Malevich Suprematism "Suprematism" is the second of the two essays which together comprise The Non-Objective World, Malevich's major treatise published in Germany in 1927. By 1912, Kasimir Malevich (1878-1935) had absorbed the impulses emanating from western Europe and was already an artist of distinction. In December 1915, at the "0.10" exhibition in Moscow, he launched Suprematism, his new visual language of flat geometric forms. After the October Revolution he was a leading force among Russian artists devoted to complete abstraction: Tatlin, Lissitzky, Rodchenko, Popova, Gabo, and others. !}. charismatic teacher in Moscow and Vitebsk, where Lissitzky became a disciple, he had a major role until the mid-1920s, when abstract art came under increasing conservative pressures. Other artists emigrated (Kandinsky, Gabo, Chagall, Exter) but Malevich remained in Russia, without making a pact with the antirevolutionary esthetic of the post-Lenin Party. He seems to have continued his art in isolation until his death in 1935, with the notable exception of the trip to Germany in 1927. Malevich came to Berlin in 1927 for an exhibition of his paintings at the Grosse Berliner Kunstausstellung. He brought with him the manuscript of his The Non-Objective World, which was translated into German by A. von Riesen and published by Albert Langen, Munich, as volume eleven of the Bauhaus books. Die Gegenstandslose Welt was presumably written over n span of years. It speaks with Malevich's own voice, and yet suits the orienta· tion of the de Stijl, Purist, and other movements of the 1920s which shared a faith in the world of modern technology in opposition to Dada and Surrealism. I have included the second part of the treatise (the first is called "Introduction to the Theory of the Additional Element in Painting") because it is the clearest exposition of his ideas. The first part is actually an applica· tion of the principles enunciated in the second, and though ideally both should be read together, it was essential, for this anthology, to find the text that most completely exposed Malevich's esthetic principles. The entire text was translated by Howard Dearstyne from the German (the Russian manuscript has not been uncovered) and, accompanied by many illustrations and an introduction by L. Hilbersheimer, was published by Paul Theobald and Company, Chicago, in 1959. I am grateful to Paul Theobald and Company for authorizing me to reproduce "Suprematism." 116 Suprematism Under Suprematism I understand the supremacy of pure feeling in creative art. quite apart from the environment in which it is called forth. The so-called "materialization" of a feeling in the conscious mind really means a materialization of the refl,ection of that feeling through the medium of some realistic conception.Such a realistic conception is without value in suprematist art....And not only in suprematist art but in art generally, because the enduring, true value of a work of art (to whatever school it may belong) resides solely in the feeling expressed. Academic naturalism, the naturalism of the Impressionists, Cezanneism, Cubism, etc.-all these, in a way, are nothing more than dialectic methods which, as such, in no sense deter-mine the true value of an art work. An objective representation, having is someHence, to the Suprematist, the appropriate means of representation is always the one which gives fullest possible expression to feeling as such and which ignores the familiar appearance of objects. Objectivity, in itself, is meaningless to him; the concepts of the conscious mind are worthless. Feeling is the determining factor . . . It reaches a "desert" in which nothing can be perceived but feeling. Everything which determined the objective-ideal structure of life and of "art"-ideas, concepts, and images-all this the artist has cast aside in order to heed pure feeling. The art of the past which stood, at least ostensibly, in the service of religion and the state, will take on new life in the pure (unapplied) art of Suprematism, which will build up a new world-the world of feeling.... When, in the year 1913, in my desperate attempt to free art from the ballast of objectivity, I took refuge in the square form and exhibited a picture which consisted of nothing more than a black square on 117 To the Suprematist the visual phenomena of the objective world are, in themselves, meaningless;; the significant thing is feeliag, as such, objectivity as its aim:, 1 hing which, as such, has nothing to do with art, and yet the use of objective forms in an art work does not preclude the possibility of its Iicing•ot�high artistic value. and thus art arrives at nonobjective representation-at Suprematism. 118 Modern Artists on Art a white field, the critics and, along with them, the public sighed, "Everything which we loved is lost. We are in a desert. . . . Before us is nothing but a black square on a white background!" "Withering" words were sought to drive off the symbol of the "desert" so that one might behold on the "dead square" the beloved likeness of "reality" ("true objectivity" and a spiritual feeling). The square seemed incomprehensible and dangerous to the critics and the public . . . and this, of course, was to be expected. The ascent to the heights of nonobjective art is arduous and painful . . . but it is nevertheless rewarding. The familiar recedes ever further and further. into the background. . . . The contours of the objective world fade more and more and so it goes, step by step, until finally the world-"everything we loved and by which we have lived" becomes lost to sight. No more "likeness of reality," no idealistic images-nothing but a desert! But this desert is filled with the spirit of nonobjective sensation which pervades everything. Even I was gripped by a kind of timidity bordering on fear when it came to leaving "the world of will and idea," in which I had lived and worked and in the reality of which I had believed. But a blissful sense of liberating nonobjectivity drew me forth into the "desert," where nothing is real except feeling . . . and so feeling became the substance of my life. This was no "empty square" which I had exhibited but rather the feeling of nonobjectivity. I realized that the "thing" and the "concept" were substituted for feeling and understood the falsity of the world of will and idea. Is a milk bottle, then, the symbol of milk? Suprematism is the rediscovery of pure art which, in the course of time, had become obscured by the accumulation of "things." It appears to me that, for the critics and the public, the painting of Raphael, Rubens, Rembrandt, etc., has become nothing more than a conglomeration of countless "things," which conceal its true valuethe feeling which gave rise to it.The virtuosity of the objective representation is the only thing admired. If it were possible to extract from the works of the great masters the feeling expressed in them-the actual artistic value, that is-and to hide this away, the public, along with the critics and the art scholars, would never even miss it. So it is not at all strange that my square seemed empty to the public. If one insists on judging an art work on the basis of the virtuosity of the objective representation-the verisimilitude of the illusionand thinks he sees in the objective representation itself a symbol of the inducing emotion, he will never partake of the gladdening content of a work of art. Malevich 119 The general public is still convinced today that art is bound to perish if it gives up the imitation of "dearly-loved reality" and so it observes with dismay how the hated element of pure feeling-abstraction-makes more and more headway.... Art no longer cares to serve the state and religion, it no longer wishes to illustrate the history of manners, it wants to have nothing further to do with the object, as such, and believes that it can exist, in and for itself, without "things" (that is, the "time-tested wellspring of life"). But the nature and meaning of artistic creation continue to be misunderstood, as does the nature of creative work in general, because feeling, after all, is always and everywhere the one and only source of every creation. The emotions which are kindled in the human being are stronger than the human being himself ...they must at all costs find an outlet-they must take on overt form-they must be communicated or put to work. It was nothing other than a yearning for speed ...for flight ... which, seeking an outward shape, brought about the birth of the airplane.For the airplane was not contrived in order to carry business letters from Berlin to Moscow, but in obedience to the irresistible drive of this yearning for speed to take on external form. The "hungry stomach" and the intellect which serves this must �lways have the last word, of course, when it comes to determining the origin and purpose of existing values ...but that is a subject in itself. And the state of affairs is exactly the same in art as in creative technology....In painting (I mean here, naturally, the accepted "artistic" painting) one can discover behind a technically correct portrait of Mr. Miller or an ingenious representation of the flower girl at Potsdamer Platz not a trace of the true essence of art-no evidence whatever of feeling.Painting is the dictatorship of a method of representation, the purpose of which is to depict Mr. Miller, his environment and his ideas. The black square on the white field was the first form in which nonobjective feeling came to be expressed.The square =feeling, the white field =the void beyond this feeling. Yet the general public saw in the nonobjectivity of the representation the demise of art and failed to grasp the evident fact that feeling had here assumed external form. The suprematist square and the forms proceeding out of it can be likened to the primitive marks (symbols) of aboriginal man which represented, in their combinations, not ornament but a feeling of rhythm. Suprematism did not bring into being a new world of feeling but rather, an altogether new and direct form of representation of the world of feeling. 120 Modern Artists on Art The square changes and creates new forms, the elements of which can be classified in one way or another depending upon the feeling which gave rise to them. hen we examine an antique column, we are no longer interested in the fitness of its construction to perform its technical task in the building but recognize in it the material expression of a pure feeling. We no longer see in it a structural necessity but view it as a work of art in its own right. "Practical life," like a homeless vagabond, forces its way into every artistic form and believes itself to be the genesis and reason for existence of this form. But the vagabond doesn't tarry long in one place and once he is gone (when to make an art work serve "practical purposes" no longer seems practical) the work recovers its full value. Antique works of art are kept in museums and carefully guarded, not to preserve them for practical use but in order that their eternal artistry may be enjoyed. difference between the new, nonobjective ("useless") art and the art of the past lies in the fact that the full artistic value of the latter comes to light (becomes recognized) only after life, in search of some new expedient, has forsaken it, whereas the unapplied artistic element of the new art outstrips life and shuts the door on "practical utility." An antique temple is not beautiful because it once served as the haven of a certain social order or of the religion associated with this, but rather because its form sprang from a pure feeling for plastic relationships. The artistic feeling which was given material expression in the building of the temple is for us eternally valid and vital but as for the social order which once encompassed it-this is dead. Life and its manifestations have hitherto been considered from two different standpoints-the material and the religious. It would seem that a consideration of life from the standpoint of art ought to become a third and equally valid point of view. But in practice, art (as a second-rate power) is relegated to the service of those who view the world and life from one or the other of the first two standpoints.This state of affairs is curiously inconsistent with the fact that art always and under all circumstances plays the decisive role in the creative life and that art values alone are absolute and endure forever. With the most primitive of means (charcoal, hog bristles, modeling sticks, catgut, and steel strings) the artist creates something which the most ingenious and efficient technology will never be able to create. The adherents of "utility" think they have the right to regard art as the apotheosis of life (the utilitarian life, that is). And so there the new nonobjective art stands-the expression o� pure feeling, seeking no practical values, no ideas, no "promised land." w The Malevich 121 In the midst of this apotheosis stands "Mr. Miller"-or rather, the portrait of Mr.Miller (that is, a copy of a "copy" of life). The mask of life hides the true countenance of art. Art is not to us what it could be. And moreover, the efficiently mechanized world could truly serve a purpose if only it would see to it that we (every one of us) gained the �reatest possible amount of "free time" to enable us to meet the only obligation to nature which mankind has taken upon itself-namely to neate art. Those who promote the construction of useful things, things which serve a purpose, and who combat art or seek to enslave it, should bear in mind the fact that there is no such thing as a constructed object which is useful.Has the experience of centuries not demonstrated that Every object which we see in the museums clearly supports the fact that not one single, solitary thing is really useful, that is, convenient, And if it once seemed usefuI this is only because nothing more useful was then known. . . . Do we have the slightest reason to assume that the things which appear useful and convenient to us today will not be obsolete tomorrow . . . ? And shouldn't it give us pause The Suprematists have deliberately given up objective representa- 1·ion of their surroundings in order to reach the summit of the true "unmasked" art and from this vantage point to view life through the prism of pure artistic feeling. Nothing in the objective world is as "secure and unshakeable" as it appears to our conscious minds. We should accept nothing as predetermined-as constituted for eternity. Every "firmly established," familiar thing can be shifted about and brought under a new and, primarily, unfamiliar order. Why then should it not be possible to bring about an artistic order? The various complementary and conflicting feelings-or rather, images and ideas-which, as reflections of these feelings, take shape in our imaginations, struggle incessantly with each other: the awareness of God against that of the Devil; the sensation of hunger versus a feeling for the beautiful. The awareness of God strives to vanquish the awareness of the I )evil-and the flesh at the same time. It tries to "make credible" the l'vanescence of earthly goods and the everlasting glory of God. And art, too, is condemned, except when it serves the worship of ( ;od-the Church. . . . -Out of the awareness of God arose religion-and out of religion the Church. "useful" things don't long remain useful? lor otherwise it would not be in a museum! that the oldest works of art arc as impressive today in their beauty and spontaneity as they were 111any thousands of years ago? 122 Modern Artists on Art -Out of the sensation of hunger developed concepts of utilityand out of these concepts trade and industry. Both the Church and industry tried to monopolize those artistic abilities which, being creative, are constantly finding expression, in order to provide effective bait for their products (for the idealmaterial as well as for the purely material). In this way, as the saying goes, "the pill of utility is sugar-coated." The aggregated reflections of feelings in the individual's consciousness-feelings of the most varied kinds-determine his "view of life." Since the feelings affecting him change, the most remarkable alterations in this "view of life" can be observed; the atheist becomes pious, the God-fearing, godless, etc. . . . The human being can be likened, in a way, to a radio receiver which picks up and converts a whole series of different waves of feeling, the sum-total of which determines the above-mentioned view of life. Judgments concerning the values of life therefore fluctuate widely. Only art values defy the shifting drift of opinion, so that, for example, pictures of God or the saints, insofar as the artistic feeling incorporated in them is apparent, can be placed by atheists in their collections without compunction (and, in fact, actually are collected by them). Thus do we have, again and again, the opportunity of convincing ourselves that the guidance of our conscious minds-"creation" with a purpose-always calls into being relative values (which is to say, valueless "values") and that nothing but the expression of the pure feeling of the subconscious or superconscious (nothing, that is, other than artistic creation) can give tangible form to absolute values.Actual utility (in the higher sense of the term) could therefore be achieved only if the subconscious or superconscious were accorded the privilege of directing creation. Our life is a theater piece, in which nonobjective feeling is portrayed by objective imagery. A bishop is nothing but an actor who seeks with words and gestures, on an appropriately "dressed" stage, to convey a religious feeling, or rather the reflection of a feeling in religious form. The office clerk, the blacksmith, the soldier, the accountant, the general ...these are all characters out of one stage play or another, portrayed by various people, who become so carried away that they confuse the play and their parts in it with life itself. We almost never get to see the actual human face and if we ask someone who he is, he answers, "an engineer," "a farmer," etc., or, in other words, he gives the title of the role played by him in one or another affective drama. The title of the role is also set down next to his full name, and cer· tified in his passport, thus removing any doubt concerning the sur· prising fact that the owner of the passport is the engineer Ivan and not the painter Kasimir. In the last analysis, what each individual knows about himself is Malevich 123 precious little, because the "actual human face" cannot be discerned hehind the mask, which is mistaken for the "actual face." The philosophy of Suprematism has every reason to view both the mask and the "actual face" with skepticism, since it disputes the reality of human faces (human forms) altogether. Artists have always been partial to the use of the human face in their representations, for they have seen in it (the versatile, mobile, expressive mimic) the best vehicle with which to convey their feelings. The Suprematists have nevertheless abandoned the representation of the human face (and of natural objects in general) and have found new symbols with which to render direct feelings (rather than externalized reflections of feelings), for the Suprematist does not observe and does not touch-he feels. We have seen how art, at the turn of the century, divested itself of the ballast of religious and political ideas which had been imposed upon it and came into its own-attained, that is, the form suited to its intrinsic nature and became, along with the two already mentioned, a third independent and equ�lly valid "point of view." The public is still, indeed, as much convinced as ever that the artist creates superfluous, impractical things. It never considers that these superfluous things endure and retain their vitality for thousands of years, whereas necessary, practical things survive only briefly. It does not dawn on the public that it fails to recognize the real, true value of things.This is also the reason for the chronic failure of everything utilitarian. A true, absolute order in human society could only he achieved if mankind were willing to base this order on lasting values. Obviously, then, the artistic factor would have to be accepted in every respect as the decisive one. As long as this is not the case, the uncertainty of a "provisional order" will obtain, instead of the longed-for tranquillity of an absolute order, because the provisional order is gauged by current utilitarian understanding and this measuring-stick is variable in the highest degree. In the light of this, all art works which, at present, are a part of "practical life" or to which practical life has laid claim, are in some sense devaluated. Only when they are freed from the encumbrance of practical utility (that is, when they are placed in museums) will their truly artistic, absolute value be recognized. The sensations of sitting, standing, or running are, first and foremost, plastic sensations and they are responsible for the development of corresponding "objects of use" and largely determine their form. A chair, bed, and table are not matters of utility but rather, the forms taken by plastic sensations, so the generally held view that all objects of daily use result from practical considerations is based upon false premises. 124 Modern Artists on Art We have ample opportunity to become convinced that we are nevor in a position for recognizing any real utility in things and that we sl1111l never succeed in constructing a really practical object. We can evl· dently only feel the essence of absolute utility but, since a feeling 11 always nonobjective, any attempt to grasp the utility of the objectlvt is Utopian.The endeavor to confine feeling within concepts of th• conscious mind or, indeed, to replace it with conscious concepts 1111d to give it concrete, utilitarian form, has resulted in the development ur all those useless, "practical things" which become ridiculous in 1111 time at all. It cannot be stressed too often that The new art of Suprematism, which has produced new forms 1rnJ form relationships by giving external expression to pictorial feellr1M1 will become a new architecture: it will transfer these forms from tl1t surface of canvas to space. The suprematist element, whether in painting or in architecture, 11 Every social idea, however great and important it may be, st111111 from the sensation of hunger; every art work, regardless of how 111n•ll and insignificant it may seem, originates in pictorial or plastic fec:lln•, It is high time for us to realize that the problems of art lie far L\l,itrl from those of the stomach or the intellect. Now that art, thanks to Suprematism, has come into its own-rh1U is, attained its pure, unapplied form-and has recognized the inf111ll· bility of nonobjective feeling, it is attempting to set up a gemrlnt world order, a new philosophy of life.It recognizes the nonobjectlvltr of the world and is no longer concerned with providing illustrntfo111 of the history of manners. Nonobjective feeling has, in fact, always been the only ponlMt source of art, so that in this respect Suprematism is contributing nuth· ing new but nevertheless the art of the past, because of its use of objw• tive subject matter, harbored unintentionally a whole series of feell11.. which were alien to it. But a tree remains a tree even when an owl builds a nest in 11 lml low of it. Suprematism has opened up new possibilities to creative art, 11lrt�f by virtue of the abandonment of so-called "practical considerat/111111" a plastic feeling rendered on canvas can -be carried over intu 1/11ll'f, The artist (the painter) is no longer bound to the canvas (the 11lctl1Pf plane) and can transfer his.compositions from canvas to space, free of every tendency which is social or otherwise materialistit;. absolute, true values arisl� 111Jl1 from artistic, subconscious, or superconscious creation.