The Review of Economic Studies Ltd. Rational Choice and Erratic Behaviour Author(s): Jess Benhabib and Richard H. Day Source: The Review of Economic Studies, Vol. 48, No. 3 (Jul., 1981), pp. 459-471 Published by: The Review of Economic Studies Ltd. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2297158 Accessed: 15/04/2010 12:41 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=resl. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. The Review of Economic Studies Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Economic Studies. STOR http://www.jstor.org Review of Economic Studies (1981) XLVIII, 459-471 0034-6527/80/00390459$02.00 © 1981 The Society for Economic Analysis Limited Rational Choice and Erratic Behaviour JESS BENHABIB University of Southern California and RICHARD H. DAY University of Southern California 1. INTRODUCTION In this paper we show that rational choice in a stationary environment can lead to erratic behaviour when preferences depend on experience. We mean by erratic behaviour choice sequences that do not converge to a long-run stationary value or to any periodic pattern. Early investigations of the effects of experience on choice goes back to Pareto (see also Benhabib (1979)); some Keynesian theories of the consumption function incorporate the effects of experience and habit formation on current levels of consumption (Duesen-berry (1949), Modigliani (1949) and Brown (1952)); a general model of experience dependent choice was described in Day (1970) and investigated in Day and Kennedy (1971) while the specific issue of the existence of stable representable long-run consumer demand when tastes vary endogenously has been treated by Gorman (1967), Poliak (1970, 1976), Weizsäcker (1971), McCarthy (1974) and Hammond (1976). Poliak gave conditions for the representability of long-run choice when the equations of preference dependence are linear and utility additive. Hammond, in a generalization of these findings, provides conditions for stable, representable long run choice when preferences are acyclic, a condition which in essence assures convergence to a long-run choice. Our concern here is with the contrary case when preferences are at least partially cyclic. In a stable environment (for example, fixed prices and incomes) acyclic preferences rule out feasible alternatives that have been rejected in previous periods. Thus sequences of alternating choices (consisting for instance of holidays in the mountains alternating with vacations at the sea) are impossible. While habit formation may explain the absence of such behaviour, diversity of behaviour and fluctuation in choices are too common to be assumed away. The surprising implication of some cyclicity in preferences is the occurrence of erratically fluctuating behaviour, which in our theory emerges endogenously from a completely deterministic structure in a stationary environment. This "chaos" contrasts with the usual explanations for such phenomena which are couched in terms of exo-genously determined random shocks. Many of the ideas which we present were already introduced, in heuristic form, in Georgescu-Roegen's (1950) analysis of consumer choice under endogenously changing preferences. (See also Georgescu-Roegen (1971, pp. 126-127).) He clearly realized the erratic nature of dynamic choice behaviour which led him to conclude the following: "Does the preceding analysis justify the negation of the constancy of economic laws? The right answer seems to be that, on the contrary, it eliminates the variability of consumer's behaviour as an eventual argument against such a constancy. However, the micro-approach is deprived to a large extent of any quantitative predictability over finite (i.e. important) changes." 459 460 REVIEW OF ECONOMIC STUDIES Erratic behaviour of the type under investigation here was first shown to exist for equations of hydrodynamic flow applied to modelling turbulence in fluids or weather phenomenon by Lorenz (1963, 1964). Applications in biological population theory followed in the work of May (1975), May and Oster (1976) and Guckenheimer, Oster and Ipaktchi (1977) (to mention a few authors). A formal theory and existence conditions for the discrete case has been set forth by Li and Yorke (1975) whose results were generalized by Diamond (1976). Chaos in the sense of Lorenz and Li and Yorke has its continuous time counterpart in the phenomenon of "strange attractors" first discussed by Ruelle and Takens (1971). A highly readable survey will be found in Yorke and Yorke (1980). In Section 2 of this paper we review the "chaos" theorems of Li and Yorke and Diamond and present a generalization suitable for application to the set-valued choice functions that arise in general economic theory. We then give, in Section 3, two examples of unique choice in U2 based on experience dependent utility to which the basic Li-Yorke theorem applies. This is followed in Section 4 by a general definition and analysis of tricyclic preferences in Un and by the extension to dynamic, set-valued choice functions in Section 5. The paper concludes with remarks concerning interpretation. From the point of view of empirical application the examples of Section 3 are highly suggestive. They show that erratic sequences of rational choices do not arise when income is low but can when wealth gets sufficiently high. Thus the "poor" might exhibit quite stable responses to price and income changes while the "rich" may be quite unstable appearing arbitrary or whimsical. 2. ERRATIC BEHAVIOUR OR "CHAOS" The investigation of behaviour when preferences depend on experience boils down to the study of solutions of the dynamic choice functions. We will show that when preferences possess a special type of cyclic structure there exist periodic choice sequences (cycles) of every order and also choice sequences that are erratic in the well-defined sense that they are not stationary, periodic or asymptotically stationary or periodic. Before proceeding with the analysis we review some basic concepts, definitions and theorems. The iterated map Ck(-;a,s) is defined recursively by Cfe+1(-; a, s), a, s] = C[Ck(-; a, s); a, s], k = 0, 1,2,... where C°(•; a, s) = / (the identity map) and where C (•; a,s) = C(-; a,s). A point xeX(s) is called fc-periodic if C {x\ a,s) = x and if C'(x ; a, s) ť* x for 0 0, (3) BENHABIB & DAY ERRATIC BEHAVIOUR 461 where x (t) and y (t) are any two chaotic trajectories in 5. In addition chaotic trajectories in S wander away from periodic cycles of any period so that the equality in (2) is changed to an inequality. The existence of erratic or chaotic trajectories depends on an "over-shoot" or nonlinearity condition. This was established by Li and Yorke in a theorem which we present here without proof. Theorem 1 (Li and Yorke). Let J be an interval in U and consider the difference equation xt+i=f(xt) (4) in which f is a continuous mapping ofJ-*J. Suppose there exists a point xeJ such that f(x)^x0 (iii) for every p in S and periodic set P in A, then for all q in P \imsupk^\fk(p)-fk(q)\>0. Diamond's simple extension of the Li-Yorke theorem brings out very nicely the fact that the proof of chaos rests exclusively on the combinatorial and topological character of the sequence of maps f,f,___No properties of Un other than its metrical nature are exploited. For this reason it is possible to state a chaos theorem for set-valued maps. This enables us to extend the results on erratic economic behaviour to dynamic, set-valued choice functions. We state the theorem which we use in Section 5 here. For completeness the proof is stated in the Appendix. 462 REVIEW OF ECONOMIC STUDIES Theorem 3. Let F be an upper-semicontinuous, compact, set-valued map (correspondence) from a metric space V-+3P(V) with metric d. Assume there exists asetX <=V such that (CI) XvF(X)aF2(X)c:V (C2) XnF(X) = 0. Then A. For all k = 1,2,3,... there exists a k-periodic set, say Xk c: Vsuch thatFk(Xk) = Xk; B. There exists an uncountable setS^V which contains no periodic set, such that F (S) c S and such that (i) for all x, y eS,XŤ*y, andF(x) nF(y) = 0, there exist trajectories xt+\ e F(xt), x0 = x, and yt+i£F(yt), yo = y such that lim supř->oo d(xt, y t) > 0. (ii) for all xeS for any k-periodic set P in X, for all y eP lim supř->oo d(xt, yt) > 0. 3. ERRATIC DEMAND WHEN TASTES ARE ENDOGENOUS: TWO EXAMPLES In order to illustrate the existence of erratic sequences of rational choices, consider the familiar utility function u(x,y;a) = xay1~a, (5) in which x and y are amounts of two goods consumed within a given period and a is a utility weight with 0 < a < 1. Maximizing utility subject to the usual budget constraint px + qy = m (6) yields the demand equations x=a-, y = (l-a)~ (7) P q The dependence of these functions upon experience is obtained by supposing that the parameter of the utility function representing preferences depends endogenously on past choices. Consider the case in which this dependence is upon the immediate past according to a function at+1 = g(xt, yt;a). (8) The demand functions now become m . m xx Xt+i = — g(xt, yt\ot), yt+x = — (1 - g(xt, y t; a)), (9) P 1. The maximum consumption of good x (e.g. leisure) occurs when past experience is xt = jt* = m/2. In this case xt+1 = {am3)/A. If this is to satisfy the budget constraint then am2^4. Consequently, we need only consider a system with income endowment m and experience dependence parameter a such that Kam2^4. When am2 is close to 1, the stationary state is stable. As am2 increases past 3 cycles emerge. At some combination am such that (am2)2(r-am2)<8<4am2 a three period cycle occurs with period 3 points, am (4-am )/16, m/2 and m /4. Let us call this point c, the chaos point. Hence, by Theorem 1, for c(*; a, s). (19) Definition 1. The preferences represented by (A; a, j)nAT(j); a, 5). Partially tricyclic preferences are illustrated in Figure 1. It is seen that they imply an oscillation in choice. *2(A) C(X) C3(X;«,S) CM C(X;«,S) X(s) -♦X (a) A Period 3 Cycle in Choice (b) ,Mustration of Defjnftion Figure 1 Consider the allocation of an individual's time between tennis, reading, and a composite activity which we call sleep, over a three day weekend. Let the individual always sleep eight hours. If he plays tennis between 10 to 14 hours the first day, let him play tennis between 4 to 9 hours the second day depending on his choice the first day, and having done so the second day, let his choice for tennis vary between 4 to 14 hours for the third day depending on his choice for the second day. Then his choice function will be partially tricyclical. This is illustrated in Figure 2. It should be emphasized that the conditions of partial tricyclicity in Definition 1 has to hold for some but not every subset A of X(s) for a given s. Furthermore, our results will require partial tricyclicity for some s, not over the whole range of 5. When X(s) is "small" (for example when income is low) preferences may be acyclic, but when X(s) is "large" (for example when income is large) tricyclicity may emerge. Indeed, this latter possibility was precisely the character of the examples of Section 3. 9999999999999999� 466 REVIEW OF ECONOMIC STUDIES o z Q < S 12-1 21 —---------1 i—i------------------------1------- 4 9 10 14 Tennis 2nd day to 3rd day: Clearly 2 maps to 3 which includes 1. 0) CC 121 71 61 4 9 10 14 Tennis 1st day to 2nd day: Cross-Section for 8 hours of sleep. The intersection is empty. Figure 2 It is immediately apparent that the tricyclicity of preferences imply that the dynamic choice function has a similar tricyclic character. For completeness, we note this fact in the following lemma. Lemma. Suppose that preferences are tricyclic on a compact, convex choice setX(s) in the sense of Definition 1. Then the choice function C(y;a,s) is tricyclic in the same sense, that is, there exists a setA<^X(s) such that (a) AnC(A;a,s)=0, (b) AuC(A;a,í)cC2(A;a,í), Proof Let A be the set satisfying Definition 1 which exists by hypothesis. Then (a) follows from the facts that A n X(s) = A and <ř(A; a, s) n X(s) = C (A; a, s). To prove (b) note that 4>(<1>(A; a, s) nX(s); a, s) nX(s) = 4>(C(A; a, s); a, s) nX(s) = C2(A; a, s). Also, (A; a, s)uAnX(s) = C(A;a, s)vA. Using (b) of Definition 1, the result follows. || The existence of erratic sequences of experience dependent choices now follows immediately from Diamond's theorem. We state our finding as: Proposition 1. Let preferences be partially tricyclic on a choice set X(s) <^Rn as in Definition 1. Then for the dynamic choice function (15) (a) there exist periodic choice sequences of every period fc = l,2,3,...; and (b) there exists an uncountable set S c X (s) such that for every initial condition in S the choice sequence remains in S and is aperiodic, i.e. is erratic. The relationship between partially tricyclic choice functions as defined in the Lemma and the conditions for erratic behaviour originally stated by Li and Yorke (Theorem 1 in Section 2) can be seen in Figure 3. Here x3 = C3(x0)o satisfying jci+i eF(xrt) and xrteXt for all t Let S:{xr}r. This set is uncountable because the map r-» {Xrt} is one-one. Suppose r ť* s e (0,1) and consider the distinct sequences {Xrt}, {Xst}. There exist infinite subsequences {Xrtp}, {Xstp} such that X\v ^Xstp (either Xstp =X while Xstp = F(X) or vice versa). Let ô0 = infxex,yeF(x) d(x, y), 80>0 because X nF(X) = 0. Hence, there exist trajectories {xrt}, {yst} such that d(x í, y J) > 0 for an infinite subsequence. Thus limř_oo sup d(xrh y J) > 0. The remainder of the proof follows analogously. || First version received June 1979; final version accepted November 1980 (Eds.). REFERENCES BENHABIB, J. (1979), "Pareto vs. Wicksell on the Adjustment Costs in Consumption: A Reformulation", Economics Letters 2, 121-124. BERGE, C. (1963) Topological Spaces (New York: The Macmillan Co.). BROWN, T. M. (1952), "Habit Persistence and Lags in Consumer Behavior", Econometrica, 20 (3), 355-371. BUTLER, G. J. and PIANIGIANI, A. (1978), "Periodic Points and Chaotic Functions in the Unit Interval", Bulletin of the Australian Mathematical Society, 18, 255-265. DAY, R. H. (1970), "Rational Choice and Economic Behavior", Theory and Decision, 1, 229-251. DAY, R. H. and KENNEDY, P. E. (1971), "Recursive Decision Systems: An Existence Analysis", Econometrica, 38 (5), 666-681. DIAMOND, P. (1976), "Chaotic Behavior of Systems of Difference Equations", International Journal of Systems Science, 7 (8), 953-956. DUESENBERRY, J. S. (1949) Income, Saving, and the Theory of Consumer Behavior (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press). BENHABIB & DAY ERRATIC BEHAVIOUR 471 GEORGESCU-ROEGEN, N. (1950), "The Theory of Choice and the Constancy of Economic Laws", Quarterly Journal of Economics, 44, 125-138. GEORGESCU-ROEGEN, N. (1971) The Entropy Law and the Economic Process (Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press). GORMAN, W. M. (1967), "Tastes, Habits and Choices", International Economic Review, 8, 212-222. GUCKENHEIMER, J., OSTER, G. and IPAKTCHI, A. (1977), "Dynamics of Density Dependent Population Models", Journal of Mathematical Biology, 4, 101-147. HAMMOND, P. J. (1976), "Endogenous Tastes and Stable Long-Run Choice", Journal of Economic Theory, 13, (76), 329-340. KLOEDEN, P. E. (1976), "Chaotic Difference Equations are Dense", Bulletin of the Australian Mathematical Society, 15, 371-379. LI, T. Y. and YORKE, J. A. (1975), "Period Three Implies Chaos", American Mathematical Monthly, 82, 895-992. LORENZ, E. N. (1963), "Deterministic Non-Periodic Flow", Journal of Atmospheric Science, 20, 130-141. LORENZ, E. N. (1964), "The Problem of Deducing the Climate from the Governing Equations", Tellus, 16, 1-11. MAY, R. M. (1975), "Biological Populations Obeying Difference Equations: Stable Points, Stable Cycles, and Chaos", Journal of Theoretical Biology, 51, 511-524. MAY, R. M. and OSTER, G. F. (1976), "Bifurcations and Dynamic Complexity in Simple Ecological Models", . The American Naturalist, 110 (974), 573-594. McCARTHY, M. D. (1934), "On the Stability of Dynamic Demand Systems", International Economic Review, 15, 256-259. MODIGLIANI, F. (1949), "Fluctuations in the Income-Saving Ratio: A Problem in Economic Forecasting", Studies in Income and Wealth, 11, (New York: National Bureau of Economic Research). PARETO, V. (1964), Bousquet, G. H. and Busino, G. (eds.) Cours D'economie Politique (Geneva: Librairie Droz) Volume 2, Chapter 3, Section 928, 280-285. PESTON, M. H. (1967), "Changing Utility Functions", in M. Shubik (ed.) Essays in Mathematical Economics in Honor of Oskar Morgenstern (Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press) 233-236. POLLAK, R. A. (1970), "Habit Formation and Dynamic Demand Functions", Journal of Political Economy, 78, 745-783. POLLAK, R. A. (1976), "Habit Formation and Long-Run Utility Functions", Journal of Economic Theory, 13, 272-297. RUELLE, D. and TAKENS, F. (1971), "On the Nature of Turbulence", Communications in Mathematical Physics", 20, 167-192. WEIZSÄCKER, C. C. VON (1971), "Notes on Endogenous Change of Tastes", Journal of Economic Theory, 3, 345-372. YORKE, J. A. and YORKE, E. D. (1979), "Chaotic Behaviour and Fluid Dynamics", forthcoming in Swinney, H. L. and Gollub, J. P. (eds.) Hydrodynamic Instability and the Transition to Turbulence.