L. WITTG ENSTEIN LECTURES & CONVERSATIONS on Aesthetics, Psychology and Religious Belief Compiled/rom Notes taken byYorick Smythies, Rush Rhees and]ames Taylor Edited by Cyril Barrett .UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA PRESS Berkeley and Los Angeles· 1967 University of California Press Berkeley and Los Angeles, California All Rights Reserved Second printing, 1967 Library of Congress Catalog Card Number: 66-19347 Printed in the United States of America CONTENTS Preface Lectures on Aesthetics Conversations on Freud Lectures on Religious Belief vii 1 41 53 PREFACE The first thing to be said about this book is that nothing contained herein was written by Wittgenstein himself. The notes published here are not Wittgenstein's own lecture notes but notes taken down by students, which he neither saw nor checked. It is even doubtful if he would have approved of their publication, at least in their present form. Since, however, they deal with topics only briefly touched upon in his other published writings, and since for some time they have been circulating privatdy, it was thought best to publish them in a form approved by their authors. The lectures on aesthetics were delivered in private rooms in Cambridge in the sumer of 1938. They were given to a smail group of students, which included Rush Rhees, Yorick Smythies, JamesTaylor,CasmirLewy, Theodore RedpathandMauriceDrury (whose names occur in the text). The name of another student, Ursell, also occurs in the text (p. 28), but he did not attend the lectures. The lectures on religious belief bdong to a course on belief given about the same time. The conversations on Freud between Wittgenstein and Rush Rhees took place between 1942 and 1946. Besides the notes of the. conversations on Freud, those of the fourth lecture on aesthetics are by Rush Rhees; the rest are by Smythies. Since· we possess three versions of the first three lectures on aesthetics (by Smythies, Rhees and Taylor-referred to respectively as S, R, and T) and two versions of the fourth lecture, the most complete version has been chosen as the text and significant variants have been added in footnote. The notes have been printed as they were taken down at the time, except for some minor gramtical corrections and a few omissions where the original was indecipherable. Although the diferent versions agree to a remarkable extent, their authors·do not vouch for their accuracy in every detail: they do not claim to give a verbatim report of what Wittgenstein said. The inclusion of variants may give to what were, after al, no more than informal discussions, an importance and solemnity PREFACE which may seem inappropriate. On the other hand, as should be clear, the difrent versions complement and clarify each other, and at the same time hint at their close agreement (which could be demonstrated only by printing al versions in ful). It might have been possIble to confiate the versions into a single text, but it seemed better to preserve each version as it was taken down and leave the reader to reconstruct a composite text for himself. At times, in the interests of clarity and smoother reading, some of the variants have been introduced into the text. Wherever this is done, and also where editorial emendations have been made, square brackets have been employed. The use of three dots (...) usualy indicates that there is a lacuna or an indecipherable passage in the text. Finally, a w.ord about the choice of material. This is only a selection from the extant students' notes of Wittgenstein's lectures. Yet, in spite of appearances, it is not a random selection. The notes printed here reflect Wittgenstein's opinions on and attitude to life, to religious, psychological and artistic questions. That Wittgenstein himself did not keep these questions separate is clear, for example, from G. E. Moore's account of the 1930-33 lectures (Mind 1955). C. B. LECT U R E S ON A E S THETIC S I 1 . The subject (Aesthetics) is very big and entirely misunderstood as far as I can see. The use of such a word as 'beautiful' is even more apt to be misunderstood if you look at the linguistic form of sentences in which it occurs than most other words. 'Beautiful' [and 'good'-R] is an adjective, so you are inclined to say: "This has a certain quality, that of being beautiful". 2. We are going from one subject-matter of philosophy to another, from one group of words to another group of words. 3. An intelligent way of dividing up a book on philosophy would be into parts of speech, kinds of words. Where in fact you would have to distinguish far more parts of speech than an ordinary gram does. You would talk for hours and hours on the verbs 'seeing', 'feeling', etc.,. verbs describing personal experience. We get a peculiar kind of confusion or confusions which comes up with al these words.1 You would have another chapter on numerals-here there would be another kind of confusion: a chapter on 'al', 'any', 'some', etc.-another kind of confusion: a chapter on 'you', '1', etc.-another kind: a chapter on 'beautiful', 'good'-another kind. We get into a new group of confusions; language plays us entirely new tricks. 4. I have often compared language to a tool chest, containing a hamer, chisel, matches, nails, screws, glue. It is not a chance that al these things have been put together-but there are important differences between the diferent tools-they are used in a family of ways-though nothing could be more diferent than glue and a chisel. There is constant surprise at the new tricks language plays on us when we get into a new field. 5. One thing we always do when discussing a word is to ask how we were taught it. Doing this on the one hand destroys a variety of misconceptions, on the other hand gives you a primitive language in which the word is used. Although this language is not what you talk when you are twenty, you get a 1 Here we find similarities-we find peculill1' sorts of confusion which come up with ali these W01'ds.-R. 2 LECTURES AND CONVERSATIONS rough approximation to what kind of Ia.ngua.ge game is going to be played.. a. How did we leam 'I dreamt so and so'? The interesting point is that we didn't learn it by being shown a dream. If you ask yourself how a· child learns 'beautiful', 'fine', etc., you find it learns them roughly as interjections. ('Beautiful' is an odd word to talk about because it's hardly ever used.) A child generally applies a word like 'good' first to food. One thing that is inunensely important in teaching is exaggerated gestures and facial expressions. The word is taught as a substitute for a facial expression or a gesture. The gestures, tones of voice, etc., in this case are expressions of approval. What makes the word an interjection of approval?l It is the game it appears in, not the form of words. (If I had to say what is the main mistake made by philosophers of the present generation, including Moore, I would say that it is that when language is looked at, what is looked at is a form of words and not the use made of the form of words.) Language is a characteristic part of a large group of activities-talking, writing, travelling on a bus, meeting a man, etc.2 We are concentrating, not on the words 'good' or 'beautiful', which are entirely uncharacteristic, generally just subject and predicate ('This is beautiful'), but on the occasions on which they are said-on the enormously complicated situation in which the aesthetic expression has a place, in which the expression itself has almost a negligible place. 6. If you came to a foreign tribe, whose language you didn't know at al and you wished to know what words corresponded to 'good', 'fine', etc., what would you look for? You would look for smiles, gestures, food, toys. ([Reply to objection:] If you went to Mars and men were spheres with sticks coming out, you wouldn't know what to look for. Or if you went to a tribe where noises made with the mouth were just breathing or making music, and language was made with the ears. Cf. "When you see trees swaying about they are talking to one another." ("Every- 1 And not of disappl:'oval 01:' of sutpl:'ise, fol:' example? (The child undetStands the gestUl'es which you use in teaching him. If he did not, he could undel'Stand nothing.)-R. I When we build houses, we talk and wl:'ite. When I take a bus, I say to the conductol:': 'Thl'ecpeny.' We ue concenttating not just on the word 01:' thesentence in which it is used-which is highly unc:huac:tistic-but on the ocion on which it is said: the framework in which (nota bene) the actual aesthetic judgment is pl'actically nothing at al.-R. LECTURES ON AESTHETICS 3 thing has a soul.") You compare the branches with arms. Certainly we must interpret the gestures of the tribe on the analogy of ours.) How far this takes us from normal aesthetics [and ethics-T]. We don't start from certain words, but from certain occasions or activities. 7.. A characteristic thing about our language is that a large number of words used under these circumstances are adjectives -'fine', 'lovely', etc. But you see that this is by no means necessary. You saw that they were first used as interjections. Would it matter if instead of saying "This is lovely", I just said "Ah!" and smiled, or just rubbed my stomach? As far as these primitive languages go, problems about what these words are about, what their real subject is, [which is called 'beautiful' or 'good'.-R.]l don't come up at al. 8. It is remarkable that in real life, when aesthetic judgements are made, aesthetic adjectives such as 'beautiful', 'fine', etc., play hardly any role at alt Are aesthetic adjectives used in a musical criticism? You say: "Look at this transition'',Z or [Rhees] "The passage here is incoherent". Or you say, in a poetical criticism, [Taylor]: "His use of images is precise". The words you use are more akin to 'right' and 'correct' (as these words are used in ordinary speech) than to 'beautiful' and'lovely'.3 9. Words such as 'lovely' are first used as interjections. Later they are used on very few occasions. We might say of a piece of music that it is lovely, by this not praising it but giving it a character. (A lot of people, of course, who can't express themselves properly use the word very frequently. As they use it, it is used as an interjection.) I might ask: "For what melody would I most like to use the word 'lovely'?" I might choose between calng a melody 'lovely' and calling it 'youthful'. It is stupid to cal a piece of music 'Spring Melody' or 'Spring Symphony'. But the word 'springy' wouldn't be absurd at all, any more than 'stately' or 'pompous'. 1 What the thing that is really good is-T. I 'The transition was made in the right way.'-T. a It would be better to use 'lovely' descriptively, on a level with 'stately', 'pompous,' etc.-T. 4 LECTURES AND CONVERSATIONS 10. If I were a good draughtsman, I could convey an innumerable number of expressions by four strokesSuch words as 'pompous' and 'stately> could be expressed by faces. Doing this, our descriptions would be much more flexible and various than they are as expressed by adjectives. If I say of a piece of Schubert's that it is melancholy, that is like giving it a face (I don't express approval or disapproval). I could instead use gestures or [Rhees] dancing. In fact, if we want to be exact, we do use a gesture or a facial expression. 11. [Rhees: What rule are we using or referring to when we say: "This is the correct way"? If a music teacher says a piece should be played this way and plays it, what is he appealing to?] 12. Take the question: "How should poetry be read? What is the correct way of reading it?" If you are talking about blank verse the right way of reading it might be stressing it correctlyyou discuss how far you should stress the rhythm and how far you should hide it. A man says it ought to be read this way and reads it out to you. You say: "Oh yes. Now it makes sense." There are cases of poetry which should almost be scannedwhere the metre is as clear as crystal-others where the metre is entirely in the background. I had an experience with the 18th century poet Klopstock.1 I found that the way to read him was to stress his metre abnormally. Klopstock put .. -� (etc.) in front of his poems. When I read his poems in this new way, I said: "A.h-ha, now I know why he did this." What had happened? I had read this kind of stuff and had been moderately bored, but when I read it in this particular way, intensely, I smiled, said: "This is grand," etc. But I might not have said anything. The important fact was that I read it again and again. When I read these poems I made gestures and facial expressions which were what would be called gestures of approval. But the important 1 Friedrich Gottlieb K!opstock (1724-1803). Wittgenstein is referring to the Odes. (Gesammelte Werke, Stuttgart, 1886-7). Klopstock believed that poetic diction was distinct from popular language. He rejected rhyme as vulgar and introduced instead the metres of ancient literature. Ed. LECTURES ON AESTHETICS 5 thing was that I read the poems entirely differently, more intensely, and said to others: "Look ! This is how they should be read."l Aesthetic adjectives played hardly any role. 13. What does a person who knows a good suit say when trying on a suit at the tailor's? "That's the right length", "That's too short", "That's too narrow". Words of approval play no role, although he will look pleased when the coat suits him. Instead of "That's too short" I might say "Look!" or instead of "Right" I might say "Leave it as it is". A good cutter may not use any words at all, but just make a chalk mark and later alter it. How do I show my approval of a suit? Chiefly by wearing it often, liking it when it is seen, etc. 14. (If I give you the light and shadow on a body in a picture I can thereby give you the shape of it. But if I give you the highlights in a picture you don't know what the shape is.) 15. In the case of the word 'correct' you have a variety of related cases. There is first the case in which you learn the rules. The cutter learns how long a coat is to be, how wide the sleeve must be, etc. He learns rules--he is drilled-as in music you are drilled in harmony and counterpoint. Suppose I went in for tailoring and I first learnt al the rules, I might have, on the whole, two sorts of attitude. (1) Lewy says: "This is too short." I say: "No. It is right. It is according to the rules." (2) I develop a feeling for the rules. I interpret the rules. I might say: "No. It isn't right. If isn't according to the rules."2 Here I would be making an aesthetic judgement about the thing which is according to the rules in sense (1). On the other hand, if I hadn't learnt the rules, I wouldn't be able to make the aesthetic judgement. In learning the rules you get a more and more refined judgement. Learning the rules actualy changes your judgement. (Although, if you haven't learnt Harmony and haven't a good ear, you may nevertheless detect any disharmony in a sequence of chords.) 16. You could regard the rules laid down for the measurement of a coat as an expression of what certain people want.3 People separated on the point of what a coat should measure: 1 If we speak of the right way to read a piece of poetry-approval enters, but it plays a fairly small r6le in the situation.-R. 2 'Don't you see that if we made it broader,it isn't right and it isn't according to the rules.'-R. 8 These may be extremely explicit and taught, or not formulated at al.-T. 6 LECTURES AND CONVERSATIONS there were some who didn't care if it was broad or narrow, etc.; there were others who cared an enormous lot.l The rules of harmony, you can say, expressed the way people wanted chords to follow-their wishes crystallized in these rules (the word 'wishes' is much too vague.)! All the greatest composers wrote in accordance with them. ([Reply to objection :] You can say that every composer changed the rules, but the variation was very slight; not al the rules were changed. The music was still good by a great many of the old rules.-This though shouldn't come in here.) 17. In what we call the Arts a person who has judgement developes. (A person who has a judgement doesn't mean a person who says 'Marvelous!' at certain thingS.)8 If we talk of aesthetic judgements, we think, among a thousand things, of the Arts. When we make an aesthetic judgement about a thing, we do not just gape at it and say : "Oh! How marvellous!" We distinguish between a person who knows what he is talking about and a person who doesn't.4 If a person is to admire English poetry, he must know English. Suppose that a Russian who doesn't know English is overwhelmed by a sonnet admitted to be good. We would say that he does not know what is in it at al. Similarly, of a person who doesn't know metres but who is overwhelmed, we would say that he doesn't know what's in it. In music this is more pronounced. Suppose there is a person who admires and enjoys what is admitted to be good but can't remember the simplest tunes, doesn't know when the bass comes in, etc. We say he hasn't seen what's in it. We use the phrase 'A man is musical' not so as to cal a man musical if he says "Ah!" when a piece of music is played, any more than we cal a. dog musical if it wags its tail when music is played.& 1 But-it is just a fact that people have1aid down such and such rules. We say 'people' but in fact it was a particular class• . • . When we say 'people', these were although we have talked of 'wishes' here, the fact is just that these rules were laid down.-R. I In what we cal the arts there developed what we cal a 'judge'-i.e. one who has judgment. This does not mean just someone who admires or does not admire. We have an entirely new element.-R. , He must react in a consistent way over a long period. Must know all sorts of things.-T. 6 cr. the who likes hearing music but canot talk about it at all, and is u get imitations-or when thousands of people are interested in the minutest details. A picture of what happens when a dining-room table is chosen more or less at random, when no one knows where it came from.2 23. We talked of correctness. A good cutter won't use any words except words like 'Too long', 'All right'. When we talk of t That is aesthetics.-T. I Explain what happens when a craft deteriomtes. A period in which everything ismed and extraordinary care is lavished on certain details; and a period in which is copied and nothing is thought about.-T. . great number of people are highly interested in a detail of a dining-room chair. And then there is a period when a dining-room chair is in the dmwing-room a d no one knows where this came from or that people had once given enormous thou ht in order to know how to design it.-R. 8 LECTURES AND CONVERSATIONS a Symphony of Beethoven we don't talk of correctness. Entirely diferent things enter. One wouldn't talk of appreciating the tremendous things in Art. In certain styles in Architecture a door is correct, and the thing is you appreciate it. But in the case of a Gothic Cathedral what we do is not at al to find it correct-it plays an entirely diferent role with us.1 The entire game is diferent. It is as diferent as to judge a human being and on the one hand to say 'He behaves well' and on the other hand 'He made a great impression on me'. 24. 'Correcdy', 'charmingly', 'finely', etc. play an entirely diferent role. Cf. the famous address of Bufon-a terrific man -on style in writing; making ever so many distinctions which I only understand vaguely but which he didn't mean vague1y-all kinds of nuances like 'grand', 'charming', 'nice'.2 25. The words we cal expressions of aesthetic judgement play a very complicated role, but a very definite role, in what we cal a culture of a period. To describe their use or to describe what you mean by a cultured taste, you have to describe a culture.S What we now cal a cultured taste perhaps didn't exist in the Middle Ages. An entirely diferent game is played in diferent ages. 26. What belongs to a language game is a whole culture. In describing musical taste you have to describe whether children give concerts, whether women do or whether men only give them, etc., etc.' In aristocratic circles in Vienna people had [such and such] a taste, then it came into bourgeois circles and women joined choirs, etc. This is an example of tradition in music. 27. [Rhees: Is there tradition in Negro art? Could a European appreciate Negro art?] 28. What would tradition in Negro Art be? That women wear cut-grass skirts ? etc., etc. I don't know. I don't know how Frank Dobson's appreciation of Negro Art compares with an 1 Here there is no of Mgre8.-R. 2 Ducolil'S .rut' /8 the addres on his reception into L'Ac:ademie Fran�se. 1753.-Ed. 8 To describe a set ot aesthetic rules fuly means realy to describe the culture of a period.-T. . , That children are taught by adults who go to concerts, etc., that the schools are like they are, etc.-R. LEcrURES ON AESTHETIGS 9 educated Negro's.l If you say he appreciates it, I don't yet know what this means.2 He may fil his room with objects of Negro Art. Does he just say: "Ah!"? Or does he do what the best.. Negro musicians do? Or does he agree or disagree with so and so about it? You may call this appreciation. Entirely diferent to an educated Negto's. Though an educated Negro may also have Negro objects of art in his room. The Negro's and Frank Dobson's are diferent appreciations altogether. You do some· thing diferent with them. Suppose Negroes dress in their own way and I say I appreciate a good Negro tunic-does this mean I would have one made, or that I would say (as at the tailor's): "No... this is too long",or does it mean I say: "Howcharmingl"? 29. Suppose Lewy has what is called a cultured taste in painting. This is something entirely diferent to what was called a cultured taste in the fifteenth century. An entirely diferent game was played. He does something entirely diferent with it to what a man did then. 30. There are. lots of people, well-offish, who have been to good schools, who can afford to travel about and see the Louvre, etc., and who know a lot about and can talk fluendy about dozens of painters. There is another person who has seen very few paintings, but who looks intensely at one or twl:) paintings which make a profound impression on him.3 Another person who is broad, neither deep nor wide. Another person who is very narrow, concentrated and circumscribed. Are these diferent kinds of appreciation? They may al be called 'appreciation'. 31. You talk in entirely diferent terms of the Coronation robe of Edward II and of a dress suit.' What did they do and say about· Coronation robes? Was the Coronation robe made by a tailor? Perhaps it was designed by Italian artists who had their own traditions; never seen by Edward II until he put it on. Questions like 'What standards were there?', etc. are al relevant 1 FrankDobson (1888-1963) painterand sculptor;W8S thefirst to bring toEngland the interest in African and Asian sculpture which characteri%ed the work of Picasso and the other Cubists during the years immediately prece and following the First World War.-Ed. I Here you haven't made what you mean by 'appreciate Negro.Ad clear.-T. 8 Someone who has not traveled but who makes certain observations which show that he 'realy does appreciate' • • . an appreciation which concentrates on one thing and is very that you would give your last penny for it.-R. 'Edward the B 10 LECTURES AND CONVERSATION'S to the question