the form èr ‘two’ is used in arithmetical environments whereas liǎng ‘two’ is an attributive cardinal appearing in the quantifying use. Similarly, the Maltese numeral tnejn ‘two’ indicates the arithmetical function while żewġ ‘two’ has the quantifying meaning. Though the distinction in question is typically restricted to a subset of numerals in a language and there are a number of patterns of how the two forms can differ, it is a relatively widespread phenomenon across languages. Interestingly, the two families of theories discussed above make different predictions regarding the morphological make-up of cardinal numerals cross-linguistically. On the assumption that morphology expresses meaning, if the arithmetical function is derived from the quantifying function, see §4.2, then we would expect that across languages a pattern with arithmetical numerals being morphologically more complex than quantifying cardinals should be relatively widespread. This is because an additional affix is expected to introduce a shift xvi Numerals and their kin from a counting device to a number concept. On the other hand, if the quantifying function is derived from the arithmetical one, see §4.3, then we would expect an inverse pattern to be common. Namely, quantifying cardinals should include an additional morpheme encoding a shift from number concepts to quantifying modifiers. It turns out that the cross-linguistically widespread asymmetry attested, e.g., in many obligatory classifier languages, is of the latter type (Wągiel to appear; Wągiel & Caha 2020). For instance, bare cardinals in Japanese cannot modify NPs and require an additional element, traditionally referred to as a classifier, see (35a).10 However, such an element is illicit in an arithmetical environment like (35b) despite the fact that ko being a general classifier could be used to indicate any type of inanimate entity. (35) a. { *go-no five-gen / go-ko-no } five-clf-gen ringo apple ‘five apples’ b. juu ten waru divided { go-wa five-top / #go-ko-wa } five-clf-top ni-da. two-cop ‘Ten divided by five equals two.’ (Japanese) Therefore, it seems that the approaches that derive the arithmetical semantics from the quantifying one make incorrect predictions with respect to meaning/ form correspondences in cardinals cross-linguistically. However, there is a twist here since a pattern with more complex arithmetical numerals is also attested, though scarce. For instance, in German the arithmetical form for 1 consists of an additional morpheme compared to its quantifying equivalent, see (36). (36) a. { ein one / *ein-s } one-nbr Mädchen girl ‘one girl’ b. Zehn ten geteilt divided durch by { *ein one / ein-s } one-nbr ist is gleich equal zehn. ten ‘Ten divided by one equals ten.’ (German) The pattern attested in German is puzzling and seemingly indicates that both types of relationship between the two functions in question are possible. Never- 10Typically, classifiers also introduce certain restrictions on the referents of the NP modified by the cardinal, e.g., being a round object, a flat object, a plant, a big animal etc. This aspect of their meaning can be captured by accommodating various presuppositions concerning the nature of the denoted individuals (Sudo 2016). xvii Author theless, it can be accounted for by postulating a more complex morpho-semantic structure of numerals along with a spell-out mechanism based on late insertion (Wągiel & Caha 2020). On this analysis, though the arithmetical meaning is more basic, it is still derived from an even more primitive concept of a number scale. The quantifying meaning is then obtained by turning a number concept into a quantificational modifier. The pattern in (36) can be then explained by postulating that ein denotes the concept of a number scale, the suffix -s forges the name of the numerical value and that there is yet another phonologically null morpheme - that shifts the number scale into a counting device. Crucially, not only does such an account capture cross-linguistic variation but also it explains why the German pattern is rare. On the other hand, no alternative explanation of the typological facts that would build on the quantifying meaning as the primitive component has been proposed so far. To conclude, the patterns discussed above suggest that the arithmetical meaning of cardinals is the basic one and that other uses can be derived from it. In the next section, I will discuss complex numerical expressions in Slavic and suggest how this type of evidence can provide further hints on which of the two ways of relating number concepts and cardinalities discussed so far is on the right track. 5 Complex numerical expressions While the mainstream semantic research focuses mostly on cardinal numerals, there is a growing body of formal literature acknowledging that cardinals are in fact only a subset of various numerical expressions. This fact has been well known in Slavic descriptive traditions. Since Slavic languages have a rich morphology, it is not surprising that one can find abundant formal complexity also in numerals. In this section, I will briefly review recent developments in the study of different types of derivationally and semantically complex numerical expressions. Though the focus of the section is on Slavic data, some parallels with other languages will be drawn. 5.1 Ordinals The cross-linguistically most widespread type of derived numerical expressions are ordinal numerals, i.e., forms such as English fifth and Russian pjatyj ‘fifth’. Intuitively, ordinals represent position or rank in a sequential order. If a language distinguishes morphologically a class of ordinals, they are always derived by an xviii Numerals and their kin additional affix (Stolz & Veselinova 2013).11 Perhaps somewhat surprisingly, the semantics of ordinals has been typically linked to superlatives. Cross-linguistically, the two types of expressions often share identical or related morphemes (Hurford 1987; Veselinova 1998)12 and have the same syntax (Barbiers 2007). Furthermore, the acquistion of ordinals seems to be influenced by superlative morphology (Meyer et al. 2018). Even more importantly, ordinals, just like superlatives, give rise to an ambiguity between an absolute and comparative interpretation (Bhatt 2006; Sharvit 2010). On the absolute reading of (37a), John gave Mary a telescope that is older than all other telescopes. On a comparative reading, however, he might have given her a relatively new telescope than happens to be older than the telescopes other people gave her, i.e., John’s gift is compared to other gifts rather that to telescopes in general. Similarly, (37b) can mean either that Mary got a telescope that was older than other telescopes, or that John’s telescope was the first Mary has received. (37) a. John gave Mary the oldest telescope. b. John gave Mary the first telescope. However, it has been observed that ordinals, unlike superlatives, do not give rise to so-called upstairs de dicto readings in sentences with intensional operators such as want (Bylinina et al. 2015). For instance, (38a) can have a particular comparative interpretation which makes it true in the scenario below. Yet, that reading is unavailable for (38b). (38) Scenario: There are many trains throughout the day. John wants to take a train. Any of the trains between 3 pm and 4 pm is fine for him. Similarly, Bill and Steve want to take a train, and they are fine as far as the departure time is between 5 pm and 6 pm and between 7 pm and 8 pm, respectively. These people do not know anything about one another. a. John wants to take the earliest train. true b. John wants to take the first train. false As a result, Bylinina et al. (2015) argue that superlatives and ordinals differ with respect to where they are interpreted. According to that proposal, while superlatives involve movement, ordinals are always interpreted in situ. 11Unless an ordinal is suppletive, e.g., one ∼ first in English. 12Notice that this is also the case in some Slavic languages. For instance, Polish pierw-szy and Ukrainian per-šyj, both ‘first’, contain the comparative markers -szy and -šyj which also appear in superlatives, e.g., naj-star-szy and naj-star-šyj, both ‘the oldest’, respectively. xix Author 5.2 Collective numerals One of the key topics discussed in the literature on plurality regards distributive and collective interpretations of sentences including plural DPs such as (39) (e.g., Scha 1981; Link 1983; Landman 1989; 2000; Schwarzschild 1996). For instance, (39b) is ambiguous between a reading on which a total of three letters have been written, i.e., a distributive interpretation, and a reading on which only one letter has been written, i.e., a collective interpretation. The source of the ambiguity has often been located inside the VP (e.g., Hoeksema 1983; Link 1984; Schwarzschild 1991; see also Lasersohn 1995: Ch. 7 for an overview). (39) a. The boys wrote a letter. b. Three boys wrote a letter. Interestingly, Slavic languages have special numerical expressions which force a collective interpretation of the whole sentence. For instance, consider the Czech sentences in (40) (Dočekal 2012; 2013).13 While (40a) patterns with (39b) in that it is ambiguous between a distributive and a collective reading, the sentence in (40b) rules out the distributive interpretation, and thus the sole possible reading is that only one letter has been written. (40) a. Tři three chlapci boys napsali wrote dopis. letter.acc ✓coll, ✓distr ‘Three boys wrote a letter.’ b. Trojice three.coll chlapců boys.gen napsala wrote dopis. letter.acc ✓coll, # distr ‘A group of three boys wrote a letter.’ (Czech) Since the difference between the two sentences boils down to the alternation between the basic cardinal numeral tři ‘three’ and the morphologically complex derived form trojice ‘group of three’, the suffix -ice has been proposed to be a morphological reflex of a semantic operation forcing a collective interpretation, specifically the group-forming operator ↑ proposed by Landman (1989).14 Importantly, collective numerals cannot be used to refer to number concepts, as witnessed in (41). This fact is surprising if the arithmetic meaning were derived 13In the literature, expressions such as trojice ‘group of three’ have been referred to as collective or group numerals as well as denumeral group nouns (due to their nominal-like behavior). 14The affix -oj- appears only in morphologically complex numerical expressions derived from the roots for 2 and 3 and is usually assumed to have a purely structural function, i.e., it marks non-cardinal stems. xx Numerals and their kin from the quantifying one, see §4.2. Despite the collective meaning component described above, NPs involving collective numerals denote pluralities and one would expect the same shift that is posited to turn the quantificational meaning of a cardinal into the name of a number concept should be applicable also in this case, contrary to facts. (41) a. # Trojice three.coll je is prvočíslo. prime.number Intended: ‘Three is prime.’ b. # Šestice six.coll děleno divided trojicí three.coll.ins je is dvojice. two.coll Intended: ‘Six divided by three is two.’ (Czech) Collective numerals have been identified also in other Slavic languages. In particular, Polish trójka ‘group of three’ patterns with (40b) (Wągiel 2015) and similar examples include Slovak trojica, Bosnian/Croatian/Montenegrin/Serbian (BCMS) trojka and Russian trojka, all ‘group of three’.15 The existence of the discussed phenomenon in Slavic is unexpected since it is typically postulated to hold crosslinguistically that if a language has a scopal quantifier, it is a quantifier forcing a distributive interpretation (Gil 1992).16 Hence, the Slavic data discussed above compel to revise that generalization. In any case, a systematic theory-driven cross-linguistic research of collective numerals has not been carried out so far. 5.3 Both An interesting feature of many languages including Slavic is that alongside a regular cardinal numeral corresponding to English two there is also another form corresponding to English both. In an early GQ account, both has been analyzed as a quantificational determiner with the same meaning as the two (Barwise & Cooper 1981). However, it has been observed that the two expressions are not equivalent (Ladusaw 1982). For instance, both is incompatible with collective predicates, see (42a), and cannot appear inside partitives, see (42b). As witnessed in (43), the same behavior is also attested in Slavic (Łazorczyk & Pancheva 2009). (42) a. { The two / #Both } students are a happy couple. 15Russian shows a strong tendency to lexicalize collective numerals, e.g., trojka is also a word for a carriage drawn by a team of three horses abreast. 16In Hebrew, there are derived expressions that at first blush resemble Slavic collective numerals, e.g., šlišiya ‘threesome of’. However, they have been reported to differ in that they do not force a collective interpretation (Gil 1992). xxi Author b. One of { the two / #both } children sneezed. (43) a. # Obe both ženščiny woman.gen prišli came vmeste. together Intended: ‘Both women came together.’ b. Kto who iz from etix these.gen { dvoix two.gen / *oboix } both.gen sdelal did to, this.acc čto what xotel wanted otec? father ‘Which of these two did what his father wanted?’ (Russian) The data presented above led to proposals postulating that both, unlike cardinals, involves an additional distributive component (e.g., Ladusaw 1982; Landman 1989).17 Interestingly, however, there is yet another respect in which the two differ. Specifically, both and its counterparts in other languages cannot be used to refer to a number concept in an arithmetical environment, see (44). (44) a. # Oba both to that liczba number parzysta. even Intended: ‘Both is an even number.’ b. # Dziesięć ten dzielone divided przez by oba both.acc równa equals się refl pięć. five Intended: ‘Ten divided by both equals five.’ (Polish) Similarly to collective numerals, the behavior of both and its Slavic equivalents presented in (44) poses a serious challenge for approaches deriving the arithmetical function of numerals from the allegedly basic quantifying meaning. 5.4 Taxonomic numerals A unique property of some Slavic languages is that they have taxonomic numerals. Likewise collective numerals, they are derived by a special suffix which triggers a non-trivial semantic effect. Unlike cardinals, such expressions do not quantify over object-level entities, i.e., tokens of a type, but rather over subkinds of a particular kind corresponding to the meaning of the modified noun.18 For instance, let us consider the taxonomic numeral dvojí ‘two kinds of’ in Czech 17For the recent research on bona fide distributive numerals, see, e.g., Gil (2013), Cable (2014) and Wohlmuth (2019). 18For an introduction to the kind/object distinction, see, e.g., Krifka et al. (1995). xxii Numerals and their kin (Dočekal 2012; 2013; Grimm & Dočekal to appear). The phrase in (45a) does not refer to two musical instruments but rather to two types of violin, e.g., a set of classical violins and a set of electric violins. Likewise, (45b) denotes two kinds of the beverage, e.g., white and red wine, irrespective of its amount. (45) a. dvojí two.tax housle violin ‘two kinds of violin’ b. dvojí two.tax víno wine ‘two kinds of wine’ (Czech) Unlike cardinals, taxonomic numerals specify the domain of quantification to be within the realm of kinds exclusively. Therefore, the suffix -í has been proposed to introduce a quantificational operation dedicated to counting subkinds, specifically the ku (for ‘kind unit’) operation proposed by Krifka (1995). Though taxonomic numerals seem to be best preserved in Czech, Polish dwojaki and dwoisty, Bulgarian dvojak and Russian dvojakij, all ‘twofold’, are arguably expressions of a similar type. However, there appear to be certain differences with respect to their distribution and behavior that have not been described sufficiently so far. Crucially, none of the taxonomic numerals can be used to refer to an abstract number concept. 5.5 Aggregate numerals Another intriguing type of Slavic derivationally complex numerical expressions is sometimes referred to as aggregate numerals, e.g., forms such as Czech dvoje ‘two collections’ (Dočekal 2012; 2013) as well as BCMS dvoji (Lučić 2015). Likewise collective numerals, they are derived by a special suffix which triggers a non-trivial semantic effect and lack the arithmetical meaning. While cardinals simply count atomic individuals in the denotation of the modified NP, aggregate numerals are used to quantify over collections of entities that typically form a particular spatial configuration. For instance, (46a) refers to two aggregates of cards, e.g., two decks of cards. Similarly, (46b) denotes two pairs of shoes. (46) a. dvoje two.aggr karty cards ‘two sets of cards’ xxiii Author b. dvoje two.aggr boty shoes ‘two pairs of shoes’ (Czech) Aggregate numerals are not limited to Slavic. For instance, similar expressions seem to have existed in Latin, e.g., trēs ‘three’ ∼ trīnī ‘three collections’ (Ojeda 1997), and Estonian uses pluralized numerals for this purpose, e.g., kaks ‘two’ ∼ kahed ‘two collections’ (Norris 2018). However, it is the Slavic data what has been taken as evidence for the relevance of mereotopology in natural language, specifically the significance of topological relations holding between atomic members of a plurality within a part-whole structure.19 In particular, the suffix -e in phrases such as (46) is sensitive to how parts making up a whole are arranged, and thus it has been proposed to introduce a semantic operation dedicated to counting clusters, i.e., topologically structured spatial groupings of entities (Grimm & Dočekal to appear). 5.6 Gender-sensitive numerals All Slavic languages mark grammatical gender on low numerals whereas some of them, e.g., Bulgarian, Polish and Slovak, distinguish between virile (personal masculine) and non-virile forms also in higher numerals. (Cinque & Krapova 2007; Pancheva 2018; Wągiel to appear). However, what is probably even more interesting is the existence of complex expressions which I will refer here to as gender-sensitive numerals.20 Such expressions introduce non-trivial restrictions with respect to the natural gender of individuals making up a plurality. Let us consider Polish gender-sensitive numerals such as troje ‘three (at least one male and at least one female)’ (Wągiel 2014; 2015). Unlike virile and non-virile cardinals in (47a) and (47b), respectively, they do not show grammatical gender agreement with modified NPs. Instead, they are neuter, as demonstrated in (47c). And yet they introduce a gender-related effect. While (47a) denotes a plurality of either males or students whose natural gender is not known to the speaker and (47b) refers to three females, (47a) is interpreted as designating a mixed-gender group. (47) a. tych these.acc.v trzech two.v studentów students.gen.v ‘these three students (male or indeterminate)’ 19For an introduction to mereotopology, see Grimm (2012: Ch. 4), Wągiel (2018: Ch. 6). 20In traditional Slavic linguistics such forms are typically termed ‘collective numerals’. In order to avoid confusion with expressions discussed in §5.2, I will not use that term. xxiv Numerals and their kin b. te these.acc.nv trzy three.nv studentki students.nom.nv ‘these three female students’ c. to this.nom.n troje three.gndr.n studentów students.gen.v ‘these three students (at least one male and at least one female)’ (Polish) Based on the evidence discussed above, numerals such as Polish troje have been proposed to introduce a presupposition that a plurality of individuals referred to by the whole phrase is heterogeneous and consists of both male and female individuals. Though similar expressions seem to be only attested in BCMS, e.g., dvoje, ‘two (one male and one female)’, there are also other types of gender-sensitive numerals in Slavic. For instance, BCMS dvojica and Russian dvoe, both ‘two (male)’, presuppose a homogeneous group consisting of male individuals only (Kim 2009; Lučić 2015; Khrizman 2020). Interestingly, none of the gender-sensitive numerals can be used to refer to a number concept. 5.7 Indefinite numerals Another intriguing class of numerical expressions concerns indefinite numerals such as English several (Kayne 2007). Similar quantifiers appear in all branches of Slavic, e.g., compare Czech několik, Russian neskol’ko, Bulgarian nyakolko and BCMS nekoliko, all ‘several’. Particularly interesting data come from Polish which distinguishes between two different expressions of this type, specifically kilka ‘several, a few’ and ileś (tam) ‘some, some amount’. While the former is only compatible with count NPs and designates a cardinality between 3 and 9, the latter also combines with mass NPs and can indicate any quantity (Wągiel 2020b). In terms of morphosyntax and many aspects of semantics, several and its Slavic equivalents pattern with cardinals. However, one crucial respect in which the two differ is that indefinite numerals do not fit contexts calling for number concepts, see (48a) and (49) (Schwarzschild 2002; Wągiel 2020b). Despite the fact that one can easily imagine the intended meaning and paraphrase it using the existential quantifier, as in (48b), this is not what one gets in (48a) and (49). (48) a. # Four plus several is less than ten. b. There is a number n such that four plus n is less than ten. xxv Author (49) # Cztery four plus plus { kilka several / ileś (tam) } some to this mniej less niż than dziesięć. ten Intended: ‘Four plus several/some is less than ten.’ (Polish) Polish indefinite numerals have been analyzed as complex expressions with an incorporated measure function and choice function. The difference between kilka and ileś (tam) is due to a different type of set the choice function selects a number from and a different kind of built-in measure function (Wągiel 2020b). 5.8 Multipliers In many languages there is a heavily understudied class of numerical expressions sometimes referred to as multipliers, e.g., English double. Though Germanic and Romance languages have borrowed their multipliers from Latin, in Slavic they are morphologically transparent and one can easily notice that they are derived from numerical roots by various affixes, e.g., compare Polish podwójny, Russian dvojnoj and Czech dvojitý, all ‘double’. Interestingly, multipliers display non-trivial quantificational behavior. Specifically, they do not quantify over whole entities or events, as cardinals would, but rather over parts thereof (Wągiel 2018; 2020a). For instance, the phrase in (50a) denotes a set of singular objects having a complex internal structure. Each of those objects is a crown but crucially it also has two parts that could be considered as having the property of being a crown themselves, e.g., entities such as the ancient Egyptian Pschent or the papal tiara. Similarly, (50b) refers to a murdering event with two victims. But this means that there were two parts of that event each of which could be described as a murder in its own right. (50) a. dvostruka two.mult.f kruna crown.n ‘double crown’ b. dvostruko two.mult.n ubistvo murder.n ‘double murder’ (BCMS) The behavior of multipliers has been argued to stem from the phenomenon of subatomic quantification (Wągiel 2018). According to the proposal, natural language is sensitive to the arrangement of parts within a singular entity. Certain expressions, e.g., proportional partitives and multipliers, can access such subatomic part-whole structures and quantify over parts conceptualized as contiguous objects within a whole. xxvi Numerals and their kin 5.9 Event numerals Yet another class of cross-linguistically frequent though surprisingly understudied numerical expressions consists of event numerals also known as multiplicatives (but see Landman 2006; Donazzan 2013; Kayne 2015). They include adverbial expressions such as English twice and two times which are primarily used to quantify over events but can be also employed in comparative and equative constructions. Event numerals are attested in all Slavic languages with BCMS dvaput and Czech dvakrát, both ‘two times, twice’, being representative examples. Intuitively, event numerals seem to be a type of a broader class of adverbs of quantification including frequency adverbs such English often and French souvent ‘often’ (Abeillé et al. 2004; Doetjes 2007). However, close examination reveals interesting differences between event numerals and frequency adverbs one of which regards degree modification (Dočekal & Wągiel 2018). For instance, the sentence with the event numeral in (51a) is ambiguous between the quantifiedevent reading and the quantified-degree reading. On the former interpretation there were two events of increasing the demand and the total value of the increase is unknown whereas on the latter interpretation there was a twofold increase in the demand irrespective of the number of events on which it increased. Interestingly, (51b) lacks the quantified-degree reading. (51) a. Poptávka demand po after dotacích subsidies.loc vzrostla increased.pfv dvakrát. twice ✓event, ✓deg ‘The demand for subsidies increased (by) two times.’ b. Poptávka demand po after dotacích subsidies.loc rostla increased.ipfv často. often ✓event, #deg ‘The demand for subsidies increased often.’ (Czech) In addition, while event numerals are perfectly fine in comparatives and equatives, frequency adjectives are infelicitous in such constructions, as witnessed by the contrast in (52). (52) Petr Petr je is { dvakrát twice / #často often } vyšší taller než than Marie. Marie ‘Petr is two times taller than Marie.’ (Czech) Unlike all other types of numerical expressions discussed in this section, event numerals can be used in arithmetical environments provided that they express multiplication. However, it is puzzling that not all event numerals can do that. For instance, Polish has two sets of event numerals but only one can be felicitously xxvii Author used in a context such as (53) which suggests that the element razy ‘times’ might be a homonymous form for a multiplicative morpheme used to quantify over events and an expression of an arithmetical relation. (53) { Dwa two razy times / #Dwukrotnie twice } trzy three równa equals się refl sześć. six ‘Two times three equals six.’ (Polish) Though event numerals seem key to understanding quantification in the domains of events and degrees, it is surprising that so far they have not received nearly as much attention as cardinals. 5.10 Frequency numerals Finally, in many languages there are expressions I will refer to as frequency numerals, i.e., multiplicative adjectives equivalent to English two-time. Slavic is no exception here and Polish dwukrotny, Czech dvojnásobný and Russian dvukratnyj, all ‘two-time’, are representative examples of the class in question. At first sight, it seems that frequency numerals such as two-time are expressions of the same type as frequency adjectives like occasional and frequent (Zimmermann 2003; Schäfer 2007; Gehrke & McNally 2015). Notice, however, that while occasional can have the adverbial reading, expressions such as two-time pattern with frequent in that they lack such an interpretation. For instance, while (54a) means that occasionally a sailor strolled by, both (54b) and (54c) cannot be understood that way. (54) a. An occasional sailor strolled by. ✓adverbial b. A frequent sailor strolled by. #adverbial c. A two-time senator strolled by. #adverbial Furthermore, frequency numerals fail to combine with sortal nouns and seem to require role nouns denoting socially salient capacities such as positions with a term and award recipients that can be acquired repetitively. That is because frequency numerals quantify over conventionalized events of acquiring a property, e.g., via a ceremony, compare (55a) and (55b). (55) a. Jan Jan to this dwukrotny two-time { mistrz champion / #człowiek man }. ‘Jan is a two-time champion.’ xxviii Numerals and their kin b. Jan Jan został became { mistrzem champion.ins / #człowiekiem man.ins } dwa two razy. times ‘Jan became a champion twice.’ (Polish) Having examined various complex numerical expressions, let us now summarize what the discussed data show us. 5.11 Summary In this section, I reviewed various types of numerical expressions in Slavic and beyond. In particular, I discussed a wide range of morphologically complex forms and examined how they correspond to certain non-trivial semantic effects. The reviewed dataset is far larger and more diverse than typically analyzed in mainstream semantic theories of numerals, see §3. And yet, there is an intuition that a general theory of numerals should cover all of the examined cases. Therefore, I believe the relevance of the above-discussed Slavic data for such a theory is twofold. First, morphological transparency of the discussed forms clearly shows that all complex numerical expressions share a common component, i.e., a numerical root designating a certain number.21 That number is somehow employed in counting but what exactly is counted may vary depending on a type of numeral, e.g., whole objects in the case of cardinals, parts in the case of multipliers and subkinds in the case of taxonomic numerals. Therefore, a theory of numerals should aim at providing a general mechanism that will allow us to capture not only the behavior of cardinals but also other numerical expressions discussed here. Second, despite sharing an element designating a number none of the complex numerical expressions can be used to refer to abstract arithmetical concepts, i.e., the arithmetical function is never available except for basic cardinals.22 This fact turns out to be problematic for the approaches deriving the arithmetical meaning from the quantifying one, see §4.2. The reason is that they shift a counting device semantics of a cardinal into a proper name of a number concept. But if so, why cannot that shift be also applied in the case of other types of counting expressions, e.g., a taxonomic, an aggregate or an indefinite numeral, or both? Semantically, these expressions do not seem to be radically different from cardinals (they all count something) to justify why shifting their meaning to a name of a number concept is impossible. If, on the other hand, the arithmetical meaning is basic, one expects to derive various quantificational flavors from it. Therefore, it would 21Unless, of course, suppletion is involved. 22And perhaps event numerals in contexts expressing multiplication. xxix Author not be surprising that only basic cardinals can have the arithmetical function and other types of numerical expressions would lack it. In the next section, I will attempt to show how the two conclusions reached above can guide formulating a particular proposal of yet another type of numerical expressions, namely label numerals. 6 Case study: Numerals as labels In this section, I will return to the label use of numerals, as already introduced in (1f) in §2, repeated here as (56). (56) Player number five twisted her ankle. So far, the label meaning has received little attention in the literature (see Hurford 1987: 167–168; Wiese 2003: 37–42; Bultinck 2005: 119–129). I will demonstrate that not only is this function conceptually different from other functions discussed in §2 but also that the distinction is reflected in grammar. I will argue that the label function is derived from the arithmetical meaning and I will propose a morphosemantic account that allows for deriving both the form and the meaning of dedicated label numerals in Slavic. The proposed analysis will combine standard compositional semantics with a Nanosyntax model of morphology. 6.1 Label uses are distinct Intuitively, label numerals provide means for identification of an object via its association with a unique number, which allows for the recognition of that object among other entities. This mechanism is sometimes referred to as nominal number assignment (Wiese 2003: 37–38). A set of numbers would be consistent labels as long as the numerals corresponding to distinct numbers in that set are uniquely used for each distinct object. This can be achieved by a one-to-one mapping between a set of labeled entities and a given set of numbers. Importantly, the actual values of the numbers represented by label numerals are irrelevant since they do not indicate quantity, order or any other type of measurement. Furthermore, the set of labels can change over time, e.g., it can grow as new entities are labeled. The only thing that matters is that at a given time every labeled entity is associated with a unique number. It is clear that from a conceptual point of view the label function differs from the quantifying and the arithmetical meaning. Importantly, however, the distinction is also encoded in grammar. First, numerals used as labels do not allow for xxx Numerals and their kin modification by numeral modifiers and prequantifiers, see (57a). Moreover, label constructions do not give rise to scalar implicatures. For instance, in the context of (57b), taking bus number six would not guarantee getting to the university. (57) a. # Tram { more than / at least / all } number five has left. b. You must take tram number five to get to the university. #at least The data in (57) differ from the quantifying function and pattern with the properties of the arithmetical use of numerals discussed in §2.3. However, these two functions can be distinguished linguistically as well. For instance, English constructions with numerals used as labels differ from other count NPs in that they are ungrammatical with the indefinite article, see (58a). On the other hand, names of number concepts cannot appear without the definite article, as demonstrated in (58b) (for a more detailed discussion on the distribution of English phrases such as number five, see Bultinck 2005: 124–129). (58) a. Kim took (*a) tram number five. b. * (The) number five is odd. Above, I argued that the label meaning of numerals is both conceptually and linguistically different from the quantifying and the arithmetical function. In the following two sections, I will discuss further evidence for the relevance of the label function as well as its relationship with the other two discussed meanings. 6.2 Evidence from co-lexicalizations In many languages, an additional expression can be optionally used alongside the numeral in order to indicate its quantifying, arithmetical or label use. Sometimes, the same lexical item can introduce all of the functions above. For instance, English employs a single noun, namely number, to indicate cardinality, to designate a mathematical object and to signal that an entity is identified via association with a relevant integer, see (59). (59) a. The cats are five in number. b. The number five is odd. c. Tram number five left. While English shows full co-lexicalization, i.e., the noun number can be used to indicate all three functions, more often lexicons develop a different word for at least one of the functions in question. For instance, Bulgarian exhibits a pattern xxxi Author with no co-lexication, i.e., each of the discussed functions is signalled by a morphologically distinct expression, specifically broj is for quantification, čislo is for arithmetic and nomer is for the label function, all ‘number’. Though ways in which meanings and forms correspond to each other vary, it seems that they do not vary in an unrestricted manner. The co-lexicalization patterns found in Slavic are summarized in Table 1. Interestingly, the pattern that is not attested in the sample is a case of non-contiguous co-lexicalization where the quantifying and label function are expressed with the same form while the arithmetical function is expressed by a different lexical item. Perhaps surprisingly, this result resembles the well-known *ABA principle (Bobaljik 2012). Table 1: Co-lexicalization of ‘number’ language qantifying arithmetical label BCMS A broj A broj A broj Polish A liczba A liczba B numer Slovak A počet B číslo B číslo Bulgarian A broj B čislo C nomer unattested A B A Examining permissible patterns of co-lexicalization is rarely considered evidence in formal semantics. However, I believe that looking at how certain parts of lexicon are structured can be instructive. Arguably, it can reveal that some meanings have more in common than others and in some cases that certain categories, though theoretically possible, are empirically unrealized.23 Consequently, one can gain valuable hints regarding what those meanings are. On the assumption that co-lexicalization does in fact reflect the relationship between concepts, the data in Table 1 suggest that while the quantifying and the label meaning are unrelated, they both seem to stem from the arithmetical function. The reason is that if both the quantifying and the label meaning are derived from the arithmetical meaning, the attested co-lexicalization patterns are unsurprising since the unrelated derived functions are not expected to be expressed by a single term that is different from the one expressing the underlying meaning (ABA). On the other hand, if the quantifying meaning were basic, then one would expect to find the ABA pattern instead of the Czech and Slovak ABB. 23This way of viewing data has been successful in lexicology, e.g., in generalizations about kinship terms (see, e.g., Hage 1997). xxxii Numerals and their kin Whether a language which has a term for the quantifying and the label function to the exclusion of the arithmetical function can be found is an empirical issue. So far, the Slavic co-lexicalization data suggest a strong relationship between the label and the arithmetical meaning and no relationship between the label and the quantifying meaning. In the next section, I will discuss a class of complex numerical expressions for labeling in Slavic. 6.3 Derived label numerals An interesting property of Slavic languages is that they have specialized label numerals. Such dedicated expressions are derived with the suffixes -ka and -ica. Table 2 gives an overview of the label forms for the numerals forresponding to 5 across Slavic. Table 2: Cardinal and label ‘five’ in Slavic language number cardinal label Czech 5 pět pětka Polish 5 pięć piątka Russian 5 pjat’ pjaterka Slovenian 5 pet petka/petica BCMS 5 pet petica Though there are a number of interesting differences in their productivity and distribution, e.g., Polish derives label forms with -ka up to 999 while Russian has them only for 2–10, 20 and 30, all Slavic label numerals are morphosyntactically nominal expressions used to refer to objects that can be identified via nominal number assignment. Though very often they appear bare, the noun specifying what entity is labeled can optionally precede the label numeral, as in (60). In the absence of the noun this information is typically provided by the context. (60) (Tramvaj) tram pět-ka five-lbl vyjede will.go.out na on novou new.acc trať track.acc v in listopadu. November.loc ‘Tram number five will head out on the new track in November.’ (Czech) Similarly to classifier constructions and other complex numerical expressions, recall §4.4 and §5, Slavic label numerals exhibit uniform behavior in that they cannot be felicitously used in mathematical statements such as (61), This, in turn, sug- xxxiii Author gests that their semantics is more intricate compared to the arithmetical meaning of cardinal numerals. (61) a. Dva-krát two-times pět five se refl rovná equals deset. ten ‘Two times five equals ten.’ b. # Dvoj-ka five-lbl krát times pět-ka two-lbl se rovná equals desít-ka. ten-lbl Intended: ‘Two times five equals ten.’ (Czech) The data above show that Slavic label numerals are both morphologically and semantically complex. With this in mind, let us now propose an account that will capture their morpho-semantics as well as the relationship between the arithmetical meaning, quantification and labeling. 6.4 Analysis In order to account for the relationship between the three uses of cardinal numerals discussed in this paper, i.e., their arithmetical, quantifying and label function, I develop a morpho-semantic system combining a standard inventory of formal semantics with the Nanosyntax model of morphology (see Wągiel & Caha 2020). The core of the proposal is that the quantifying and the label function are both derived from the arithmetical meaning which is taken to be basic. I propose the ingredients in (62) as a set of morpho-semantic components that numeral expressions conveying the relevant functions are formed of. Specifically, I postulate the bottom-most NumPn (for ‘number’) layer along with two additional heads, namely Cl (for ‘classifier’) and Lbl (for ‘label’). (62) a. NumPn n = n b. Cl ⟨n, ⟨⟨e,t ⟩, ⟨e,t ⟩⟩⟩ = λnλPλx[*P(x) ∧ #(P)(x) = n] c. Lbl ⟨n, ⟨⟨e,t ⟩,e ⟩⟩ = λnλPιx[P(x) ∧ LABEL(n,x)] The meaning of NumPn is simply an abstract number concept (type n), see (62a). The subscript indicates that NumPn is lexically encoded. Though for the purpose of this paper I assume that it is the basic structural component of each cardinal numeral, I do not claim that it is primitive. It might very well be further decomposed into a number of features.24 On the other hand, the components Cl and Lbl are interpreted as shifts from n to a more complex type. 24This is indicated by the triangle in Figure 1 and 2. For why one would want to further decompose NumPn, see Wągiel & Caha (2020). xxxiv Numerals and their kin I will assume here that Cl is interpreted as a function from a number concept to a predicate modifier devised for counting individuals (type ⟨n, ⟨⟨e,t⟩, ⟨e,t⟩⟩⟩), see (62b).25 Cl takes a number and yields an expression with the built-in pluralization operation ∗ and measure function #(P), see §3.3. In cases such as English five or Czech pět ‘five’, Cl is already incorporated in the structure of a numeral but in some other languages it is encoded in as additional morpheme, e.g., a classifier. On the other hand, Lbl is a labeling device (type ⟨n, ⟨⟨e,t⟩,e⟩⟩) which selects a number and returns a function from properties to unique individuals such that they have the relevant property and are labeled with the corresponding number by the LABEL operation, as provided in (62c). Lbl is typically introduced by a free morpheme such as number or a specialized affix like the Czech suffix -ka, as discussed in §6.2 and §6.3, respectively. As a result of combining the components in (62) by syntax, we obtain the structures in Figure 1 and 2. The tree in Figure 1 represents the structure and meaning of the quantifying function of a numeral corresponding to 5 whereas the tree in Figure 2 depicts the parallel label function. ClP⟨⟨e,t ⟩, ⟨e,t ⟩⟩ λPλx[*P(x) ∧ #(P)(x) = 5] Cl⟨n, ⟨⟨e,t ⟩, ⟨e,t ⟩⟩⟩ λnλPλx[*P(x) ∧ #(P)(x) = n] NumP5 n 5 . . . Figure 1: The quantifying function LblP⟨⟨e,t ⟩,e ⟩ λPιx[P(x) ∧ LABEL(5, x)] Lbl⟨n, ⟨⟨e,t ⟩,e ⟩⟩ λnλPιx[P(x) ∧ LABEL(n, x)] NumP5 n 5 . . . Figure 2: The label function When a quantifying numeral, e.g., Czech pět ‘five’, and a label expression, e.g., Czech číslo pět ‘number five’, combine with an NP, what we obtain are the denotations such as those in (63). In particular, (63a) denotes a set of pluralities of players such that each plurality in that set consists of five players. On the other hand, (63b) refers to the contextually unique player identified via their association with the number 5. (63) a. pět hráčů ⟨e,t ⟩ = λx[∗player(x) ∧ #(player)(x) = 5] b. hráč číslo pět e = ιx[player(x) ∧ LABEL(5,x)] 25For the purpose of this paper, it is not important what the exact interpretation of Cl is. The proposed system is compatible with other theories of quantifying numerals discussed in §3 as long as it is possible to shift the primitive type n to a type for the quantifying function. xxxv Author But how to account for the fact that a numeral such as Czech pět ‘five’ can be used to express both the quantifying and the arithmetical meaning? This ambiguity can be captured as a consequence of a core property of late insertion, namely that lexical entries are not tailor-made for one specific use.26 In Nanosyntax, a lexical entry pairs a well-formed syntactic structure with phonology. For instance, let us assign to the cardinal pět the lexical entry in Figure 3. When syntax builds a structure interpreted as the quantifying meaning, as in Figure 1, the entry in Figure 3 can be used to lexicalize it. Consequently, the structure or, more precisely, its top-most phrasal node is pronounced by /pjɛt/, as indicated by the big circle in Figure 4. ClP Cl NumP5 . . . ⇔ /pjɛt/ Figure 3: Lexical entry ClP Cl NumP5 . . . pět Figure 4: Lexicalizations Crucially, however, when syntax builds a structure interpreted as the arithmetical meaning, i.e., the sole NumP5, it can also be pronounced by Figure 3, as indicated by the small circle in Figure 4. This is due to the Superset Principle, defined in (64) (Starke 2009), which states that a lexical entry can be used to pronounce a particular structure iff it contains that structure as a sub-part (either proper or improper). As a result, the Czech numeral pět ‘five’ is ambiguous between the quantifying and the arithmetical meaning since both circled structures in Figure 4 are contained in the tree in Figure 3. (64) The Superset Principle (Starke 2009) A lexically stored tree matches a syntactic node iff the lexically stored tree contains the syntactic node. Let us now consider how the label meaning arises. For this purpose, I will demonstrate how specialized label numerals such as Czech pětka ‘number five’ are derived. Since pět ‘five’ is stored as Figure 3, and thus cannot express the label meaning, the Lbl component needs to be spelled out by a separate entry, e.g., as 26For an introduction to late insertion models such as Distributed Morphology and Nanosyntax, see, e.g., Bobaljik (2017) and Baunaz & Lander (2018), respectively. xxxvi Numerals and their kin the suffix -ka in Figure 5. Notice that the semantics of Lbl is not compatible with the quantifying meaning and requires type n as its input, recall (62c). Thanks to the Superset Principle, see (64), pět can also pronounce the arithmetical meaning, i.e., the sole NumP5, as indicated by the small circle in Figure 4. However, in order for this structure to apply at the LblP node, NumP5 must move from its base-position. In Figure 6, its trace, i.e., the lower copy of the displaced element, is shaded.27 After the NumP5 is moved, Figure 5 matches the lower LblP, as shown in Figure 7, where the label suffix -ka is inserted at the relevant node. LblP Lbl ⇔ ka Figure 5: Czech label suffix LblP NumP5 . . . LblP Lbl NumP5 . . . pět Figure 6: Movement LblP NumP5 . . . LblP Lbl pět ka Figure 7: Spellout The proposed analysis has several advantages. First of all, it provides a unified approach that captures the relationship between the arithmetical, the quantifying and the label meaning. Second, it explains when and how a numeral can be ambiguous between different meanings. Finally, it gives a detailed account for the meaning/form correspondences both in cardinal and in label numerals. 7 Conclusion In this paper, I explored the semantics of numerals in Slavic and beyond. I discussed various functions that cardinal numerals can have as well as different approaches to capturing the relationships between these functions. Furthermore, I 27In Nanosyntax, the movement in Figure 6 is driven by the need to lexicalize the phrasal LblP node by the lexical entry in Figure 5. For a detailed explanation of how precisely the movement in Figure 6 is triggered, see Baunaz & Lander (2018) and Caha et al. (2019). xxxvii Author examined many types of complex numerical expressions that only recently attracted attention in the literature. I also provided novel evidence in favor of the view suggesting that the arithmetical meaning is basic while other functions are derived from it. Finally, I explored the so-far understudied label function and proposed a morpho-semantic analysis of Slavic derived label numerals that could be further extended to other types of complex numerical expressions. Abbreviations acc accusative aggr aggregate numeral clf classifier cop copula f feminine gen genitive gndr gender-sensitive numeral ins instrumental ipfv imperfective lbl label numeral loc locative mult multiplier n neuter nbr number-denoting numeral nv non-virile pfv perfective refl reflexive pronoun tax taxonomic numeral top topic v virile References Abeillé, Anne, Jenny Doetjes, Arie Molendijk & Henriëtte de Swart. 2004. Adverbs and quantification. In Francis Corblin & Henriëtte de Swart (eds.), Handbook of French semantics, 185–209. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications. Babby, Leonard H. 1987. Case, prequantifiers, and discontinuous agreement in Russian. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 5(1). 91–138. DOI:10.1007/BF00161869 Barbiers, Sjef. 2007. Indefinite numerals ‘one’ and ‘many’ and the cause of ordinal suppletion. Lingua 117(5). 859–880. DOI:10.1016/j.lingua.2006.03.003 Barwise, Jon & Robin Cooper. 1981. Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy 4(2). 159–219. DOI:10.1007/BF00350139 Baunaz, Lena & Eric Lander. 2018. Nanosyntax: The basics. In Lena Baunaz, Karen De Clercq, Liliane Haegeman & Eric Lander (eds.), Exploring Nanosyntax, 3–56. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Bhatt, Rajesh. 2006. Covert modality in non-finite contexts. Oxford: Mouton de Gruyter. xxxviii Numerals and their kin Bobaljik, Jonathan D. 2012. Universals in comparative morphology: Suppletion, superlatives, and the structure of words. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bobaljik, Jonathan David. 2017. Distributed Morphology. In Mark Aronoff (ed.), Oxford research encyclopedia of linguistics. Oxford: Oxford University Press. DOI:10.1093/acrefore/9780199384655.013.131 Bultinck, Bert. 2005. Numerous meanings: The meaning of English cardinals and the legacy of Paul Grice. Amsterdam: Elsevier. Bylinina, Lisa, Natalia Ivlieva, Alexander Podobryaev & Yasutada Sudo. 2015. An in situ semantics for ordinals. In Thuy Bui & Deniz Özyıldız (eds.), NELS 45: Proceedings of the Forty-Fifth Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society, 135–145. Amherst, MA: GLSA. Bylinina, Lisa & Rick Nouwen. 2018. On ‘zero’ and semantic plurality. Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics 3(1). DOI:10.5334/gjgl.441 Bylinina, Lisa & Rick Nouwen. 2020. Numeral semantics. Language and Linguistics Compass e12390. 1–18. DOI:10.1111/lnc3.12390 Cable, Seth. 2014. Distributive numerals and distance distributivity in Tlingit (and beyond). Language 90(3). 562–606. DOI:10.1353/lan.2014.0055 Caha, Pavel, Karen De Clercq & Guido Vanden Wyngaerd. 2019. The fine structure of the comparative. Studia Linguistica 73(3). 470–521. DOI:10.1111/stul.12107 Champollion, Lucas & Manfred Krifka. 2016. Mereology. In Maria Aloni & Paul Dekker (eds.), Cambridge handbook of formal semantics, 369–388. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Chierchia, Gennaro. 1985. Formal semantics and the grammar of predication. Linguistic Inquiry 16(3). 417–443. Chierchia, Gennaro. 2010. Mass nouns, vagueness and semantic variation. Synthese 174(1). 99–149. DOI:10.1007/s11229-009-9686-6 Cinque, Guglielmo & Iliyana Krapova. 2007. A note on Bulgarian numeral classifiers. In Gabriela Alboiu, Andrei A. Avram, Larisa Avram & Daniela Isac (eds.), Pitar Moş: A building with a view. Papers in honour of Alexandra Cornilescu, 45–51. Bucharest: Editura Universităţii din Bucureşti. Dočekal, Mojmír. 2012. Atoms, groups and kinds in Czech. Acta Linguistica Hungarica: An International Journal of Linguistics 59(1–2). 109–126. DOI:10.1556/aling.59.2012.1-2.5 Dočekal, Mojmír. 2013. What do we count with numerals? Semantic analysis of Czech group-denoting and kind-denoting NPs. In Uwe Junghanns, Dorothee Fehrmann, Denisa Lenertová & Hagen Pitsch (eds.), Formal Description of Slavic Languages: The ninth conference. Proceedings of FDSL 9, Göttingen 2011, 87–105. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang. xxxix Author Dočekal, Mojmír & Marcin Wągiel. 2018. Event and degree numerals: Evidence from Czech. In Denisa Lenertová, Roland Meyer, Radek Šimík & Luka Szucsich (eds.), Advances in formal Slavic linguistics 2016, 77–108. Berlin: Language Science Press. Doetjes, Jenny. 2007. Adverbs and quantification: Degrees versus frequency. Lingua 117(4). 685–720. DOI:10.1016/j.lingua.2006.04.003 Donazzan, Marta. 2013. On counting and measuring events. In Emmanuel Chemla, Vincent Homer & Grégoire Winterstein (eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 17, 219–236. Paris: ENS. http://semanticsarchive.net/sub2012/. Donohue, Mark. 2005. Numerals and their position in Universal Grammar. Journal of Universal Language 6(2). 1–37. DOI:10.22425/jul.2005.6.2.1 Franks, Steven. 1994. Parametric properties of numeral phrases in Slavic. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory 12(4). 597–674. DOI:10.1007/BF00992929 Frege, Gottlob. 1884. Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik. Breslau: Wilhelm Koebner. Gehrke, Berit & Louise McNally. 2015. Distributional modification: The case of frequency adjectives. Language 91(4). 837–870. DOI:10.1353/lan.2015.0065 Geurts, Bart. 2006. Take ‘five’: The meaning and use of a number word. In Svetlana Vogeleer & Liliane Tasmowski (eds.), Non-definiteness and plurality, 311– 329. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Gil, David. 1992. Scopal quantifiers: Some universals of lexical effability. In Meaning and grammar: Cross-Linguistic perspectives, 303–346. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Gil, David. 2013. Numeral classifiers. In Matthew S. Dryer & Martin Haspelmath (eds.), The world atlas of language structures online. Leipzig: Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology. http://wals.info/chapter/55. Gillon, Brendan S. 1987. The readings of plural noun phrases in English. Linguistics and Philosophy 10(2). 199–219. DOI:10.1007/BF00584318 Grimm, Scott. 2012. Number and individuation. Stanford, CA: Stanford University dissertation. http://www.sas.rochester.edu/lin/sgrimm/publications.html. Grimm, Scott & Mojmír Dočekal. to appear. Counting aggregates, groups and kinds: Countability from the perspective of a morphologically complex language. In Hana Filip (ed.), Counting and measuring across languages. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Grimshaw, Jane. 2007. Boxes and piles and what’s in them: Two extended projections or one. In Annie Zaenen, Jane Grimshaw, Joan Maling, Christopher D. Manning & Jane Simpson (eds.), Architectures, rules, and preferences: A Festschrift for Joan Bresnan, 245–252. Stanford, CA: CSLI. xl Numerals and their kin Hackl, Martin. 2000. Comparative quantifiers. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation. http://web.mit.edu/hackl/www/papers/files/NThesis5.pdf. Hage, Per. 1997. Unthinkable categories and the fundamental laws of kinship. American Ethnologist 24(3). 652–667. DOI:10.1525/ae.1997.24.3.652 Heim, Irene & Angelika Kratzer. 1998. Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell. Hoeksema, Jack. 1983. Plurality and conjunction. In Alice G.B. ter Meulen (ed.), Studies in modeltheoretic semantics, 63–83. Dordrecht: Foris. Hurford, James R. 1987. Language and number: The emergence of a cognitive system. Oxford: Blackwell. Hurford, James R. 1998. The interaction between numerals and nouns. In Frans Plank (ed.), Noun phrase structure in the languages of Europe, 561–620. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Hurford, James R. 2001. Languages treat 1–4 specially. Mind & Language 16(1). 69–75. Ionin, Tania & Ora Matushansky. 2006. The composition of complex cardinals. Journal of Semantics 23(4). 315–360. DOI:10.1093/jos/ffl006 Ionin, Tania & Ora Matushansky. 2018. Cardinals: The syntax and semantics of cardinal-containing expressions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Kayne, Richard S. 2007. Several, few and many. Lingua 117(5). 832–858. DOI:10.1016/j.lingua.2006.03.005 Kayne, Richard S. 2015. Once and twice. Studies in Chinese Linguistics 36(1). 1–20. Kennedy, Christopher. 2013. A scalar semantics for scalar readings of number words. In Ivano Caponigro & Carlo Cecchetto (eds.), From grammar to meaning: The spontaneous logicality of language, 172–200. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Kennedy, Christopher. 2015. A ‘de-Fregean’ semantics (and neo-Gricean pragmatics) for modified and unmodified numerals. Semantics & Pragmatics 8. 1– 44. DOI:10.3765/sp.8.10 Kennedy, Christopher & Jason Stanley. 2009. On ‘average’. Mind 118(471). 583– 646. DOI:10.1093/mind/fzp094 Khrizman, Keren. 2020. The cardinal/collective alternation in Russian numerals. In Teodora Radeva-Bork & Peter Kosta (eds.), Current developments in Slavic linguistics: Twenty years after, 325–338. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang. Kim, Hyoung Sup. 2009. The structure and use of collective numeral phrases in Slavic: Russian, Bosnian/Croatian/Serbian, and Polish. Austin, TX: University of Texas dissertation. http://hdl.handle.net/2152/10655. xli Author Klockmann, Heidi. 2012. Polish numerals and quantifiers: A syntactic analysis of subject-verb agreement mismatches. Utrecht: Utrecht University MA thesis. http://dspace.library.uu.nl/handle/1874/253961. Krifka, Manfred. 1989. Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics. In Renate Bartsch, Johan van Benthem & Peter von Emde Boas (eds.), Semantics and contextual expression, 75–115. Dordrecht: Foris. Krifka, Manfred. 1995. Common nouns: A contrastive analysis of Chinese and English. In Gregory N. Carlson & Francis J. Pelletier (eds.), The generic book, 398–411. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Krifka, Manfred. 1999. At least some determiners aren’t determiners. In Ken Turner (ed.), The semantics/pragmatics interface from different points of view, 257–291. Oxford: Elsevier. Krifka, Manfred, Francis J. Pelletier, Gregory N. Carlson, Gennaro Chierchia, Godehard Link & Alice G.B. ter Meulen. 1995. Genericity: An introduction. In Gregory N. Carlson & Francis J. Pelletier (eds.), The generic book, 1–124. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ladusaw, William. 1982. Semantic constraints on the English partitive construction. In Daniel Flickinger, Marlys Macken & Nancy Wiegand (eds.), Proceedings of the West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics 1, 231–242. Stanford, CA: Stanford University. Landman, Fred. 1989. Groups, I. Linguistics and Philosophy 12(5). 559–605. DOI:10.1007/BF00627774 Landman, Fred. 2000. Events and plurality: The Jerusalem lectures. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Landman, Fred. 2003. Predicate-argument mismatches and the adjectival theory of indefinites. In From NP to DP: Volume 1: The syntax and semantics of noun phrases, 211–237. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Landman, Fred. 2004. Indefinites and the type of sets. Oxford: Blackwell. Landman, Fred. 2006. Indefinite time-phrases, in situ-scope, and dual-perspective intensionality. In Svetlana Vogeleer & Liliane Tasmowski (eds.), Nondefiniteness and plurality, 237–266. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Landman, Fred. 2016. Iceberg semantics for count nouns and mass nouns: Classifiers, measures and portions. Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 11(1). 1–48. DOI:10.4148/1944-3676.1107 Lasersohn, Peter. 1995. Plurality, conjunction and events. Boston: Kluwer. Łazorczyk, Agnieszka & Roumyana Pancheva. 2009. From ‘two’ to ‘both’: Historical changes in the syntax and meaning of ‘oba’ in Slavic. In Ronald P. Leow, xlii Numerals and their kin Héctor Campos & Donna Lardiere (eds.), Little words: Their history, phonology, syntax, semantics, pragmatics and acquisition, 9–19. Washington: Georgetown University Press. Link, Godehard. 1983. The logical analysis of plural and mass nouns: A lattice– theoretical approach. In Rainer Bäuerle, Christoph Schwarze & Arnim von Stechow (eds.), Meaning, use, and interpretation of language, 302–323. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. Link, Godehard. 1984. Hydras: On the logic of relative constructions with multiple heads. In Fred Landman & Frank Veltman (eds.), Varieties of formal semantics, 245–257. Dordrecht: Foris. Lučić, Radovan. 2015. Observations on collective numerals in standard Croatian. Journal of Slavic Linguistics. 3–31. DOI:10.1353/jsl.2015.0006 Lyons, John. 1977. Semantics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Matushansky, Ora & Tania Ionin. this volume. Measurement and cardinals in Slavic. In Berit Gehrke & Radek Šimík (eds.), Semantics of Slavic languages. Berlin: Language Science Press. Matushansky, Ora & Joost Zwarts. 2017. Making space for measures. In Andrew Lamont & Katerina Tetzloff (eds.), NELS 47: Proceedings of the Forty-Seventh Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society, 261–274. Meyer, Caitlin, Sjef Barbiers & Fred Weerman. 2018. Ordinals are not as easy as ‘one’, ‘two’, ‘three’: The acquisition of cardinals and ordinals in Dutch. Language Acquisition 25(4). 392–417. DOI:10.1080/10489223.2017.1391266 Morzycki, Marcin. 2016. Modification. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Norris, Mark. 2018. The morphosyntax of number in Estonian numeral-noun constructions. Proceedings of the Linguistic Society of America 3(1(45)). 1–13. DOI:10.3765/plsa.v3i1.4337 Nouwen, Rick. 2010. Two kinds of modified numerals. Semantics & Pragmatics 3. 1–41. DOI:10.3765/sp.3.3 Ojeda, Almerindo E. 1997. A semantics for the counting numerals of Latin. Journal of Semantics 14(2). 143–171. DOI:10.1093/jos/14.2.143 Pancheva, Roumyana. 2018. How many flowers? So many colors! Number marking in cardinality exclamatives in Bulgarian. In Steven L. Franks, Vrinda Chidambaram, Brian D. Joseph & Iliyana Krapova (eds.), Katerino Mome: Studies in Bulgarian morphosyntax in honor of Catherine Rudin, 197–234. Bloomington, IN: Slavica Publishers. Partee, Barbara H. 1986. Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In Jeroen Groenendijk, Dick de Jongh & Martin Stokhof (eds.), Studies in Dis- xliii Author course Representation Theory and the Theory of Generalized Quantifiers, 115–143. Dordrecht: Foris. Partee, Barbara H. & Vladimir Borschev. 2012. Sortal, relational, and functional interpretations of nouns and Russian container constructions. Journal of Semantics 29(4). 445–486. DOI:10.1093/jos/ffs009 Pesetsky, David. 1982. Paths and categories. Cambridge, MA: MIT dissertation. https://dspace.mit.edu/handle/1721.1/15467. Rothstein, Susan. 2010. Counting and the mass/count distinction. Journal of Semantics 27(3). 343–397. DOI:10.1093/jos/ffq007 Rothstein, Susan. 2011. Counting, measuring and the semantics of classifiers. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 6. 1–42. DOI:10.4148/biyclc.v6i0.1582 Rothstein, Susan. 2017. Semantics for counting and measuring. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Rutkowski, Paweł. 2002. The syntax of quantifier phrases and the inherent vs. structural case distinction. Linguistic Research 7(1). 43–74. Scha, Remko. 1981. Distributive, collective and cumulative quantification. In Jeroen A.G. Groenendijk, Theo M.V. Janssen & Martin B.J. Stokhof (eds.), Formal methods in the study of language, 483–512. Amsterdam: Mathematisch Cen- trum. Schäfer, Roland. 2007. On frequency adjectives. In Estela Puig-Waldmüller (ed.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 11, 555–567. Barcelona: Universitat Pompeu Fabra. Schwarzschild, Roger. 1991. On the meaning of definitive plural noun phrases. Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts dissertation. Schwarzschild, Roger. 1996. Pluralities. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Schwarzschild, Roger. 2002. The grammar of measurement. In Brendan Jackson (ed.), Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory 12, 225–245. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications. DOI:10.3765/salt.v12i0.2870 Scontras, Gregory. 2014. The semantics of measurement. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University dissertation. http://nrs.harvard.edu/urn-3:HUL.InstRepos: 13064988. Sharvit, Yael. 2010. Infinitival superlatives: English vs. Modern Hebrew. Brill’s Journal of Afroasiatic Languages and Linguistics 2(1). 213–247. DOI:10.1163/187666310X12688137960821 Starke, Michal. 2009. Nanosyntax: A short primer to a new approach to language. Nordlyd 36(1). 1–6. DOI:10.7557/12.213 xliv Numerals and their kin Stolz, Thomas & Ljuba Veselinova. 2013. Ordinal numerals. In Matthew S. Dryer & Martin Haspelmath (eds.), The world atlas of language structures online. Leipzig: Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology. https : / / wals . info / chapter/53. Sudo, Yasutada. 2016. The semantic role of classifiers in Japanese. Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 11(1). 1–15. DOI:10.4148/1944-3676.1108 Veselinova, Ljuba. 1998. Suppletion in the derivation of ordinal numerals: A case study. In Benjamin Bruening (ed.), Proceedings of the 8th Student Conference in Linguistics, 429–447. Cambridge, MA: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics. Wągiel, Marcin. 2014. Boys, girls, and scissors: A semantic analysis of Polish NPs headed by the numeral ‘dwoje’. In Ludmila Veselovská & Markéta Janebová (eds.), Nominal structures: All in complex DPs, 69–84. Olomouc: Palacký Uni- versity. Wągiel, Marcin. 2015. Sums, groups, genders, and Polish numerals. In Gerhild Zybatow, Petr Biskup, Marcel Guhl, Claudia Hurtig, Olav Mueller-Reichau & Maria Yastrebova (eds.), Slavic grammar from a formal perspective: The 10th anniversary FDSL conference, Leipzig 2013, 495–513. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang. Wągiel, Marcin. 2018. Subatomic quantification. Brno: Masaryk University dissertation. https://is.muni.cz/th/lax8m/wagiel-subatomic-quantification.pdf. Wągiel, Marcin. 2020a. Entities, events, and their parts: The semantics of multipliers in Slavic. In Teodora Radeva-Bork & Peter Kosta (eds.), Current developments in Slavic linguistics: Twenty years after, 105–130. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang. Wągiel, Marcin. 2020b. Several quantifiers are different than others: Polish indefinite numerals. In Lanko Marušič, Rok Žaucer & Petra Mišmaš (eds.), Advances in formal Slavic linguistics 2017, 323–353. Berlin: Language Science Press. Wągiel, Marcin. to appear. Grammatical gender meets classifier semantics: Evidence from Slavic numerals. In Vera Gribanova, Sabrina Grimberg, Erika Petersen O Farrill, Eva Portelance & Brandon Waldon (eds.), Formal Approaches to Slavic Linguistics 27. Ann Arbor, MI: Michigan Slavic Publications. Wągiel, Marcin & Pavel Caha. 2020. Universal semantic features and the typology of cardinal numerals. Catalan Journal of Linguistics 19. 199–229. DOI:10.5565/rev/catjl.296 Wiese, Heike. 2003. Numbers, language, and the human mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. xlv Author Wohlmuth, Kata. 2019. Atomicity and distributive reference. Barcelona: Universitat Pompeu Fabra dissertation. http://hdl.handle.net/10803/667116. Zimmermann, Malte. 2003. Pluractionality and complex quantifier formation. Natural Language Semantics 11(3). 249–287. DOI:10.1023/A:1024937316555 xlvi