Berghahn Books The Art of the Possible — The Bullet or the Ballot Box: Defining Politics in the Emerging Global Order Author(s): Olle Frödin Source: Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory, Vol. 58, No. 128 (SEPTEMBER 2011), pp. 1-20 Published by: Berghahn Books Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/41802508 Accessed: 31-10-2019 16:24 UTC REFERENCES Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article: https://www.jstor.org/stable/41802508?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Berghahn Books is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theoria: A Journal of Social and Political Theory This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Art of the Possible - The Bullet or the Ballot Box Defining Politics in the Emerging Global Order Olle Frödin Abstract : In the wake of globalisation different social science disciplines have found themselves entering into similar terrains of inquiry. However, each discipline tends to draw on different and often contradictory understandings of the political, and of related notions such as power. The lack of a shared notion of politics may prevent social scientists from gaining important insights from other disciplines. In this paper I therefore seek to demonstrate that seemingly contradictory notions of politics are better seen as different forms of political interaction. I define politics as activities through which people and groups articulate, negotiate, implement and enforce competing claims. By distinguishing different types of claims made within different institutional circumstances, I outline three basic forms of political interaction: governance, stalemate and social dilemma, and give examples of how each of these forms of political interaction has emerged in response to the global integration of market in different circumstances and areas of the world. Keywords: constructivism, definition of politics, governance, institutions, political theory, social ontology The study of politics is plagued by conceptual confusion to such an extent that scholars of politics do not even agree on the nature of their subject of study. Some confine politics to the doings of actors in the formal political sphere, while others see politics everywhere, suggesting that family matters and monetary phenomena are always and everywhere political (e.g. Kirshner 2003). Such conceptual confusion is problematic but perhaps unavoidable since politics, along with other key social science notions such as democracy and justice, are typical examples of 'essentially contested concepts', that is concepts 'the proper use of which inevitably involves endless disputes about their proper uses on the part of their users' (Gallie 1956: 169). Defining politics is controversial and difficult, not only because different understandings of politics carry with them different implications for methodology, but also because 'defining politics and specifying the content of the discipline are themselves Theoria, September 2011 doi: 10.3 167/th.201 1.5812801 This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 2 Olle Frödin political pro tional difficu was once reached so as to enable a division of the modern social sciences into separate disciplines such as politics, economics, sociology and anthropology. The political sphere was thereby analytically disconnected from economics and social relations, and political, social and economic aspects of human life came to be studied in separate disciplines, as Wolf (1982: 7-8) notes. Within the discipline of politics, another distinction was drawn between two different types of political order, 'ungoverned interaction' or anarchy in the case of international relations, and governmental authority with regard to domestic politics (Coward 2006). Given the relative stability of these disciplinary boundaries, the concept of politics, at least when used as a basis for disciplinary divisions, is perhaps best described as 'contingently contested' (Ball 1988). Contingent contestability 'remains a permanent possibility even though it is, in practice, actualized only intermittently', as Ball (1988: 14) argues. In the last few decades, worldly and scholarly developments have called into question established notions of politics and concomitant disciplinary boundaries. The constitution and governance of the global political order have changed in such as way as to challenge established paradigms and disciplinary boundaries. In the previously dominant state-centric perspective, which presumed clear disciplinary boundaries, the world is constituted by states claiming a monopoly of violence within their borders. In this view, states interact in the absence of a global government leading to episodic wars between them in the event that they cannot cooperate. In the wake of globalisation, it is necessary to acknowledge that increasing transnational connectivity has changed both the constitution and governance of the global political order (Coward 2006). In a world in which states are best understood as 'disaggregated' sets of organisations arranged in various networks, many of which are transnational - where the OECD countries in practice constitute a security complex, where low-intensity conflicts involving insurgents who do not operate as disciplined armies are much more common than interstate wars, where transnational corporations and transnational criminal networks may play major roles in the development of societies, and where it consequently is difficult to distinguish clear boundaries between public, private, domestic and international realms disciplines like international relations, criminology and domestic politics no longer focus on separate terrains of scholarly inquiry. Social scientists from various disciplines are now increasingly focusing on how polities and actors at different levels respond to a dominant global political order (Neumann and Sending 2007). As different social science disciplines and branches enter into similar terrains of inquiry, the potential for interdisciplinary cross-fertilisation seems greater than ever. However, different disciplines carry with them different understandings of the political, and of related notions such as power. As a result, a wide variety of different and often contradictory understandings of This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Art of the Possible - The Bullet or the Ballot Box 3 politics, and of the nature and role of power and coercion processes, circulate in the contemporary social sciences. For instan tively oriented scholars may define politics as reasoned deliber formal decision-making fora. By contrast, realist IR speciali Clausewitzian perspective view war as a continuation of polit means, while Weberians may see the establishment of a monopoly as a precondition for politics. More recently, social scientists draw works of Foucault see politics practically everywhere. Thus, there clarity as to whether the use of force implies the breakdown whether the establishment of a monopoly of violence is a prec politics, whether politics is confined to specific arenas or if it is to all areas of social life. While it can be argued that this concept merely reflects the fact that scholars seek to do different things respective notions, the lack of a shared understanding of what co tics may prevent social scientists from gaining important insight disciplines in trying to make sense of the contemporary world or In this paper, I therefore set out to clarify the conceptual confus to concept of politics by outlining a theoretical framework throug ingly contradictory understandings can be seen as different form rather than mutually exclusive activities. I begin with a review of social science understandings of politics, mainly government-cent and various power-centred perspectives. I then introduce the conc work and use it as a basis to outline three basic types of political Finally, I give examples of how these different types of inte emerged in response to globalisation in different areas and circum Classical and Modern Notions of Politics According to the classical Greek understanding, politics refers to the ways in which free citizens of a state or polis govern themselves through public debate. In this view, politics is seen as an activity through which collective decisions are made through discussion and persuasion. Accordingly, politics breaks down in cases where conflicting parties resort to coercion rather than persuasion (Crick 2004: 73). In line with the classical notion, Crick (2004: 67) defines politics as a 'distinctive form of rule whereby people act together through institutionalized procedures to resolve differences, to conciliate diverse interests and values and to make public policies in the pursuit of common purposes'. Consequently, he concurs with Arendt that the use of violence implies the breakdown of politics, not its continuation by other means (Crick 2004: 70). Government-centred notions are probably the most commonly used in twentieth-century social science. They differ from classical understandings in that they are linked to the potential use of force on the part of a government branch that enjoys the monopoly of legitimate violence. Weber formulated This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 4 Olle Frödin the most in which a polit ing organisat imate use of In this persp oly of legitim denotes publ concerning i and the pro the monopo from those 2004: 14; W through the are closely r wider in sco The power-c junction wit ties'. When Europe in th or, more spe rule in a com of the doctri state, in the means, just o the classical tant role in articulated th and philosop tics, the term tred on stru In twentieth of power in ena, and the quently cen matter of 'w authoritativ tred definiti tinguish pol demarcation entists adop (1974) theor tions, thus c ity of an act well as two-d This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Art of the Possible - The Bullet or the Ballot Box 5 to control and set political agendas. According to Lukes' radical is located in collectivities sustaining institutions rather than in th individuals, and can therefore be found even in situations where o are absent. The matter of power and the political was further com many researchers subsequently turned to the work of Foucault in an go beyond Lukes' three-dimensional view of power (Gunn 2006 understanding of power differs from that of Lukes' in that Fouca believe that power is possessed by social classes. Instead, power social relations and is therefore not 'localised here or there, never hands, never appropriated as a commodity or piece of wealth' (Fou 98). Rather than studying shifts in power between groups and acto cally, Foucault was interested in the exercise of power at the Power, according to Foucault, stems from abstract political rationa than from individuals and groups with specific interests. By focus 'micro-physics' of power, Foucault rejected notions of social power in specific bodies, such as the Crown, the Parliament, or the r Foucault thus attacked both government-centred notions of power sovereignty and Marxist understandings highlighting dominan coalitions of classes that use states as their instrument of rule. In the Foucauldian perspective on politics, focus is not on parties, classes or ideologies but on techniques of rule and strategies and practices through which governance is achieved. Consequently, in the Foucauldian perspective political change involves shifts in governmental rationality and the techniques of rule, rather than shifts in policy or changing class alignments (Gunn 2006). Contemporary debates are sometimes confused by the fact that scholars may draw on either classical, government-centred or Foucauldian notions of politics. For instance, in a paper comparing how liberal scholars like Rawls, Honig and Connolly and the illiberal philosopher Carl Schmitt address problems of intractable and intolerable disagreement, Skorupska concludes that they all see politics as a solution. This may sound paradoxical but is explained by the fact that they use very different notions of politics. A disagreement is intractable and intolerable in cases where there is disagreement over which right should be protected in cases where two actions are conflicting, and where there seems to be no way of reaching rational consensus to settle the conflict in a non-coercive manner acceptable to all. In their various ways of addressing this problem, Rawls, Honig and Connolly fall back upon a normative definition of politics as a non-coercive activity based on reason and reflection through which 'the elementary problem of human living-together' is settled by peaceful means. By contrast, Carl Schmitt did not believe in peaceful, rational solutions to problems of intractable disagreement. In his view, peaceful rational solutions were only viable when politicians shared similar perspectives and where controversial questions could be excluded from the political domain. Schmitt held that in case rational consensus to intractable and intolerable disagreements is not possible to achieve, a decision, enforced through This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 6 Olle Frödin coercion, mu ultimately a This brief r and sometim lishment of politics as a p decision-mak ing feature. essentially c and influenc which they s Against this whether poli all areas of whether it r peaceful acti Is Politi These definit nomically. A criterion ind we refer to in that schoo ally being c force by the politics too n characteristi politics in te defining wh Drawing on the possibilit politics is a c essential. Po a 'family re erty require that politics and 'aggrega collections of behaviour. A politics rem tiveness' and tennis leagu This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Art of the Possible - The Bullet or the Ballot Box 1 hock (1978) points out, meaning that we still need further criteria politics. Recognising the problem of defining politics in a too narr recent works have simply acknowledged that politics may be f where in social life. For instance, Squires (2004: 119) argues 'politics where because there is no realm of life immune to relations of conflict and power'. Similarly, Leftwich holds 'politics consists of all activities of conflict (peaceful or not), negotiation and co-operation over the use and distribution of resources, whether they may be found within or beyond formal institutions, on a global level or within the family, involving two or more people (Leftwich 2004: 15). White (1993) adopts a similar view of politics as a 'process whereby power is mobilized and exercised to achieve individual, institutional or collective goals'. In this perspective, politics pervades society and the economy. White holds that markets can be seen as complex political systems with their own specific distributions of power and diverse sets of power relations, in which market actors seek to adjust the rules of the game to promote their own interests, or use their control over economic assets to constrain the choices and opportunities of other actors (White 1993). In a similar vein, Kirshner (2003) argues that monetary phenomena are always and everywhere political. Such broad definitions of the political beg the question of what we are to do with them. Even though it can be argued that politics is everywhere, what analytical purpose does it serve to equate social and economic interaction in general with politics? I believe that while power can be found everywhere in social life, not all power relations are by definition political. Politics, thus, is not everywhere. However, all social relations may become politicised. In the following, I outline a conceptual framework through which this line of argument will be clarified. Institutions and Social Interaction The mere existence of power relations does not necessarily entail conflict. In most areas of social life, institutionalised power relations are generally accepted and most interaction within institutional environments is therefore peaceful. A brief discussion on the ontology of social reality will clarify this statement. Searle (1996: 7-12) distinguishes between 'observer- independent features, - features of the world that are entirely independent of human attitudes and observer relative features, that is institutions, like money, parliaments, property, marriage and elections, that only exist in social relations Since institutions depend on shared understandings, e.g. subjective attitudes, for their existence, they can only be maintained as long as they enjoy a requisite degree of collective acceptance (Searle 2001 : 207). Institutional facts exist within frameworks of constitutive rules that enable various organised soci activities. Institutions also determine various deontic powers, that is rights duties, obligations, authorisations, permissions, empowerments, requirements This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 8 Olle Frödin and certific types of con forms of rul what those g rules that spe determine di as well as int multiple iden interests var course of a seller, citizen Belgian, whit mines in wh Each identity tions, powers able practices 1994: 385). Fo tify themselv imising ways within mark therefore de actors are usu tified as fri indeed be pr little thought invoke differ institutional On the basis rationalities a Thus institut parent, or cit what to do, a way, institut ing to which institutional called 'transaction domains'. The term transaction domain refers to a mutually agreed-upon definition of a situation according to which a particular logic of interaction, exchange or decision-making is considered socially acceptable Transaction domains lay down particular routines according to which certain logics of action, such as profit-maximisation, relational rationality, legal rationality, reciprocity, commitment, duty and so on, are considered appropriate or lawful. Moreover, each transaction domain is associated with different deontic powers, namely rights, obligations, permissions, authorisations and empowerments, pegged to a particular role or identity. Power This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Art of the Possible - The Bullet or the Ballot Box 9 and authority therefore tend to be differentially distributed with domains. Hierarchical forms of governance may be accept domains, whereas consensual forms of decision-making are requ ers. For instance, civil servants may be obliged to comply with ord members of a political committee are expected to make decision consensual manner (Frodin, 2009). In everyday life people tend to encounter a range of different t domains in which they draw on different roles, identities and for sion-making. As consumers, family members, politicians, voters or vants, people enter into different transaction domains where different rights and obligations and where they consequently act a different logics of action. For example, in a liberal-democratic, cap fare state, actors may carry out different informal obligations as family members; they accept that most rights to make collective d delegated to politicians and officials; they may invoke their rights in relation to different welfare institutions while they simultaneou edge the authority of public officials; they also recognise that goods are allocated via the market, and that 'democracy stops at gates' as the well-known aphorism goes. This suggests that liberal-d societies are not democratic in all respects. Rather, in some domain the corporate sector, the family, and in various branches of the ci tration and the military, hierarchical forms of decision-making ar accepted. Democratic decision-making is only expected in some which the parliament is the most notable. Political transaction d exist separately from market and civil society domains given that sensus has been established on such an institutional structure. Domain consensus is a concept borrowed from organisation theory (Thompson 1967: 27). We here use this term to signify the acceptance of a set of transaction domains within a particular area of social life. This definition applies to expectations about what actors will and will not do in certain social situations. Domain consensus is established when interacting actors share similar cognitive dispositions regarding behavioural expectations, rights and obligations that apply to a set of transaction domains (Frodin, 2009). Complex institutional orders are made up of a multitude of transaction domains that structure social relations in different ways, each of which cannot rely solely on the probability of third-party enforcement. Most people accept a shared 'script' according to which they are officially expected to invoke different logics of action in the roles of consumer, party member, citizen, public official, friend, relative, politician and private company employee. This means that institutions must be collectively accepted or complied with, reluctantly, carelessly or willingly, not only by groups in control of coercive means but by a wider stratum of the population. This suggests that much power is in the hands of ordinary people who may restrain elite actions. For instance, people may find it hard to accept that particular logics of exchange, such as market This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 10 OlleFrödin principles, ar education or h Having outlin distinguishing Governance and Politics All domains of social life may indeed be considered political, that is politicised, but only if someone questions a certain institutionalised practice or an entire institutional order and calls for reforms or revolutionary changes. For instance, power relations in the family or in private companies may be politicised. However, as long as a specific institution or practice is generally accepted, we may speak of governance. Governance here denotes the coordination and conciliation of interdependent activities via institutions. For instance, markets and bureaucracies can be employed to allocate goods and provide public services without anyone questioning this state of affairs. We may then speak of governance founded on a mixture of markets and administrative planning. Governance refers to processes in which different actors and organisations pursue their own goals and retain their autonomy, while they simultaneously orient their actions towards common outcomes. Cooperative relationships, or institutionalised forms of interaction, are prerequisites for governance. This implies that governance requires domain consensus as well as goal consensus. From this viewpoint, everyday practices involving institutions, such as monetary phenomena, are not always and everywhere political unless someone openly questions why, for instance, central banks are independent of parliamentary control. A certain institutional structure is consequently not considered political unless it is politicised. In other words, while this framework remains open-ended as to which social relations may become politicised, it does not claim that politics is everywhere by definition. Only if all social institutions are politicised can politics be found everywhere. While political actions are not necessarily confined to a specific arena, they usually involve the making of claims. Politics, in its very basic form, is about claims-making. Political claims are made with reference to someone else. For instance, sovereignty claims would be meaningless in the absence of others aspiring to establish sovereignty. Claims imply counterclaims or contestation, otherwise there would be no point in making them, as Sheehan (2006) points out. Politics, then, can be defined as an activity through which 'individuals and groups articulate, negotiate, implement, and enforce competing claims' to social change or to maintain status quo (Sheehan 2006: 3). Such a definition may include both classical understandings of politics as well as concepts of the political related to the potential use of force. It is possible that neither John Rawls nor Carl Schmitt would have denied that their respective notions of politics include people making various claims. The difference between classical This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Art of the Possible - The Bullet or the Ballot Box 1 1 notions centred on reasoned deliberation and power-centred notions o concerns the basis upon which claims are made, and the means by wh are defeated or defended. When political claims are made, actor appeal to some principle, standard of justice and/or a readiness to tak kind of action (Sheehan 2006). The character of politics is determined kind of powers that the claims-makers possess, appeal to and emp the ways in which claims are made, and the power upon which they are of crucial significance for the character of politics. By singling o ent types of claims, and different institutional contexts in which they we may distinguish different types of politics. Tilly (1976) distinguishes three types of claims. Firstly, competitiv claim something - a piece of land or an asset - that is also claimed groups, defined by the claims-maker as rivals, competitors or partici the same contest. Secondly, reactive collective actions consist of efforts to reassert institutionalised claims when they are violated or by someone else. Finally, proactive claims have not previously be and may aim at higher wages, better working conditions, civil r widening of existing channels for political decision-making. An additional distinction can be made between formal and informa cal claims. By formal activities we refer to activities relying on rules cedures that are codified, communicated and enforced through widely accepted as official, unlike informal institutions, which t unwritten, communicated and enforced outside of officially sanction nels (Helmke 2004). Actors and groups can make claims and engag ities that rely upon a shared formal institutional order or ignore it o from the formal rules of the game. A critical question regarding the of contemporary institutional orders concerns whether most econ political activities rely upon, or are harmonious with, formal institut system of mass democracy, a critical mass of people must accept the channels for political expression and use them to air their voices and their collective interests. Discontented groups have to accept domain sus and seek to change the character of the formal order, rather tha contest it. Making claims within formal constraints means accepting consensus. Formal political claims may concern the articulation of aim at changing the existing institutional order through constitution ments. Informal political claims can be expressed in a variety of w contented groups may violate the law, revolutionaries may aim institutional transformations and insurgents may engage in informal in which they do not operate as disciplined armies. This means th tionalised channels for political interaction are bypassed, contested or In the next section, I combine the concepts introduced above so tinguish different types of political interaction. This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 12 OlleFrödin Governanc Conventional as Parliament type of politi activities. Give be pursued thr interaction, a formly across is a basic requi recognition by in societies an can be institu that politics 'is institutionalise ests and value poses' (Crick 2 above, I view claims-making which two clai non-political. making activit be considered consensus as coordination an in a situation i claims through Liberal-democ ing interests c reached. How order is not a interaction m political exch Political inter involved are u accordance wit does not neces bring about g where domain consensus has been established. According to the argument advanced here, the classical notion of politics amounts to peaceful forms of claims-making resulting in governance, while politics also comprises a wider set of interactions, including failures to find solutions to 'the elementary problem of human living-together'. For instance, if political actors engage in competitive informal claims-making, that is if This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Art of the Possible - The Bullet or the Ballot Box 1 3 they have not established domain consensus on channels for peace of political interaction, politics basically boils down to a social dilem of situation. A social dilemma develops whenever individuals in i dent situations face choices in which 'the maximisation of short-term selfinterest yields outcomes leaving all participants worse off than feasible alternatives' (Ostrom 1998: 3). On the basis of the framework presented above, the preconditions for governance are affected by the ways in which actors define individual and collective identities and interests, and the ways in which they invoke and act on these interests in different situations. Informal institutions such as customs, status systems, gender relations and other non-organisational identities may affect formal structures in various ways. Consequently, the entire set of both formal and informal roles and identities must be taken into account in analysing politics in a particular setting. Different identities and roles may overlap and people may find it difficult to integrate them into a consistent pattern of values (Ahrne 1994). 'Informal' group loyalties and roles, such as those of a caste, may prevail over formal roles. If informal roles and interests overshadow the formal order on a major scale, formal governance regimes will collapse. From the viewpoint of this theory, there is no opposition between Putnam's (1993) statement that a strong society empowers the state and Migdal's (1988) assertion that a strong society may undermine a state. This is because Putnam and Migdal simply refer to different institutional orders. Putnam's 'strong society' operates within the confines of a formal institutional order whereas Migdal's 'strong society' is contesting it. A strong civil society, in the sense of a counter-hegemonic counterpart to the state, can only flourish in an environment where the formal institutional order is accepted and sustained by public, private and civic organisations jointly. Weak states in Migdal's sense are not sustained by formal rules since they are co-opted or contested by clans, warlords or patron-client networks that follow other rules than those formally sanctioned (Frodin, 2010). The latter form of politics, that is competitive, informal claims-making, can be found in environments where political as well as administrative institutions are weakly established, such as in medieval and early-modern Europe and in contemporary 'failed states'. Competitive 'informal' claims-making was a dominant form of politics in medieval and early-modern Europe, where governments basically consisted of shifting coalitions among competing feudal lords or warlords, of which kings headed the most powerful coalitions. Most kings faced serious challenges to their hegemony as a great deal of power was located in city-states, craft brotherhoods, peasant communities, principalities and semi-autonomous provinces (Tilly 1976). In other words, political powers were weakly institutionalised and widely diffused. Similarly, in subSaharan Africa a Western model of statehood carried 'the taint of being a foreign, white imposition on local, self-governing communities' (Bayly 2004: 265). This was because the specific kind of domain consensus required for the This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 14 Olle Frödin formal model mal group loy prevail over f postcolonial Gh rules of the bu obliged them t consensus has overtrump the were establish tended to be a result, Africa making on the short-term lo classical notio political insti absurd conclus classify Africa generating soc ther the pract responses to th outcomes acros Political Inte The establishm eties to respon process that fo to the onslaug development increased both (1997) argues. S to globalisation conditions. As coordinated ac integration, ar collective iden on these inter logic and thus such identities educated midd the upper end ing risks being is threatened b This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Art of the Possible - The Bullet or the Ballot Box 1 5 as the formal political system, or informally by engaging in illegal a or by taking up arms. Resistance may be expressed in various way nationalism or religious fundamentalism, and take various forms ran the rise of xenophobic parties in Europe to armed resistance in Afgh Finally, some movements may seek to transform rather than reject order, such as transnational environmentalist movements or coun monic globalisation movements which call for social protection to ad short-comings of the dominant market order (Evans 2008) In order for national societies or regions to respond to globalisatio with the dominant economic logic in a coordinated way, a considerab the population has to embrace the existing order and the opportunity it presents. Such responses are favoured by certain structural condit are more likely in societies where the level of education is high, whe resources are widely dispersed, where the majority of the people are rated into, and dependent on, a formal legal order, and where the m interests are mobilised into parties and civic organisations on th inclusive collective identities such as class or ideology, than in societi the general level of education is low, where valued resources are conc in the hands of smaller elites, where large parts of the population ar alised from the formal sector and where the principal societal int mobilised into patron-client networks on the basis of exclusive i founded on kinship or ethnicity. Coordinated national governance wi global order requires both domain consensus and a great deal of goal sus. The preconditions for such forms of governance may be very di replicate since they often have evolved through long-term historical under conditions where nation-wide governance has been absolut sary. For instance, the Dutch system of 'consensual corporatism' is so held as an example of a political system that has successfully attained nance to promote economic development continuously through clo ation between the public and the private sectors. According to Werli the Dutch political system is held together by a common devotion to tics of accommodation, pragmatism and consensus, as well as a shared for independent experts and for the judiciary. The system of consen poratism relies upon a context-specific type of domain consensus wh partially result from the country's particular geographical locatio cooperation in the Netherlands has always been essential in order coll to defend the country against the sea, as Hill and Hupe (2006) point o Some societies such as the Netherlands and Scandinavia have, gi relatively favourable historical conditions, largely managed to att nance in response to the global integration of markets, although it is i to note that even in the most prosperous societies of the world, subs losses and the partial dismantling of social services have contributed increasing strain on the social contract (McMichael 2004). In other are as in Portugal, Italy, Greece and Spain, it has been more difficult This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 16 OlleFrödin broad social a in the global ing governm In yet other more contrad omy has emer technology p informal sec informal sect 2000, while f (Basile and H 2000s, a mere IT-sector, sup million peop and 93 per ce mal economy has been acc White, the in adaptive respo of the Indian ate classes are small-scale fa and co-opted maintain thei connections t an outsider. T have managed the intermed in the libera lobby associat sector throug seen as conce opportunistic (Harriss-Whi to such claim istic manner. nious with t corruption. E resources to p structural re strategy of r resources. Wh to neglect pre tect marginal This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Art of the Possible - The Bullet or the Ballot Box 1 7 The failures of Indian public-sector organisations to provide social and services to large numbers of poor people, in combination with co able land acquisitions on the part of mining companies, have cont strengthening the armed Maoist rebels, also called the Naxalites, Eastern India. The history of the Naxalite Movement of India extend 1967 but it draws on a longer history of violent conflict between pe landlords. While this dimension of conflict is less prominent today, alites are primarily mobilising against 'imperialism' in the form of t quences of the globalisation of India's economy. The Naxalite m which is seen as one the most serious challenges that the Indian gove has ever faced, has sought to align itself with tribal peoples whose li is threatened as land, forests and water are acquired for mining or p eration projects. In order to strike down on the insurgency, the Indi ment created a special police force called the 'Greyhounds' which is n by law, and which operates on the same terms as the Naxalites. In ot the Indian army and police have engaged the Naxalites using the sam and means, thus violating the formal legal order they are to represe ties carried out by government forces and privately funded militias quently given people further reasons to support the Maoists, lea downward spiral of violence (Harriss 2010). Unlike areas such as North- Western Europe where the precond governance have been relatively favourable in that large sections of lations are capable of reaping the benefits of global market integ responses to globalisation have been much more contradictory an ridden in India, since most political and economic interactions occ of the formal institutional order. In the absence of domain consensu consensus, both public and private actors have engaged in various competitive claims-making, giving rise to a social dilemma type o in parts of the country. Conclusion On the basis of the concepts used in this paper, we have distinguished thre basic forms of political interaction: governance, stalemate and social dilemma. Governance denotes the coordination and conciliation of interdependent activities, and is founded on domain consensus as well as the attainment of goa consensus through processes of deliberation. Stalemate refers to political interactions taking place within institutionalised decision-making fora that doe not result in governance. Finally, social dilemma refers to forms of political interaction in which actors and groups have failed to establish a shared institutional order and engage in competitive claims-making by any means at hand, including violence, leading to outcomes that leave all members of the polity worse off than feasible alternatives. A basic predicament, which philosophers This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 18 OlleFrödin like Hobbes a lem of establ systematical through the above the rul and unfortun the army en rivals, rather legal means a In such situa scape is vuln Having defi through var politics comm analytical fr continuation ernance, whil an institutional order on which domain consensus has been reached. Olle Frödin is a research fellow at the Department of International Development, University of Oxford and the Pufendorf Institute, Lund University, Sweden. His current research is on political economic issues surrounding the emergence of supermarkets in India. His most recent publications include: 'Generalized and Particularistic thinking in Policy Analysis and Practice: The Case of Governance Reform in South Africa' {Development Policy Review , 2009), and 'Review: Feeding India. The Spatial Parameters of Food Policy' {European Journal of Development Research, 2010). References Ahme, G. (1994) Social Organisations: Interaction Inside, Outside and Between Organisations. London: Sage Publications. Ball, T. 1988. Transforming Political Discourse: Political Theory and Critical Conceptual History. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. Basile, Elisabetta , and Barbara Harriss-White. 2010. "India's informal capitalism and its regulation: Introduction." International Review of Sociology 20(3):457-71. Bayly, C. A. 2004. The Birth of the Modern World 1 780-1914: Global Connections and Comparisons. Oxford: Blackwell. Chabal, P. and J. -P. Daloz. 1999. Africa Works : Disorder as Political Instrument. Indiana: Indiana University Press. Coward, M. 2006. 'International Relations in the Post-globalisation Era', Politics 26(1): 54-61. Crick, B. 2004. 'Politics as a Form of Rule: Politics, Citizenship and Democracy', in A. Leftwich (ed.), What Is Politics? Cambridge: Polity Press, 67-85. This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms The Art of the Possible - The Bullet or the Ballot Box 1 9 Davis, J. 1992. Exchange. Buckingham: Open University Press. Easton, D. 1953. The Political System: An Inquiry into the State of Politica New York: Knopf. Evans, P. 1997. 'The Eclipse of the State: Reflections on Stateness in an E Globalization', World Politics 50(1): 62-87. 271-305. Foucault, M. 1980. Power/Knowledge: Selected interviews and Other Writings 1972- 1977. Hemel Hempstead: Harvester. Frankel, F. R. 2005. India 's Political Economy 1947-2004. New Delhi: Oxford University Press. Frodin O. 2009. Generalised and particularistic thinking in policy analysis and practice: the case of Governance Reform in South Africa. Development Policy Review 27(3): 287-306. Frodin, O. 2010. "Dissecting the State: Towards a Relational Conceptualization of States and State Failure." Journal of International Development Published online in Wiley Online Library (wileyonlinelibrary.com) DOI: 10. 1002/jid. 1 743. Frohock, F. M. 1978. 'The Structure of "Polities'", The American Political Science Review 72(3): 859-870. Gallie, W. B. 1956. 'Essentially Contested Concepts', Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series 56(1956):67-198. Gunn, S. 2006. 'From Hegemony to Governmentality: Changing Conceptions of Power in Social History', Journal of Social History 39(3): 705-720. Gupta, D. 2009. The Caged Phoenix: Can India Fly? New Delhi: Harper Collins. Harriss, J. 2010. 'The Naxalite/Maoist Movement in India: A Review of Recent Literature', ISAS Working Paper No. 109-08 July 2010. Singapore: National University of Singapore. Harriss- White, B. 2003. India Working: Essays on Society and Economy. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Helmke, G. and L. Steven. 2004. 'Informal Institutions and Comparative Politics: A Research Agenda', Perspectives on Politics 2(4): 725-740. Hill, M. and P. L. Hupe. 2006. Implementing Public Policy: Governance in Theory and in Practice. London: Sage Publications. Jeffrey, C. 2010. 'Démocratisation without Representation? The Power and Political Strategies of a Rural Elite in North India', Political Geography 19(8): 1013-1036. Kirshner, J. 2003. 'Money is Polities', Review of International Political Economy 10(4): 645-660. Lasswell, H. D. 1958. Politics : Who Gets What , When, How? New York: Meridian. Leftwich, A. 2004. 'Thinking Politically: On the Politics of Polities', in A. Leftwich (ed.), What Is Politics? Cambridge: Polity Press, 1-22. Lukes, S. 1974. Power: A Radical View. London: Macmillan. McMichael, P. 2004. Development and Social Change: A Global Perspective. Thousand Oaks: Pine Forge Press. Migdal, J. 1988. Strong Societies and Weak States: State-society Relations and Capabilities in the Third World. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Neumann, I. B. and O. J. Sending. 2007. 'The International as Governmentality'. Millennium -Journal of International Studies 35(3): 677-701. This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms 20 Olle Frödin Nicholson, P. P Is Politics? Ca Ostrom, E. 199 Collective Act University Press. Price, R. M. 1975. Society and Bureaucracy in Contemp University of California Press. Putnam, R. 1993. Making Democracy Work. Princeton: Pr Searle, J. R. 1996. The Construction of Social Reality. L 22. Sheehan, J. J. 2006. 'The Problem of Sovereignty in European History', American Historical Review 111(1): 1-18. Skorupska, J. 2008. 'Liberal Dilemmas and the Concept of Polities', Journal of Political Ideologies 13(3): 297-320. Squires, J. 2004. 'Politics Beyond Boundaries: A Feminist Perspective', in A. Leftwich (ed.), What Is Politics? Cambridge: Polity Press, 119-134. Thompson, J. D. 1967. Organizations in Action: Social Science Bases of Administrative Theory. New York: McGraw-Hill. Tilly, C. 1976. 'Major Forms of Collective Action in Western Europe, 1500-1975', Theory and Society 3(3): 365-375. Viroli , M. 1992. 'The Revolution in the Concept of Polities', Political Theory 20(3): 473-495. Weale, A. 2004. 'Politics as Collective Choice', in A. Leftwich (ed.), What Is Politics? Cambridge: Polity Press, 86-99. Weber, M. 1968. Economy and Society. Volume 1. New York: Bedminster Press. Wendt, A. 1994. 'Collective Identity Formation and the International State', The American Political Science Review 88(2): 384-396. Werlin, H. H. 2003. 'Poor Nations, Rich Nations: A Theory of Governance', Public Administration Review 63(3): 329-342. White, G. 1993. 'The Political Analysis of Markets: Editorial Introduction', IDS Bulletin 24(3): 1-11. Witsoe, J. 2009. 'Territorial Democracy: Caste, Dominance and Electoral Practice in Postcolonial India', PoLAR: Political and Legal Anthropology Review 8(1): 76- 87. Wolf, E. R. 1982. Europe and the People without History. Berkeley: University of California Press. This content downloaded from 147.251.55.74 on Thu, 31 Oct 2019 16:24:58 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms