Cognitive perspectives on counting Marcin Wągiel 1 / 25 Introduction Counting common ⇒ everyday experience cognitive ∼ linguistic perspectives three different though related concepts count list ⇒ recitation arithmetic ⇒ abstract operations quantification ⇒ cardinality of a set (1) a. one, two, three, four, five, six,… b. Three times two equals six. c. three cats 2 / 25 Number sense Two cognitive systems Hyde (2011) OTS ⇒ object tracking system ANS ⇒ approximate number system Figure 1: Object tracking Figure 2: Approximate number 3 / 25 Number sense Object tracking system Carey (1998, 2009), Piazza (2010) mental ability to immediately enumarate small sets no counting via individuation manifests in infants Figure 3: How many marks? 4 / 25 Number sense Object tracking system Carey (1998, 2009), Piazza (2010) mental ability to immediately enumarate small sets no counting via individuation manifests in infants Figure 4: How many marks? 5 / 25 Number sense Approximate number system Feigenson et al. (2004), Nieder & Dehaene (2009), Cantlon et al. (2006) estimation of the magnitude of a collection no reliance on symbolic representation manifests in infants ⇒ develops with age Figure 5: Compare 6 / 25 Number sense Number sense in non-human animals Davis & Pérusse (1998), Gallistel (1989), Dehaene (1997) primates ⇒ operations on quantities apprehension comparison approximate addition other mammals: dolphins, cats, rats also: birds, fish botanics ⇒ plant arithmetic however, no evidence for symbolic addition except for the chimpanzee after long training https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=t-SQisIYPh4 7 / 25 Psychology of counting Implicit knowledge of counting in children Gelman & Gallistel (1978) intuitive understanding of the cardinality of a set and its conservation under changes not affecting quantity each entity must be count once and once only 1 number cannot be associated with more than 1 entity no explicit formulation ⇒ children are never taught that Figure 6: Enumerating sets 8 / 25 Psychology of counting Innate principles of counting Gelman & Gallistel (1978) stable order ⇒ ordered list of symbols 1-1 correspondence ⇒ symbols related to objects cardinality ⇒ determined by the last symbol Figure 7: Counting and order 9 / 25 Psychology of counting Acquisition of counting Wynn (1990) children 6–18 months stable order and 1-1 correspondence observed fail when asked to give ‘two’ or ‘three’ objects 2,5 years understanding that counting is an abstract procedure applicable to different kinds of objects 3,5 years order of recitation ⇒ crucial order of pointing at objects ⇒ irrelevant children indicate and correct subtle errors 4 years counting can be generalized to novel situations 10 / 25 Psychology of counting Quinean bootstrapping ⇒ crucial linguistic component Carey (2009) learning the ordered list ⇒ relative order learning the meaning of symbols learning how the list represents number (2) a. eeny, meeny, miny, mo,… b. one, two, three, four, five, six,… (3) three = 3 Figure 8: Cardinality 11 / 25 Spatial integrity in counting Object/substance distinction Soja et al. (1991), Hauser & Carey (2003), Hauser & Spaulding (2006) innate ontological commitments manifested in infants assumptions ⇒ nature of objects boundedness ⇒ natural boundaries cohesion ⇒ parts stick together movement across space along continuous paths substances ⇒ not expected to have those properties also in non-human animals https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=hwgo2O5Vk_g&t=2s 12 / 25 Spatial integrity in counting Broken object experiments Shipley & Shepperson (1990), Dehaene (1997), Melgoza et al. (2008) children between 3 and 4 years count only discrete integrated objects Figure 9: Relevance of integrity in counting 13 / 25 Spatial integrity in counting Broken object experiments Shipley & Shepperson (1990), Dehaene (1997), Melgoza et al. (2008) other forms of linguistic quantification comparative constructions and pluralization Figure 10: Integrity in quantity comparison and pluralization 14 / 25 Part-whole structures Ontological intuition Varzi (2016), Priest (2014) Pre-Socratics ⇒ roots of mereology entities ⇒ made up of smaller entities (parts) Plato ⇒ Parmenides and Theaetetus unity ∼ arbitrary sum of parts structure ⇒ arrangement of parts Figure 11: Material parthood Figure 12: Individual parthood 15 / 25 Part-whole structures Part-whole perception Elkind et al. (1964), Kimchi (1993), Boisvert et al. (1999) simultaneous perception ⇒ wholes ∼ collections of parts manifests in young children Figure 13: Part-whole perception 16 / 25 Mass/count distinction Countability ⇒ mass nouns ∼ count nouns Jespersen (1913) among many others uncountable ∼ countable nouns grammatical category pluralization, compatibility with numerals intuition ⇒ object/substance distinction (4) a. cat b. cats c. two cats (5) a. mud b. *muds c. *two mud/muds 17 / 25 Mass/count distinction Object mass nouns Barner & Snedeker (2005), Chierchia (2010), Landman (2011) grammatical category ⇒ mass nouns denote discrete objects clash ⇒ grammar ∼ perception (6) a. furniture b. silverware c. footwear (7) a. nábytek b. bižuterie c. obuv Czech 18 / 25 Mass/count distinction Object mass nouns Barner & Snedeker (2005), Chierchia (2010), Landman (2011) quantity comparison task object mass nouns pattern with count nouns attested in several typologically distinct languages Figure 14: Object mass – count – mass 19 / 25 Counting and measuring Counting and measuring are independent operations Rothstein (2017), Wągiel (2018) distinct syntax and semantics counting indicates integrity ⇒ measuring does not ml1 ml2 ml3 Figure 15: Inegrity in measuring and counting (8) a. There are three mililiters of liquid on the table. b. #There are three objects on the table. 20 / 25 Counting and measuring Measuring is not sensitive to integrity Wągiel (2018) numeral phrases ⇒ counting/measuring ambiguity counting ⇒ measuring shift (possible but restricted) (9) context: John is cooking with his child. They put three whole apples on a table. John says: a. There are three apples on the table… b. Let’s count them together: one, two, three. (10) context: John is cooking with his child. They sliced three apples and put the slices into a bowl. John says: a. There are three apples in the bowl… b. #Let’s count them together: one, two, three. 21 / 25 References Acquaviva, P. (2008). Lexical Plurals: A Morphosemantic Approach. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Aikhenvald, A. Y. (2000). Classifiers: A Typology of Noun Categorization Devices. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Bale, A. and Coon, J. (2014). Classifiers are for numerals, not for nouns: Consequences for the mass/count distinction. Linguistic Inquiry, 45(4):695–707. Barner, D. and Snedeker, J. (2005). Quantity judgments and individuation: Evidence that mass nouns count. Cognition, 97(1):41–66. Boisvert, M., Standing, L., and Moller, L. (1999). Successful part-whole perception in young children using multiple-choice tests. The Journal of Genetic Psychology, 160(2):167–180. Cantlon, J. F., Brannon, E. M., Carter, E. J., and Pelphrey, K. A. (2006). Functional imaging of numerical processing in adults and 4-y-old children. PLoS BIOLOGY, 4(5):e125. Carey, S. (1998). Knowledge of number: Its evolution and ontogeny. Science, 282(5389):641–642. Carey, S. (2009). The Origin of Concepts. Oxford University Press, New York, NY. Casati, R. and Varzi, A. C. (1999). Parts and Places: The Structures of Spatial Representation. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA. Chierchia, G. (2010). Mass nouns, vagueness and semantic variation. Synthese, 174(1):99–149. Davis, H. and Pérusse, R. (1988). Numerical competence in animals: Definitional issues, current evidence, and a new research agenda. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11(4):561–579. Dehaene, S. (1997). The Number Sense: How the Mind Creates Mathematics. Oxford University Press, New York, NY. Elkind, D., Koegler, R. R., and Go, E. (1964). Studies in perceptual development: Ii. part-whole perception. Child Development, pages 81–90. Feigenson, L., Dehaene, S., and Spelke, E. (2004). Core systems of number. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 8(7):307–314. Gallistel, C. R. (1989). Animal cognition: The representation of space, time and number. Annual Review of Psychology, 40(1):155–189. 22 / 25 References Gelman, R. and Gallistel, C. R. (1978). The Child’s Understanding of Number. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Greenberg, J. H. (1978). Generalizations about numeral systems. In Greenberg, J. H., editor, Universals of Human Language, volume 3, pages 249–295. Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA. Grimm, S. (2012). Number and Individuation. PhD thesis, Stanford University, California. Hausdorff, F. (1914). Grundzüge der Mengenlehre. Veit & Comp., Leipzig. Hauser, M. and Spaulding, B. (2006). Wild rhesus monkeys generate causal inferences about possible and impossible physical transformations in the absence of experience. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 103(18):7181–7185. Hauser, M. D. and Carey, S. (2003). Spontaneous representations of small numbers of objects by rhesus macaques: Examinations of content and format. Cognitive Psychology, 47(4):367–401. Henderson, R. (2017). Swarms: Spatiotemporal grouping across domains. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory, 35(1):161–203. Hurford, J. R. (1998). The interaction between numerals and nouns. In Plank, F., editor, Noun Phrase Structure in the Languages of Europe, pages 561–620. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin. Hurford, J. R. (2001). Languages treat 1-4 specially. Mind & Language, 16(1):69–75. Hyde, D. C. (2011). Two systems of non-symbolic numerical cognition. Frontiers in Human Neuroscience, 5:1–8. Ionin, T. and Matushansky, O. (2006). The composition of complex cardinals. Journal of Semantics, 23(4):315–360. Kimchi, R. (1993). Basic-level categorization and part-whole perception in children. Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society, 31(1):23–26. Krecz, C. A. (1986). Parts and pieces. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 46(3):381–400. Kuratowski, K. (1922). Sur l’opération ā de l’analysis situs. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 3(1):182–199. 23 / 25 References Landman, F. (2011). Count nouns – mass nouns, neat nouns – mess nouns. Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, 6(1):12. Landman, F. (2016). Iceberg semantics for count nouns and mass nouns: Classifiers, measures and portions. Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication, 11(1):6. Leonard, H. S. and Goodman, N. (1940). The calculus of individuals and its uses. The Journal of Symbolic Logic, 5(2):45–55. Leśniewski, S. (1916). Podstawy ogólnej teoryi mnogości. Prace Polskiego Koła Naukowego w Moskwie, Sekcja Matematyczno-Przyrodnicza, Moscow. Lima, S. (2014). All notional mass nouns are count nouns in Yudja. In Snider, T., D’Antonio, S., and Weigand, M., editors, Proceedings of Semantics and Linguistic Theory 24, pages 534–554. CLC Publications, Ithaca, NY. Link, G. (1983). The logical analysis of plural and mass nouns: A lattice–theoretical approach. In Bäuerle, R., Schwarze, C., and von Stechow, A., editors, Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of Language, pages 302–323. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin. Markosian, N. (1998). Brutal composition. Philosophical Studies, 92(3):211–249. Melgoza, V., Pogue, A., and Barner, D. (2008). A broken fork in the hand is worth two in the grammar: A spatio-temporal bias in children’s interpretation of quantifiers and plural nouns. In Love, B. C., McRae, K., and Sloutsky, V. M., editors, Proceedings of the 30th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society, pages 1580–1585. Cognitive Science Society, Austin. Nieder, A. and Dehaene, S. (2009). Representation of number in the brain. Annual Review of Neuroscience, 32:185–208. Piazza, M. (2010). Neurocognitive start-up tools for symbolic number representations. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 14:542–551. Priest, G. (2014). One: Being an Investigation into the Unity of Reality and of its Parts, including the Singular Object which is Nothingness. Oxford University Press, Oxford. Rothstein, S. (2017). Semantics for Counting and Measuring. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. 24 / 25 References Shipley, E. F. and Shepperson, B. (1990). Countable entities: Developmental changes. Cognition, 34(2):109–136. Smith, B. (1996). Mereotopology: A theory of parts and boundaries. Data & Knowledge Engineering, 20(3):287–303. Soja, N. N., Carey, S., and Spelke, E. S. (1991). Ontological categories guide young children’s inductions of word meaning: Object terms and substance terms. Cognition, 38(2):179–211. Varzi, A. C. (2007). Spatial reasoning and ontology: Parts, wholes, and locations. In Aiello, M., Pratt-Hartmann, I. E., and van Benthem, J., editors, Handbook of Spatial Logics, pages 945–1038. Springer, Berlin. Varzi, A. C. (2016). Mereology. In Zalta, E. N., editor, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Wągiel, M. (2018). Subatomic Quantification. PhD thesis, Masaryk University in Brno. Whitehead, A. N. (1920). The Concept of Nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. Wynn, K. (1990). Children’s understanding of counting. Cognition, 36(2):155–193. 25 / 25