Ethnicity without groups Author(s): ROGERS BRUBAKER Source: European Journal of Sociology / Archives Européennes de Sociologie / Europäisches Archiv für Soziologie , 2002, Vol. 43, No. 2, Études critiques (2002), pp. 163-189 Published by: Cambridge University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.com/stable/23999234 JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to European Journal of Sociology / Archives Européennes de Sociologie / Europäisches Archiv für Soziologie This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER Ethnicity without grou I. Common sensegroupism Few social science concepts would seem as basic, even indis pensable, as that of group. In disciplinary terms, 'group' would appear to be a core concept for sociology, political science, anthropology, demography and social psychology. In substantive terms, it would seem to be fundamental to the study of political mobilization, cultural iden tity, economic interests, social class, status groups, collective action, kinship, gender, religion, ethnicity, race, multiculturalism, and minori ties of every kind. Yet despite this seeming centrality, the concept 'group' has remained curiously unscrutinized in recent years. There is, to be sure, a substantial social psychological literature addressing the concept (Hamilton et al. 1998, McGrath 1984), but this has had little resonance outside that sub-discipline. Elsewhere in the social sciences, the recent literature addressing the concept 'group' is sparse, especially by comparison with the immense literature on such concepts as class, identity, gender, eth nicity, or multiculturalism—topics in which the concept 'group' is implicated, yet seldom analyzed its own terms (1). 'Group' functions as a seemingly unproblematic, taken-for-granted concept, apparently in no need of particular scrutiny or explication. As a result, we tend to take for granted not only the concept 'group', but also 'groups'—the putative things-in-the-world to which the concept refers. Earlier versions of this paper were presented to the conference 'Facing Ethnic Conflicts', Center for Development Research, University of Bonn, December 14, 2000; the Working Group on Ethnicity and Nationalism, UCLA, January 13, 2001; the Anthropology Collo quium, University of Chicago, February 26, 2001; and the Central European University, Budapest, March 20, 2001. Thanks to partici pants in these events for their comments and criticisms, and to Margit Feischmidt, Jon Fox, Liana Grancea, David Laitin, Mara Loveman, Emanuel Schegloff, Peter Stamatov, Peter Waldmann, and Andreas Wimmer for helpful written comments. (i) Foundational discussions include Coo ley 1962 [1909], chapter 3 and Homans 1950 in sociology; Nadel 1957, chapter 7 in anthropo logy; Bentley 1908, chapter 7 and Truman 1951 in political science. More recent discus sions include Olson 1965, Tilly 1978 and Hechter 1987. 163 Rogers Brubaker, University of California (Los Angeles). Arch.europ.sociol.,XLI 11,2(2002), 163-189—0003-9756/00/0000-741 $07.soper art + $0. ioper page ©2002 A .E.S. This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER My aim in this paper is not to enter into conceptual or casuistry about the concept of group. It is rather to address atic consequence of this tendency to take groups for granted of ethnicity, race and nationhood, and in the study of ethnic national conflict in particular. This is what I will call gr tendency to take discrete, sharply differentiated, inter geneous and externally bounded groups as basic constitu life, chief protagonists of social conflicts, and fundame social analysis (2). In the domain of ethnicity, nationalis mean by 'groupism' the tendency to treat ethnic groups races as substantial entities to which interests and agency uted. I mean the tendency to reify such groups, speakin Croats, Muslims and Albanians in the former Yugoslavia and Protestants in Northern Ireland, of Jews and Palesti and the occupied territories, of Turks and Kurds in T Blacks, Whites, Asians, Hispanics and Native Americans in they were internally homogeneous, externally bounded unitary collective actors with common purposes. I mean th represent the social and cultural world as a multichrom monochrome ethnic, racial or cultural blocs. From the perspective of broader developments in social persisting strength of groupism in this sense is surprisin several distinct traditions of social analysis have challen ment of groups as real, substantial things-in-the-world. such sharply differing enterprises as ethnomethodology tion analysis, social network theory, cognitive theory, fem and individualist approaches such as rational choice and More generally, broadly structuralist approaches have variety of more 'constructivist' theoretical stances, which level of rhetoric, at least—to see groups as constructed, co fluctuating. And a diffuse postmodernist sensibility em fragmentary, the ephemeral, and the erosion of fixed fo boundaries. These developments are disparate, even cont analytical style, methodological orientation and epistem mitments. Network theory, with its methodological (an ontological) relationalism (Emirbayer and Goodwin 19 (2) In this very general sense, groupism extends well beyond the domain of ethnicity, race and nationalism to include accounts of putative groups based on gender, sexuality, age, class, abledness, religion, minority status, and any kind of 'culture', as well as putative groups based on combinations of these cat egorical attributes. Yet while recognizing that it is a wider tendency in social analysis, I limit my discussion here to groupism in the study of ethnicity, race and nationalism. 164 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY 1988) is opposed to rational choice theory, with its meth sometimes ontological) individualism; both are sharply a opposed, in analytical style and epistemological commitm modernist approaches. Yet these and other development ed in problematizing groupness and undermining axiom group being. Challenges to 'groupism', however, have been uneven. They have been striking—to take just one example—in the study of class, especially in the study of the working class, a term that is hard to use today without quotation marks or some other distancing device. Yet ethnic groups continue to be understood as entities and cast as actors. To be sure, constructivist approaches of one kind or another are now dominant in academic discussions of ethnicity. Yet everyday talk, policy analysis, media reports, and even much ostensibly constructivist academic writ ing routinely frame accounts of ethnic, racial and national conflict in groupist terms as the struggles 'of ethnic groups, races, and nations (3). Somehow, when we talk about ethnicity, and even more so when we talk about ethnic conflict, we almost automatically find ourselves talking about ethnic groups. Now it might be asked: 'What's wrong with this?' After all, it seems to be mere common sense to treat ethnic struggles as the struggles of ethnic groups, and ethnic conflict as conflict between such groups. I agree that this is the—or at least a—common-sense view of the matter. But we cannot rely on common sense here. Ethnic common sense—the tendency to partition the social world into putatively deeply constituted, quasi-natural intrinsic kinds (Hirschfeld 1996)—is a key part of what we want to explain, not what we want to explain things with\ it belongs to our empirical data, not to our analytical toolkit (4). Cognitive anthro pologists and social psychologists have accumulated a good deal of evi dence about common-sense ways of carving up the social world—about what Lawrence Hirschfeld (1996) has called 'folk sociologies'. The evi dence suggests that some common sense social categories—and notably (3) For useful critical analyses of media representations of ethnic violence, see the col lection of essays in Allen and Seaton 1999, as well as Seaton 1999. (4) This is perhaps too sharply put. To the extent that such intrinsic-kind categories are indeed constitutive of common-sense under standings of the social world, to the extent that such categories are used as a resource for par ticipants, and are demonstrably deployed or oriented to by participants in interaction, they can also serve as a resource for analysts. But as Emanuel Schegloff notes in another context, with respect to the category 'interruption', the fact that this is a vernacular, common-sense category for participants 'does not make it a first-order category usable for professional analysis. Rather than being employed in pro fessional analysis, it is better treated as a target category for professional analysis' (2000: 27). The same might well be said of common sense ethnic categories. 165 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER common sense ethnic and racial categories—tend to be and naturalizing (Rothbart and Taylor 1992; Hirschfeld 1996; Gil White 1999). They are the vehicles of what has been called a 'partici pants' primordialism' (Smith 1998: 158) or a 'psychological essential ism' (Medin 1989). We obviously cannot ignore such common sense primordialism. But that does not mean we should simply replicate it in our scholarly analyses or policy assessments. As 'analysts of naturaliz ers', we need not be 'analytic naturalizers' (Gil-White 1999: 803). Instead, we need to break with vernacular categories and common sense understandings. We need to break, for example, with the seeming ly obvious and uncontroversial point that ethnic conflict involves conflict between ethnic groups. I want to suggest that ethnic conflict—or what might better be called ethnicized or ethnically framed conflict—need not, and should not, be understood as conflict between ethnic groups, just as racial or racially framed conflict need not be understood as conflict between races, or nationally framed conflict as conflict between nations. Participants, of course, regularly do represent ethnic, racial and national conflict in such groupist, even primordialist terms. They often cast ethnic groups, races or nations as the protagonists—the heroes and martyrs—of such struggles. But this is no warrant for analysts to do so. We must, of course, take vernacular categories and participants' understandings seriously, for they are partly constitutive of our objects of study. But we should not uncritically adopt categories of ethnopolitical practice as our categories of social analysis. Apart from the general unre liability of ethnic common sense as a guide for social analysis, we should remember that participants' accounts—especially those of specialists in ethnicity such as ethnopolitical entrepreneurs, who, unlike nonspecial ists, may live 'off as well as 'for' ethnicity—often have what Pierre Bourdieu has called a performative character. By invoking groups, they seek to evoke them, summon them, call them into being. Their catego ries are for doing—designed to stir, summon, justify, mobilize, kindle and energize. By reifying groups, by treating them as substantial things-in the-world, ethnopolitical entrepreneurs may, as Bourdieu notes, 'contribute to producing what they apparently describe or des ignate' (1991a: 220) (5). Reification is a social process, not simply an intellectual bad habit. As a social process, it is central to the practice of politicized ethnicity. And (5) Such performative, group-making prac tices, of course, are not specific to ethnic entrepreneurs, but generic to political mobili zation and representation (Bourdieu 1991b: 248-251). i66 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY appropriately so. To criticize ethnopolitical entrepreneu ethnic groups would be a kind of category mistake. Rei precisely what ethnopolitical entrepreneurs are in the busin When they are successful, the political fiction of the unifie momentarily yet powerfully realized in practice. As anal certainly try to account for the ways in which—and co which—this practice of reification, this powerful crys group feeling, can work. This may be one of the most impo the theory of ethnic conflict. But we should avoid unint ling or reinforcing the reification of ethnic groups in ethn tice with a reification of such groups in social analysis. 11. Beyond groupism How, then, are we to understand ethnic conflict, if n sense terms as conflict between ethnic groups? And ho beyond groupism? Here I sketch eight basic points and then section, draw out some implications of them. In the fi illustrate the argument by considering one empirical case. Rethinking ethnicity We need to rethink not only ethnic conflict, but also wh ethnicity itself. This is not a matter of seeking agreement The intricate and ever-recommencing definitional casuistry ethnicity, race and nationalism has done little to advance and indeed can be viewed as a symptom of the non-cumulat research in the field. It is rather a matter of critically s conceptual tools. Ethnicity, race and nation should be c not as substances or things or entities or organisms or collective individuals—as the imagery of discrete, concrete, tangible, bounded and enduring 'groups' encourages us to do—but rather in relational, pro cessual, dynamic, eventful and disaggregated terms. This means think ing of ethnicity, race and nation not in terms of substantial groups or entities but in terms of practical categories, cultural idioms, cognitive schémas, discursive frames, organizational routines, institutional forms, political projects and contingent events. It means thinking of ethnicization, racialization and nationalization as political, social, cultural and psycho logical processes. And it means taking as a basic analytical category not the 'group' as an entity but groupness as a contextually fluctuating 167 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER conceptual variable. Stated baldly in this fashion, these mere slogans; I will try to fill them out a bit in what follows. The reality of ethnicity To rethink ethnicity, race and nationhood along these l way to dispute their reality, minimize their power or d significance; it is to construe their reality, power and sig different way. Understanding the reality of race, for exam require us to posit the existence of races. Racial idioms, i ratives, categories and systems of classification and racia seeing, thinking, talking and framing claims are real and especially when they are embedded in powerful organizat reality of race—and even its overwhelming coercive pow settings—does not depend on the existence of 'races'. Sim reality of ethnicity and nationhood —and the overriding pow and national identifications in some settings—does not d existence of ethnic groups or nations as substantial groups or Groupness as event Shifting attention from groups to groupness and treatin as variable and contingent rather than fixed and given (6 take account of—and, potentially, to account for—phases nary cohesion and moments of intensely felt collecti without implicitly treating high levels of groupness as con ing or definitionally present. It allows us to treat groupness as something that 'happens', as E. P. Thompson famously class. At the same time, it keeps us analytically attuned to th that groupness may not happen, that high levels of groupnes crystallize, despite the group-making efforts of ethnopoli neurs and even in situations of intense elite-level ethnopoliti Being analytically attuned to 'negative' instances in this way domain of relevant cases and helps correct for the bias in toward the study of striking instances of high groupne mobilization or conspicuous violence—a bias that can engender an 'overethnicized' view of the social world, a distorted representation of whole world regions as 'seething cauldrons' of ethnic tension (Brubaker 1998) and an overestimation of the incidence of ethnic violence (Fearon (6) For accounts (not focused specifically on ethnicity) that treat groupness as variable, see Tilly 1978: 62//; Hechter 1987: 8; Hamilton et al. 1998. These accounts, very different from one another, focus on variability in groupness across cases; my concern is primarily with variability in groupness over time. i68 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY and Laitin 1996). Sensitivity to such negative instances c potentially fruitful analytical attention toward the problem failed efforts at ethnopolitical mobilization. Groups and categories Much talk about ethnic, racial or national groups is ob failure to distinguish between groups and categories. If mean a mutually interacting, mutually recognizing, mut effectively communicating, bounded collectivity with a ity, corporate identity and capacity for concerted action adopt a less exigent understanding of 'group', it should category is not a group (Sacks 1995, I: 41, 401; Hand McKay and Lewins 1978; Jenkins 1997: 53ff) (7). It is at basis for group-formation or 'groupness' (8). By distinguishing consistently between categories and gro problematize—rather than presume—the relation betw can ask about the degree of groupness associated with a egory in a particular setting and about the political, so and psychological processes through which categories g with groupness (Petersen 1987). We can ask how people—and organizations—do things with categories. This includes limiting access to scarce resources or particular domains of activity by excluding catego rically distinguished outsiders (Weber 1968 [1922]: 43//, 34 iff, Barth 1969; Brubaker 1992; Tilly 1998), but it also includes more mundane actions such as identifying or classifying oneself or others (Levine 1999) or simply 'doing being ethnic' in an ethnomethodological sense (Moer man 1968). We can analyze the organizational and discursive careers of categories—the processes through which they become institutionalized and entrenched in administrative routines (Tilly 1998) and embedded in culturally powerful and symbolically resonant myths, memories and narratives (Armstrong 1982; Smith 1986). We can study the politics of (7) Fredrik Barth's introductory essay to the collection Ethnic Groups and Boundaries (1969) was extraordinarily influential in direct ing attention to the workings of categories of self- and other-ascription. But Barth does not distinguish sharply or consistently between categories and groups and his central metaphor of 'boundary' carries with it connotations of boundedness, entitativity and groupness. (8) This point was already made by Max Weber, albeit in somewhat different terms. As Weber argued—in a passage obscured in the English translation—ethnic commonality, based on belief in common descent, is 'in itself mere (putative) commonality [(geglaubte) Gemeinsamkeit], not community [Gemein schaft] [...] but only a factor facilitating com munal action [Vergemeinschaftung]' (1964: 307; cf. 1968: 389). Ethnic commonality means more than mere category membership for Weber. It is—or rather involves—a category that is employed by members themselves. But this shows that even self-categorization does not create a 'group'. 169 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER categories, both from above and from below. From abov on the ways in which categories are proposed, propagat institutionalized, discursively articulated, organizational and generally embedded in multifarious forms of 'gove (Noiriel 1991 ; Slezkine 1994; Brubaker 1994; Torpey 2000; Martin 2001). From below, we can study the 'micropolitics' of categories, the ways in which the categorized appropriate, internalize, subvert, evade or transform the categories that are imposed on them (Dominguez 1986). And drawing on advances in cognitive research, ethnomethodology and conversation analysis (9), we can study the sociocognitive and interac tional processes through which categories are used by individuals to make sense of the social world; linked to stereotypical beliefs and expectations about category members (10); invested with emotional associations and evaluative judgments; deployed as resources in specific interactional contexts; and activated by situational triggers or cues. A focus on categories, in short, can illuminate the multifarious ways in which ethnicity, race and nationhood can exist and 'work' without the existence of ethnic groups as substantial entities. It can help us envision ethnicity without groups. Group-making as project If we treat groupness as a variable and distinguish between groups and categories, we can attend to the dynamics of group-making as a social, cultural and political project, aimed at transforming categories (g) Ethnomethodology and conversation analysis have not focused on the use of ethnic categories as such, but Sacks, Schegloff and others have addressed the problem of situated categorization in general, notably the question of the procedures through which participants in interaction, in deploying categories, choose among alternative sets of categories (since there is always more than one set of categories in terms of which any person can be correctly described). The import of this problem has been formulated as follows by Schegloff (2000: 30-31): 'And given the centrality of [...] cate gories in organizing vernacular cultural 'knowledge', this equivocality can be pro foundly consequential, for which category is employed will carry with it the invocation of common-sense knowledge about that category of person and bring it to bear on the person referred to on some occasion, rather than bringing to bear the knowledge implicated with another category, of which the person being referred to is equally a member'. For Sacks on categories, see 1995: I, 40-48, 333 340, 396-403, 578-596; II, 184-187. (10) The language of 'stereotypes' is, of course, that of cognitive social psychology (for a review of work in this tradition, see Hamilton and Sherman 1994). But the general ethno methodological emphasis on the crucial importance of the rich though tacit back ground knowledge that participants bring to interaction and—more specifically—Harvey Sacks' discussion of the 'inference-rich' cat egories in terms of which much everyday social knowledge is stored (1995: I, 40ff et passim; cf. Schegloff 2000: 29ff) and of the way in which the knowledge thus organized is 'protected against induction' {ibid., 336$), suggest a domain of potentially converging concern between cognitive work on the one hand and ethnomethodological and conversation analytic work on the other—however different their analytic stances and methodologies. 170 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY into groups or increasing levels of groupness (Bourdieu 1991 Sometimes this is done in quite a cynical fashion. Ethnic an insurgencies, for example, often adopt what is called in French du pire, a politics of seeking the worst outcome in the short ru bolster their legitimacy or improve their prospects in the l When the small, ill-equipped, ragtag Kosovo Liberation Arm up its attacks on Serb policemen and other targets in early example, this was done as a deliberate—and successful—str provoking massive regime reprisals. As in many such situa brunt of the reprisals was borne by civilians. The cycle of a counterattacks sharply increased groupness among both Kos ians and Kosovo Serbs, generated greater support for the K both Kosovo and diaspora Albanians and bolstered KLA recr and funding. This enabled the KLA to mount a more serious to the regime, which in turn generated more brutal regime rep so on. In this sense, group crystallization and polarization result of violence, not the cause (Brubaker 1999). Of course, this group-making strategy employed in the late 1 not start from scratch. It had already begun with relatively hig groupness, a legacy of earlier phases of conflict. The propi materials' the KLA had to work with no doubt help explain of its strategy. Not all group-making projects succeed and th succeed (more or less) do so in part as a result of the cultur chological materials they have to work with. These materials only, or especially, 'deep', longue-durée cultural structures s mythomoteurs highlighted by Armstrong (1982) and Smith also the moderately durable ways of thinking and feeling that r 'middle-range' legacies of historical experience and political a while such raw materials—themselves the product and prec past struggles and predicaments—constrain and condition th ities for group-making in the present, there remains conside for deliberate group-making strategies. Certain dramatic eve ticular, can serve to galvanize and crystallize a potential gr ratchet up pre-existing levels of groupness. This is why del lence, undertaken as a strategy of provocation, often by a v number of persons, can sometimes be an exceptionally effective of group-making. Groups and organizations Although participants' rhetoric and common sense accoun ethnic groups as the protagonists of ethnic conflict, in fact 171 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER protagonists of most ethnic conflict—and a fortiori of violence—are not ethnic groups as such but various kin tions, broadly understood and their empowered and aut bents. These include states (or more broadly autonomo their organizational components such as particular ministries, of fices, law enforcement agencies and armed forces units; they include terrorist groups, paramilitary organizations, armed bands and loosely structured gangs; and they include political parties, ethnic associations, social movement organizations, churches, newspapers, radio and televi sion stations and so on. Some of these organizations may represent themselves, or may be seen by others, as organizations of and for par ticular ethnic groups (i i). But even when this is the case, organizations cannot be equated with ethnic groups. It is because and insofar as they are organizations and possess certain material and organizational resources, that they (or more precisely their incumbents) are capable of organized action and thereby of acting as more or less coherent pro tagonists in ethnic conflict (12). Although common sense and partici pants' rhetoric attribute discrete existence, boundedness, coherence, identity, interest and agency to ethnic groups, these attributes are in fact characteristic of organizations. The IRA, KLA and PKK claim to speak and act in the name of the (Catholic) Irish, the Kosovo Albanians and the Kurds; but surely analysts must differentiate between such organi zations and the putatively homogeneous and bounded groups in whose name they claim to act. The point applies not only to military, parami litary and terrorist organizations, of course, but to all organizations that claim to speak and act in the name of ethnic, racial or national groups (Heisler 1991). A fuller and more rounded treatment of this theme, to be sure, would require several qualifications that I can only gesture at here. Conflict and violence vary in the degree to which, as well as the manner in which, organizations are involved. What Donald Horowitz (2001) has called the deadly ethnic riot, for example, differs sharply from organized ethnic insurgencies or terrorist campaigns. Although organizations (sometimes ephemeral ones) may play an important role in preparing, provoking and permitting such riots, much of the actual violence is committed by broader sets of participants acting in relatively spontaneous fashion and in starkly polarized situations characterized by high levels of groupness. (11) One should remember, though, that organizations often compete with one another for the monopolization of the right to re present the same (putative) group. (12) In this respect the resource mobiliza tion perspective on social movements, eclipsed in recent years by identity-oriented new social movement theory, has much to offer students of ethnicity. For an integrated statement, see McCarthy and Zald 1977. 172 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY Moreover, even where organizations are the core protagonis depend on a penumbra of ancillary or supportive actio of sympathetic non-members. The 'representativeness' of organi zations—the degree to which an organization can justifiably claim to represent the will, express the interests and enjoy the active or passive support of its constituents—is enormously variable, not only between organizations, but also over time and across domains. In addition, while organizations are ordinarily the protagonists of conflict and violence, they are not always the objects or targets of conflict and violence. Entire population categories—or putative groups—can be the objects of organ ized action, much more easily than they can be the subjects or underta kers of such action. Finally, even apart from situations of violence, eth nic conflict may be at least partly amorphous, carried out not by orga nizations as such but spontaneously by individuals through such everyday actions as shunning, insults, demands for deference or conform ity, or withholdings of routine interactional tokens of acknowledgment or respect (Bailey 1997). Still, despite these qualifications, it is clear that organizations, not ethnic groups as such, are the chief protagonists of ethnic conflict and ethnic violence and that the relationship between organizations and the groups they claim to represent is often deeply ambiguous. Framing and coding (13) If the protagonists of ethnic conflict cannot, in general, be considered ethnic groups, then what makes such conflict count as ethnic conflict? And what makes violence count as ethnic violence? Similar questions can be asked about racial and national conflict and violence. The answer cannot be found in the intrinsic properties of behavior. The 'ethni quality of 'ethnic violence', for example, is not intrinsic to violent conduct itself; it is attributed to instances of violent behavior by perpetr tors, victims, politicians, officials, journalists, researchers, relief wo ers or others. Such acts of framing and narrative encoding do not simply interpret the violence; they constitute it as ethnic. Framing may be a key mechanism through which groupness is constructed. The metaphor of framing was popularized by Goffma (1974), drawing on Bateson 1985 [1955]. The notion has been elaborate chiefly in the social movement literature (Snow et al. 1986; Snow a Benford 1988; Gamson and Modigliani 1989; Gamson 1992; unitin rational choice and framing approaches, Esser 1999). When ethnic fra (13) These paragraphs draw on Brubaker and Laitin 1998. 173 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER ing is successful, we may 'see' conflict and violence not only i but in groupist terms. Although such imputed groupness is th of prevailing interpretive frames, not necessarily a measure groupness felt and experienced by the participants in an even pelling ex post interpretive framing or encoding may exercise a p feedback effect, shaping subsequent experience and increasing groupness. A great deal is at stake, then, in struggles over the tive framing and narrative encoding of conflict and violence. Interpretive framing, of course, is often contested. Violen more generally, conflict—is regularly accompanied by social strug label, interpret and explain it. Such 'metaconflicts' or 'conflic the nature of the conflict', as Donald Horowitz has called them do not simply shadow conflicts from the outside, but are int consequential parts of the conflicts. To impose a label or pre interpretive frame—to cause an event to be seen as a 'pogrom' or a 'rebellion'—is no mere matter of external interpretation constitutive act of social definition that can have important quences (Brass 1996b). Social struggles over the proper coding and interpretation of conflict and violence are therefore important subjects of study in their own right (Brass 1996a, 1997, Abelmann and Lie 1995). Coding and framing practices are heavily influenced by prevailing interpretive frames. Today, ethnic and national frames are accessible and legitimate, suggesting themselves to actors and analysts alike. This generates a 'coding bias' in the ethnic direction. And this, in turn, may lead us to overestimate the incidence of ethnic conflict and violence by unjustifiably seeing ethnicity everywhere at work (Bowen 1996). Actors may take advantage of this coding bias and of the generalized legitimacy of ethnic and national frames, by strategically using ethnic framing to mask the pursuit of clan, clique or class interests. The point here is not to suggest that clans, cliques or classes are somehow more real than ethnic groups, but simply to note the existence of structural and cultural incentives for strategic framing. Ethnicity as cognition (14) These observations about the constitutive significance of coding and framing suggest a final point about the cognitive dimension of ethnicity. Ethnicity, race and nationhood exist only in and through our percep tions, interpretations, representations, categorizations and identifica tions. They are not things in the world, but perspectives on the ( 14) These paragraphs draw on Brubaker et al. 2001. 174 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY world (15). These include ethnicized ways of seeing (an construing (and misconstruing), of inferring (and mis remembering (and forgetting). They include ethnically o schémas and narratives and the situational cues that acti as the ubiquitous televised images that have played such role in the latest intifada. They include systems of cla egorization and identification, formal and informal. An the tacit, taken-for-granted background knowledge, e sons and embedded in institutionalized routines and pra which people recognize and experience objects, places, p or situations as ethnically, racially or nationally marked or Cognitive perspectives, broadly understood (16), can constructivist research on ethnicity, race and nationh stalled in recent years as it has grown complacent with of simply asserting that ethnicity, race and nationhood are they can help specify how they are constructed. They c how—and when—people identify themselves, perce perience the world and interpret their predicaments in national rather than other terms. They can help specify ho can 'crystallize' in some situations while remaining lat potential in others. And they can help link macro-level micro-level processes. III. Implications At this point a critic might interject: 'What is the poi Even if we can study 'ethnicity without groups', w Concepts invariably simplify the world; that the concept o bounded ethnic groups does so, suggesting something m and clear-cut than really exists, cannot be held against it. T (15) As Emanuel Schegloff reminded me in a different context, this formulation is poten tially misleading, since perspectives on the world—as every Sociology 1 student is taught—are themselves in the world and every bit as 'real' and consequential as other sorts of things. (16) Cognitive perspectives, in this broad sense, include not only those developed in cognitive psychology and cognitive anthropo logy but also those developed in the post- (and anti-) Parsonian 'cognitive turn' (DiMaggio and Powell 1991) in sociological and (more broadly) social theory, especially in response to the influence of phenomenological and ethno methodological work (Schutz 1962; Garfinkel 1967; Heritage 1984). Cognitive perspectives are central to the influential syntheses of Bourdieu and Giddens and—in a very different form—to the enterprise of conversation analy sis. 175 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER ethnic group may be a blunt instrument, but it is good enough as approximation. This talk about groupness and framing and p categories and cognitive schémas is all well and good, but mean killing goes on. Does the critique matter in the real world, o all—only in the ivory tower? What practical difference does it m I believe the critique of groupism does have implication rather general ones, for the ways in which researchers, journ icymakers, NGOs and others come to terms, analytically and prac with what we ordinarily—though perhaps too readily—ca conflict and ethnic violence. Here I would like to enumerate five o before going on in the final section to discuss an empirical case. First, sensitivity to framing dynamics, to the generalized codin in favor of ethnicity and to the sometimes strategic or even cyni ethnic framing to mask the pursuit of clan, clique or class int alert us to the risk of over-ethnicized or overly groupist interpre of (and interventions in) situations of conflict and violence 1996). One need not subscribe to a reductionist 'elite manipulat of politicized ethnicity (Brubaker 1998) to acknowledge that t put on conflicts by participants may conceal as much as it re that the representation of conflicts as conflicts between ethnic o al groups may obscure the interests at stake and the dynamics What is represented as ethnic conflict or ethnic war—such a lence in the former Yugoslavia, may have as much or more to thuggery, warlordship, opportunistic looting and black-mar teering than with ethnicity (Mueller 2000; cf. Collier 1999). Second, recognition of the centrality of organizations in e conflict and ethnic violence, of the often equivocal character leaders' claims to speak and act in the name of ethnic groups a performative nature of ethnopolitical rhetoric, enlisted in the ser group-making projects, can remind us not to mistake groupist for real groupness, the putative groups of ethnopolitical rhet substantial things-in-the-world. Third, awareness of the interest that ethnic and nationalist may have in living off politics, as well as for politics, to borrow distinction of Max Weber (1946: 84), and awareness of the p divergence between the interests of leaders and those of their constituents, can keep us from accepting at face value leader about the beliefs, desires and interests of their constituents. Fourth, sensitivity to the variable and contingent, waxing and nature of groupness and to the fact that high levels of groupness more the result of conflict (especially violent conflict) than i 176 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY lying cause, can focus our analytical attention and policy on the processes through which groupness tends to de tallize and those through which it may subside. Some att given recently to the former, including tipping and cascade (Laitin 1995, Kuran 1998) and mechanisms governing the diffusion of schémas and the 'epidemiology of represent 1985). But declining curves of groupness have not been atically, although they are just as important, theoretically Once ratcheted up to a high level, groupness does not re of inertia. If not sustained at high levels through spec cognitive mechanisms, it will tend to decline, as every reassert themselves, through a process of what Weber (in a apposite context [1968 (1922): 246-254]) called 'routin taeglichung, literally 'towards everydayness'). Lastly, a disaggregating, non-groupist approach can br lytical and policy focus the critical importance of intra nisms in generating and sustaining putatively interethn baker and Laitin 1998: 433). These include in-group 'policing,' monitoring, or sanctioning processes (Laitin 1995); the 'ethnic outbid ding' through which electoral competition can foster extreme ethnici zation (Rothschild 1981; Horowitz 1985); the calculated instigation or provocation of conflict with outsiders by vulnerable incumbents seeking to deflect in-group challenges to their positions; and in-group processes bearing on the dynamics of recruitment into gangs, militias, terrorist groups or guerrilla armies, including honoring, shaming and shunning practices, rituals of manhood, intergenerational tensions and the prom ising and provision of material and symbolic rewards for martyrs. IV. Ethnicity at work in a Transylvanian town At this point, I would like to add some flesh to the bare-bones ana lytical argument sketched above. It is tempting to comment on the United States. It would be easy to score rhetorical points by emphasiz ing that the 'groups' taken to constitute the canonical 'ethnoracial pen tagon' (Hollinger 1995)—African Americans, Asian Americans, Whites, Native Americans and Latinos—are (with the partial exception of African Americans) not groups at all but categories, backed by political entrepreneurs and entrenched in governmental and other organizational routines of social counting and accounting (Office of Manage 177 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER ment and Budget 1994). It would be easy to highlight th cultural heterogeneity within these and other putative 'gr minimal degree of groupness associated with many ethnic the US (Gans 1979; Heisler 1991). But rather than take this tack, I will try to address a h drawn from a region historically characterized by much h of ethnic and national groupness. I want to consider brief ity works in an East Central European context characteri uous and often intense elite-level ethnonational conflict since the fall of communism (and, of course, by a much longer history of ethnonational tension). Here too, I want to suggest, we can fruitfully analyze ethnicity without groups. The setting, familiar to me from field research conducted in the second half of the 1990s, is the city of Cluj, the main administrative, economic and cultural center of the Transylvanian region of Romania. Of the approximately 330,000 residents, a substantial minority— somewhere between 14 and 23 percent—identify themselves as Hunga rian by ethnocultural nationality (17). The city, as I indicated, has been the site of protracted and seemingly intractable ethnonational conflict since the collapse of the Ceauçescu regime in December 1989. But this is not, I will argue, best understood as a conflict between ethnic or national groups. To think of it as a conflict between groups is to conflate cate gories ('Hungarian' and 'Romanian') with groups ('the Hungarians', 'the Romanians'); to obscure the generally low, though fluctuating, degree of groupness in this setting; to mistake the putative groups invoked by ethnonational rhetoric for substantial things-in-the-world; to accept, at least tacitly, the claims of nationalist organizations to speak for the 'groups' they claim to represent; and to neglect the every day contexts in which ethnic and national categories take on meaning (i7) In the US and much of northern and western Europe, 'nationality' ordinarily means 'citizenship', that is, membership of the state; and 'nation' and 'state' are often used inter changeably. In central and eastern Europe, by contrast, 'nation' and 'nationality' do not refer in the first instance to the state, but ordinarily invoke an ethnocultural frame of reference independent of—and often cutting across the boundaries of—statehood and citizen ship. To identify oneself as Hungarian by nationality in Transylvania is to invoke a state-transcending Hungarian ethnocultural 'nation'. In the text, following the usage in this setting, I use 'ethnic' and 'national' inter changeably. At the last census, conducted in 1992, 23 % of the population of Cluj identified as Hungar ian. More recent statistics, however, suggest a smaller population identifying as Hungarian, at least among younger age cohorts. Of persons getting married in 1999, 14.4% identified their nationality as Hungarian. Of primary, middle school and secondary school students in 1999 2000, 15.1%, 14.3% and 14.8%, respectively, identified as Hungarian. Contextual differ ences in identification may account for part of the difference, as might different age structures of Romanian and Hungarian populations and differential emigration rates during the 1990s. 178 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY and the processes through which ethnicity actually 'wor life. Here, as elsewhere, the protagonists of the conflict have been organi zations, not groups. The conflict has pitted the town's three-term mayor—the flamboyant Romanian nationalist Gheorghe Funar—and the statewide Romanian nationalist parties against the Cluj-based Democratic Association of Hungarians of Romania (DAHR), at once a statewide political party with its electoral base in Transylvania and an organization claiming to represent and further the interests of the Hungarian minority in Romania. Rhetoric has been heated on both sides. Mayor Funar has accused Hungary of harboring irredentist designs on Transylvania ( 18); he has called the DAHR a 'terrorist organization'; and he has accused Transylvanian Hungarians of secretly collecting weapons, forming paramilitary detachments and planning an attack on Romanians. Funar has ordered bilingual signs removed from the few buildings that had them; banned proposed celebrations of the Hungarian national holiday; called for the suspending of Hungarian language broadcasts on Romanian state television; called for punish ment of citizens for displaying the Hungarian flag or singing the Hun garian anthem; and proposed to rename after Romanian personages the few Cluj streets that bear the names of Hungarians. The DAHR, for its part, is committed to a number of goals that outrage Romanian nationalists (19). It characterizes Hungarians in Romania as an 'indigenous community' entitled to an equal partnership with the Romanian nation as a constituent element of the Transylvanian state—thereby directly challenging the prevailing (and constitutionally enshrined) Romanian understanding of the state as a unitary nation state like France. At the same time, it characterizes Transylvanian Hun garians as an 'organic part of the Hungarian nation' and as such claims the right to cultivate relations with the 'mother country' across the border, which leads Romanian nationalists to call into question their loyalty to the Romanian state. It demands collective rights for Hungarians as a national minority and it demands autonomy, including territorial auto nomy, for areas in which Hungarians live as a local majority, thereby raising the specter of separatism in the minds of Romanian nationalists. It demands that Hungarians have their own institutional system in the domain of education and culture—yet that this institutional system ( 18) Transylvania had belonged to Hungary for half a century before the First World War and again for four years during the Second World War. (19) The DAHR program can be found in English at http: //www.rmdsz.ro/angol/ aboutus/p rog. htm. 179 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER should be financed by the Romanian state. It demands t public, state-funded education in Hungarian at every level branch of the educational system, including vocational e demands the right to take entrance exams to every school an in Hungarian, even if the school or department to which applying carries out instruction in Romanian. And it re-establishment of an independent Hungarian universit the establishment of publicly funded but independent H guage radio and TV studios. Like ethnic and nationalist organizations everywhere, claims to speak for the Hungarian minority in Romanian, terizing it as a singular entity, 'the Hungariandom of R româniai magyarsâg). But no such entity exists (20). The residents who self-identify as Hungarian are often sharply c DAHR and there is no evidence that the demands of the DAHR are the demands of 'the Hungarians'. On the question of a Hungarian university—the most contentious political issue of the last few years—a survey conducted by a Hungarian sociologist found that a plurality of Hungarian university students in Cluj preferred an autonomous system of Hungarian-language education within the existing university to the DAHR goal of re-establishment of a separate Hungarian university (Magyari-Nândor and Péter 1997). Most Hungarians, like most Roma nians, are largely indifferent to politics and preoccupied with problems of everyday life—problems that are not interpreted in ethnic terms. Although survey data and election results suggest that they appear to vote en bloc for the DAHR, most Hungarians are familiar only in a vague way with the DAHR program. Similarly, there is no evidence that Mayor Funar's anti-Hungarian views are widely shared by the town's Romanian residents. When Funar is praised, it is typically as a 'good housekeeper' (bun gospodar); he is given credit for sprucing up the town's appearance and for providing comparatively good municipal services. Almost everyone—Romanian and Hungarian alike—talks about ethnic conflict as something that 'comes from above' and is stirred up by politicians pursuing their own interests. The near-universal refrain is that ethnicity is 'not a problem'. To be sure, a similar idiom—or perhaps ideology—of everyday interethnic harmony can be (2o) Of course this point holds not only, or especially, of the Hungarian minority, or of minorities generally. In Romania as elsewhere, those who claim to speak for dominant nations—nations that are closely identified with the states that bear their names, referred to in German as Staatsvölker or 'state peo ples'—also routinely reify those 'nations' and characterize them as singular entities with a common will and common interests, where in fact no such entity exists. i8o This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY found in many other settings, including some deeply d plagued ones. So the idiom cannot be taken as evidence evance of ethnicity. The point here is simply to under between nationalist organizations and the putative 'gro names they claim to speak. Despite the continuous elite-level ethnopolitical confli the fall of Ceauçescu, 'groupness' has generally remain time did Hungarians and Romanians crystallize as disti bounded groups; in this sense groupness failed to 'happe with Târgu Mureç, another Transylvanian city where g tallize in 1990, is instructive. In Târgu Mureç, ethnically fr over the control of a high school and over the control ment in the immediate aftermath of the fall of Ceauçescu broadened into a generalized conflict over the 'ownership' a the ethnodemographically evenly divided city. The conf in mass assemblies and two days of street fighting that dead and 200 injured. In the days leading up to the viole categories had become palpable, sharply bounded group intensely felt collective solidarity and animated by a si distinction between 'us' and 'them'. The violence itself reinforced this sense of groupness, which then subsided gradually as life returned to normal and no further Hungarian-Romanian violence occurred, here or elsewhere in Transylvania. No such crystallization occurred in Cluj. There were, to be sure, a few moments of moderately heightened groupness. One such moment—among Hungarians—occurred when Mayor Funar ordered a new plaque installed on the base of a monumental equestrian statue of Matthias Corvinus, celebrated king of Hungary during the late fifteenth century, in the town's main square. The statue, erected at the turn of the last century at a moment of and as a monument to, triumphant Hun garian nationalism, is perceived by many Hungarians as 'their own' and the new plaque deliberately affronted Hungarian national sensibilities by emphasizing the (partly) Romanian origin of Matthias Corvinus and representing him—contrary to the triumphalist image projected by the statue—as having been defeated in battle by 'his own nation', Moldavia (Feischmidt 2001). Another moment occurred when archeological excavations were begun in front of the statue, again in a manner calcu lated to affront Hungarian national sensibilities by highlighting the ear lier Roman—and by extension, Romanian—presence on the site. A third moment occurred in March 1998, when Mayor Funar tried to bar Hungarians from carrying out their annual March 15 celebration com 181 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER memorating the revolution of 1848, this year's celebrat quicentennial year, having special significance (Brubake midt 2002) (21). A final moment occurred in June 1999 a much-hyped soccer match in Bucharest between the nat Romania and Hungary. In Cluj, the match was televised on a huge outdoor screen in the main square and some fans chanted 'Afarä, afarä, eu Ungurii din faräV (out, out, the Hungarians out of the country!) and vandalized cars with Hungarian license plates (Adevärul de Cluj 1999) In each of these cases, groupness—especially among Hungarians, though in the final case among Romanians as well—was heightened, but only to a modest degree and only for a passing moment. The first event occasioned a substantial but isolated Hungarian protest, the second a smaller protest, the third some concern that the commemoration might be broken up (in the event it proceeded without serious incident) and the last some moments of concern for those who happened to be in the town center during and immediately after the soccer match. But even at these maximally group-like moments, there was no overriding sense of bounded and solidary groupness for those not immediately involved in the events (22). In short, when one shifts one's focus from presupposed groups to variable groupness and treats high levels of groupness as a contingent event, a crystallization, something that happens, then what is striking about Cluj in the 1990s is that groupness remained low and groups failed to happen or to crystallize. (21) To Romanian nationalists, Hunga rians' commemoration of 1848 is illegitimate, for it celebrates a regime that was as much nationalist as revolutionary, aspiring to—and briefly securing—unitary control over Tran sylvania. Romanian nationalist mythology commemorates not the revolution, but the guerilla struggle against the Hungarian revolu tionary regime, led by Avram Iancu, to whom a colossal monument was erected under Funar's sponsorship in 1993. (22) Even for those who were involved in the events, one should be cautious about infer ring an overriding sense of groupness. I was in Cluj in the summer of 1994, when excavations in the main 'Hungarian' square were about to begin. I was staying with the family of a lead ing figure of the DAHR, albeit one of the more liberal figures. At one point, he proposed: 'Menjünk âsni? [Shall we go dig?]' At a moment of overriding groupness, such a joke would be unthinkable; here, the nationalist projects of Mayor Funar were—at least for some—a joking matter. One further incident is worth mentioning in this connection. In 1997, a long-closed Hungarian consulate re-opened in Cluj, reflecting a warming of relations between Budapest and the newly elected pro western government in Bucharest. Funar protested—in vain—against its opening and when it opened, tried to fine it for flying the Hungarian flag. A few weeks after its opening, five men pulled up in a pickup truck, placed an extendable ladder against the side of the build ing, and—removed the flag, in broad daylight, as a small crowd looked on. The next day, they were apprehended by the police; Funar char acterized them as 'Romanian heroes'. Elsewhere, this sort of incident—which could easily be construed as involving the desecration of a sacred national symbol—has been enough to trigger a riot. Here, nobody paid much attention; the incident was coded as farce, not as sacred drama. 182 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY To note the relatively low degree of groupness in Clu between organizations and the putative groups they claim t not to suggest that ethnicity is somehow not 'real' in this s it is purely an elite phenomenon. Yet to understand how et it may help to begin not with 'the Romanians' and 'the groups, but with 'Romanian' and 'Hungarian' as categor suggests a different set of questions than those that come t we begin with 'groups'. Starting with groups, one is le groups want, demand or aspire towards; how they think and others; and how they act in relation to other grou almost automatically by the substantialist language to attrib agency, interests and will to groups. Starting with cat contrast, invites us to focus on processes and relations substances. It invites us to specify how people and org things with and to ethnic and national categories; how are used to channel and organize processes and relation egories get institutionalized and with what consequences. ask how, why and in what contexts ethnic categories ar used—to make sense of problems and predicaments, to a ities and affiliations, to identify commonalities and conn frame stories and self-understandings. Consider here just two of the many ways of pursuin centered rather than a group-centered approach to eth First, a good deal of common-sense cultural knowledge a world and one's place in it, here as in other settings, is org ethnonational categories (23). This includes knowledge and others' ethnocultural nationality and the ability to a others to ethnonational categories on the basis of cues su accent, name, sometimes dress, hair style, and even ph includes knowledge of what incumbents of such categor how they typically behave and how ethnonational catego matters in various spheres of life. Such common-sense (23) On categories as 'repositories] for common sense knowledge' generally (Sche gloff 2000: 29), see Sacks 1995, I, 40-48, 333 340. For cognitive perspectives on social cat egories as structures of knowledge, with spe cial regard to ethnic, racial and other 'natural kind', like categories, see Rothbart and Taylor 1992; Hamilton and Sherman 1994; Hirsch feld 1996. (24) Even when such common-sense, category-based stereotypical knowledge is overridden, the very manner of overriding may testify to the existence (and the content) of the category-based knowledge that is being over ridden. On the general phenomenon of 'modifiers' that work by asserting that what is generally known about members of a category is not applicable to some particular member, see Sacks (1995), I, 44*45- Among Hungarians—even liberal, cosmopolitan Hun garians—I have on several occasions heard someone referred to as 'Roman, de rendes' (Romanian, but quite all right) or something to that effect. i83 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER knowledge shapes everyday interaction, figures in stor about themselves and others and provides ready-made e certain events or states of affairs. For Hungarians, for e rizing an unknown person as Hungarian or Romanian m one interacts with him or her, determining not only the la the manner in which one will speak, a more personal an (bizalmas) style often being employed with fellow Hung Romanians, categorizing two persons speaking Hungari language setting as Hungarian (rather than, for example, happen to be speaking Hungarian) provides a ready-ma for their conduct, it being common-sense knowledge ab that they will form a bisericufa (clique, literally: smal others of their kind, excluding co-present Romanians, w have the chance. Or again for Hungarians, categorically organized common-sense knowledge provides a ready-made framework for per ceiving differential educational and economic opportunities as structur ed along ethnic lines, explaining such differentials in terms of what they know about the bearing of ethnic nationality on grading, admissions, hiring, promotion and firing decisions and justifying the commonly voiced opinion that 'we [Hungarians] have to work twice as hard' to get ahead (Feischmidt 2001; Fox 2001). These and many other examples suggest that ethnicity is, in important part, a cognitive phenomenon, a way of seeing and interpreting the world and that, as such, it works in and through categories and category-based common sense knowledge. Ethnic categories shape institutional as well as informal cognition and recognition. They not only structure perception and interpretation in the ebb and flow of everyday interaction but channel conduct through official classifications and organizational routines. Thus ethnic (and other) categories may be used to allocate rights, regulate actions, distri bute benefits and burdens, construct category-specific institutions, identify particular persons as bearers of categorical attributes, 'cultivate' populations or, at the extreme, 'eradicate' unwanted 'elements' (25). In Cluj—as in Romania generally—ethnic categories are not institu tionalized in dramatic ways. Yet there is one important set of institutions built, in part, around ethnic categories. This is the school system (26). (25) On 'population politics' and the meta phor of the gardening state, see Holquist 1997: 131; Bauman 2000; Weiner 2001. Genocide, as Bauman observes, 'differs from other murders in having a category for its object' (2000: 227, italics in original). (26) Traditional churches, too, are built around ethnic categories, with two 'Hungar ian' churches (Roman Catholic and Calvinist) and two 'Romanian' churches (Orthodox and Greek-Catholic or Uniate). With aging con gregations, dwindling influence and increased competition from less ethnically marked neo-Protestant denominations, the traditional 184 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY In Cluj, as in other Transylvanian cities, there is a sepa language school system paralleling the mainstream syste from preschool through high school. These are not priv part of the state school system. Not all persons identifying Hungarian attend Hungarian schools, but most do (85grades 1-4, smaller proportions, though still substantia later grades) (27). In Cluj, moreover, there are also parall university level in many fields of study. Categories need ecological niches in which to survive the parallel school system provides such a niche for 'H ethnonational category. It is a strategically positioned n schools not only provide a legitimate institutional home public space for the category. They also generate the so foundations for a small Hungarian world within the la one (Feischmidt 2001). Since the schools shape opportu and contact probabilities and thereby influence friendship at the high school and university level, marriage patter world is to a certain extent a self-reproducing one. Note th reproduction of this social world—this interlocking se tionships linking school, friendship circles and family— strong nationalist commitments or group loyalties. Ethn be reproduced without high degrees of groupness, large logic of contact probabilities and opportunity structure ting moderately high degrees of ethnic endogamy (28). This brief case study has sought to suggest that even intense elite-level ethnic conflict and (by comparison States) deeply rooted and stable ethnic identifications, the workings of ethnicity without employing the langu groups. V. Conclusion What are we studying when we study ethnicity and ethnic conflict? This paper has suggested that we need not frame our analyses in terms churches are less significant than schools as institutional loci of ethnic categories. (27) Data are drawn from figures provided by the School Inspectorate of Cluj County. (28) Of the Hungarians who married in Cluj in 1999, nearly 75 percent married other Hungarians, while about 25 percent married Romanians. This suggests a moderately high degree of ethnic endogamy, but only modera tely high, for about 40 percent of all marriages involving Hungarians were mixed marriages. Data were compiled from forms filled out by couples, consulted at the Cluj branch of the National Commission for Statistics. i8s This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER of ethnic groups and that it may be more productive to focu categories, cultural idioms, cognitive schémas, commonsense knowledge, organizational routines and resources, discursive frames, institutionalized forms, political projects, contingent events and vari able groupness. It should be noted in closing, however, that by framing our inquiry in this way and by bringing to bear a set of analytical pers pectives not ordinarily associated with the study of ethnicity—cognitive theory, ethnomethodology, conversation analysis, network analysis, organizational analysis and institutional theory, for example—we may end up not studying ethnicity at all. It may be that 'ethnicity' is simply a convenient—though in certain respects misleading—rubric under which to group phenomena that, on the one hand, are highly disparate and, on the other, have a great deal in common with phenomena that are not ordinarily subsumed under the rubric of ethnicity (29). In other words, by raising questions about the unit of analysis—the ethnic group—we may end up questioning the domain of analysis: ethnicity itself. But that is an argument for another occasion. (29) As Weber put it nearly a century ago (1964 [1922]: 313; cf. 1968 [1922]: 394-5). a precise and differentiated analysis would 'surely throw out the umbrella term "ethnic" altogether', for it is 'entirely unusable' for any 'truly rigorous investigation'. REFERENCES Abelmann, Nancy and John Lie, 1995, Blue Dreams: Korean Americans and the Los Angeles Riots (Cambridge: Harvard Univer sity Press). Adevärul de Cluj, 1999, Confruntarea dintre România çi Ungaria a continuât §i dupä meci [The confrontation between Romania and Hungary continued also after the match], June 7, 1999. Allen, Tim and Jean Seaton (eds), 1999, The Media of Conflict: War Reporting and Representations of Ethnic Violence (London: Zed Books). Armstrong, John A., 1982, Nations Before Nationalism (Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press). Bailey, Benjamin, 1997, Communication of Respect in Interethnic Service Encounters, Language in Society 26, 327-356. Barth, Fredrik, 1969, Introduction, in Fredrik Barth (ed.), Ethnic Groups and Boundaries: The Social Organization of Culture Differ ence (London: George Allen & Un win), 9-38. Bateson, Gregory, 1985 [1955], A Theory of Play and Fantasy, in Robert E. Innis (ed.), Semiotics: An Introductory Anthology, 131 144. Bauman, Zygmunt, 2000 [1989], Modernity and the Holocaust (Ithaca: Cornell Univer sity Press). Bentley, Arthur F., 1908, The Process of Government: A Study of Social Pressures (Chicago: University of Chicago Press). Bourdieu, Pierre, 1991a, Identity and Re presentation: Elements for a Critical Reflection on the Idea of Region, in Pierre Bourdieu, Language and Symbolic Power (Cambridge: Harvard University Press), 220-228. —, 1991b, Social Space and the Genesis of 'Classes', in Pierre Bourdieu, Language and i86 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY Symbolic Power (Cambridge: Harvard Uni versity Press), 229-251. Bowen, John R., 1996, The Myth of Global Ethnic Conflict, Journal of Democracy 7(4), 3-14 Brass, Paul R. (ed.), 1996a, Riots and Pogroms (Washington Square: New York University Press). —, 1996b, Introduction: Discourse of Ethni city, Communalism and Violence, in Paul R. Brass (ed.), Riots and Pogroms (Washington Square: New York University Press), 1-55. —, 1997, Theft of an Idol: Text and Context in the Representation of Collective Violence (Princeton: Princeton University Press). Brubaker, Rogers, 1992, Citizenship and Nationhood in France and Germany (Cam bridge, MA: Harvard University Press). —, 1994, Nationhood and the National Ques tion in the Soviet Union and Post-Soviet Eurasia, Theory and Society 23(1), 47-78. —, 1998, Myths and Misconceptions in the Study of Nationalism, in John Hall (ed.), The State of the Nation: Ernest Gellner and the Theory of Nationalism (New York: Cambridge University Press), 272-306. —, 1999, A Shameful Debacle, UCLA Maga zine, Summer 1999, 15-16. Brubaker, Rogers and Margit Feischmidt, 2002, 1848 in 1998: The Politics of Com memoration in Hungary, Romania, and Slovakia, forthcoming in Comparative Stu dies in Society and History. Brubaker, Rogers and David D. Laitin, 1998, Ethnic and Nationalist Violence, Annual Review of Sociology 24,423-452. Brubaker, Rogers, Mara Loveman and Peter Stamatov, 2001, 'Beyond Social Construc tion: The Case for a Cognitive Approach to Race, Ethnicity and Nationalism'. Unpub lished manuscript. Collier, Paul, 1999, Doing Well Out of War. http : /lwww.world.bank .org/ research/conflict/ papers/econagenda .htm. Cooley, Charles H., 1962 [1909], Social Organization (New York: Schocken Books). DiMaggio, Paul J. and Walter W. Powell, 1991, Introduction, in Walter W. Powell and Paul J. DiMaggio (eds), The New Institutionalism in Organizational (Chicago: University of Chicago Press), 1-38. Dominguez, Virginia R., 1986, White by Defi nition: Social Classification in Creole Loui siana (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press). Emirbayer, Mustafa and Jeff Goodwin, 1994, Network Analysis, Culture and the Problem of Agency, American Journal of Sociology 99(6), 1411-1454. Esser, Hartmut, 1999, Die Situationslogik ethnischer Konflikte: Auch eine Anmerkung zum Beitrag 'Ethnische Mobilisierung und die Logik von Identitätskämpfen' von Klaus Eder und Oliver Schmidtke, Zeitschrift für Soziologie 28(4), 245-262. Fearon, James and David D. Laitin, 1996, Explaining Interethnic Cooperation, Ameri can Political Science Review 90(4), 715-735. Feischmidt, Margit, 2001, Zwischen Abgrenzung und Vermischung: Ethnizität in der siebenbürgischen Stadt Cluj (Kolo zsvâr, Klausenburg). Ph. D. dissertation (Humboldt University, Berlin). Fox, Jon E., 2001, Nationness and Everyday Life: Romanian and Hungarian University Students in Transylvania. Paper presented to the Center for Comparative Social Ana lysis Workshop, Department of Sociology, UCLA. Gamson, William A., 1992, Talking Politics (New York: Cambridge University Press). Gamson, William A. and Andre Modi gliani, 1989, Media Discourse and Public Opinion on Nuclear Power: A Construction ist Approach, American Journal of Sociology 95,i-37 Gans, Herbert J., 1979, Symbolic Ethnicity: The Future of Ethnic Groups and Cultures in America, Ethnic and Racial Studies 2,1 20. Garfinkel, Harold, 1967, Studies in Ethno methodology (Englewood Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice-Hall, Inc.) Gil-White, Francisco, 1999, How Thick Is Blood? The Plot Thickens...: If Ethnic Actors Are Primordialists, What Remains of the Circumstantialist/Primordialist Contro versy? Ethnic and Racial Studies 22(5), 789 820. Goffman, Erving, 1974, Frame Analysis (San Francisco: Harper Colophon Books). Hamilton, David L. and Jeffrey W. Sher man, 1994, Stereotypes, in Robert S. Wyer and Thomas K. Srull (eds), Handbook of Social Cognition, 2nd ed. (Hillsdale, NJ: L. Erlbaum Associates), 1-68. Hamilton, David L., Steven J. Sherman and Brian Lickel, 1998, Perceiving Social Groups: The Importance of the Entitativity Continuum, in Constantine Sedikides, John Schopler and Chester A. Insko (eds), 187 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ROGERS BRUBAKER Intergroup Cognition and Intergroup Behav ior (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Asso ciates), 47-74. Handelman, Don, 1977, The Organization of Ethnicity, Ethnic Groups 1,187-200. Hechter, Michael, 1987, Principles of Group Solidarity (Berkeley: University of Califor nia Press). Heisler, Martin, 1991, Ethnicity and Ethnic Relations in the Modern West, in Joseph Montville (ed.), Conflict and Peacemaking in Multiethnic (Lexington: Lexington Books), 21-52. Heritage, John, 1984, Garfinkel and Ethno methodology (Cambridge: Polity Press). Hirschfeld, Lawrence A., 1996, Race in the Making: Cognition, Culture and the Child's Construction of Human Kinds (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press). Hollinger, David A., 1995, Postethnic Ameri ca: Beyond Multiculturalism (New York: Basic Books). Holquist, Peter, 1997, Conduct Merciless 'Mass Terror': Decossackization on the Don, 1919, Cahiers du Monde russe 38(1-2), 127-162. Homans, George C., 1950, The Human Group (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.) Horowitz, Donald L., 1985, Ethnic Groups in Conflict (Berkeley, CA: University of Cali fornia Press). —, 1991, A Democratic South Africa?: Consti tutional Engineering in a Divided Society (Berkeley: University of California Press). —, 2001, The Deadly Ethnic Riot (Berkeley, CA: University of California Press). Jenkins, Richard, 1997, Rethinking Ethnicity (London: Sage). Kuran, Timur, 1998, Ethnic Norms and their T ransformation through Reputation al Cascades, Journal of Legal Studies 27, 623-659. Laitin, David D., 1995, National Revivals and Violence, Archives européennes de sociologie xxxvi, 3-43. Levine, Hal B., 1999, Reconstructing Ethnic ity, Journal of the Royal Anthropological Institute (New Series) 5,165-180. Magyari-Nândor, Lâszlô and Lâszlô Péter, 1997, Az egytemröl magyar diâkszemmel [Hungarian students' views on the univer sity], Korunk 1997/4, 112-119. Martin, Terry, 2001, The Affirmative Action Empire (Ithaca: Cornell University Press). McCarthy, John D. and Mayer N. Zald, 1977, Resource Mobilization and Social Movements: A Partial Theory, American Journal of Sociology 82 (6), 1212-1241. McGrath, Joseph E., 1984, Groups: Interac tion and Performance (New Jersey: Prentice Hall). McKay, James and Frank Lewins,i978, Eth nicity and the Ethnic Group: A Conceptual Analysis and Reformulation, Ethnic and Racial Studies 1 (4), 412-427. Medin, Douglas L., 1989, Concepts and Conceptual Structure, The American Psy chologist 44,1469-1481. Moerman, Michael, 1968, Being Lue: Uses and Abuses of Ethnic Identification, in June Helm (ed.), Essays on the Problem of Tribe (Washington: University of Washington Press). Mueller, John, 2000, The Banality of 'Ethnic War', International Security 25,42-70. Nadel, S. F., 1957, A Theory of Social Struc ture (London: Cohen & West). Noiriel, Gérard, 1991, La Tyrannie du nation al: le droit d'asile en Europe 1793-1993 (Paris: Calmann-Lévy). Office of Management and Budget, 1994, Standards for the classification of fed eral data on race and ethnicity, http :/lwww.whitehouse.gov/omb/fedregl notice-15.html. Olson, Mancur, 1965, The Logic of Collective Action: Public Goods and the Theory of Groups (Cambridge: Harvard University Press). Petersen, William, 1987, Politics and the Measurement of Ethnicity, in William Alonso and Paul Starr (eds), The Politics of Numbers (New York: Russell Sage Foun dation), 187-233. Rothbart, Myron and Marjorie Taylor, 1992, Category Labels and Social Reality: Do We View Social Categories As Natural Kinds? in Gün R. Semin and Klaus Fiedler (eds), Language, Interaction and Social Cognition (London: Sage Publications). Rothschild, Joseph, 1981, Ethnopolitics: A Conceptual Framework (New York: Colum bia University Press). Sacks, Harvey, 1995, Lectures on Conversation (Oxford, Blackwell Publishers). Schegloff, Emanuel A., 2000, Accounts of Conduct in Interaction: Interruption, Overlap and Turn-Taking, in J. H. Turner (ed.), Handbook of Sociological Theory (New York: Plenum). Forthcoming. 188 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms ETHNICITY Schutz, Alfred, 1962, Collected Papers I: The Problem of Social Reality, Maurice Natan son (ed.) (The Hague: Marinus Nijhoff). Seaton, Jean, 1999, Why Do We Think the Serbs Do It? The New 'Ethnic' Wars and the Media, Political Quarterly 70(3), 254 270. Slezkine, Yuri, 1994, The USSR As a Com munal Apartment, or How a Socialist State Promoted Ethnic Particularlism, Slavic Review 53(4), 4H-452. Smith, Anthony D., 1986, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (Oxford: Basil Blackwell). —, 1998, Nationalism and Modernism : A Criti cal Survey of Recent Theories of Nations and Nationalism (London: Routledge). Snow, David A. and Robert D. Ben ford, 1988, Ideology, Frame Resonance and Participant Mobilization, International Social Movement Research 1,197-217. Snow, David A., E. B. Rochford Jr., Steven K. Worden and Robert D. Benford, 1986, Frame Alignment Processes, Micromobili zation and Movement Participation, Ameri can Sociological Review 51,464-481. Sperber, Dan, 1985, Anthropology and Psy chology: Towards an Epidemiology of Representations, Man 20, 73-89. Tilly, Charles, 1978, From Mobilization to Revolution (Reading, Mass.: Addison Wesley Publishing Company). —, 1998, Durable Inequality (Berkeley: Uni versity of California Press). Torpey, John, 2000, The Invention of the Passport: Surveillance, Citizenship and the State (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press). Truman, David B., 1951, The Governmental Process: Political Interests and Public Opin ion. 2nd ed. (New York: Alfred A. Knopf). Weber, Max, 1946, From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, H. H. Gerth and Wright Mills (eds) (New York: Oxford University Press). —, 1964, Wirtschaft und Gesellschaf. 4th ed. (Köln: Kiepenheurer & Witsch). —, 1968 [1922], Economy and Society, Guen ther Roth and Claus Wittich (eds) (Ber keley: University of California Press). Weiner, Amir, 2001, Making Sense of War: The Second World War and the Fate of the Bolshevik Revolution (Princeton: Princeton University Press). Wellman, Barry, 1988, Structural Analysis: From Method and Metaphor to Theory and Substance, in Barry Wellman and S. D. Berkowitz (eds), Social Structures: A Network Approach (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 19-61. 189 This content downloaded from 147.231.205.2 on Tue, 29 Nov 2022 14:13:38 UTC All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms